Education After Dewey PA U L FA I R F I E L D
Continuum International Publishing Group The Tower Building, 11 York Ro...
41 downloads
1161 Views
3MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
Education After Dewey PA U L FA I R F I E L D
Continuum International Publishing Group The Tower Building, 11 York Road, London SE1 7NX 80 Maiden Lane, Suite 704, New York, NY 10038 www.continuumbooks.com © Paul Fairfield 2009 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. Paul Fairfield has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Author of this work. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: 978-1-4411-4586-4 (hardcover) Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Fairfield, Paul, 1966Education After Dewey / Paul Fairfield. p. cm. ISBN 978-1-4411-4586-4 (hardcover) 1. Education--Philosophy. 2. Education--Aims and objectives. 3. Education, Humanistic. 4. Dewey, John, 1859-1952. I. Title. LB14.7.F33 2009 370.1--dc22 2009012059
Typeset by Kenneth Burnley, Wirral, Cheshire Printed and bound in Great Britain by . . .
Chapter 1
Contents
A Note about References Introduction: An Enigmatic Transition
vii 1
Part 1: The Educative Process 1 2 3
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism Dewey’s Copernican Revolution What Is Called Thinking?
13 52 101
Part 2: Education in the Human Sciences 4 5 6 7 8 9
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination? Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship Teaching History: The Past and the Present Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
149 183 210 233 257 280
Index
305
For Gwyneth Fairfield
Chapter 1
A Note about References
All references to John Dewey’s texts are from The Collected Works, 1882– 1953, edited by Jo Ann Boydston and published by Southern Illinois University Press. In the endnotes, EW refers to The Early Works, 1882– 1898 (5 volumes), MW refers to The Middle Works, 1899–1924 (15 volumes), and LW refers to The Later Works, 1925–1953 (17 volumes).
This page intentionally left blank
Introduction
An Enigmatic Transition
The crucial matter in education is the transition from relative ignorance to a condition as difficult to attain as to describe theoretically: intellectual agency, maturity, emancipation, or, more modestly, being informed are a few possibilities. Education is the name for this transition or transformation, the ambiguity of which has long been a topic of theoretical reflection. In describing the learning process, Plato first emphasized the difficulty of leading the mind from the world of illusion that is its original abode to enlightenment. His account of this process was couched in epistemological and metaphysical terms that no longer warrant belief even as the story of the cave itself and the prisoners’ gradual introduction to the world above retains a special relevance, as a metaphor at least. This should not surprise us; metaphorical interpretations often shed light in a way that literal and theoretical propositions do not, particularly when what we would describe is as ambiguous as the nature of the educative process and the aims that guide it. Our goal in this study is to understand this process. It is a project that will not succeed if we overlook this ambiguity or insist on reducing it to zero, for the ambiguity of education directly reflects that of human experience in general. It is a quality that we must cope with and endeavor to clarify, but gaining clarity has its limits when the thing itself is no mere technical puzzle but belongs fundamentally to our experience of the world. Several possibilities suggest themselves, some more metaphorical than others, in speaking of this transition: from bondage to liberation, illusion to enlightenment, ignorance to the truth, nature to culture, immaturity to maturity, possessing less information or skills to more, and so on. Each succeeds in some measure in illuminating the phenomena of teaching and learning. In thinking about education we are often tempted to select one such phrase and set it up as a model to which everything can be reduced, but if the object of inquiry is itself multidimensional, so as well must be our account of it. It is here that reductionist theories run aground: deeming clarity and simplicity cardinal virtues of theorizing in general, they reduce all richness and complexity to artificial simplicity and so misunderstand the object. This remains a common failing of educational theories. On the side of the individual, education represents a transformation of perspective that 1
2
Introduction
in one fashion or another raises the mind to a condition of some higher kind, or kinds. It informs and transforms in about equal measure, depending on the subject matter, the stage of the learning process, and a variety of other factors. On the side of the social, education initiates the young into a tradition; it produces acculturation and makes it possible for the younger generation to participate in the ways of an historical community. The individual and the social dimensions of education are themselves inseparable, adding further to its complexity. This practice also has an unmistakable political dimension, is often difficult to distinguish from indoctrination, draws upon an underdeveloped and often reductive understanding of human psychology, and has long been the playground of social engineers and enthusiasts of every possible kind, all of whom maintain that the solution to our problems is to mold the young in accordance with whatever opinions they hold dear. No practice is as vulnerable as education to political or scientific fashion, its practitioners continually pulled this way and that by the latest findings in the social sciences as well as by economic imperatives and societal trends that have little to do with the cultivation of intellectual maturity. Educational meddling by an endless array of the well meaning but misinformed remains as commonplace in our times as in any other, the effect of which is not only, and not primarily, to educate the mind but to produce a certain form of subjectivity: workers, consumers, or believers of one kind or another. A consequence of scientific and philosophical theorizing, social forces and economic pressures, as well as the complexities already inherent to the learning process, is a certain lack of orientation on the part of educators, or an orientation beset by contradictions. Educators are charged with delivering a curriculum they have little or no part in selecting, preparing students for standardized tests produced by ostensible experts, training a workforce, preserving traditions, managing behavior, instilling values, acting as role models and therapists, applying techniques and research findings while raising standards as governments understand or misunderstand the phrase. Education today can be likened to a soup over-rich in ingredients: every new cook in the kitchen adds a pinch of this and a dash of that until at last the concoction has everything in it but flavor. Cooks, to push the metaphor a bit, typically do not see their customers, while those responsible for serving up the tasteless brew know very well how it is going over, yet neither server nor customer has any say as to its composition. By the time the reviews reach the kitchen, the recipe has changed yet again along with the cook. The situation is different for university professors, of course, who have long and jealously guarded their autonomy in the classroom, but teachers at the primary and secondary levels have found their status as professionals severely compromised as the scope for independent judgment diminishes. Teachers faced with these conditions may be forgiven for being bewildered, caught as they
An Enigmatic Transition
3
are in the maelstrom of empirical studies and social realities, politics and religion, philosophy and other philosophies, psychology and other psychologies, and lacking the autonomy proper to any professional to form and act on their own judgment. The real world of education is a miscellany of often irreconcilable aims, imperatives, and fashions, many of which are extraneous to the practice and simply imposed from without, and all of which individual educators must square in some precarious way with the realities of the classroom. To get our bearings we must gain a more explicit understanding of the transition noted above and the principles that belong to it. There is, as I shall argue, a logic that is always already inherent to the educative process. The philosopher’s task is to render this logic or dynamic explicit and to identify its implications. It is also to critique approaches to education that effectively undermine this logic either by pursuing means that negate the practice’s own aims or by substituting extraneous ends, a common occurrence at present if it is not indeed a universal phenomenon. Like any social practice, education contains its own immanent conditions and ends which can be undermined when pursued by improper means or when conflicting aims supplant them. The temptation toward the latter is great and certainly not limited to our own time and place. The classroom will remain the playground of politicians and social engineers, religionists and enthusiasts, social scientists and philosophers, sometimes for the better and sometimes not. When they are for the better, such efforts recognize a kind of integrity – an integration of principles – inherent to the learning process, principles that must be identified and implemented if the practice is to succeed. When for the worse, these efforts reduce education to a mere means to an end, usually an end defined in terms of economics, politics, or religion. Whatever education is at the most fundamental level of analysis, it is not merely a means to an end. While it has always been known that a good education prepares one for a career and for later life in general – whether directly or indirectly, by intention or by accident – its meaning is not limited to this. In particular, it is not limited to economic utility. There is a higher purpose that education serves, as Plato taught us to see even while misdescribing this purpose or construing it in crude, metaphysical terms. To understand the nature and purpose of education we must view it in the larger context of human experience. The philosophical concept of experience provides the most appropriate point of view from which to interpret our theme for the reason that the transition that education essentially is is a transition in our experience of ourselves and our world. Beyond having acquired a certain amount of information, the educated mind possesses a capacity for experience that is richer and more expansive than its less
4
Introduction
educated counterpart. The transition that it undertakes is from an experience that is narrow and superficial to one that is broad and profound. When it achieves its purpose, education leads the mind from the world of the familiar and narrowly practical to the unfamiliar and abstract; it teaches us how to see beneath surfaces and beyond the false certainties with which our culture provides us as a talisman against thinking. Above all, the educated mind is open, and radically so, to new experiences and ideas that require critical reflection and, if adopted, a rearrangement of our prior opinions. It is inclined to ask questions, to seek justifications for ideas, and to have its experience of the world transformed. Education requires a venturing beyond oneself to what is foreign and unexpected and a consequent alteration of the conversation that is our culture while cultivating a range of capacities and intellectual virtues necessary to that end. What education is not is a world unto itself, something divorced from experience outside the classroom or a realm of ideas disconnected from life. At its worst this is precisely what education becomes: a cloister of other-worldly concerns or intellectual gymnastics that connect in no way with the ordinary search for understanding of which our experience consists. The relation of formal education to experience, as I shall argue in this study, is that of species to genus. Understanding education requires that we investigate this connection and see how the former, when it is successful, originates in the latter and also returns to it. It is the nature of human experience to encounter situations that upset our expectations and that are in some manner or other problematic. Everyday life brings us into contact not only with that which confirms our knowledge and anticipations but especially with that which disconfirms them. This happens most often on a small scale, but occasionally on a larger one: our assumptions about the world come up against competing views, our beliefs are called into question in the encounter with texts or persons not of like mind, or our self-certainty is challenged by a sense of contingency. If experience is our point of departure, and if it is of the nature of experience to be beset with problems to be resolved and questions to be answered, then education consists in the search for solutions and answers or in a series of investigations. The concept of inquiry is fundamental here and is importantly different and places students in a different role than older conceptions of students as essentially passive receptacles of a curriculum consisting entirely of predigested information. Students are better regarded as participants in investigation and fellow discussants – perhaps discussants in training – in the conversation that is their culture. The accent on experience, participation, and inquiry requires us to take seriously contemporary notions of dialogue, thinking or ‘critical thinking’, and to inquire into their meanings. Education, as all can agree, crucially bears on a student’s ability to think
An Enigmatic Transition
5
intelligently, whatever this means exactly for students at different stages of the learning process and in different fields of study. Is thinking one or many? Is there a theoretical model that can capture everything properly describable as thought? For that matter, can thinking be taught, and if so, then by what means? Intelligent thought is what the educated mind is ostensibly capable of and what experience culminates in, yet in what does it consist? These are philosophical questions all, and they are neither straightforward nor avoidable if we are to get a handle on what education is. Thinking undoubtedly has to do with the search for understanding that is central to education, but beyond the preliminaries and slogans, in exactly what does it consist? The concepts of experience and thinking are fundamentally connected, but what is the nature of this connection and what are its educational consequences? What educational success ultimately looks like is a mind that is both well informed and capable of intelligent reflection. It is also what our times, rather desperately in my view, call for: the ability to exercise judgment and to engage in intelligent discussion about ideas and worldly events, to think outside of narrow specialties and rules and to be able to justify with some semblance of rationality whatever beliefs that we hold. Our educational institutions appear to be of two minds on the question of thinking, and it is an ambivalence that directly reflects an ambivalence of our age: we speak of the imperative to think outside the box, of the need for creativity and innovation that would match the innovation of technology and the progress of scientific knowledge, yet at the same time we are troubled by unconventionality of values, by the concept of judgment, and by ideas that cause more than small modifications in our understanding of the world. The concept of judgment, for instance, appears to many to be inseparable from intolerance or even fanaticism unless it is practiced by a body of specially trained experts. To judge is to be judgmental, we commonly hear, thus to commit a certain intellectual or moral failing. Yet the capacity for judgment is indispensable both in education and in our experience in general. Like common sense and imagination, what is called good judgment – practical, political, ethical, aesthetic, and so on – is fundamental to intellectual agency. Limiting this to experts is an abdication of reason, of ordinary capacities of thought and intelligence that largely define what it means to be a human being. Judgment in these forms does not permit of expertise, however it can be trained through habitual use. The same can be said of thinking in general, in its higher reaches: while it sometimes works with formal methods and techniques, often there are neither rules to be followed nor expertise to be gained, and one must undertake a more creative act of cognition than the concepts of technique and expertise suggest. Whether there are rules to be followed or not depends on the object of investigation and the questions we are asking about it. In an age in which science is regarded as more or less
6
Introduction
synonymous with rational thought in general, it seems to many dangerously subjectivist to speak of a reflection that is unscientific and not governed by rules of some objective kind. If it is the nature of human thought, experience, and education that we are investigating, then there are indeed empirical questions to be asked, yet there are also properly philosophical ones for which scientific methods will not help us. In particular, there is something called the art of thinking – of imagining and judging, justifying and criticizing, interpreting and questioning, narrating and metaphorizing, understanding and self-understanding, speculating and wondering – which is highly resistant to scientific explanation and which requires philosophical and phenomenological investigation. I regard this as an urgent matter both in view of the ambivalence regarding thinking just noted and because the art of thinking, whatever we take this to mean in specific terms, appears in many ways to be out of step with the times. A variety of historical conditions, from the scientific and technological to the philosophical and epistemological, the economic and political, and so on, has had the effect not only of reducing thought to a technique but of gradually reducing opportunities for its exercise. Increasingly thought is the preserve of expertise, something that ordinary persons need not and perhaps ought not engage in; instead we must defer and adapt to what the experts determine, and in a society that offers up experts on just about everything there is. Even the well educated now have information and opinions but not knowledge – not the genuine article, that is. For this they must look elsewhere, to persons with specialized qualifications, even if only a short time ago the item of knowledge in question was considered a matter of ordinary common sense. If what is called thinking were one day to disappear from the face of the earth, it would be due not to any breakdown in societal structures or to the ‘school failures’ about which we hear so much, but to simple irrelevance. When there is no need any longer for educated professionals to make ethical judgments in the workplace due to the availability of specialized ‘ethicists’, when citizens of a democracy need only defer to the political and economic expertise of television pundits, when we are unable even to take care of ourselves in ordinary matters of mind and body but must defer to an endless proliferation of caring professionals, we have indeed become an unthinking society. Whether, as Allan Bloom has asserted, the American mind has been closed, I do not know, and not only because I am not American.1 I suspect it has not, or not in the way that he suggests. It may be closer to the truth to say with Martin Heidegger that ‘we are still not thinking’, that our conceptual framework has become excessively beholden to technology and dangerously one- or perhaps two-dimensional.2 His worry, and the worry of numerous existential and phenomenological thinkers following him, was that by the twentieth century thinking had become thoroughly assimilated into
An Enigmatic Transition
7
the machinery of technological civilization and that genuinely novel ways of seeing the world had become a veritable impossibility. The new credulity toward science and technology spells trouble for any ideas that wish to announce themselves in an unscientific vocabulary. Were I to devise a blueprint for making an unreflective culture still less reflective, I would do the following: reduce knowledge or thinking to a single form, reduce that form to so many bits of useable information, organize education around the possession of information in the largest possible quantity, and standardize the information that is taught and learned in educational institutions. The result would be a pretty good assurance that nothing new would be said and that mainstream culture would become even more hegemonic. There are many today who see education precisely in this light, who warn of the dangers of a young generation unprepared to enter the workforce and compete in the global economy. I am not in the least sympathetic to their cause and instead regard the central business of education at all levels as the cultivation of intellectual agency, something that necessitates acquiring a good deal of information and scientific knowledge but that also surpasses this. In advancing this argument my primary interlocutor will be John Dewey. In spite of the vast educational literature that has emerged in recent decades from a variety of disciplines and theoretical approaches, I believe that none has surpassed Dewey if what we are after is a principled account of the educative process. No more contemporary philosopher in this area has rendered his thought outdated, nor in my view has the philosophy of education that he advanced been convincingly refuted. It has been clarified and refined, interpreted and very often misinterpreted, used and abused, but refuted or surpassed it has not. As so often happens in the history of ideas, the conversation has moved on since Dewey’s time, yet a change in direction is not always an indication of progress. Like several other aspects of Dewey’s philosophy, his theory of education is no longer the fashion, if indeed it ever was. Students of education and teachers in training typically know a certain amount about Dewey – that he was associated with the progressive movement, for instance, and that his texts do not make for light reading – but they do not usually read his work. Nor, it would seem, do many of his critics, past and present, or not with the care that is usual in scholarly discourse. For all their ostensible influence and fame, most especially Democracy and Education of 1916, his writings in this field have been so misread, by so many and for so long, that it remains necessary for scholars to correct the misunderstandings that greeted his work from the beginning. Dewey’s own efforts to repeat and clarify his position did little to dispel the caricatures. His theory of education is neither positivistic nor an excuse for lowering academic standards; it is neither unclear nor to be understood in isolation from his philosophy as a whole. Indeed his educational thought is highly
8
Introduction
integrated with his contributions to epistemology, psychology, philosophy of science, politics, ethics, and even aesthetics. A model of experimental knowing underlies his philosophy in general and must be understood if we are to assess the relevance of his philosophy of education a century after its original formulation. Additional reasons for returning to Dewey are that he explicitly grounded education in a theory of human experience that continues to warrant our attention. Understanding the nature of the learning process requires that we view it in the larger context of experimental and intellectual maturation, of the gradual formation and transformation of the self, and in terms that recognize the individual’s thorough embeddedness in culture. As Dewey often pointed out, what takes place in the classroom is, or ought to be, continuous with life outside it. Questions regarding curriculum, techniques of instruction, and so on must not be approached as if the mind of the student were an ahistorical mechanism of some kind, a computer to be programmed or a producer-consumer in training. Nor should the question of development be approached in quasi-objective fashion, apart from phenomenological description of our lived experience. The transition that education brings about is a rising up to humanity, a cultivation of the self as an intellectual agent and active participant in the life of its society. It does not merely prepare the young for later life but transforms their perspective on the world and puts them in the role of questioners, inquirers, and participants in dialogue. While these are contemporary themes, they were also familiar to Dewey and to many of his predecessors, including G. W. F. Hegel and the Bildung tradition in German philosophy. Examining these themes obliges us to reconsider Dewey’s educational thought, where this means both elucidating its meaning and examining its contemporary relevance. Dewey’s educational philosophy, minus the misinterpretations to which it has long been subject, continues to demand our attention. Yet its appropriation, or perhaps its rehabilitation, must be a critical one. It is a philosophy whose basic outline was formulated well prior to the publication of Democracy and Education in 1916, in the final decade of the nineteenth century and the first decade of the twentieth, and which not surprisingly bears the traces of that era. I shall be treating Dewey as an interlocutor in the chapters that follow, thus neither as a villain to be castigated for whatever failings we believe our educational institutions suffer from, nor as a Master Thinker whose views may be wholeheartedly assented to once suitably understood. An interlocutor is not one whose views meet with an unqualified yes or no. While I find myself in substantial agreement with his writings on education and on some other matters as well, the title of this book is not Education According to Dewey. The significance of the ‘After’ is that I shall be bringing his views into contact with some more contemporary philosophical developments, including
An Enigmatic Transition
9
figures and themes following his time and in some cases figures who belong to a tradition that interested Dewey very little. This is the tradition, or traditions, of continental European philosophy that includes, among many other figures, Friedrich Nietzsche, Martin Heidegger, Hannah Arendt, HansGeorg Gadamer, Paul Ricoeur, Michel Foucault, Paulo Freire, and John Caputo, all of whom will be interlocutors as well in the study that follows. My question is how well Dewey’s position stands up today, in view of what we may consider to be developments in the field. Do Heidegger’s statements on the nature of thinking, for instance, add anything of importance to Dewey’s view or compel a re-examination? Does Gadamer’s philosophy of experience advance beyond Dewey’s experimental model? How does a Deweyan view of moral or political education look in light of Arendt’s theory of judgment or Freire’s theory of dialogical education? Does Ricoeur’s narrative theory of the self supplement a Deweyan view of literary education, and does Foucault’s genealogical conception of history complement or undermine Dewey’s notion of an historical education? These are the questions that orient the following studies. In addressing them I have endeavored to bring Dewey’s thought into contact with ideas not radically unlike his own or, at any rate, that are sufficiently commensurable with it to make productive dialogue possible. Conversation across philosophical traditions is always difficult but rarely impossible, and while it is clear that Dewey was not well disposed to continental philosophy much after Hegel, or especially knowledgeable of it, deep affinities do exist between Dewey and several strains in the continental thought of the twentieth century. Some of these affinities are traceable to his profound and lifelong indebtedness to Hegel while other similarities will be due to factors less readily identifiable. Dewey was a profoundly American philosopher, one for whom the works of his European contemporaries for the most part held little or no interest, in spite of his deeply phenomenological sensibility and the important similarities between his work and much of what was happening in French and (especially) German philosophy during his lifetime. While in 1930 Dewey would describe how his ‘acquaintance with Hegel has left a permanent deposit in my thinking’, the same cannot be said of the continental thought of his day.3 Indeed, even his knowledge of such key figures as Nietzsche, Husserl, and Heidegger was surprisingly scant, with no or very few references to their works appearing in Dewey’s writings, and none demonstrating a proper understanding of their significance or affinity to his own thought. My own views on education will emerge in the confrontations between Dewey and the above-mentioned theorists. Part 1 looks at Dewey in connection with two of the most important figures in twentieth-century phenomenology and hermeneutics: Heidegger and Gadamer. After examining in some detail Dewey’s conceptions of experience and thinking, I shall place
10
Introduction
these views in relation to Gadamer’s conception of experience (Chapter 2) and Heidegger’s notion of thinking (Chapter 3). I also return in Part 1 (Chapter 1) to an old distinction in the philosophy of education between progressivism and conservatism, the contemporary relevance of which is plain to see. Conservatism remains alive and well in some influential circles, although its recent incarnations differ in some ways from the forms of traditional instruction that Dewey sharply criticized. This distinction still emerges into the foreground of current debates, although more often it operates in the background. I return to it in order to situate and clarify Dewey’s position as well as to enframe the argument of this book. Part 2 applies the principled framework developed in Part 1 to the teaching of several disciplines of the human sciences. The disciplines are philosophy (Chapter 4), religion (Chapter 5), ethics (Chapter 6), politics (Chapter 7), history (Chapter 8), and literature (Chapter 9), and our interlocutors in the same order are Nietzsche, Caputo, Arendt, Freire, Foucault, and Ricoeur. The list of disciplines is clearly non-exhaustive and is based in part on Dewey’s interests, in part on my own, and in part on the need to avoid undue repetition in the argument. The chapters in Part 2 are arranged in no particular order. Their guiding questions concern the aims that fundamentally orient teaching and learning in these fields and what the marks of success of an historical, literary, or moral education might be. While this book is an inquiry in the philosophy of education, I hope it will be found relevant not only to philosophers but to those in the various branches of the human sciences who have a serious interest in education, and not only at the university level. These reflections pertain most directly to university education, but they apply as well to teachers in secondary institutions who are charged with teaching literature, history, and related subjects. If there is still such a thing as an educated reading public, as I believe there is, hopefully this book will not be irrelevant to them as well.
Notes 1. 2. 3.
Allan Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1987). Martin Heidegger, What Is Called Thinking?, trans. J. Glenn Gray (New York: Harper and Row, 1968), 4. Dewey, ‘From Absolutism to Experimentalism’ (1930). LW 5: 154.
PA RT 1
The Educative Process
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 1
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
Progressivism as a movement in the philosophy of education is associated in historical terms primarily with the early and middle decades of the twentieth century in North America and Europe, and with the writings of such figures as Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Herbert Spencer, Jean Piaget, John Dewey, William Heard Kilpatrick, and Clarence Kingsley. Its basic principles were formulated in reaction against traditional methods of direct and whole-class instruction, memorization and learning by rote, standardized subject matters and standardized tests, emphasis on grades and competition, and a traditional curriculum of information and skills considered useful in later life. Advocates of progressive education reacted strongly against the conservatism of traditional educational institutions, favoring not only new methods of teaching and learning but as their political accompaniment a far more liberal ethos for which individual activity and the development of autonomy supplanted older values of conservation and socio-cultural transmission. Progressives favored more active, collaborative, and experiential modes of learning, greater choice of educational goals and subject matters, and the placing of educational policy more generally on a politically liberal and scientifically secure basis. New theories of psychological and cognitive development seemed to undermine many of the methods of traditional education and to entail new, ‘developmentally appropriate’ approaches to pedagogy and curriculum. Progressivism would have a radical effect on education in the twentieth century, and while the term itself is dated and perhaps passé, its legacy remains very much with us. Several of its principles have become something of an orthodoxy in current educational research and teaching colleges even while being transformed in a great many ways, often to the point of unrecognizability. Progressivism has become a part of the common knowledge that educational theorists and practitioners largely share, even as the writings of its classical theorists remain largely unread by those in the business of applying them. Presently, advocates and critics of progressivism alike often demonstrate a surprising lack of familiarity with its history, including the writings of its foremost philosophical representative. John Dewey’s philosophy of education is presently in the odd position of constituting an 13
14
The Educative Process
important part of the current thinking that prevails among most theorists and practitioners of education while the texts themselves are often forgotten, caricatured, or misread. Conservative and other critics of progressive education are often similarly inclined toward misinterpretation of Dewey in particular, often faulting him for good reason or bad for what they consider the failings of our educational institutions.1 While we continue to hear of the enduring legacy of progressive education and the pre-eminent status of Dewey in that movement, progressivism can also appear to be a merely historical phenomenon which recent advances in educational research have consigned to the past along with its conservative antithesis. A vital question becomes whether the old dispute between progressives and conservatives has lost its relevance in light of findings in the philosophical and especially the scientific dimension of education. Philosophical debates often appear to have been superseded by developments in learning theory and developmental psychology in particular, raising the hope in many minds that the essential business of education might finally transcend the contested realm of politics and philosophy and be placed on a scientific foundation. The prospect of education becoming a purely scientific, technical, or otherwise non-philosophical field of research is one that should give us pause. While the dichotomy of progressive or conservative education may well need to be replaced it must first be worked through in dialectical fashion. If this opposition is to be superseded, this will occur not on a scientific or technical basis alone but on philosophical grounds. The ultimate questions of education have always been and will remain philosophical, despite the efforts of many to transform them into purely technical issues. In one sense this old binary opposition is of merely historical interest as the conversation moves on and different issues come to the fore, yet in a deeper sense the dichotomy, or at least the distinction, remains very much with us. New forms of educational conservatism and of what might still be characterized as progressivism, however loosely, have many defenders at the present time both in theoretical discourse and at the policy level, obliging us to revisit some of the questions that Dewey was engaged with a century ago, albeit in altered form. As two commentators have recently pointed out, ‘It might be argued that classical progressivist approaches and methods, at least in some school systems, have become the new orthodoxy.’2 It is undoubtedly not an orthodoxy that Dewey envisioned, but it retains at least a family resemblance with his philosophy of education and with other classical progressive views which claimed to be influenced by him. The continuing relevance of this distinction is also apparent in recent defenses of educational conservatism from such writers as R. S. Peters, Allan Bloom, and E. D. Hirsch, the latter two of whose views I shall examine in this chapter. The purchase that conservative views have gained, particularly
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
15
among policy-makers, politicians, and the general public, makes them impossible to ignore, even as we may be tempted to do so. They serve as a reminder that while the theoretical discourse has in many ways moved on from the progressive/conservative debate, the real world of education remains fundamentally oriented by this distinction. Our present vocabularies remain oriented around notions of conservation and ‘cultural literacy’, the efficient transmission and retention of information, vocational and professional values, as well as by student- versus curriculum-centeredness, individual autonomy and development, students’ experience and nature, discovery learning, critical thinking, and so on. These vocabularies continue to generate heated political debate between liberals and conservatives, of course, and are prominent in the culture wars that continue to loom large in public debate. While ‘it is tempting’, as David Carr writes, ‘to suppose that the weary centuries-old debates between traditionalists and progressivists might once and for all be settled by value-neutral scientific method’, efforts by educational theorists and researchers to transcend these debates typically remain within their orbit, often by endeavoring to subject these views to empirical or quasi-empirical examination. The opposition of progressive or conservative education is, as Carr correctly observes, ‘a real and persisting one’ and ‘is alive and well in almost every contemporary public debate about educational policy’.3 Perhaps the most basic hypothesis of progressivism is that education must be tailored to the students’ nature and experience, and where this nature is understood on a developmental model. Enlisting empirical psychology, this basic hypothesis has given rise to ambitious investigation into early development and learning theory as well as into the psycho-social dimension of education. As educational discourse assumed an increasingly scientific and psychological guise throughout the course of the twentieth century, the imperative to legitimate teaching methods and the curriculum with reference to the latest findings of developmental psychology has become paramount. The conventional wisdom, and no longer among progressives alone, is that educational matters can and must be scientifically grounded. The necessity of making it scientific is so widely felt at present that even many conservatives and other antiprogressives increasingly attempt to turn the discourse of empirical psychology to their advantage. ‘Research shows’ has become a singularly ubiquitous phrase in departments of education which are anxiously seeking to establish their scientific credentials within the university. When conservatives are not questioning the empirical basis of progressivism, they are frequently given to holding this philosophy in particular responsible for the failings of contemporary education. The criticisms here are many, and include the charge that an over-concentration on or simple
16
The Educative Process
misunderstanding of students’ nature and experience has eclipsed the matter of their acquiring information that is important for reasons of both cultural transmission and practical life. Graduates of institutions at all levels, we now regularly hear, possess too little knowledge in terms of the Western canon in general and also in terms of practically useful information, a development attributable, its critics allege, to the influence of progressivism in general and often of Dewey in particular.4 The criticism is often couched in economic terms: either an individual graduate’s or an entire generation’s lack of knowledge causes an unpreparedness for productive work and in turn a loss of national competitiveness with foreign economies. The global competition for prosperity will be won, we so often hear, by economies whose workforces possess the most useful and up-to-date information available, especially as this pertains to mathematics and science in an increasingly technological world. Progressivism’s de-emphasis on practical information is the cause of our falling behind our national competitors in the quest for wealth. Another argument decries the loss of culture among younger generations due to the displacement of the traditional Western canon, as important fields of study are either postponed for later grades or removed from the curriculum altogether on grounds of developmental appropriateness. Lack of acquaintance with traditional subject matters causes students to become culturally adrift, their minds and characters being deprived of proper nourishment. Progressive methods, it is alleged, have diminished the importance of knowledge itself, particularly informational knowledge about traditional fields of study such as history, literature, and language, rendering students ignorant of their own cultural traditions in efforts to emphasize problemsolving and critical thinking skills of which traditionalists are often skeptical. Especially intriguing are critiques of progressivism that single out Dewey as the source of our current educational woes. The charge has been made for a few decades now that Dewey, being the pre-eminent theorist of progressivism, bears ultimate responsibility for the movement’s excesses and failures, whatever these are said to be. Thus Allan Bloom, for one, alleges that Dewey is the source of American students’ present lack of historical knowledge; Dewey, he writes, ‘saw the past as radically imperfect and regarded our history as irrelevant or as a hindrance to rational analysis of our present’.5 Another critic claims that Dewey’s ‘concept of reconstruction in education, which includes problem solving and critical thinking, represents a narrow, technical application of reason’, while a couple of other recent critics’ views may be gleaned from the titles of their books: John Dewey and the Decline of American Education (Henry Edmondson) and Getting It Wrong From the Beginning: Our Progressivist Inheritance from Herbert Spencer, John Dewey, and Jean Piaget (Kieran Egan).6 Perhaps the most general complaint against Dewey in this regard is that his views have led to a deterioration in academic
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
17
standards at all educational levels due to his ostensible de-emphasis on traditional subject matter and overemphasis on the students’ nature and experience. His defense of active learning rendered old-fashioned learning from books passé, thereby discouraging students from gaining an adequate appreciation of the canon or sufficient knowledge for later life. What makes such critiques intriguing is that Dewey himself addressed them and as far back as 1938 leveled strikingly similar criticisms at progressives who had claimed to be following his lead. Experience and Education is an important text in that Dewey here clarified and refined the argument of Democracy and Education (1916) and numerous other works in light of the impact that progressive ideas were beginning to have and the misinterpretations of his views which were becoming, and unfortunately remain, commonplace. In this clearly written and brief text Dewey reminded both progressive and conservative educators of the need to reject the false oppositions that both camps had accepted uncritically and which he himself had rejected from the beginning. Student- or curriculum-centeredness, critical reflection or conservation, active or passive learning, interest or discipline and other dichotomies that divided early progressives and traditionalists, and indeed dichotomous thinking in general, Dewey categorically rejected, and not only in his educational writings. Dewey’s style of thought on all subjects was invariably dialectical and suspicious of the tendency toward binary oppositions that has been prevalent since the beginning of the Western philosophical tradition. The still prevalent misinterpretation of Dewey as a defender of child-centered education was one he was already trying to dispel in 1902: [Let us] get rid of the prejudicial notion that there is some gap in kind (as distinct from degree) between the child’s experience and the various forms of subject-matter that make up the course of study. From the side of the child it is a question of seeing how his experience already contains within itself elements – facts and truths – of just the same sort as those entering into the formulated study; and what is of more importance, how it contains within itself the attitudes, the motives and the interests which have operated in developing and organizing the subject-matter to the plane which it now occupies.7 The persistence of such misinterpretation was a frequent source of frustration for Dewey and by the 1938 text had moved him to undertake a largerscale clarification of views he had already expressed numerous times in the past. The argument of Experience and Education takes particular aim at Dewey’s would-be follower William Heard Kilpatrick, whose book of 1925, Foundations of Method, had exerted wide influence on the development of progressive ideas. As Robert Westbrook writes,
18
The Educative Process Though Dewey rarely named names in his criticisms of progressive reform, one of his principal targets was William H. Kilpatrick, his colleague at Columbia University, whose ‘project method’ was perhaps the single most influential practical curriculum reform to emerge from childcentered progressivism. The Teachers College Record distributed some sixty thousand reprints of the 1918 article in which Kilpatrick first described the project method, and by the twenties Kilpatrick was the dominant figure at the leading school of education in the country. . . . Kilpatrick thought of himself as Dewey’s disciple. . . . But [Dewey] insisted that projects must have as one of their goals the child’s mastery of organized subjects. . . . [M]uch of what critics then (and now) attacked as aimless, contentless ‘Deweyism’ was in fact aimless, contentless ‘Kilpatrickism’.8
The disparagement of subject matter which came to be associated with progressivism had nothing whatever to do with Dewey’s texts or with the socalled Laboratory School at the University of Chicago which was modeled on these texts and overseen by Dewey himself. Rather, it was Kilpatrick and other early progressives, many of whom claimed Dewey as an influence while misreading or neglecting his texts, who formulated the new philosophy in simple oppositional terms to the older practice, creating a new set of dichotomies which Dewey emphatically rejected, and the legacy of which is with us still. As Dewey would write in this text, There is always the danger in a new movement that in rejecting the aims and methods of that which it would supplant, it may develop its principles negatively rather than positively and constructively. Then it takes its clew in practice from that which is rejected instead of from the constructive development of its own philosophy. This was the fundamental mistake of the progressive movement, he maintained, and a grievous one since the new doctrine was being formulated in undialectical, reactionary terms. Thus experience was placed in false opposition to tradition, active to passive learning, interest to discipline, and so on, with the predictable consequence that the latter value in each of these pairings was replaced by the former, and with unfortunate consequences. As he observed in the same context: [M]any of the newer schools tend to make little or nothing of organized subject-matter of study; to proceed as if any form of direction and guidance by adults were an invasion of individual freedom, and as if the idea of education should be concerned with the present and future meant
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
19
that acquaintance with the past has little or no role to play in education. Without pressing these defects to the point of exaggeration, they at least illustrate what is meant by a theory and practice of education which proceeds negatively or by reaction against what has been current in education rather than by a positive and constructive development of purposes, methods, and subject-matter on the foundation of a theory of experience and its educational potentialities.9 Far from being diminished in importance, organized subject matter and book learning were to be regarded as instruments within a larger investigative process, with the student in the role of researcher in an intellectually rigorous sense of the word. Education as Dewey envisioned it is a demanding affair in which traditional skills of reading, writing, and so on are pressed into service within larger fields of experience, not placed in false opposition to experience and divested of importance thereby. Similarly, Dewey made much of the concept of interest as a source of students’ motivation, yet without creating a dichotomy between interest and discipline, as many other progressives would and inevitably at the expense of the latter. The students’ existing interests, he argued, are neither to be ignored nor fetishized but guided along properly educative channels and brought into contact with an organized curriculum. ‘[T]he danger of the “new education”’, he would write in The Child and the Curriculum, is ‘that it regards the child’s present powers and interests as something finally significant in themselves’, a tendency formulated in reaction to the older practice. The newer tendency to regard interests as sacrosanct, or to allow students simply to do as they please, would ‘inevitably . . . result in indulgence and spoiling’. ‘Any power,’ he further argued, ‘whether of child or adult, is indulged when it is taken on its given and present level in consciousness. Its genuine meaning is in the propulsion it affords toward a higher level.’10 It was the vital connection of an organized curriculum to the students’ interests and lived experience that Dewey constantly emphasized, an idea that in no way entailed the neglect of subject matter. Unfortunately, the movement that Dewey had helped to inspire lacked the dialectical nuance and flexibility of Dewey’s own views, leaving these views to be caricatured for decades by critics and ostensible followers alike. Determining the actual influence that Dewey has had on the practice of education, or indeed on the theory, is a rather difficult matter in view of the widespread misunderstanding that originally greeted his works and which continues to do so. For a few generations now educators at all levels know of the importance of John Dewey as an early figure in the progressive movement and frequently acquire a little knowledge about his views, usually from second-hand sources or textbook descriptions. They will often hear
20
The Educative Process
about the ambiguity and difficulty of his texts, and perhaps for this reason (or for reasons of their datedness or the fact that they may not be required reading in educational faculties and teaching colleges) do not read them. Yet the idea persists that Dewey has had an all-pervasive influence on both the theory and practice of education. One recent and rather vociferous critic, for example, alleges that Dewey has had a disastrous effect on American education in particular while also noting (apparently without noticing the contradiction) that ‘[i]t is impossible to determine exactly how much influence Dewey has had on American education’. The same critic writes: Unfortunately, despite his iconic status, Dewey is rarely read and his work is poorly understood in public schools and in colleges of education. Future teachers often learn a little bit ‘about’ Dewey the man and educator, but they are never given the opportunity to assess critically the Deweyan ideas that underlie their classes and permeate their professional organizations.11 Even the assertion that ‘Deweyan ideas’ in some form or other have had a profound impact on education is difficult to assess precisely for the reason that the texts themselves are seldom read by educators and are badly caricatured. Speaking of Dewey’s early influence, Sidney Hook noted in 1939 that [a]s important as that influence has been – and no recent theoretical influence has been more important – it has been limited. Limited by the way it has been interpreted, limited by the way it has been applied, limited by the absence of certain social conditions whose existence its ideals presupposed – and limited, above all, in comparison with the tremendous possibilities of educational reconstruction which would follow from a nationwide experiment in carrying out its basic principles.12 Of course, this large-scale experiment was never effected, educators and administrators being in the main far more concerned with practical realities than philosophical ideas. Perhaps the most accurate statement we can make in this regard is that a highly distorted rendering of Dewey’s philosophy of education – essentially ‘Kilpatrickism’, as Westbrook calls it – has indeed exercised a large influence on the conventional wisdom within teaching colleges and university departments of education, and in a way that has never translated into the kind of classroom practice that Dewey, and perhaps even Kilpatrick, envisioned. Recent decades have seen a new influence emerge which increasingly dominates the official thinking within educational departments and teaching colleges as well as the actual practices of teaching and learning, an
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
21
influence that bears less and less resemblance to Dewey’s views. While still showing signs of continuity with progressivism, the more recent trend has taken a decided turn toward the scientific, the technical, and the managerial. The matter of how students learn – different categories of students at different stages of development – has become the dominant issue in the discourse of education. Dewey as well posed the general question of ‘how we think’ (not least in his 1910 book of that title, published again in revised form in 1933), yet while his approach to this question can be best described as phenomenological, the current thinking is framed strictly within a vocabulary of empirical and developmental psychology, a non-phenomenological and ostensibly apolitical methodology. Education, according to this new orthodoxy, is essentially a scientific matter and its central question is one of technique: how (not why or whether) to bring about certain predetermined educational ‘outcomes’. These outcomes are often described in vaguely progressive terms, to be sure. The language of individual growth and autonomy, of creativity and critical thinking, now enjoys very broad appeal and is coupled with a more political terminology of empowerment and democratic equality. To all appearances the spirit of progressive education lives on, yet on closer inspection it appears closer to the truth to say that certain Deweyan themes have been thoroughly transformed and perhaps co-opted to lend legitimacy to a philosophy that Dewey would have rejected. The broad outlines of this trend are as follows. It includes a decided emphasis on technology, particularly the use of computers in an ever more pervasive way, an exhortation toward managerial efficiency and costeffectiveness, the concept of the student as customer and the educator as resource, service provider, or facilitator of a kind, student-centeredness, an emphasis on ‘learning outcomes’ conceived as tangible and measurable results of one kind or another, general skills of problem-solving and critical thinking, the acquisition of useful information, particularly in the areas of mathematics and science, cognitive and psycho-social development, the various and growing number of learning styles, individual autonomy, education as a commodity, and so on. Increasingly it is the language not only of science and technology but of the marketplace that dominates the discourse of education (I would not say the philosophy of education in view of the resolutely un- or indeed antiphilosophical nature of so much of this discussion). A general mindset of technology and of scientific and economic rationality is now so entrenched, and its basic orientation so contrary to Dewey’s stance, that its connection with progressive education is increasingly difficult to see. Perhaps the most accurate description of the current thinking in education remains one put forward in 1979 by Jean-François Lyotard in his wellknown book The Postmodern Condition, in which he pronounced a diagnosis of the state of education, research, and knowledge in general in the second
22
The Educative Process
half of the twentieth century. To be educated, he wrote, now means to have mastered all the various bits of informational knowledge that are necessary for the maintenance of efficiency and for the optimizing of technological and economic use-value. According to the new standard of ‘performativity’, The question (overt or implied) now asked by the professionalist student, the state, or institutions of higher education is no longer ‘Is it true?’ but ‘What use is it?’ In the context of the mercantilization of knowledge, more often than not this question is equivalent to: ‘Is it saleable?’ And in the context of power-growth: ‘Is it efficient?’ Knowledge in postmodernity, on this influential account, has been reduced to the status of a commodity, and along with it the whole business of education, particularly at the post-secondary level which is the focus of Lyotard’s analysis. Values of experimentation, inventiveness, and judgment become subordinated within a new ethos that is at once positivistic and corporate. It is the performativity and efficiency of the economic system that drives the entire process, while ‘[t]he old principle that the acquisition of knowledge is indissociable from the training (Bildung) of minds, or even of individuals, is becoming obsolete and will become ever more so’. As education and research are absorbed within a logic of the marketplace, ‘[k]nowledge is and will be produced in order to be sold, it is and will be consumed in order to be valorized in a new production: in both cases, the goal is exchange’.13 The essential business of educational institutions, accordingly, is the production and consumption of information which must itself be ‘useful’ in an economic sense. Its utility consists in the credentials with which it supplies students intent on entering the workforce and making a living. Knowledge and education cease to be ends in themselves or essential ingredients of the good life but are reduced to their functionality. Lyotard pronounced this diagnosis in 1979 and the trend that he was describing at that time has continued to gain momentum in the present ‘information age’, as the economy becomes increasingly oriented toward technology and informational knowledge and as social and political institutions become ever more beholden to technological rationality. He, of course, is not alone in his diagnosis. It has been a frequent observation among philosophers in the continental European traditions for a century that scientific and technological rationality has assumed an altogether dominant presence in the conduct of social life no less than in the science of nature. Hans-Georg Gadamer, for instance, remarked upon this phenomenon in 1965 in the following terms, and in a manner reminiscent of his teacher, Martin Heidegger:
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
23
What appears to me to characterize our epoch is not the surprising control of nature we have achieved, but the development of scientific methods to guide the life of society. Only with this achievement has the victorious course of modern science, beginning in the nineteenth century, become a dominant social factor. The scientific tendencies of thought underlying our civilization have in our time pervaded all aspects of social praxis. Scientific market research, scientific warfare, scientific diplomacy, scientific rearing of the younger generation, scientific leadership of the people – the application of science to all these fields gives expertise a commanding position in the economy of society.14 Max Weber’s description of the ‘iron cage of rationality’, Martin Heidegger’s analysis of ‘science-technology’, and Michel Foucault’s ‘regimes of truth’ all have relevance here. What all depict is the hegemony of scientific and technological ways of thinking within social reality and the consequent delegitimation of ways of thinking and knowing that do not fit this model. It is not surprising, then, that the practice of education and the ways of thinking that have come to assume a dominant position within it are no exception. Here as well, a kind of managerial or corporate scientism has largely displaced progressivism, even as the language of progressive education continues to have a place in the current thinking. If Dewey’s influence on the progressive movement was limited, his impact at the present time is slight indeed. Let us use the expression ‘corporate scientism’ to refer to the general phenomenon that Lyotard and many other educational theorists have called to our attention. The first principle of this new positivism is that education should be scientific. Why this should be so is a question seldom answered and seldom asked. As a branch of social science, educational research must be strictly empirical and draw upon the latest findings of empirical psychology, cognitive science, sociology, and any other field of inquiry that will support its claim to constitute a legitimate form of scientific knowledge and an independent discipline within the university. Educational research must above all strive to be rigorously methodological and concerned with means far more than ends. If it cannot be entirely apolitical or value-free, as the older philosophical positivism urged (together with the requirement to dismiss metaphysical and evaluative questions as nonsense), it must approach evaluative matters in as empirical and technical a manner as the topic will permit. Whenever possible, quantitative methods are employed, and if it cannot be denied that qualitative ‘methods’ have a place, one suspects the concession is somewhat grudging, the positivist dichotomy of fact and value still having considerable purchase.15 The managerial or corporate dimension of the current thinking is sufficiently evident, I trust, to require little demonstration. The marketing
24
The Educative Process
material of educational departments and teaching colleges alone is unambiguous in its descriptions of the research conducted therein and the decided emphasis on professional credentials. The vocabulary of economics is blended with one of technical rationality. As one group of observers notes, The new theoretical emphases are on statistics and the countable, on observation and testing, on the useful and on ‘what works’. Its new watchwords are skills, competences and techniques, flexibility, independence, targets and performance indicators, qualifications and credentials, learning outcomes. Profound objections, from both theoretical and practical perspectives, to established shibboleths are angrily dismissed as idle or self-indulgent diversions from brute educational necessities. . . . The standard under which this movement marches is itself that of ‘raising standards’.16 Two other theorists writing in the same volume similarly lament this new ‘rhetoric of the marketplace’: Headteachers’ conference bars rang to the sound of ‘marketing strategies’, ‘mission statements’ and ‘business plans’, ‘performance measures’ and ‘performance-related pay’; parents became ‘customers’ or ‘clients’; heads of department were constituted into ‘senior management teams’ and became ‘line managers’. Schools ‘delivered’ ‘products’ in the most ‘cost-effective’ ways they could invent.17 Surely no one could stand opposed to raising standards or evidence-based learning outcomes, but the gloss that is put on these terms is increasingly and crudely economic. The aim is to produce a certain kind of subject and a certain kind of worker: one that is efficient, informed, technically competent, and skilled in the execution of tasks spelled out in advance, perhaps not especially creative or reflective unless this can be disciplined by technique and turned to profitable use. In the end, one must have a product. It matters only as a secondary issue whether this be a good or a service, a trade or a profession, but one must have the necessary preparation and credentials to enter the workforce, and education is ultimately a means to this end. Students themselves are consumers of a service, but it is as future producers that they are trained. This new corporatism is encouraged by governments that continually warn of impending economic crisis if education is permitted to go its own way or underemphasize science and mathematics. Anxiety regarding economic preparedness is instilled in students’ consciousness, and in such a way that even the fashionable political language of empowerment becomes
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
25
translated in many minds into issues of competitive advantage and the relative speed at which one is likely to ascend the corporate ladder. The values of autonomy and freedom shrink down to the freedom to consume and the secure knowledge that this will not be easily jeopardized in the event of economic downturn. Perhaps the most fundamental problem with this managerial and positivist mindset is its tendency to regard education in general as a mere means to an end. When this view prevails, it is perfectly irrelevant what end education is thought a means of achieving, whether it be economic success, preservation of tradition, or what have you. Whatever the ultimate ends of the educative process are, they are nothing outside of that process itself, as I shall argue throughout this study. What we need to be reminded of is that while education does surely serve, and has always served, as a means of attaining practical and economic ends, it is also, at a more fundamental level of interpretation, an end in itself. The meaning and implications of this thesis will be our focus in the chapters that follow. So as well will be our untimely claim that education is and will always remain an art. While it undoubtedly benefits from empirical investigation into human psychology and cognition, the essence of education remains the search for understanding and selfunderstanding that occurs between educators, students, and the subject matter. The imperative to ‘make it scientific’, whether it be for purposes of disciplinary legitimation or simply because in an age of science the imperative has become something of an axiom, will not succeed in transforming what is by its nature an art and a practice into a science or technique. Regarding this art on the behaviorist model of stimulus and response, for instance, or as any kind of closed causal system in which learning is construed as a certain kind of effect and teaching a certain cause or technology, constitutes a profound misunderstanding of this practice and an overestimation of science. The present enthusiasm for technique and instrumental rationality must be reminded of its limits and be regarded within a larger context of education as a cultural practice and art. A major difficulty of the new corporate scientism that I have described is that it leaves little room for genuine agency on the part of students and indeed their educators. The cognitive development and learning outcomes about which we hear a great deal presuppose a level of personal and intellectual agency together with the conditions that make such agency possible. The educated mind is fundamentally one with a capacity for free thinking, an inventive and self-directing agent. It is the human being who is able and vitally concerned to participate in the conversation that is its culture, who is therefore learned in the great texts and ideas that make up that conversation and, no less important, capable of taking it further and relating it to one’s own existence. Education at a more fundamental level of analysis is not an
26
The Educative Process
outcome or a science but a life process that has no end beyond itself. Educational institutions no more approximate corporations than students are human capital in the making or laboratory rats in a behaviorist’s maze. Their purpose far exceeds instilling virtues of adaptation and efficiency, but includes such economically useless qualities as inquisitiveness, wonder, originality, and self-understanding. There is still a place for such values in a scientific age, and if these and similar intellectual virtues are being deemphasized and consequently unlearned in the rage to make it scientific, then it is not only our educational institutions that are in trouble. What students must ultimately learn is the art of thinking, yet this is precisely what defies measurable outcomes, standardization, and formal calculation. While I shall not urge that the vocabulary of performativity and educational science be rejected in its entirety – a proposition that is surely absurd – my focus in this study will be the limits of this vocabulary and its subordinate place within a roughly Deweyan philosophy of education. What must not be lost sight of, as Dewey himself never did, are the limits of science. There is no doubt that knowledge derived from psychology, cognitive science, sociology, and other branches of social science have profitably informed our understanding of the educative process, particularly regarding issues of means: how students of different descriptions and at different maturational levels successfully integrate new knowledge into an established conceptual framework and how our pedagogical practices may be adjusted in this light. Enormous quantities of empirical study have devoted themselves to this purpose for some decades now; however what too much of this research overlooks is that the question of how learning takes place is not only an empirical matter but a properly philosophical one, and that as a philosophical question it calls upon the resources of phenomenology, hermeneutics, and perhaps epistemology. This again is an issue of which Dewey was well aware and that educational researchers today often are not. Furthermore, empirical questions regarding the means, or the how, of education remain subordinate to the matter of its ends, or its why. Here again we are faced with a philosophical question for which science will not help us, as Dewey also knew. Empirical investigation will never disclose what the ultimate aims of education are, or what the whole enterprise is for. It cannot account for which ‘learning outcomes’ we ought to seek and why, which subject matters are of importance and why, or any other question pertaining to ends. Like politics, education is a matter about which we may certainly ask scientific questions, but a science itself it is not. Treating it as one narrows rather than deepens our understanding of it and causes us to overlook the often tenuous connection between empirical – particularly psychological – research and the actual practices of teaching and learning. Inferences drawn from the realm of empirical study to what actually takes place in classrooms are often
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
27
less than obvious, and educators obliged to bridge these worlds are often and quite understandably at a loss as to how to do this. The confusion itself is instructive, I would suggest, and affects very little whether education succeeds or fails. Educational success depends to a great extent on the intangibles and unquantifiables of the classroom, precisely on that which no method can teach. There is no technique for instilling a fascination with history, a capacity for inventive interpretation, or a sense of justice. It is on this last point that Lyotard placed his emphasis. The heart and soul of education, on his account, is the students’ own capacity for novelty in fashioning ideas and in questioning received bodies of knowledge. Research and education are likewise centered on dissension rather than consensus. Success occurs when we are able to invent novel moves within settled language games or, better still, to invent new language games and thus ‘disturb the order of “reason”’.18 The truest indicator of educational success is that for which there is no science and no method: the power of the imagination to destabilize what presently passes for knowledge and to invent new ways of seeing the world. The conditions that would make this possible, of course, are not present when imperatives of scientificity and performativity gain a dominant position, effectively creating a world that is ever more an object of calculation and administration and of means over ends. Corporate scientism has little use for the intangibles of education or for that which cannot be brought within an ethos of scientific and economic rationality. The arts and humanities in particular are regularly, and quite inevitably, deemed unnecessary luxuries in comparison with the sciences and mathematics and the utilitarian benefits that these disciplines provide. Those champions of the arts and humanities who are obligated to plead their case within a vocabulary that is foreign, if not antithetical, to them are engaged in a losing cause indeed. No cost–benefit analysis redeems the study of music or philosophy. The problem here is not that we are unable to provide such an accounting – without resorting to clever but inauthentic marketing – but that we are required to do so.
The conservatism of Allan Bloom The new managerial positivism that I have been describing can be alternately described as the latest form, perhaps the dead end, of progressivism or as an attempt by means of objective science to transcend the progressive/conservative opposition altogether. A case can be made for either interpretation, however if by progressivism we have in mind a philosophy stemming directly from Dewey’s writings, then the former reading would be misleading. A positivist in any sense Dewey most certainly was not.19 His faith in what he would often call ‘scientific intelligence’ bears little relation to the scientism that we
28
The Educative Process
presently see and would never lead him to overlook the limits of scientific knowledge or to regard education itself as a science. Fundamentally, Dewey’s project was never to issue a prescription proclaiming under the banner of science what education should be but to describe what it is. It is, he argued, a process that is continuous with human experience more generally, not something that can be sharply distinguished from the ordinary life of students and not merely a means to an end of whatever kind. The educative process has ends internal to itself, and it is these ends that provide the whole business of teaching and learning with their basic orientation. This idea has been lost sight of by progressives and positivists alike. If there are grounds in Dewey’s philosophy, as there undoubtedly are, on which to critique the corporate scientism of the present, there are other, more conservative, grounds on which to do so as well. Surprisingly perhaps, some of these arguments Dewey himself advanced, yet their contemporary proponents most often call not for a critical appropriation of Dewey’s thought but for an unDeweyan return of sorts to traditional education. Allan Bloom and E. D. Hirsch are particularly interesting cases in point. Their views warrant attention here for reasons of both the considerable influence they have had since the nearly simultaneous publication in 1987 of Bloom’s bestseller, The Closing of the American Mind and Hirsch’s bestseller, Cultural Literacy, as well as the evidence they provide of the continuing relevance of the progressive/conservative distinction and the inherent merits of at least some of their arguments. Bloom’s version of educational conservatism begins with a broad-ranging critique of education in American universities or of particular trends within them, the primary sources of which, Bloom asserts, are the thought not of Dewey or Kilpatrick but of Friedrich Nietzsche and Martin Heidegger.20 While I cannot do justice here to the scope of Bloom’s harsh and wide-ranging critique, the main thrust of it concerns the lack of knowledge of and reverence for the canon which has become commonplace among the university students of today – or of 1987, although this has hardly changed in more recent years. As Bloom writes, ‘Today’s select students know so much less, are so much more cut off from the tradition, are so much slacker intellectually, that they make their predecessors look like prodigies of culture.’ Speaking of the students whom Bloom taught during the latter part of his career in comparison with those he encountered at the beginning, he laments: The loss of the books [the great canonical texts of the Western tradition] has made them narrower and flatter. Narrower because they lack what is most necessary, a real basis for discontent with the present and awareness that there are alternatives to it. They are both more contented with what is and despairing of ever escaping from it. The longing for the beyond has
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
29
been attenuated. The very models of admiration and contempt have vanished. Flatter, because without interpretations of things, without the poetry or the imagination’s activity, their souls are like mirrors, not of nature, but of what is around. The refinement of the mind’s eye that permits it to see the delicate distinctions among men, among their deeds and their motives, and constitutes real taste, is impossible without the assistance of literature in the grand style.21 The kind of ignorance about which Bloom worries is far less a lack of practical, informational knowledge which students of prior generations possessed in greater quantity but a lack of acquaintance with and deep appreciation for the great works of literature, art, philosophy, and so on which, for Bloom, still constitutes the heart and soul of education. The humanities in particular have fallen into disarray since ‘[w]ith the “information explosion”, tradition has become superfluous’. Rather than being a source of edification or inspiration, tradition has become merely the dead weight of the past if not an oppressive force or a cause of boredom. No longer do students believe that the canon is where they may expect to find truths more profound than in popular culture or the mass media. As reverence for the canon erodes, so too do students’ capacities for depth of feeling and aesthetic appreciation, for separating what is important from what is trivial, and for gravity or seriousness of purpose. The love of reading and expectation of personal improvement through reading the classics are disappearing and being replaced by more immediate forms of entertainment. Education and students’ characters themselves have become shallow and unimaginative as the more ultimate matters of life disappear from view and as utilitarian values and ‘careerism [become] the centerpiece of the university’.22 Books and ideas no longer change the lives of the young but, when they are attended to at all, provide a pleasing diversion from the business of acquiring professional credentials. The very raison d’être of the university is in question, Bloom maintains, when students are no longer expected to know the tradition in which they stand and to gain a proper appreciation of its canonical texts. Students who do not read fail to understand themselves and become more alike in their thinking and actions due to a lack of awareness that what is might be otherwise. As Bloom expresses this rather important point, ‘the failure to read good books both enfeebles the vision and strengthens our most fatal tendency – the belief that the here and now is all there is’.23 It is literature in particular that educates the imagination and instills both the means and the desire to understand human existence differently. It is, then, no lack of funding or underattention to the basics that is the source of educational failure but a forgetfulness of the university’s proper mission and the consequent neglect of the arts and humanities.
30
The Educative Process
If this is the cause of what ails the contemporary university, then the remedy is not far to seek: Of course, the only serious solution is the one that is almost universally rejected: the good old Great Books approach, in which a liberal education means reading certain generally recognized classic texts, just reading them, letting them dictate what the questions are and the method of approaching them – not forcing them into categories we make up, not treating them as historical products, but trying to read them as their authors wished them to be read. Tradition, accordingly, is the very essence of good education, and it is its preservation, not its critique or disruption, and not its contribution to resolving the problems of the present, that is the appropriate goal of a university education. On the question of how students and their educators should approach the great texts of the past, he remarks: There is an enormous difference between saying, as teachers once did, ‘You must learn to see the world as Homer or Shakespeare did’, and saying, as teachers now do, ‘Homer and Shakespeare had some of the same concerns you do and can enrich your vision of the world.’ In the former approach students are challenged to discover new experiences and reassess old; in the latter, they are free to use the books in any way they please. Beyond Bloom’s call for a return to the canon he offers little or nothing by way of recommendations for educational reform. As he puts it, ‘One cannot and should not hope for a general reform. The hope is that the embers do not die out.’24 One keeps tradition alive as it were by placing it carefully under glass and urging students to study its features, to transport themselves into the past without any apparent concern for transforming the present and without any genuine critique. This in a phrase is the nature and goal of educational conservatism: the point is to conserve. It is also to encounter texts in the manner in which their authors would have wished: with an attitude of receptivity and indeed reverence. The point is not to take issue with the texts or with tradition itself but rather to preserve it in essentially unaltered form. Bloom’s traditionalism, like all forms of this doctrine, represents a misunderstanding of the very nature of tradition and the way in which it reproduces itself. When culture or tradition is a living phenomenon rather than merely the dead weight of the past, which Bloom fears it has become in the hands of today’s students, it is appropriated selectively, critically, and with an eye to how it may in one way or another serve the needs of the present. We
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
31
become slaves to the past when we encounter it in the reverential and passive manner that Bloom recommends. While we may have a certain sympathy – indeed a great deal – for his lament for the erosion of the canon, the failure to instill in students a passion for reading, and the narrowing of perspective and slackening of thought that this causes, the remedy does not lie in an uncritical conservatism. Nor does the respect for tradition entail any manner of traditionalism, if by this term we mean the insistence on preserving the past in unaltered form. What distinguishes a living from a moribund tradition is precisely that the former is appropriated in the way in which one joins a conversation that began long ago: by listening and learning, to be sure, but equally, and perhaps more essentially, by participating in it. To participate in tradition, or to take it up authentically, always means to carry it forward, to apply it to present circumstances, and more than occasionally to critique and transform it, sometimes radically. Where tradition is not a source of dogmatism and intellectual conformity it is a conversation which students and all members of a culture are called upon to take up and creatively transform. Keeping tradition alive therefore does not consist in merely preserving the embers or in any museum tour through the canon. It amounts not to a simple repetition of the past but to a task of critical appropriation, and it is the critical dimension that traditionalists like Bloom either underemphasize, ignore, or deny. The slackness and narrowing of intellect about which he rightfully worries is not remedied by having students adopt quite as passive and unresisting a stance toward tradition as Bloom recommends. If he is correct in his view that the ‘most fatal tendency’ to which students can succumb is ‘the belief that the here and now is all there is’, it is incorrect to assert that the only or best alternative to the present is the past. Dissolving the common assumption that how matters currently stand is either axiomatic, natural, or ahistorically given is indeed fundamental to education and to wisdom itself. (This is not, incidentally, an original insight of Bloom’s, and was a major theme in the writings of both Nietzsche and Heidegger, the ostensible sources of the ills Bloom describes.) What is, will not always be, nor has it always been so; there are alternatives to the present arrangement of things, whether we are speaking of social institutions, worldviews, or what have you. When this lesson is not imparted, one goes through life overly contented with what is and unable to imagine that things could be otherwise. Undoubtedly the commonness of this phenomenon represents an important educational failure, however it is eminently doubtful both that there was a time in the past (Bloom’s youth perhaps) when this failure or this assumption was less prevalent and that the remedy to it lies in a traditionalism that is equally dogmatic. Bloom’s conservatism should not be dismissed outright, as many have done (understandably, given the harsh and often cantankerous tone of his
32
The Educative Process
critique), but viewed within a larger context. Conservation of tradition is about equally fundamental to education as its critique and application to the present. One learns not merely about the past but also from it, and where the latter signifies more than that one is able to see the world as Homer did (important as that is) but that one is able to apply what one has learned – the lessons of history, for example – in one’s critical understanding of the present. This does not mean that in reading the classics students ‘are free to use the books in any way they please’, but very nearly the opposite: they are free, and indeed obliged, to turn what lessons they learn from such texts to constructive use in their present ways of thinking and experience of life. Nor is this a formula for disconnection from tradition but a precondition of its authentic appropriation.
The conservatism of E. D. Hirsch Similar difficulties arise in other forms of educational conservatism, including the influential formulation defended for the last two decades by E. D. Hirsch. Like Bloom, Hirsch laments the general decline in standards that progressive and student-centered approaches have purportedly brought about in what has come to be called, owing to his well-known book of that title, ‘cultural literacy’. Evidence of decline Hirsch finds less in students’ relative lack of knowledge and appreciation of canonical texts than in the deficit in informational knowledge that is demonstrated by standardized test scores. Citing as evidence the test scores of students attending institutions implementing ostensibly progressive policies relative to both nations that have never implemented such policies and the same institutions prior to their introduction, Hirsch and many other conservatives speak of an alarming and prevalent decline in knowledge among students at all stages of the learning process. What has declined in particular, according to Hirsch, is culturally shared information which traditional pedagogical methods accentuate as a means of cultural reproduction. The consciousness of the student Hirsch conceives in quasi-empiricist terms as a kind of mental container empty at the beginning of the learning process and awaiting to be filled by subject matters which constitute the ‘intellectual capital’ necessary for later reflection, a conception that counsels a return to direct and whole-class instruction, a standardized curriculum, standardized testing, memory work, and so on.25 According to Hirsch, it is the nature of education and the duty of educators to impart to students large quantities of information that is deemed to be of cultural significance. The aim of teaching and learning at all levels is the amassing of ‘factual knowledge’ in ‘the traditional disciplines’ by means of ‘drill and practice, memorization, whole-class instruction’, and other traditional pedagogical techniques.26 If we are to take seriously the crisis in
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
33
education which progressivism in particular has brought about and which is proven by low scores by international standards on standardized tests – tests that Hirsch regards as wholly objective indicators of educational success or failure – then we must rehabilitate the techniques of traditional education which Dewey and the progressives rejected. Hirsch’s ‘core knowledge movement’, accordingly, represents ‘a countervailing theory of education that once again stresses the importance of specific information in early and late schooling’. He continues, in a vein that purports to be scientific: The corrective theory might be described as an anthropological theory of education, because it is based on the anthropological observation that all human communities are founded upon specific shared information. Americans are different from Germans, who in turn are different from Japanese, because each group possesses specifically different cultural knowledge. In an anthropological perspective, the basic goal of education in a human community is acculturation, the transmission to children of the specific information shared by the adults of the group or polis. Deploying the same rhetoric of science that he decries, often heatedly, among progressives and other contemporary educational theorists, Hirsch appeals to the science of anthropology and the contention made by some (certainly not all) in that field that the pre-eminent aim of education in human communities universally is the transmission of information between generations as a means of cultural reproduction. In the passing down of information, students acquire not only the received wisdom of their tradition but, in an argument directed squarely at progressivism, also the cognitive skills that progressives prize over information in the traditional disciplines. On the question of whether ‘facts’ ought to receive priority over ‘skills’ among the aims of education, Hirsch defends the former option on the grounds that the amassing of large quantities of information is both a necessary and sufficient condition of the development of the higher cognitive capacities. The acquisition of such skills, he asserts, follows automatically upon the acquisition of factual information. Hirsch expresses this intriguing claim as follows: Once the general knowledge has been acquired, the skill follows. General programs contrived to teach general skills are ineffective. AI research shows that experts perform better than novices not because they have more powerful and better oiled intellectual machinery but because they have more relevant and quickly available information. What distinguishes good readers from poor ones is simply the possession of a lot of diverse, task-specific information.27
34
The Educative Process
Hirsch is advancing three claims in this passage and it is important that they be distinguished: the first concerns the futility of teaching general thinking skills in a curricular vacuum; second, possessing information in large quantities is a necessary condition of higher-order thinking; and third, it is a sufficient condition as well. It is the third claim that is especially important, and also peculiar when we consider that its author is not himself a cognitive psychologist or researcher in artificial intelligence but a professor of English literature – a field in which skilled readers are customarily distinguished from unskilled ones on grounds that far exceed the quantity of factual information at their disposal (something that a detailed plot summary could provide), and include capacities of aesthetic appreciation, interpretation, and critical discernment, the ability to articulate questions and to see what is questionable, to be appropriately receptive or resistant to the message of a text depending on what emerges in the reading of it, to negotiate one’s way about the hermeneutic circle, to search for coherence, detect tensions and contradictions, and so on. I shall return to this later. Essential, Hirsch also maintains, to the rehabilitation of traditional education is not only the return to traditional pedagogical techniques but a standardized curriculum, standardized testing, and a renewed accent on particular ethical and religious values, specifically those of the Judeo-Christian tradition. Shifting with perfect equanimity from the language of science to the language of religious politics, Hirsch defends the notion of an ‘American civil religion’ that was bequeathed by the founders and that remains foundational to American society. Against ‘secularist-Americans’ – who, Hirsch tells us, are ‘just another species of hyphenated Americans’ – he insists on returning to a religious ethics in the classroom at both elementary and advanced levels.28 ‘Consensus values’ such as Christian altruism, the golden rule, civic duty, patriotism, and loyalty, along with a reverence for national symbols and belief in God, are to be directly instilled by educators in the minds of the young.29 This form of conservatism spells trouble for plurality and indeed for intellectual freedom itself. Despite occasional protestations to the contrary, the concept of education that Hirsch espouses directly entails both cultural and intellectual homogeneity. Evidence of this is plentiful throughout Hirsch’s educational writings. In addition to the ‘consensus values’ that purportedly constitute the ‘American civil religion’, Hirsch speaks in highly dismissive terms of bilingualism and multiculturalism in the schools on the grounds of the ‘cultural fragmentation, civil antagonism, illiteracy, and economictechnological ineffectualness’ that such policies cause both in parts of the United States and in nations such as Canada and Belgium in which they are applied on a larger scale. The latter two nations are singled out in particular as examples that, as he puts it, ‘are not encouraging’. Cultural monoliteracy
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
35
being already in steep decline, he reasons, the prospect of multiliteracy is dim indeed. For Hirsch, values of ‘civil peace and national effectiveness’ could not withstand the challenge that bilingualism and multiculturalism pose to mainstream America and its institutions of learning.30 A culture of homogeneity, the nostalgic yearning for which is evident throughout Hirsch’s writings, is directly entailed by a philosophy of education that conscripts students into a way of life and a way of thinking in which it is their lot to conform. This love of sameness is carried to the point where Hirsch is sharply critical of curricular guidelines that allow any flexibility whatever in their applications or professional judgment on the part of educators. Guidelines that call, for instance, for the teaching of national symbols or historical events in the primary grades must be specific and standardized, leaving no room for the educator’s discretion or for students’ interests. Such guidelines must specify which symbols or events are to be taught in which grades, for otherwise ‘the children are learning quite different things’.31 Why it is problematic if some students learn about the Statue of Liberty while others learn about the Washington Monument is not plain to see, but for Hirsch’s warnings about dire economic and social consequences if students do not absorb exactly the same information at the same time and in the same manner. What is plain to see is that curricular guidelines, in Hirsch’s view, are not to be guidelines at all but hard-and-fast rules. What is equally clear is that the culture in ‘cultural literacy’ means ‘mainstream culture’ or ‘the basic culture of the nation’, in contrast to ‘some local, regional, or ethnic culture’, to any sub- or counter-culture, and especially to cultural plurality. The culture that Hirsch designates as mainstream is what others call dominant, of course, and while he is aware of the objection, he is untroubled by it. It is wholly inevitable that a culture be ‘fundamentally conservative’ and that ‘its core contents change very slowly’, if indeed at all. ‘Changes at its core must occur with glacial slowness if it is to accommodate all the people and serve as our universal medium of communication.’32 Culture is a unitary monolith of information, highly resistant to change but for periodic additions and few if any subtractions. It is to be received by students as an altogether given and prepackaged body of material to be committed to memory without troubling themselves to think, apart from purely mechanical acts of memorization. This, Hirsch believes, constitutes the true meaning of acculturation: not to become initiated into a conversation that is ongoing but the veritable antithesis – to conform to the cultural mainstream and its ‘consensus values’. It is to become normalized, not especially critical, and intellectually docile. Hirsch’s account wholly assumes that it is the nature of human cultures to be discrete, homogeneous, and fixed. The (quasi-) anthropological, objectivistic notion of culture on which he relies – one constituted by ‘information’ and ‘factual knowledge’ rather than a
36
The Educative Process
lifeworld of shared practices, understandings, and language – may well entail a conception of education as exclusively occupied with the transmission of material that is ready made, complete, and unassailable, yet this is a thoroughly naive view of what culture itself is, and hence education as well. Neither culture nor tradition nor knowledge has the homogeneous, monolithic character that educational conservatives commonly attribute to them. Anthropologists are far from agreeing upon a proper definition of culture, a fact that Hirsch does not appear to be aware of as he confidently proffers his reified, informational theory of culture as the ‘anthropological perspective’. Far more nuanced and sophisticated conceptions of culture have been proposed by anthropologists and philosophers, of course, including phenomenological, hermeneutical, and poststructuralist views in which culture is described in terms of meaning, texts, interpretation, language, and social practices of various kinds rather than in terms of simple information. Clifford Geertz, for one, has defended a semiotic or hermeneutical theory of culture for which the basic condition of the human being as an acculturated agent is to be ‘suspended in webs of significance he himself has spun’ or to live according to a set of meanings that precede one but in which one is nonetheless a participant in a rich and critical sense of the word.33 Without becoming embroiled in this debate, it suffices to say that whatever culture is, it is far more complex than Hirsch supposes. His account of culture as a body of information is anything but uncontrovertible scientific fact; nor is it such a fact that education is by nature and universally a simple means to an end, whether it be the conservation of tradition or anything else. An observation of Alfred North Whitehead is relevant in this connection: It must never be forgotten that education is not a process of packing articles in a trunk. Such a simile is entirely inapplicable. It is, of course, a process completely of its own peculiar genus. Its nearest analogue is the assimilation of food by a living organism: and we all know how necessary to health is palatable food under suitable conditions.34 The merit of Whitehead’s remarks will be evident to any who attend closely to the practices of teaching and learning as they are actually experienced. The process succeeds, we say, not when a prepackaged collection of data is stored away in the inner recesses of a student’s mental warehouse, where it is placed neatly on a shelf and preserved for future use, but when a degree of insight or self-understanding is gained by means of the subject matter that is appropriated. Such appropriation is no merely superficial absorption of information but a more profound process in which an active intellect integrates deeply and critically transforms a given subject matter in a way that is consistent with any learning experience undergone in the course of
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
37
ordinary life. A learning experience, or indeed any experience that is worthy of the name, leaves its subject in an important respect changed, and in a sense utterly unlike the storing away of articles in a trunk. So as well does acculturation change, indeed constitute, the subject; it fashions one as a particular being-in-the-world or existing individual, in the language of existential phenomenology. Becoming initiated into a culture does undoubtedly involve absorbing information of particular kinds, and a great deal of it, but that it involves something far more and far deeper than this is wholly missed by Hirsch’s account. Both everyday acculturation and formal education involve a reciprocal process in which new items of knowledge are integrated into an existing orientation or conceptual framework while altering that framework in significant ways. Learning allows one not only to preserve existing facts but to do so in a spirit of intelligent criticism, to enlarge one’s horizon while adding coherence, depth, and meaning to experience, and to make oneself at home in the world by this means. Becoming literate in one’s culture involves but also far exceeds gaining familiarity with a catalog of truths more or less familiar to a population; it involves becoming a certain kind of subject, one constituted by a lifeworld of shared meanings and practices, language, tradition, and common sense. It is to adopt a particular way of being-in-the-world, an historically contingent understanding of the world and self-understanding, and to participate in a conversation that precedes one. A culture is a fundamentally dynamic enterprise into which the individual is taken up and that sets in motion the full range of human capacities. Hirsch’s conservatism, then, errs in its simplistic notions of culture, learning, and experience as essentially informational matters and of reflective capacity as an inevitable and happy by-product of the mere accumulation of facts. Cultural literacy stands or falls on an understanding of culture as a reified and given body of facts, initiation into which consists in the simple reception of data and the acceptance of values presented in the guise of ‘consensus’. It presupposes a view of tradition as a kind of absolute that students are obliged to take up in unrevised form rather than a conversation in which they freely participate, something that is unitary, homogeneous, and highly resistant to change. It presupposes as well a folksy and unphilosophical view of the educated mind as something that is easily measured and quantified by means of standardized testing which examines only the amount of information that has been committed to memory and which lacks any means of testing the quality of understanding that has been gained. Finally, it presupposes a naive view of reflective capacity or thinking as a skill that follows automatically upon the accumulation of information. While such knowledge is obviously a necessary condition of abstract reflection – one must, needless to say, have something to think about – it is hardly sufficient. Hirsch provides no account of the higher reaches of thought but for
38
The Educative Process
the insistence that those who are capable of it are also well informed, an observation that is true but uninformative. Learning to think, however this is accomplished, is far more complex a matter than Hirsch’s account allows. One point, however, on which educational conservatives do not err is their worry regarding the kind and amount of knowledge that students are currently gaining. Whether it be higher capacities of reflection and inventiveness that we are speaking of, Hirsch’s informational knowledge, or Bloom’s beloved canon, students who pass successfully through the various stages of education today are not, let us say, and without putting too fine a point on it, overburdened with knowledge. Educators are well aware of what their students know and care about and what they do not know and care about, and while the matter may be less dire than some conservatives believe, nor is it a cause for celebration that universities are now obliged to provide remedial education in writing or mathematics, that students’ knowledge of language and grammar is often lamentable, and that the love of reading or of knowledge as an end in itself has seen better days. Conservatives are right to worry about this, but tempting as it may be to hark back to a time in the past when students ostensibly knew more, in whatever sense of this phrase that one prefers, such a stance is nostalgic and foolish. It is no simple return to tradition that is called for, or to progressivism for that matter, but a new thinking that gets us beyond the dichotomies that Dewey was already urging us to reject a century ago and that continue to orient so much of the discourse of education. Hackneyed oppositions of student-centered or curriculum-centered education, critical thinking or factual knowledge, active or passive learning, and so on must be overcome, and in a fashion more convincing than what I have called corporate scientism has managed. It should be obvious, for instance, that there is no genuine dichotomy between the possession of informational knowledge – which conservatives like Hirsch dwell upon to the point of excluding other, equally important educational aims – and the development of critical thinking skills – which progressives have sometimes overemphasized, misunderstood, or presumed can be imparted apart from subject matter. One does not think critically in a curricular vacuum, nor does one appropriate a heritage by accepting it as an unquestionable given. Understanding education requires that we orient the discussion no longer around oppositions that a growing number of theorists are correctly urging us to abandon, and that we attend less to theoretical -isms that mistake a part of the educative process for the whole, and focus our attention instead on that process itself and the conditions that make it possible. Learning experiences that happen in institutions are not different in kind from learning experiences that happen in ordinary life. We would do well, then, to ask what the nature and conditions of such experience are.
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
39
The educative process It was Dewey who urged educational theorists to take this process itself as their point of departure and to identify its own immanent ends and conditions rather than import ends from other areas of life in ways that effectively distort the educative process. This important methodological move was central both to his critique of conservatism and to his own positive views, but was adopted only in a limited way by progressives such as Kilpatrick and Kingsley. Progressive theorists concurred with Dewey in regarding traditional curriculum-centered, if not teacher-centered, approaches as unduly regimented and divorced from the actual course of human experience and from the practice of learning itself. In severing theory and abstract subject matters from practice – the vital process of experience and learning – traditional education was compelled to seat students in orderly rows, their attention centered on the figure standing imposingly at the front of the room, diligently absorbing their lessons on pain of physical and moral censure, and submitting to a regime of institutional power. What is needed, Dewey and the progressives argued, is the replacement of such regimentation, along with the separation of theory and practice that made it possible and necessary, with a new accent on the learning process as it actually unfolds within the intellectual life of the student. This new phenomenological concentration on ‘how we think’ – the basic manner in which human beings negotiate their experience of the world – and on the stages of development that students pass through on the way to intellectual maturity, entails a shift in accent from the educator and the curriculum to the students and the conditions that foster development. Progressives taken by Dewey’s account amplified this relative shift in emphasis into a full-blown dichotomy and a categorical elevation of students, their cognitive development and indeed their social and emotional wellbeing, above the curriculum itself, giving new life to the very dichotomies that Dewey had urged us to leave behind. From Dewey’s point of view, the reforms that progressives were calling for amounted to a mere swing of the pendulum from one side of the old binary oppositions to the other rather than the more radical stance for which he called, a pendulum swing that had the effect of sacrificing the curriculum in a way that he himself had never intended. Dewey’s educational writings had never advocated any sacrifice in knowledge to whatever is identified as the students’ needs, whether they be cognitive, psychological, or social, but that the curriculum should complement students’ experience outside of the classroom and be taught and learned in ways that are conducive to higher capacities of thought. That these capacities could not be educated in the absence of a challenging, indeed tough-minded, curriculum seemed to go without saying for Dewey,
40
The Educative Process
and it was only when this seemingly obvious proposition was overlooked by progressive educators that he was compelled to point this out explicitly. Yet point it out he did, and in a way that left no doubt of his ambivalence for the movement he had ostensibly inspired. If it is a common mistake to identify Dewey as the originator of the dichotomies that continue to orient much educational theory as well as the principal cause of progressivism’s more unfortunate consequences – including especially the sacrifice of a rigorous curriculum to the supposed conditions of students’ well-being – it remains that much of progressive education did arise directly or indirectly from Dewey’s writings, including especially its critique of traditional, schoolmasterish pedagogy. This critique, as applicable to contemporary as to older forms of conservatism, maintains that while it is among the principal aims of education to transmit traditional subject matters, it is essential that this be carried out in the spirit of research and critical inquiry rather than simply ingested for the purpose of conservation. Dewey’s reasons for rejecting the notion of education as either a simple repetition of the past or a preparation for later life – or, as for Hirsch, a combination of the two – were at once political and philosophical. While the political objection concerned the kinds of democratic citizens which the older education was designed to produce, the philosophical objection concerned the nature of knowledge and experience. It is the nature of human knowledge, Dewey the pragmatic experimentalist maintained, not simply to accommodate the present to the past but to appropriate traditional ideas in the spirit of intelligent criticism and with an eye to their enhancement and transformation. Received knowledge is not merely bestowed on groups of students as a fait accompli but taken up into an inquiry which learns about and from the past while identifying the errors that have also been handed down in tradition. As Dewey expressed it, Education has accordingly not only to safeguard an individual against the besetting erroneous tendencies of his own mind – its rashness, presumption, and preference of what chimes with self-interest to objective evidence – but also to undermine and destroy the accumulated and self-perpetuating prejudices of long ages.35 We err equally in regarding knowledge as a mass of previously assembled information and in regarding education as a simple piling up of such data in the largest possible quantity. Knowledge is not a static value but a fundamentally dynamic one that is properly gained in the course of inquiry. The mark of knowledge having been acquired is less the ability to retrieve information for the purpose of inspection – although this is involved – than habits of reflective attention, curiosity and originality, and an appetite for contin-
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
41
ued learning. Informational knowledge acquired through rote learning typically fails to reach the desired depth and can become an obstacle to thought when ‘it swamps thinking’ by cluttering the mind with a mass of data the large majority of which remains at a surface level of consciousness. That knowledge is not a monolithic edifice to be passively beheld but something to be pressed into service – ‘vital energy seeking opportunity for effective exercise’ – is fundamental both to Dewey’s critique of traditional education and to his own positive conception.36 In keeping with his general philosophical view of the theory–practice relation, Dewey’s philosophy of education refuses all external impositions on the practices of teaching and learning, recognizing no higher authority than the learning process itself and the conditions that it requires. On this essentially practice-immanent account, education unfolds according to a logic of its own and is distorted when ends extraneous to that process are imposed on it from without. This logic is always already present and at least vaguely understood by educators and students alike; rendering it explicit is the task of the theorist. Dewey articulated this important methodological point as follows: A true aim is thus opposed at every point to an aim which is imposed upon a process of action from without. The latter is fixed and rigid; it is not a stimulus to intelligence in the given situation, but is an externally dictated order to do such and such things. Instead of connecting directly with present activities, it is remote, divorced from the means by which it is to be reached. Instead of suggesting a freer and better balanced activity, it is a limit set to activity. In education, the currency of these externally imposed aims is responsible for the emphasis put upon the notion of preparation for a remote future and for rendering the work of both teacher and pupil mechanical and slavish.37 Dewey would often express this view in his educational writings.38 The learning process must receive its basic orientation from knowledge itself and the manner in which it is acquired in human experience. Educational aims are ‘an outgrowth of existing conditions’ and are ‘based upon a consideration of what is already going on’, where ‘what is already going on’ is everyday experience and the search for understanding.39 Herein lies the principal failing of traditional (also some less traditional) education and the one from which many others stem: in articulating educational aims in the abstract (preparation for later life, the requirements of economic prosperity, performativity) and importing these into the learning process as an external imposition, the process itself is distorted by extraneous values inflexibly held and inserted into a practice that by its own constitution expressly forbids
42
The Educative Process
them. Inevitably the imposition of aims from without reduces education to a means to an end and supplants what it always already aims to achieve. When we reflect upon our experience of the learning process, be it as educators or students, we find that when the process is successful a certain ethos or spirit prevails, one that is intangible and eludes easy description but that gets us to the heart of what education truly is. This is an ethos that is shared, that is in the air, as it were, and which belongs to everyone and no one. It is a common reality that is sustained by educators and students alike and which is dominated by none. It is a process into which all are taken up, in the manner of a conversation in which one participates but that one does not control. An intersubjective phenomenon, the spirit or the logic of education, like a good conversation, is dominated by none of the participants, including the educator, but is conducted in dialogical fashion. Hans-Georg Gadamer provided a fitting phenomenological description of this process, albeit without applying it to education: We say that we ‘conduct’ a conversation, but the more genuine a conversation is, the less its conduct lies within the will of either partner. Thus a genuine conversation is never the one that we wanted to conduct. Rather, it is generally more correct to say that we fall into conversation, or even that we become involved in it. The way one word follows another, with the conversation taking its own twists and reaching its own conclusion, may well be conducted in some way, but the partners conversing are less the leaders of it than the led. No one knows in advance what will ‘come out’ of a conversation. Understanding or its failure is like an event that happens to us. Thus we say that something was a good conversation or that it was ill fated. All this shows that a conversation has a spirit of its own, and that the language in which it is conducted bears its own truth within it – i.e., that it allows something to ‘emerge’ which henceforth exits.40 Gadamer’s description readily applies to the educational setting. Here as well what takes place in the classroom ‘has a spirit of its own’; it is ‘like an event that happens to us’, one in which we are ‘less the leaders of it than the led’, with ‘the conversation taking its own twists and reaching its own conclusion’ – a conclusion that ‘allows something to emerge’. When successful, education involves a voluntary relinquishing of control comparable to the at once active and passive nature of conversation, oriented as it is toward a critical examination of the subject matter and not a merely expertocratic bestowing of knowledge on docile minds. Dewey reminded us that educators ‘conduct’ the conversation in the limited sense of providing clarification, posing questions, inviting observations, and so on rather than presiding over it dogmatically. Their task, in his words, ‘is to protect the spirit of inquiry, to
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
43
keep it from becoming blasé from overexcitement, wooden from routine, fossilized through dogmatic instruction, or dissipated by random exercise upon trivial things’.41 The educator, accordingly, is not the one who knows but a participant in the investigative process – one, to be sure, with a different role in inquiry than the students, but a participant nonetheless. Education is misunderstood when regarded in isolation from the larger extracurricular process of inquiry and experience to which it is related as species to genus. As Dewey took great pains to demonstrate, learning experiences that take place in classrooms, while more formally arranged and structured, are not different in kind from the learning experiences of ordinary life. Education is entirely consistent with the basic human practice of making ourselves at home in the world through understanding. Far from a simple amassing of information, it opens the mind, broadens horizons and interests, connects disparate fields of experience, arranges traditional subject matters into meaningful configurations, and cultivates habits of contemplation and inventiveness. It draws upon existing curiosities while directing these along lines that are less narrow or parochial and that open up a larger field of vision. The acculturation that it surely involves extends beyond gaining factual knowledge or learning how to see the world as Homer did, and includes extending students’ acquaintance with a lifeworld and deepening their understanding of themselves. It is the nature of human experience, Dewey held, to search for a resolution to the perplexities with which we are daily confronted. A given line of inquiry begins with an experienced confusion or difficulty through the observation of relevant phenomena, formulating a hypothesis to resolve the difficulty, refining and testing the hypothesis through application and observation of its consequences, and inferring a conclusion. This is an experiential as well as a social undertaking, drawing each of us into common participation with our fellow inquirers rather than proceeding in the fashion of a Cartesian meditator. For Dewey, this account of experience and inquiry is not an a priori prescription governing how we ought to think but is a phenomenological description of the structure of thought itself. It is the nature of thought to arise from experience and at the end of the day to return to it in order to provide illumination and to clear up the perplexities that it continually generates. The subject matter of education, then, must connect with experience and lead toward new experiences of a properly educative kind. While simple curiosity carries a certain authority here, this is not to be understood as mere self-indulgence, but is governed by a dynamic of its own. Except in its trivial forms, curiosity does not terminate as soon as a new bit of information has been acquired, but initiates a process of opening up further avenues of inquiry. One thing, as we say, leads to another; curiosity is a prospective value
44
The Educative Process
that leads us from an existing interest toward a more expansive set of these, interests that are more abstract and theoretical than the original curiosity. A common, and potentially misleading, way of stating this is that the curriculum must ‘be relevant’ or ‘engage students’ interests’ in a sense that is contrasted with the traditional separation of students’ experiences inside and outside the classroom. This does not mean that educators should indulge whatever interests students happen to have or, what is worse, restrict their experience to the merely enjoyable. Education makes demands on us, just as human experience in general does, and requires all who take it seriously to engage in a process that is taxing, rigorous, and seldom entertaining. While not always pleasurable, education as Dewey described it is nonetheless an end in itself in the sense that its aims are immanent to a learning process that is itself continuous with the broader course of human experience. If its beneficiaries are not mere cogs in the economic machinery but beings who, as Aristotle told us, ‘by nature desire to know’ then even as education serves to prepare students to earn a livelihood it always aims beyond this to instill higher capacities of thought, including especially the capacity for learning itself. As Dewey remarked, The best thing that can be said about any special process of education, like that of the formal school period, is that it renders its subject capable of further education: more sensitive to conditions of growth and more able to take advantage of them. Acquisition of skill, possession of knowledge, attainment of culture are not ends: they are marks of growth and means to its continuing.42 To speak of ‘ends’ here in no way signifies a termination of inquiry or any finally realizable end-state (professional credentials, economic preparedness, cultural literacy, performativity), but habits of mind that in a larger sense yield an understanding of the world and of oneself. While it is rooted in the concept of experience, then, Dewey’s philosophy of education must not be confused with those student-centered approaches that regard the critique of traditional pedagogy as entailing a de-emphasis on the curriculum or any lessening of intellectual standards in the name of the students’ ostensible well-being. Dewey harshly criticized progressive schools that claimed to accentuate cognitive skills, along with psychological and social skills, over the subject matter, insisting that such skills do not develop apart from a challenging curriculum and that the dichotomy of skills versus knowledge is spurious. Intelligent reflection is not learned apart from something to reflect upon, an abstract skill cultivated in courses specially designated ‘critical thinking’, as if this were separable from subject
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
45
matter or even a curriculum unto itself comprised of inferential rules which if scrupulously followed directly produce the ability to think. One does not learn to think by being supplied with a method and told to venture forth in applying it. One learns to think by thinking, which always means thinking about this or that subject matter in some depth and in the most rigorous way possible. Emphasizing the continuity between education and the larger course of human experience is not unique to Dewey but has deep roots in Western philosophy and an obvious affinity to hermeneutics and the Bildung tradition in particular. The paradox of Meno might serve as an origin point: how does one learn about a given object, Meno asked, unless one already possesses a prior knowledge of it, for otherwise the process of inquiry cannot begin? Plato’s solution came in the form of the doctrine of recollection, while in modern times a less metaphysical answer is provided by hermeneutics: understanding invariably takes place within a circular process in which a particular item of knowledge is related to a larger context or universal, while the universal itself is understood only in relation to particulars. Inquiry is thus a movement back and forth between universal and particular, between a context of background knowledge, experience, or prereflective understandings comprising one’s cultural heritage on one hand and on the other an inquiry into what is not yet understood. One acquires new items of knowledge by absorbing them within a prior framework of language and experience, a framework that is in turn modified by the addition. Since the conceptual framework that defines one’s point of view is an historical inheritance, education is inseparable from acculturation and may be understood on the model of joining a conversation. If we imagine culture to be a living conversation, then to become educated is to gain the capacity to participate – to listen and to learn as a necessary prelude to finding a voice that is properly one’s own. A hermeneutical approach to education would share Dewey’s view of the curriculum as inseparable in principle from students’ experience and the ‘problematic situations’ and curiosities that arise within it.43 The process of formal education is a species of the larger genus that is the search for understanding and self-understanding, these two being themselves ultimately inseparable, as Gadamer in particular has taught us to see.44 Education belongs as well to a larger movement of Bildung or the gradual formation of the individual in the transition from nature to culture. While Dewey himself did not make explicit reference to the Bildung tradition which extends from medieval mysticism through German idealism and into the twentieth century, his affinity to this tradition is plain to see.45 As Hegel spoke of this concept in his Phenomenology of Spirit, Bildung involves a never-ending process of cultivating one’s natural capacities and finding one’s way toward the
46
The Educative Process
universal. This cultivation of the self is its own end and involves the simultaneous formation of an object – a work – and oneself. As Gadamer wrote, In forming the object – that is, in being selflessly active and concerned with a universal – working consciousness raises itself above the immediacy of its existence to universality; or, as Hegel puts it, by forming the thing it forms itself. What he means is that in inquiring a ‘capacity’, a skill, man gains the sense of himself. The work of education forms and transforms the self, calls it into question and requires a ‘distancing from the immediacy of desire, of personal need and private interest, and the exacting demand of a universal’.46 In similar terms, Dewey would speak of the formation of the individual student as a competent citizen of a democracy, one with cultivated faculties and sympathies which incline the individual toward constructive forms of social engagement. The transition from childhood to maturity expressed in the notion of Bildung is at once a matter of individual formation and acculturation; one gains a sense of oneself in forms of social participation, by risking oneself and one’s judgments in the conversation that one’s culture essentially is. Education requires an openness to what is other and a dialectical movement back and forth between a venturing beyond oneself into the unfamiliar and having one’s point of view and one’s being transformed in the process. Here at last we get to the heart of the matter: education fundamentally is an unending process of fashioning and refashioning the self by rising to the universal, as Hegel would say. In Deweyan terms it is the cultivation of habits and capacities which make us competent democratic citizens and fully rational beings. While education inevitably informs students and prepares them to take their place in the workforce, such aims are subordinate to the formation of the self as a reflective agent. In only the loosest sense of the term may we speak of education as a science; while it is informed by various kinds of empirical inquiry, education itself is an art by virtue of that with which it is ultimately concerned: human understanding and the formation of persons as cultural participants. The model for this art remains Socrates engaged in conversation with the citizens of Athens, an informal and undogmatic mode of inquiry in which all are participants and no one, including the educator, is above the fray of dialogue. From the educator this art requires the skilful guidance of inquiry from a given set of interests toward a broader horizon, a guidance that draws upon a variety of methods – from direct instruction and lecturing to informal discussion, posing questions, hazarding opinions, interpreting texts, and provoking thought in any way one is able. The common tendency in educational research to treat this practice as an application of empirically discoverable laws of learning is
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
47
scientistic idolatry in its most crude form, as William James already noted in his Talks to Teachers on Psychology of 1899: . . . you make a great, a very great mistake, if you think that psychology, being the science of the mind’s laws, is something from which you can deduce definite programmes and schemes and methods of instruction for immediate classroom use. Psychology is a science and teaching is an art; and sciences never generate arts directly out of themselves. An intermediary inventive mind must make the application by using its originality.47 Nor necessarily is this art even an indirect application of scientific psychology. We are all familiar with highly competent educators who know nothing of this science yet who bring to their profession a depth of knowledge and passion for the subject matter, a care for what their students are getting from their education, and an experience and professional judgment of which science knows nothing. Such teachers are not technicians or mere custodians of information but educators in the truest sense, professionals who rely upon their judgment in selecting or tailoring the curriculum to particular groups of students and in training minds using whatever approaches prove effective. Proponents of standardization, again in the rage to be scientific, effectively reduce educators to functionaries with no scope for professional judgment and who must be strictly monitored to ensure that outcomes prescribed by external authority are achieved. Such teachers are not properly speaking educators at all, but a certain variety of technician, facilitators not of cultural literacy but of intellectual homogeneity. The current emphasis on ‘accountability’ in the teaching profession is in large part a veneer beneath which lies the corporate scientism discussed above – a philosophy for which standardization and rule-following are seemingly ends in themselves or objective requirements of scientific rationality – together with a thoroughly conservative political program. Beneath such phrases as accountability, teacher evaluation, professionalization, learning outcomes, and so on are underlying imperatives that make it increasingly unlikely that the graduates of our educational institutions will have either the ability or the inclination to think anything that is genuinely new and unanticipated by educational authorities. It is no small irony that at a time when ‘dialogue’ and ‘thinking outside the box’ have become popular slogans the institutions whose business is to train these capacities have rendered their attainment a singular improbability owing to trends toward scientism, curriculum standardization, and an overemphasis on informational knowledge at the expense of the higher reaches of thought. As educational conservatives lament a diminishing reverence for the canon and the loss of practically useful information, what
48
The Educative Process
they do not lament, but ought to, is an unlearning of an altogether different kind, and one that is far more worrisome. This is a diminution of capacities and intellectual virtues that yield no tangible utilities but on which the fate of our culture depends: habits of contemplation and critical questioning, imagination and inventiveness, the love of reading and writing for their own sake, the art of conversation and listening, the hospitality to new ideas and the refusal of false self-certainty, and capacities of judgment, prolonged concentration, and unhurried deliberation. The kind of unlearning I have in mind was already pointed out some decades ago by Karl Jaspers in the following terms: We see, also, the loss of the capacity for meditation, for solitude, for sustained thinking that can concentrate only on one thing at a time, not on an infinite number. Are the pessimists right in claiming that the actual rule of mediocrity calls for drill in place of a free intellectual life, that it requires existence to be divided into an empty bustle of work and no less empty pleasures? Or is it possible to give another chance to a free life – one that would be spiritually intensive rather than just scholastically extensive?48 The relevance of Jaspers’ remarks is plain to see, as is Nicholas Burbules’ more recent observations along similar lines: When teacher–student interchange becomes primarily a matter of telling, or a matter of asking extremely narrow, one-way questions, the capacities of both participants to listen, think, question, and consider alternatives atrophy. When instruction is geared toward ‘correct answers’, the inclination toward discussions that pertain more to investigation and divergent points of view is suppressed. When student–student dialogue is actively discouraged, or relegated only to very specific limited domains . . . particular communicative skills and dispositions are certainly deterred. But more than this, a tacit message is expressed that these dialogical skills and dispositions are not themselves educationally (or socially, or politically) significant; because, clearly, if they were significant, the curriculum would acknowledge them.49 Educational theorists who worry about a diminution in knowledge among the students of today must avoid overstating their case and becoming nostalgic, as Bloom, Hirsch, and other conservatives are especially inclined to do. At no time in the past did younger generations as a whole stand head and shoulders above the youth of today in terms of either the possession of factual knowledge, an appreciation of the canon, or the intellectual virtues
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism
49
to which Jaspers and Burbules allude. Short of nostalgia and exaggeration, however, it is perfectly appropriate to worry about all of the above: the kind and amount of information that students now possess relative to prior generations (certainly different information and likely less overall), a knowledge and appreciation of the great works of the Western tradition (again, likely less), and intellectual habits of reflection. No method or standardized test allows us to gain an accurate measurement here, but there can be little doubt that we have cause for concern about all of these matters, and particularly for the intellectual capacities that produce no immediate payoff in terms of performativity, professional credentials, or what now passes for cultural literacy. When the cultivation of the self as an informed but also critical, contemplative, and moderately inventive participant in the life of its society is consigned to the margins in the rage to place education on the secure path of a science or to prepare students to attain a high grade on a standardized test at the expense of other educational aims, those aims will go by the wayside, leaving new generations too well adapted to the economictechnological apparatus and unable to see beyond it. The argument of this chapter is best developed in relation to specific disciplines, where our guiding question concerns the aims of education in different fields of study. Our basic hypothesis may be stated in general terms, the details of which I shall examine in the following two chapters, while its relevance to specific fields is the focus of the chapters in Part 2. That hypothesis is that we must look to the fundamental conditions and requirements of the learning process itself, its own immanent dynamic and ends, rather than to educational aims articulated outside of that process in fashioning policies. The philosopher’s task is to articulate the aims that are always already in play in the educative process and identify distorting influences caused by impositions from without. I shall undertake this task in relation to several disciplines in the human sciences, especially at the secondary and postsecondary levels where these questions take on increasing urgency.
Notes 1. A few unfortunate examples of this in the contemporary literature are Henry Edmondson’s John Dewey and the Decline of American Education (Wilmington: ISI Books, 2006), Kieran Egan’s Getting It Wrong From the Beginning: Our Progressivist Inheritance from Herbert Spencer, John Dewey, and Jean Piaget (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002), and E. D. Hirsch’s Cultural Literacy: What Every American Needs to Know (New York: Vintage, 1988) and The Schools We Need and Why We Don’t Have Them (New York: Doubleday, 1996). 2. John Darling and Sven Erik Nordenbo, ‘Progressivism’ in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Education, eds N. Blake, P. Smeyers, R. Smith and P. Standish (Malden: Blackwell, 2003), 288. The same authors also raise ‘the delicate question of whether such approaches and methods still merit the term “progressivism”’ (Ibid., 288).
50
The Educative Process
3. David Carr, Making Sense of Education: An Introduction to the Philosophy and Theory of Education and Teaching (New York: Routledge Falmer, 2003), 215–16, 214. 4. See for instance Edmondson, John Dewey and the Decline of American Education, 4; Egan, Getting It Wrong From the Beginning, 5; Allan Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1987), 3; and Hirsch, Cultural Literacy, 8, 9. 5. Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind, 56. 6. Shaun Gallagher, Hermeneutics and Education (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), 185. 7. Dewey, The Child and the Curriculum (1903). MW 2: 277–8. 8. Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991), 504–5. 9. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 9. 10. Dewey, The Child and the Curriculum (1903). MW 2: 280–1. 11. Edmondson, John Dewey and the Decline of American Education, 110, 4. 12. Sidney Hook, John Dewey: An Intellectual Portrait (Amherst: Prometheus Books, 1995), 177. 13. Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans. Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), 51, 4. 14. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Hans-Georg Gadamer on Education, Poetry, and History: Applied Hermeneutics, trans. Lawrence Schmidt and Monica Reuss, eds Dieter Misgeld and Graeme Nicholson (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), 165. 15. Derek Briton observes regarding adult education in particular: ‘The commonsense assumption that the modern practice of adult education is a disinterested, scientific endeavor that need not, indeed, should not concern itself with moral and political questions has become all but impossible to question because the field’s normative base can no longer be addressed within its narrowly defined, depoliticized, dehistoricized, technicist, professional discourse.’ Derek Briton, The Modern Practice of Adult Education: A Postmodern Critique (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996), 9. 16. N. Blake, P. Smeyers, R. Smith and P. Standish, ‘Introduction’ to The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Education, 8. 17. David Bridges and Ruth Jonathon, ‘Education and the Market’ in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Education, 29. 18. Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, 61. 19. The mistaken but still common reading of Dewey as a positivist of sorts is convincingly critiqued by James Scott Johnston in his excellent study, Inquiry and Education: John Dewey and the Quest for Democracy (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2006). 20. As Bloom puts it, ‘Our stars are singing a song they do not understand, translated from a German original and having a huge popular success with unknown but wideranging consequences, as something of the original message touches something in American souls. But behind it all, the master lyricists are Nietzsche and Heidegger.’ Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind, 152. Careful readers of Nietzsche and Heidegger – which Bloom clearly is not – will appreciate just how preposterous this claim is. 21. Ibid., 51, 61. 22. Ibid., 58, 340. 23. Ibid., 64. 24. Ibid., 374, 380. 25. Hirsch, The Schools We Need, 19. 26. Ibid., 176. 27. Hirsch, Cultural Literacy, xv–xvi, 61. 28. Ibid., 99.
Beyond Progressivism and Conservatism 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45.
46. 47. 48. 49.
51
Hirsch, The Schools We Need, 236. Hirsch, Cultural Literacy, 92. Hirsch, The Schools We Need, 28. Hirsch, Cultural Literacy, 22, 102, 107. Throughout this book, italics in quoted material are in the original. Clifford Geertz, ‘Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture’ in The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1977), 5. Alfred North Whitehead, The Aims of Education and Other Essays (New York: The Free Press, 1967), 33. Dewey, How We Think (1910). MW 6: 201. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 165, 77. Ibid., 117. See, for example, MW 9: 107, 111; LW 8: 222–3; and LW 13: 6. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 111. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 1989), 383. Dewey, How We Think (1910). MW 6: 207. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 185. See Shaun Gallagher, Hermeneutics and Education. See Gadamer, Truth and Method. James A. Good provides a thorough account of this in his exemplary study, A Search for Unity in Diversity: The ‘Permanent Hegelian Deposit’ in the Philosophy of John Dewey (Lanham: Lexington Books, 2006). Gadamer, Truth and Method, 13. William James, Talks to Teachers on Psychology (New York: W. W. Norton, 1958), 24. Karl Jaspers, Philosophy and the World: Selected Essays, trans. E. B. Ashton (Washington: Gateway Editions, 1963), 28. Nicholas C. Burbules, Dialogue in Teaching: Theory and Practice (New York: Teachers College Press, 1993), 152.
Chapter 2
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
Dewey was an unlikely revolutionary. Seldom given to impassioned prose, provocation, or literary excess, Dewey’s writings throughout his long and remarkably prolific career are marked by an unusual sobriety of analysis and a common sense seldom associated with a revolutionary purpose. Yet such a purpose unmistakably characterized his educational writings throughout his career. When Dewey spoke of his aim in the philosophy of education as to affect a revolution of Copernican proportions, this is to be understood not as an uncharacteristic rhetorical flight but as an altogether accurate statement of his goal.1 That goal begins with a shift in the ‘center of gravity in education, one that would often be misunderstood by progressivists and others who began to insist on a student-centered conception of education’. Whereas traditional views had identified the subject matter – conceived as a ready-made body of knowledge – as the center around which the educational process properly revolves, progressive educators placed the student at the center, citing Dewey as their authority. Dewey’s considered position, however, differs considerably from many of those who would claim him as their inspiration. It is, for Dewey, not the student him- or herself but the student’s experience that constitutes this new center of gravity. Recognizing this, he argued, requires a radical transformation in both the theory and practice of education. For Dewey, the educative process contains an immanent logic which it is the theorist’s task to render explicit. The aims of the practice of education, as we have seen, are internal to the practice itself. The theorist’s primary task, accordingly, is descriptive rather than prescriptive; it is to describe in explicit terms what aims and purposes always already belong to the learning process and thus to refrain from pronouncing upon what such aims ought to be in the traditional manner. Fundamentally, Dewey’s intention was not to prescribe in the usual fashion ‘what education should be’, in the sense that the theorist reflecting a priori would ‘set up ideals and norms for it’ from a point of view external to the educative process, but rather to describe in a phenomenological manner ‘what actually takes place when education really occurs’.2 This seemingly modest aim would represent an important methodological departure from traditional views for which education’s purpose and 52
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
53
center of gravity are determined by considerations unrelated to students’ experience and to the integrity of the learning process itself, by a body of knowledge that educators must instill by whatever pedagogical methods prove most effective and which students must learn in the sense of receive, comprehend, and remember. The principal aim in the philosophy of education is neither to prescribe the most efficient techniques by which a given curriculum may be deposited into students’ minds nor to judge which items of knowledge or belief are most important from the standpoint of cultural transmission or practical necessity. Without rejecting these aims, Dewey insisted on their subordination to experience, a consideration that for Dewey represents the Alpha and Omega of education. If the Copernican revolution that Dewey set out to effect shifts the locus of education to experience, the questions this move raises for the philosophy of education include what the nature of experience itself is, what this move entails, and why it is necessary. My focus in this chapter is on the first question, yet before turning to this it is important to recall the argument Dewey provided for why such a revolution is called for and what defects he identified in traditional educational approaches. Without repeating the argument of Chapter 1, let us recall the original impetus that prompted Dewey to reject more conservative views. Dewey provided an early summary of his critique in the following terms: Upon the whole, I believe that the crying evil in instruction today is that the subject-matter of the curriculum, both as a whole and in its various stages, is selected and determined on the objective or logical basis instead of upon the psychological. The humble pedagogue stands with his mouth and his hands wide open, waiting to receive from the abstract scientific writers the complete system which the latter, after centuries of experience and toilsome reflection, have elaborated. Receiving in this trustful way the ready-made ‘subject’, he proceeds to hand it over in an equally readymade way to the pupil. The intervening medium of communication is simply certain external attachments in the way of devices and tricks called ‘method’, and certain sugar-coatings in the way of extrinsic inducements termed ‘arousing of interest’.3 Dewey never tired of criticizing, often in the harshest terms, the conservative approaches that were the norm in his day and which he himself endured as a youth in the public school system of Vermont, an educational system likely no worse than the norm of that time but nonetheless lamentable. To appreciate Dewey’s critique here, it is necessary to understand first the manner in which he typically engaged in criticism of views that he rejected. Unlike so many philosophers of his time and our own, Dewey was an uncommonly
54
The Educative Process
gentle critic. Slow to criticize at all, invariably measured, dispassionate, and charitable when he did, and never prone to exaggeration, nonetheless when his topic was the educational practices on which he himself was raised and the theory that underlies them, he was uncharacteristically severe. His critique focused on the nearly total eclipse of students’ experience that occurs within the traditional paradigm in which students stand to the curriculum as subject to object while the essential business of learning involves impressing information on students’ minds in the largest possible quantity and in the most efficient way possible, in so doing overcoming the resistance to learning that (ostensibly) naturally characterizes the young. A curriculum at once abstract and formal, disconnected from experience, the significance of which will become apparent to the students only in a remote future, is presented and received as a deliverance from on high, perhaps as the dead weight of the past, and in any event as a body of knowledge that is ‘essentially static . . . a finished product, with little regard either to the ways in which it was originally built up or to changes that will surely occur in the future’.4 Such a regime produces an atmosphere that discourages learning precisely by denying the ground from which it emerges – the students’ experience. It is ‘an atmosphere of timidity’,5 lack of interest, ‘docility, receptivity, and obedience’.6 The ‘average traditional school’, he wrote, is marked by ‘wooden routine’ and ‘deadly conventionality’, an atmosphere completely removed from the students’ lives outside of the classroom.7 Lacking motivation to learn under such conditions, students must be given artificial inducements ‘so that the mind may swallow the repulsive dose unaware’, inducements such as a teacher’s approval, high grades, or entertaining pedagogy combined with an array of disincentives for failure.8 Even when education succeeds by these standards, it typically produces students who are themselves disconnected from life, ‘academic’ in the colloquial sense, unduly bookish, and above all conventional in their thinking. Having succeeded in amassing great quantities of information, they tend to remain deficient in the capacity for original and critical thought. While Dewey’s judgment of traditional education was harsh, he stopped short of embracing its logical antithesis, as the progressive movement he inspired often did and for which he faulted them as well, particularly in his short monograph of 1938, Experience and Education. A dialectical thinker, Dewey almost invariably refused to think in terms of binary oppositions and was no less skeptical of philosophical dichotomies than his German predecessor (with whose works it appears he had only a passing acquaintance), Friedrich Nietzsche. The dichotomy of progressive or student-centered versus traditional, curriculum-centered education which it had appeared Dewey himself presupposed he instead rejected. The progressive movement had begun contrasting in starkly dichotomous terms discipline and freedom,
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
55
effort and interest, imposition from on high and expression from experience, preparation for the future and present life, and so on, in each case replacing the former with the latter. Dewey would not follow them in this – more accurately, he would rebuke them for not following him – insisting instead that it is the dichotomy of progressivism and conservatism itself that must be rejected in favor of a more nuanced position whose point of departure is the students’ experience but that endeavors to develop this in a direction and manner that is determined by the logic of experience itself. To accomplish this, Dewey would insist that educators seek not merely to ‘hammer in’ or ‘plaster on’ the curriculum into students’ minds by the traditional pedagogical means of memorization, drill, recitation, and so on, but to create an environment of a kind that is instrumental in ‘calling out certain responses’. If we think of education on the model of organic growth and of life itself, it becomes ‘a fostering, a nurturing, a cultivating, process’, all of which concepts represent ‘conditions of growth’.9 Supplying these conditions expresses a conception of education as in a sense intermediate between the progressive idea of ‘development from within’ and the conservative ‘formation from without’, although as with so many issues Dewey remained closer to the former.10 One of the criticisms Dewey would most often level against traditional education precisely concerns the environment in which it occurs – typically one that stifles intellectual growth rather than promotes it. An educational environment is properly regulated with a view to its effects on such development and is produced by creating ‘experienced situations’ that ‘call out thinking’ or spontaneously elicit reflection ‘in the way in which . . . out-of-school situations do’. Thinking, if it occurs at all in academic settings, does so when certain conditions are in place; when they are not, thought typically stops in its tracks, if it arises at all. If it is characteristic of thinking in general that it ‘arises out of a directly experienced situation’ rather than out of an entirely predigested curriculum, or perhaps ‘out of nothing’, it becomes the business of the educator to provide and draw upon experienced situations, directing them in the course of the learning process along particular lines.11 Dewey’s accent on experience was not intended, as so many of his critics and even his supporters often took him to mean, to devalue the curriculum or knowledge itself but to insist on its connection with the experiential. When this connection is not apparent, as so often it is not, the consequence is not the pursuit of knowledge for its own sake but its veritable opposite: the unmotivated mind confronting information ‘simply as information to be retained for its own sake’, knowledge that ‘tends to stratify over vital experience’ rather than shed meaning on it.12 This motivation deficit has long been one of the chief ills of education at all levels, yet rather than view this in the traditional way as a sign of intellectual laziness on the part of the young,
56
The Educative Process
Dewey regarded it as a symptom of pedagogical failure. Even as abstract a subject matter as mathematics, Dewey argued, can be presented to students in ways that accentuate rather than ignore its roots in human experience. If at the elementary level in particular ‘the study of number suffers from . . . lack of motivation’, what causes this is nothing in the nature of students’ minds or which is perhaps inherent to mathematics itself, as if the subject were inherently uninteresting, but ‘the radical mistake of treating number as if it were an end in itself, instead of the means of accomplishing some end. Let the child get a consciousness of what is the use of number, of what it really is for, and half the battle is won.’13 A motivation deficit is a predictable consequence when an answer to the student’s perennial question, ‘Why are we studying this?’ is far to seek. For Dewey, this is a question that educators at every level must take more seriously than they traditionally have and answer in terms not wholly discontinuous with students’ extracurricular experience. As Dewey noted, it is characteristic of young minds in particular to have a nearly inexhaustible appetite for knowledge regarding nearly everything with which life brings them into contact – provided that it is life or vital experience from which knowledge derives: A little child, when awake, is always busy. If we analyze this tendency we shall find that the mind, acting through the medium of the body, is all the time seeking for something. For instance, the child seems always hungry for physical food. In that respect he is certainly not a blank piece of paper. On the contrary, his hunger is an active thing, so active that it causes him to search eagerly for food. Now the child’s eyes, his ears, his fingers, his nose are just as hungry as his stomach. Children naturally hunger for what gives health, for what makes up life; for form, for color, for sound, and especially for holding things and doing something with them.14 Dewey was hardly the first to note the natural inclination of the mind to seek knowledge. Aristotle, in one of the most frequently cited remarks in the history of Western thought, opened the Metaphysics with the observation that ‘All men by nature desire to know’, an observation with which few would disagree, yet as every educator knows, it is a desire that can become remarkably attenuated in academic settings.15 Why is it, Dewey asked, that the imperative to understand that is so pronounced and ubiquitous in ordinary experience is so often replaced with indifference in the classroom? His answer was that students in traditional institutions are presented with information in ways so removed from ordinary life that students begin to perceive the world of knowledge as an altogether remote and ‘strange world’ that ‘overlies’ rather than connects with ‘the world of personal acquaintance’.
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
57
To the students’ way of thinking, academic knowledge becomes a wholly separate affair from the more vital knowledge to which Aristotle alluded, the value and purpose of which can be utterly mysterious apart from authoritative commands. As Dewey continued: The sole problem of the student is to learn, for school purposes, for purposes of recitations and promotions, the constituent parts of this strange world. Probably the most conspicuous connotation of the word knowledge for most persons to-day is just the body of facts and truths ascertained by others; the material found in the rows and rows of atlases, cyclopedias, histories, biographies, books of travel, scientific treatises, on the shelves of libraries.16 The traditional reply to this is that the purpose of education can be confidently expected to become apparent to students later in life and consists essentially in preparing them for that life, a matter that the immature mind cannot be expected to comprehend. Dewey countered that while the notion of education as a preparation for the future is not wholly without merit, it faces insurmountable difficulties, beginning with the fact that the disconnection between the subject matter of education and present life undermines the motivation to learn, distorts students’ conception of knowledge, and fosters attitudes of intellectual docility and conventionality. Additionally, the doctrine of preparation undermines itself by overlooking the very factors that make a genuine preparation for the future possible. As he argued, ‘only by extracting at each present time the full meaning of each present experience are we prepared for doing the same thing in the future’.17 Supplying students with knowledge that in the educator’s estimation they will some day need creates a sizeable problem regarding retention, as is apparent when we reflect on our own years of schooling and how much of the information presented to us we have managed to retain.18 When we compare this with the capacity to absorb and retain information that vitally connects with students’ experience, the contrast is remarkable. It is commonplace for a child or young adult to possess little capacity to retain their lessons in mathematics or literature while having an encyclopedic knowledge of sports or music that can remain with them for decades.19 It is nothing inherent to sports, music, or the youthful mind that explains this contrast but the connection of the former to the lived experience of the young. When educators are able to draw genuinely upon students’ experience outside the classroom the situation is dramatically different. Unless we wish to assert that students do not learn outside of institutions, or that what they learn there does not constitute education, we must explain why it so often happens that one and the same mind can be lackluster and indifferent to learning in an academic setting yet
58
The Educative Process
intensely inquisitive outside it. The ‘indirect education’, as Dewey referred to it, that we receive through experience provides a model by which to conceive education in the academic connotation of the term.20 It is a model in which activities of the kind that once took place in the home are reproduced in the classroom. In elementary school, for instance, such as the one that Dewey himself instituted at the University of Chicago (the so-called ‘Laboratory School’ of 1896–1903, created as an experimental attempt to put Dewey’s philosophy of education into practice), academic subject matters are organized around such activities as woodworking and carpentry, nature study, domestic farming, cooking, and similar practices which in former times belonged to the ordinary experience of childhood in rural areas or small cities. The ‘ideal home’ prior to modern urbanization and technological mechanization included ‘a workshop where the child could work out his constructive instincts’ as well as ‘a miniature laboratory in which his inquiries could be directed’. Additionally, ‘[t]he life of the child would extend out of doors to the garden, surrounding fields, and forests. He would have his excursions, his walks and talks, in which the larger world out of doors would open to him.’21 The school that Dewey envisioned is larger in scale, more explicitly social or public, more carefully structured and directed in its activities than domestic life, yet in its essentials is modeled on the ideal home as he conceived of it. The ultimate justification of this idea lies in the nature of the educative process itself: knowledge acquisition must be rooted directly in human experience since the latter is the ground from which knowledge emerges and is that upon which knowledge ultimately bears. If one senses a hint of nostalgia in Dewey’s conception of the ideal home one would not be wholly mistaken. During his long lifetime (1859–1952) Dewey witnessed first-hand the profound changes that modernization was bringing about and viewed them with a mixture of optimism and lamentation. While his general outlook was by no means conservative, Dewey did view with regret the exodus into large cities and suburbs that was occurring during the latter nineteenth and early twentieth centuries as well as some of the changes in childhood experience that this was bringing about. With his characteristic even-handedness, Dewey lamented the disconnection from nature that urban life causes together with the narrowing of experience and loss of practical knowledge that children raised in rural settings traditionally acquire, and the loss of the small scale of life in which Dewey himself grew up, yet without becoming backward-looking or overlooking the merits of modern life. As Dewey wrote in 1899: But it is useless to bemoan the departure of the good old days of children’s modesty, reverence, and implicit obedience, if we expect merely by bemoaning and by exhortation to bring them back. It is radical
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
59
conditions which have changed, and only an equally radical change in education suffices. We must recognize our compensations – the increase in toleration, in breadth of social judgment, the larger acquaintance with human nature, the sharpened alertness in reading signs of character and interpreting social situations, greater accuracy of adaptation to differing personalities, contact with greater commercial activities. These considerations mean much to the city-bred child of today.22 If modernity is in so many respects a mixed blessing, exacting a heavy price for the myriad practical and cultural advantages that it ushers in and which we would be loath to give up, the question for education is how to ensure that the learning process is rooted in the only ground from which it can spring. If experience, in an expansive sense of the term, constitutes this ground, how can educators prevent the disconnection of knowledge and experience from becoming still more pronounced or, more optimistically, reverse it? For Dewey, the answer must come in the form of a curriculum that arises directly from activities and situations of real life which he encapsulated in the term experience, a concept that he would seek to elucidate over the course of several decades. If the root of the problem with traditional education is its neglect of the experiential dimension of life, Dewey’s task was to make the implications of his Copernican revolution explicit – to spell out which kinds of experience he held to be educative, how they are to be directed along properly educational lines, and of course what his conception of experience itself is. This old term, which has its roots in ancient Greek philosophy and later underwent profound transformation during the modern Enlightenment period in the thought of the British empiricists and others, Dewey would endeavor to overhaul in radical terms while also demonstrating its far-reaching implications in several areas of philosophical concern. It is to this question of experience itself and the conditions under which it is properly educative that I now turn.
Experience as experimental inquiry The long history of the concept of experience in the Western philosophical tradition is, of course, a topic to which I cannot do justice here; however in order to orient matters let us take a very brief excursion into epistemology and the more orthodox conceptions of experience that have come down to us from the Greeks and from modern empiricism, rationalism, and idealism, since it is these views that Dewey’s notion of experience seeks to overcome. The concept of experience as experimental inquiry is fundamental not only to Dewey’s theory of education but to his entire philosophical outlook, from
60
The Educative Process
his pragmatic epistemology to logic, psychology, aesthetics, ethics, politics, and other areas of investigation. It is an idea that has played a central role as well in the epistemology of the ancients and in the great age of Enlightenment, yet as Dewey often had occasion to remark, it continues into the twentieth century to be plagued by ancient associations that invite us to regard it in a rather dim light. The general disparagement of experience began in Greek philosophy, particularly in the writings of Plato and Aristotle, and belongs to a broader critique of such items as practice, rhetoric, opinion, and appearance, among others, all of which were asserted in one fashion or another to belong to a subaltern realm in the order of knowledge and being. The most eminent of Greek philosophers instituted a series of hierarchically ordered dichotomies that would fundamentally structure Western thought into the modern age. Binary oppositions ranging from reality/appearance to knowledge/opinion, theory/practice, reason/desire, dialectic/rhetoric, human/animal, man/woman, public/private, virtue/vice, and so on and so forth lent the several branches of philosophical investigation their basic trajectory, in each case the former possessing a status of categorical superiority over the latter. Classical philosophy would speak of experience as well in dichotomous and hierarchical terms. The realm of experience and the empirical belonged to a decidedly lower order of cognition than the rational – the faculty that constitutes our human essence, elevates us above the brutes, and enables us to know the true nature of being. Experience became associated in the Greek mind with the sum of opinions and practices that custom had authorized and hence with the past. Empirical knowledge or belief was limited in scope to the world of contingency, probability, and change, and lacked the necessity and certainty of the knowledge that is founded on the secure basis of reason. If reality in its ultimate dimension transcended the order of mere appearances it could not be known by empirical means but required a categorically higher order of cognition, one capable of grasping the forms, essences, first causes, and what have you. Mathematics and logic, for instance, were quite beyond the reach of experience while constituting the purest forms of knowledge available to human beings. Their very purity was precisely a result of their being unmixed with the merely empirical, with the senses or the reliance on opinions accumulated from the past. For the Greeks, the higher reaches of knowledge bear less on what a thing is than why it is, its underlying reason or cause. The ultimate aim of science is not to gain empirical knowledge about a given object but to comprehend it rationally, where this means explaining its causes. During the Enlightenment the concept of experience would undergo transformation in the thought of the rationalists, idealists, and of course the empiricists of the British school while in many ways continuing along the
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
61
trajectory set by classical philosophy. What remained firmly in place within rationalism and idealism is the ancient depreciation of the empirical and the insistence on the unreliability of the senses without the tutelage of rational categories. Descartes’ Meditations famously outlined the case against empirical observation unaided by clear and distinct ideas, concepts whose guarantor can only be of a divine, not an empirical, order. The concepts of reason for rationalists and German idealists alike are located above experience and possess a self-sufficiency with respect to the empirical such that the latter can neither confirm nor negate such concepts. Whereas experience can never rise above the order of particularity, probability, and contingency, the categories of rational thought enable us to grasp universal and necessary laws, principles, and a priori certainties which form the true basis of knowledge. For Kant, it is the categories of pure reason that impose intelligibility on an experience that unto itself is chaotic and unknowable. While Kant would attempt to demonstrate the limits of the reason that is divorced from experience, what is decisive in Dewey’s reading of Kant is the ‘dogmatic rigidity’ that still clings to the latter’s critical project: [B]ecause he taught that the understanding employs fixed, a priori, concepts, in order to introduce connection into experience and thereby make known objects possible (stable, regular relationships of qualities), he developed in German thought a curious contempt for the living variety of experience and a curious overestimate of the value of system, order, regularity for their own sakes. Dewey faulted Kant in particular for introducing into German philosophy a ‘system of absolutism’ that looks away from worldly realities in favor of a transcendent order, and whose characteristic stance is both polarizing and conservative: ‘a resolution of experience into atomic elements that afford no support to stable organization or a clamping down of all experience by fixed categories and necessary concepts’. The political implications of this are dangerously apologetic if we are compelled to choose between ‘complete radicalism neglecting and attacking the historic past as trivial and harmful, or complete conservatism idealizing institutions as embodiments of eternal reason’.23 Continental rationalism and idealism were not alone in separating reason from experience, even if British empiricism would take a far less disparaging view of experience itself than these other schools. If the empiricism of Hobbes, Locke, Hume, and so on would insist that it is the evidence of the senses rather than abstract reason that constitutes the foundation of knowledge, it would nonetheless employ a conception of experience that Dewey would later reject. Orthodox empiricism defined experience as an essentially
62
The Educative Process
passive beholding of nature or what modern epistemology often refers to as the ‘external world’. The knowing subject, which Hobbes articulated as a system of matter in motion, confronts its environment in a fundamentally passive manner, the reliability of its ‘simple ideas’ resting precisely on their coerciveness. Sensations impose themselves forcefully on our awareness, giving observation an inescapable quality that affords a guarantee of validity superior to that provided by ostensibly rational ideas, all of which, empiricists insisted, have their origin not a priori but rather in the simple ideas of experience. If there is nothing in the mind that was not once in the senses then it is empirical observation alone that supplies the content of human knowledge. The concept of experience itself would be characterized in orthodox empiricism as an atomistic matter rather than one marked by continuity in time and space. Consciousness receives impressions as discrete deliverances of sense (red, spherical, firm, sweet) rather than holistically (apple), leaving it with the problem of how to string these ideas together without resorting to speculation or in a manner that is accurate and empirically grounded. The foundation of knowledge is accordingly first-hand, direct observation of material objects or their qualities, an experience that provides the ingredients that give rise to more complex ideas and operations of thought. What experience does not supply, empiricists insisted, is any perception of relations such as causality, contiguity, or necessity. Hume, for instance, would provide the classical empirical analysis of causality, arguing that nowhere in human experience does one perceive a necessary connection between events rather than their constant conjunction. It is habit alone that accustoms consciousness to expect one event to follow another, not a direct beholding of causal necessity or any other unseen powers operative behind the back of sense. The marks of knowledge, then, in classical empiricism are a passive awareness, a well-functioning sensory apparatus, strict refusal to embrace beliefs not traceable to simple ideas, and a method by which such ideas can be strung together to form inferences. Any concepts that we deem ‘rational’ are inventions of the mind and are known only on the basis of empirical observation. In the beginning, the mind is a blank slate upon which experience inscribes all that we can genuinely know, there being neither innate nor a priori concepts that structure our awareness or constitute a foundation of knowledge. Toward the end of the nineteenth century empiricism in the United States would take a ‘radical’ – one might also say phenomenological – turn in the writings first of William James and subsequently of Dewey. James’ work in both philosophy and psychology during this period profoundly influenced Dewey’s entire outlook, helping (along with Darwinian biology and his reading of Hegel) to reorient his thought from an earlier allegiance to a
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
63
form of British idealism indebted in the main to Hegel and T. H. Green (an allegiance that Dewey never abandoned entirely, or, at any rate, not to Hegel24) and toward a Jamesian psychology and ‘radical empiricism’ modeled rather directly on biology. Where earlier epistemologies had failed, radical empiricists now maintained, is in the basic notion of mind as confronting the world from an external perspective, as an essentially worldless subjectivity standing to the ‘external world’ as if on one side of an ontological abyss, in the world in one manner or another but not of it. The epistemological problematic of knowing the world meant escaping by some reliable method the inner confines of subjectivity and ascertaining whether objects in the world resemble in their true being the ideas of them that are immediately before the mind. The empiricism that James and Dewey put forward rejects this model in its entirety and replaces it with a naturalistic and biological model of experience. Human experience is fundamentally bound up with, is indeed ultimately inseparable from, the world – an idea that the phenomenological movement, following Edmund Husserl, would speak of as the intentionality of consciousness. Conscious experience, radical empiricism and phenomenology likewise maintained, has an intentional structure and is always already directed toward, bound up with, and ultimately inseparable from its object. The subject–object dichotomy represents a distortion of how we experience both objects in the natural world and social phenomena belonging to what Husserl would now call the lifeworld. Experience does not occur in a vacuum, these thinkers now asserted and elaborated in vocabularies rather different both from each other and from the earlier epistemologies of empiricism, rationalism, and idealism. While it is highly regrettable that radical empiricism and phenomenology would develop as entirely separate traditions of thought, barely on speaking terms with each other, with phenomenology emerging in Germany and France and radical empiricism remaining an American phenomenon, the basic premises they share include a general skepticism of Enlightenment foundationalism, the primacy of practice and lived experience, the intentionality of consciousness, and some related ideas. For James in particular, conceiving of experience in a non-atomistic way meant affirming what the earlier empiricism had expressly denied: that we do indeed experience connections or relations between different objects of sense rather than wholly discrete and disconnected events. As James articulated the basic point of radical empiricism: To be radical, an empiricism must neither admit into its constructions any element that is not directly experienced, nor exclude from them any element that is directly experienced. For such a philosophy, the relations that connect experiences must themselves be experienced relations, and any kind of relation experienced must be accounted as ‘real’ as anything else in the system.25
64
The Educative Process
Such relations as conjunction and disjunction, causality, contiguity, and resistance, for example, are proper objects of human experience, and where experience itself is conceived as a ‘stream of thought’ or consciousness (to use James’ term26) rather than a succession of discrete perceptions. The problem that the older empiricism faced of how to link together an array of experiential atoms in a fashion that is non-speculative and empirically sound, for James and Dewey alike, is a pseudo-problem that is premised on a phenomenologically inadequate and altogether artificial conception of how human beings encounter their world. Dewey outlined his conception of empiricism, or what in one of his very earliest works from 1886 he termed ‘the psychological standpoint’, as follows: We are not to determine the nature of reality or of any object of philosophical inquiry by examining it as it is in itself, but only as it is an element in our knowledge, in our experience, only as it is related to our mind, or is an ‘idea’. . . . [T]he nature of all objects of philosophical inquiry is to be fixed by finding out what experience says about them.27 Dewey would never waver in his commitment to radical empiricism and to Jamesian psychology, and would return to the general theme of experience and its implications for philosophy throughout his career, repeating as late as 1949 the basic point that ‘my philosophical view, or theory, of experience does not include any existence beyond the reach of experience’.28 The proper objects of awareness, that is, what our experience ultimately is an experience of, are not observations or what the British empiricists had called ‘ideas’, but things, relations, and the ‘dynamic continuities’ between objects. As a thing of this world, experience is no crossing of an ontological divide but is ‘bound up with the movement of things by most intimate and pervasive bonds’, and ‘is of necessity a matter of ties and connexions, of bearings and uses’.29 The world as it is disclosed in our lived experience is very different from the particularistic or atomistic world of the earlier empiricism and closer, if not altogether identical, to the lifeworld of phenomenology – a world of connections, continuities, and meaningful relations of a myriad kinds. The empiricism of James and Dewey rejected both the age-old depreciation of experience and the separation of the rational from the experiential, preferring to speak of the latter in terms variously describable as phenomenological, naturalistic, or holistic. Human experience is most aptly spoken of in its verbal connotation as a doing as well as an undergoing, a continual process of acting and reacting, synthesizing and transforming an environment rather than merely suffering or passively registering sense impressions. Reason is not an extra-empirical faculty or method but is rather inherent to
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
65
the interaction of the human organism and its world, a part of the process by which human life sustains itself and negotiates its way about an environment on a model that is at once biological and social. The concepts of rational thought are neither Descartes’ clear and distinct ideas nor Kant’s a priori categories nor innate ideas; instead they are historical and linguistic constructions that fundamentally structure our experience. Dewey anticipated in some ways the new accent on language that would prevail in phenomenological, hermeneutical, and other philosophical traditions throughout the twentieth century in drawing attention to the linguistic and interpretive dimension of human thought. Thus in Reconstruction in Philosophy, Dewey wrote: The conceptions that are socially current and important become the child’s principles of interpretation and estimation long before he attains to personal and deliberate control of conduct. Things come to him clothed in language, not in physical nakedness, and this garb of communication makes him a sharer in the beliefs of those about him. These beliefs coming to him as so many facts form his mind; they furnish the centers about which his own personal expeditions and perceptions are ordered. Here we have ‘categories’ of connection and unification as important as those of Kant, but empirical not mythological.30 This important passage – which owes as much to James as to Hegel – not only anticipates a great deal of later twentieth-century philosophy but puts in question the orthodox empiricism of Hobbes, Locke, and Hume. The empirical is now to be theorized in terms of James’ ‘stream of thought’ or consciousness, as an organic and synthetic process by which human beings find their way about the world. The rationality that, for Dewey, is immanent to human experience is what he termed ‘experimental intelligence’, a rather expansive concept which I shall analyze in more detail in Chapter 3. If the older empiricism erred in its conception of mind as a passive and prelinguistic receptacle of sensory data, the new empiricism would accentuate the active and synthetic dimension of experience that Dewey articulated in his concept of the experimental. It is the nature of experience to be at once passive and active, not merely to receive sensory input but actively to interpret, categorize, and transform it in the manner of an experiment directed toward a pragmatic end. Particular sensations are not self-enclosed units but rather ‘points of adjustment’ by which consciousness is organized in an organic and dialectical fashion into a larger flow of perceptions all of which are ultimately subservient to, or indeed are, the life of the organism. Experience in this sense is life itself, the growth or being-in-motion of a worldly subjectivity.31 It is an experience that
66
The Educative Process
is temporal and adaptive, that adjusts itself to objects in the world while simultaneously transforming them to suit its own purposes, and that is continually growing and expanding. Experience is ‘an affair of the intercourse of a living being with its physical and social environment’.32 Such ‘intercourse’, to use one of Dewey’s favorite expressions, is to be understood not solely in biological or evolutionary terms but in social and cultural terms as well. The human being is a social animal in every facet of its being, and is by no means the worldless atom of Hobbesian lore (a theme that Dewey frequently discussed in his ethical and political writings33). The experimental model of experience and rationality finds its highest expression in scientific investigation wherein inquiry is both a social practice of co-operative experimentation and dialogical reciprocity as well as an empirical inquiry into the constitution of our environment. While the experimental attitude seeks knowledge regarding the way the world is, it is not limited to this but aims as well at achieving a high degree of control. If experience, as Dewey put it, ‘is a matter of simultaneous doings and sufferings’, and thus includes both an active and a passive dimension, its active side consists of interaction with an environment that is, again, conceived on the model of biological life.34 Experience has a vitality about it that impels the subject of experience to take action in pursuit of its ends rather than merely to receive impressions or perhaps adapt to the world as it is encountered. Every living creature, while it is awake, is in constant interaction with its surroundings. It is engaged in a process of give and take, of doing something to objects around it and receiving back something from them – impressions, stimuli. This process of interacting constitutes the framework of experience.35 The successful negotiation of experience issues in a kind of growth in which one stage leads into the next or prepares the conditions for future experiences. An intelligent agent uses its experiences from the past to transform conditions in which future experiences will occur, thus establishing partial control over the direction its future will take. Scientific experimentation is the most explicit instance of a rationality implicit in all intelligently directed awareness, one in which a particular set of observations and conclusions generates a hypothesis that in turn directs the course of future inquiry, and that opens up new paths of experience while closing off others. Dewey also spoke of experience in a more emphatic connotation, most notably in his writings on art and aesthetics.36 These are experiences that we speak of in ordinary language in their singularity; we speak of ‘an experience’ in an emphatic and particular sense to set it apart from the ordinary course of events and to give it a special significance. This may be a learning
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
67
experience or some other culmination of a larger experiential process. If it is the nature of experience to include a certain orientation and purposiveness then it may either fulfil its course or fail to do so. The project that we take up may fail in its purpose or lead toward a dead end; it may become misdirected, lose its bearings, or otherwise fail to lead anywhere that we would wish to go. Alternatively, a course of experience may reach an important culmination – a purpose realized, a destination reached, a lesson learned. It is the latter that Dewey spoke of as ‘an experience’ in a singular and emphatic connotation and which, he maintained, has special relevance in the interpretation of art and aesthetic experience. Returning now to education, if it is the students’ experience that affords the appropriate point of departure for educational practice rather than a curriculum that is altogether ready made and imposed from on high, then the notion of interest assumes a special importance. The learning process as it takes shape within an institutional setting properly begins from the same starting point from which learning occurs in ordinary life: the existing, vital interests of the young. While Dewey qualified this statement in important ways, he was adamant in rejecting the customary view according to which it is effort rather than interest that is of optimal importance in education. On traditional views, effort and self-discipline in a rather advanced degree are urgent requirements of education since these qualities produce a vigorous and resolute temperament whereas education that is organized around students’ interests molds character in the opposite direction, toward egoism, self-indulgence, and indolence. Children’s interests in particular are superficial, non-educative, and fleeting, conventional views have it. Students must cultivate habits that will be useful in later life, and if left to pursue their natural impulses this will occur only by chance. The purpose of education, conventional wisdom maintains, is very nearly the opposite of cultivating the given interests of students (unless they be at a post-secondary level, although even this is strongly qualified): it is to train the mind to be capable of exerting effort to complete tasks that it may not find particularly interesting or enjoyable. Intellectual maturity requires the cultivation of such dispositions no less than the acquisition of information. In his typically dialectical way, Dewey rejected not the traditional concentration on effort altogether but the dichotomy of effort versus interest to which conservatives and progressives both subscribed. The process of formal education must begin somewhere, whether we are speaking of a young child entering elementary school or an adult entering the university. At whatever stage of maturity they may be, students enter upon the educative process with a formidable baggage of experience, interests, and capacities, and never as a Lockean tabula rasa upon which the educator can simply set to work impressing information, likely with the admixture of whatever degree of
68
The Educative Process
discipline is necessary to ensure attention and behavioral decorum. If attention and the will to learn are necessary conditions of education, these conditions are not met by externally imposed discipline alone or when students are compelled to ingest information almost against their will. Where it is present, a genuine will to learn arises on the basis of lived experience and the interests that it incorporates. The failure of the older view, Dewey held, is visible not only theoretically but practically as well, in the motivation deficit noted above and in the manner in which knowledge is so often illdigested and quickly forgotten after the examination period ends. The motivation to seek and retain knowledge is present only when it acquires a grounding in the ‘existing natural interests’ of students, and while it is undoubtedly the case that some such interests will be fleeting and superficial – most obviously at the elementary level – it remains that ‘they are all there is, so to speak, to the child; they are all the teacher has to appeal to; they are the starting points, the initiatives, the working machinery’.37 As with so many of Dewey’s hypotheses, this one was promptly misunderstood by critics and progressives alike to entail that educators are to regard such interests as sacrosanct, as desires to be appeased for their own sake rather than directed along properly educative lines. The purpose of education, Dewey was well aware, is not to entertain or amuse but to learn. The question is what conditions make such learning possible, and the answer must include enlisting existing interests into forms of inquiry that lead from old interests to new and more sophisticated ones. Interests are pursued not for their own sake or for the sake of any pleasure that may attend them but for that to which they lead if appropriately interpreted and harnessed. The widespread misunderstanding of Dewey’s position on this matter is surprising given how explicitly and how often he articulated the point from his earlier to his later writings. In 1896, for instance, he wrote: ‘And the teacher who always utilizes interest will never merely indulge it. Interest in its reality is a moving thing, a thing of growth, of richer experience, and fuller power. Just how to use interest to secure growth in knowledge and in efficiency is what defines the master teacher.’38 One senses a clear note of exasperation on Dewey’s part when in 1938 he was compelled to reiterate the point yet again: In an educational scheme, the occurrence of a desire and impulse is not the final end. It is an occasion and a demand for the formation of a plan and method of activity. Such a plan, to repeat, can be formed only by study of conditions and by securing all relevant information.39 It should have gone without saying, although for many of Dewey’s casual readers it did not, that no little effort is an inevitable part of the learning
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
69
process, that discipline and rigor are fundamental to the pedagogical practice of directing interests within certain channels in view of the educator’s knowledge. Interest is the starting point of education, but in order for the process to advance it must lead into lines of inquiry that require concentration, perseverance, and intellectual discipline. Where traditional views had erred was not in prizing effort or the disciplined mind but in misconceiving the conditions that make this possible. A worthy goal may be undermined by the means used to pursue it, as is the case when the older practice of emphasizing drill and rote learning creates a docile and unimaginative mind. As Dewey was well aware from his own experience as a student, children educated in the traditional manner can be remarkably adept at giving the appearance of effort and attention while the mind wanders the moment the teacher’s gaze is no longer fixed upon them. The only guarantee of attention is when students see for themselves the relevance of the subject matter to life and to that in which they take an unforced interest. Without this condition in place, we fashion not the virile character so prized by the conservative philosophy but ‘a character dull, mechanical, unalert, because the vital juice of spontaneous interest has been squeezed out’ or ‘the narrow, bigoted man who is obstinate and irresponsible save in the line of his own preconceived aims and beliefs’.40 For Dewey, it is a mystifying proposition that discipline should be effectively gained only when the mind studies a subject matter more or less against its will rather than on the basis of intelligent interest. If conservatives would sometimes concede the need to ‘make it interesting’ by identifying pedagogical techniques that make the curriculum more palatable to young minds, it remained for Dewey that in the absence of a vital connection between the subject matter and students’ interests such techniques can only serve as the sugar coating on a bitter pill. Having identified the point of departure of the educative process as the experience and interests that students bring with them into the classroom, everything in education then depends upon that to which such interests lead. It is here that the educator’s role is vital in directing or redirecting these interests along properly educative lines. If the traditional practice had trained the young to imitate prematurely ‘the fixed pattern of adult habits of thought and affection’, Dewey’s proposal was that schools not regard children as little adults but instead concentrate on guiding their experience by centering an interest on a particular end.41 It is in the nature of experience and interest alike that one thing, as we say, leads to another; when appropriately directed, a relatively narrow and pedestrian interest can lead into an organized activity or inquiry that broadens the scope of that interest and introduces an intelligent ordering of experiences. In an important passage from a short book of 1912, Interest and Effort in Education, Dewey
70
The Educative Process
asked his readers to recall how their present intellectual interests originally took shape. What occurs is that an interest, usually limited in scope, leads beyond itself into a larger sequence of activities, a project or investigation into the whys and wherefores surrounding it. Questions arise as to an object’s composition, history, or implications in one direction or another, and an organized subject matter arises. What we find, as Dewey put it, is that wherever his activities have grown in extent and range of meaning (instead of becoming petrified and fossilized) . . . narrower and simpler types of interest (requiring a shorter time for their realization) have been expanding to cover a longer time. With this change they have become richer and fuller.42 A given interest can grow well beyond its original context as new questions are formed and inquiries undertaken. With the passage of time the original interest is outgrown and replaced with a series of other, more sophisticated ones. A subject matter that had been regarded with indifference when viewed solely as an abstract matter can take on urgency when it is shown to arise out of a series of activities and interests that already engage the student, while immature interests are superseded. Thus a child’s interest in his or her home and neighborhood can lead into an interest in the larger town, into the town’s history or geography, and subsequently into the history or geography of the native country, continent, and so on. In time, the child’s interest in history may develop into one in larger historical patterns, the history of other civilizations, or intellectual history. A child’s interest in the parents’ hardware store may grow into a larger curiosity about economics, accounting, or political economy; a childish interest in paint, for instance, may develop into an interest in its physical or chemical composition, and in time into dimensions of chemistry or physics far afield from paint. An attachment to an old article of furniture may grow into an interest in antiques or the history of furniture or architectural styles, into the trade of cabinetmaking or woodworking, and so on.43 The examples may be easily multiplied, and the point that they illustrate is the interconnectedness of human activities and, due to this, the organic nature in which interests develop from relative immaturity to progressive sophistication. Outside of an academic setting, interests may develop quite spontaneously on the basis of lived experience alone and occurrences that may be entirely happenstance. However, within these settings it is the business of educators to guide intellectual development by redirecting interests and not, as some progressives took Dewey to imply, by leaving students at complete liberty to do as they will. While it is a mistake for a teacher to dominate the course of inquiry by directing students’ interests along lines that suit only the purpose
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
71
of the teacher rather than the students, the mistake is not remedied by a swing to the opposite extreme in which the teacher takes no active part in the process. In his later years Dewey would criticize many progressives for falling into the second error while traditionalists had committed the first: Sometimes teachers seem to be afraid even to make suggestions to the members of a group as to what they should do. I have heard of cases in which children are surrounded with objects and materials and then left entirely to themselves, the teacher being loath to suggest even what might be done with the materials lest freedom be impinged upon.44 While freedom to choose activities and lines of inquiry is an important part of the learning process, this gives rise not to a laissez-faire policy but, on the contrary, to a specific conception of the educator’s role in the classroom: as a leader or director of inquiry rather than dictator or passive onlooker (an issue to which I shall return). Since the educator has a larger scope of knowledge and breadth of experience than the students, it falls to him or her to introduce an intelligent order or plan of activity that will lead a given interest in the direction of an inquiry that is likely to bear fruit in the form of a discovery, the acquisition of knowledge, or the enlarging of horizons. Most often the direction such inquiry takes is from the narrow to the broad, from the concrete to the abstract, from the particular to the universal, and from the practical to the theoretical. If a student’s immediate interest pertains more often to the former in each of these pairings, the educator’s role is to lead it in the direction of the latter or toward any experience that is properly educative. In the course of intellectual development the latter may gain an importance to the students that is quite remote from the original, childish interest that had first occasioned reflection. This, for Dewey, is the nature or general pattern of maturation. One does not take an interest in theoretical matters at any stage of intellectual development unless the ground has been prepared in the practical and experiential. Whether it is elementary mathematics or university-level philosophy, a new interest takes hold when it is rooted firmly in an existing one and cannot be plastered on by clever pedagogy. Educators are well familiar with the phenomenon of the student whose mind appears utterly impervious to a new theoretical subject matter. What difference does it make, the student will unfailingly ask, whether we are rationalists or empiricists, realists or antirealists, foundationalists or antifoundationalists, interactionists or epiphenomenalists? For the professor the question is pedestrian and perhaps insulting; the answer is selfevident, he or she will declare. For the student, of course, it is anything but, and the issue has every appearance of perfect irrelevance. The chasm that can separate the educator from the student on such matters most often
72
The Educative Process
pertains not to a simple difference in intelligence level, as the former is often inclined to suppose, but to the fact that the professor has long since stopped asking the question, having perceived its experiential ramifications and become convinced over the course of time that it is not only an important question but indeed the question on which all else turns, perhaps even the only important question that remains for theorists in the field (a phenomenon with which, I trust, we are all familiar). A theoretical interest may become an end in itself (and indeed can deteriorate into scholasticism), yet its origin remains pragmatic and experiential, a principle that Dewey again conceived on the model of organic growth. ‘There is no difference’, he maintained, ‘between the growth of a plant and the prosperous development of an experience’, where such development proceeds from the practical to the theoretical and from the concrete to the abstract.45 This conception of growth or of intellectual development as growth is one example of a larger principle of continuity which together with the principle of interaction constitute Dewey’s criteria for an experience to qualify as educative. Not all experiences have educational value, he insisted, but only those that meet certain conditions. Here again is an issue on which Dewey’s critics and disciples alike would often misread him, taking him to intend that any experience, no matter how trivial, may be appropriately pursued in the classroom so long as students find it interesting. Dewey, of course, never countenanced this view – which he regarded as self-evidently silly – and with evident consternation set about to correct yet another misinterpretation in Experience and Education. There he repeated that the direction in which the educator ought to guide the students is toward experiential continuity or toward a continuing and habitual process of intellectual growth. ‘[T]he principle of continuity of experience’, he wrote, ‘means that every experience both takes up something from those which have gone before and modifies in some way the quality of those which come after.’ Educative experience takes an existing interest as its point of departure, but it must lead somewhere, in the direction of new questions and discoveries. The students’ future must be uppermost in the mind of the educator, yet not in the sense that what they are presently learning is solely a preparation for what will some day prove useful but that what is currently being taught and learned will generate a momentum that will continue in the future course of intellectual maturation. With this in mind the teacher arranges for experiences and lines of inquiry that can be anticipated to lead to further learning. It is the very nature of experience to lead beyond itself and to orient one toward what is to follow. Since ‘every experience lives on in further experiences’, rather than being a disconnected happening, ‘the central problem of an education based upon experience is to select the kind of present experiences that live fruitfully and creatively in subsequent experiences’.46
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
73
Of special importance in this connection is the cultivation of habits of thought and conduct that will ensure an enduring interest in a field of knowledge and a capacity to develop new interests. The idea of education as crucially involving habit formation, of course, has clear roots in the educational thought of Plato and Aristotle and is repeated with great regularity throughout the history of the philosophy of education. Dewey is no exception in this regard, arguing that the habit of thought itself and the abiding curiosity that sustains it are among the marks of an educated mind. It is not uncommon for students to say of a certain subject matter that they have ‘taken it’, with the implication that the matter is over and done with. University students, for instance, who have received credit for an introductory course surveying Western intellectual history from ancient Greece to yesterday often report that they ‘have taken’ Plato, Descartes, or Freud – likely for a class or two each coupled with a textbook introduction to their thought and perhaps a handful of selected passages from the thinker him- or herself – and that since the important information has been registered and retained long enough to pass an examination, the subject is behind them. No interest in further inquiry remains, nor even a sense of why this might be desirable. For Dewey, it is an indication of educational failure when ‘a student does not take into subsequent life an enduring concern for some field of knowledge and art, lying outside his immediate profession preoccupations’, and irrespective of ‘how good a “student”’ he or she was or how successful the examination.47 This is counted as a failure because of the habits both instilled – in this case of regarding ideas as soundbites and great texts as capable of being distilled into small doses or flattened out entirely into textbook descriptions – and not instilled – an enduring sense of the importance of ideas and the continuing relevance of classic texts. So much of mental life is governed by habit that it is difficult to overestimate its importance in the learning process. Habits of thought formed in childhood can control the life of the mind – from its fundamental orientation to its capacity for attention, its tastes and sense of what is important – throughout life and can be remarkably resistant to change at later stages of intellectual development. The habits of mind that take shape at a relatively early developmental level, as Dewey noted, ‘are usually deepest and most unget-at-able just where critical thought is most needed – in morals, religion and politics’ – a point to which I shall return in later chapters.48 The survival of habits associated with the immature mind into adulthood severely limits the individual’s capacity for new experiences and most often results in a permanent arrest in intellectual growth. An early plasticity and openness of mind settles into a defined set of inclinations which actively seek occasions for expression and have a controlling influence on later experience.49 This is exemplified in the will to learn itself, which may be urgent and enduring
74
The Educative Process
throughout life or entirely lifeless, but in either case is an habitual matter. If continuity marks the first criterion of educative experience, Dewey’s second criterion is what he referred to as the principle of interaction, where this signifies the integration or the hanging together of different experiences in a coherent configuration. It is the nature of mature experience to display not only continuity from one course of inquiry or activity to the next but also an interaction between conditions both external and internal to the individual which comprise a given situation. ‘Any normal experience’, as Dewey expressed it, ‘is an interplay of these two sets of conditions’, that is, of the ‘objective’ conditions that belong to an educational situation and the conditions that are ‘internal’ to the mental life of the inquirer.50 If traditional educational methods erred in ignoring the importance of conditions internal to the individual student, or ‘what he is at a given time’, progressives made the opposite error of ignoring objective conditions.51 The two principles of continuity and interaction are not altogether separate in meaning and still less so in their applications since both refer to the essential connectedness of human experience and speak against the experiential atomism of orthodox empiricism. If experience is experimental then there is a flexible give and take between the inquirers themselves and the situation that is to be inquired into, and it is the combination of these two principles that marks an experience as properly educative. By the same token, then, a miseducative experience is one that fails to promote the continued development of students’ minds. It is the experience that leads nowhere, either to a dead end or, what is worse, to the promotion of mental habits that block the path of future learning. Examples of the former include undertakings that students find ‘interesting’ merely in the sense of being entertaining without broadening horizons or culminating in anything beyond immediate enjoyment, while the latter includes a broad range of classroom experiences the net effect of which is the narrow and dulled state of mind that Dewey associated with traditional education. While the traditional methods undoubtedly give rise to experiences, they are too often miseducative both in the sense that they fail to connect with extracurricular experience and that they ‘deaden and stupefy’ the mental life of the young in ways that often become habitual and irreversible.52 The mind that is inattentive and indifferent to matters that are not immediately rewarding, that is incurious, unimaginative, or uncritically obedient to authority is the usual outcome of conservative educational methods, Dewey and the progressives maintained. Yet while other progressives were asserting that experiences of most any kind simply are not had in traditional schools, Dewey’s critique was that they are indeed had but that they are of the wrong kind. As he wrote, in a passage hardly less relevant today than in 1938:
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
75
How many students, for example, were rendered callous to ideas, and how many lost the impetus to learn because of the ways in which learning was experienced by them? How many acquired special skills by means of automatic drill so that their power of judgment and capacity to act intelligently in new situations was limited? How many came to associate the learning process with ennui and boredom? How many found what they did learn so foreign to the situations of life outside the school as to give them no power of control over the latter? How many came to associate books with dull drudgery, so that they were ‘conditioned’ to all but flashy reading matter?53 The distinction, then, between the educative and the non- or miseducative turns upon the relation of a given experience to further experience, including both what is prior to it and that to which it leads. The role of the educator, accordingly, is not to be the passive bystander in the classroom that many progressives mistakenly took Dewey to be recommending, nor to be the classic authoritarian of the traditional philosophy, but to take up an intermediate position or perhaps a higher synthesis of the two extremes. Whether in the elementary school or the university, the educator is a leader of inquiry and director of the kind of activities that he or she can anticipate will lead in a direction that is worth pursuing, whether for the knowledge that is to be gained, the intellectual habits it will instill, or the capacities it will develop. In many ways, then, the educator’s role is far more difficult than has traditionally been thought, and extends beyond mastering the subject matter or knowing effective pedagogical techniques and perhaps disciplinary methods to include a knowledge of the students themselves, of their psychology and life experience, of the various avenues toward which a given curriculum may lead, and in general of the larger trajectory of which the present inquiry is a part. It extends as well to knowing the obstacles in a student’s psychology or social background that can adversely affect their ability to learn, the different styles of learning, and related issues that traditional methods had overlooked. The ultimate concern of the educator as Dewey conceived of it thus accords fully with the etymology of the word ‘education’ itself, a term that connotes both ‘a drawing out’ and ‘a leading forth’.54 Human intelligence is drawn out precisely by a leading forth of the student from what they have experienced to what they might yet experience. This process of intellectual development or growth may unfold outside of the classroom environment, but the true business of the teacher and professor is to carry the process forward in a way that is not dependent on chance occurrences in the students’ out-of-school environment and to lead them toward any experience or knowledge that enhances the capacity to learn after the period of formal education ends.
76
The Educative Process
Intellectual virtues and vices What the educative process ultimately aims to achieve has traditionally been viewed as something external to that process itself: a sum of knowledge and habits that will be instrumental in later life, particularly in the individual’s efforts to gain a livelihood, to achieve social respectability, or to carry on a tradition. Education so conceived is a means to ends variously pertaining to career, class, or creed, and in no important sense is to be considered an end in itself. When stated plainly, this view might be associated more with the past than the present, yet evidence of its persistence is easily found, from the university student majoring in a discipline within the arts or humanities who is compelled to admit with embarrassment that they do not know what they are going to ‘do’ with their degree, to the politician who is continually warning of the economic perils that await if test scores in mathematics and the sciences are permitted to fall behind other nations. Even that last bastion of the ‘useless degree’, the department of philosophy, is now regularly compelled to include in its marketing material and its website dubious information regarding the practical advantages of a degree in this field and the glorious careers that their graduates have gone on to achieve. The view, in short, that a university degree is essentially a means to an end – which may also, as a secondary matter, yield less tangible benefits or even be inherently rewarding for a few eccentric characters – remains widespread if it is not indeed the majority belief. The plausibility of this view is evident enough: formal education is indeed instrumentally valuable in any number of respects, particularly as it concerns earning qualifications necessary for certain careers. The question, however, is whether the aims of education are limited to the order of instrumental values or whether there is something more to it than this, a higher purpose that is inherent to the educative process itself and to which its utilitarian value is ultimately subordinate. I wish to defend the latter view in a manner that is roughly consistent with Dewey if it is not in the end altogether identical. I shall argue that there is a conception of experience and of ‘being experienced’ that is still more expansive than Dewey’s experimental view as well as a conception of the intellectual virtues that accords with the spirit of Dewey’s thought while hopefully advancing a step beyond its letter. The ‘something more’ to education that transcends its practical utility may be conceived as a set of intellectual virtues, dispositions, and habits that are indispensable ingredients of the educated mind. In broad terms this is the position that Dewey defended as well, in opposition to the more conventional views alluded to above – that formal education is essentially an instrumentally valuable training for later life. Dewey’s Copernican revolution reorients the practices of teaching and learning to
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
77
students’ experience and the conditions of its further development, yet even revolutions gain their orientation from the ancien régime to which they are a response and typically remain in the latter’s orbit long after the revolution has taken place. If this is observable in political history it is equally evident in the fashioning of philosophical positions which inevitably retain traces of that in opposition to which they were originally formulated. Dewey’s radical reformulation of the philosophy of education is no exception to this, although I would urge this point not as a critique of Dewey’s position but as a reminder of the manner in which we ought to interpret and ultimately come to terms with it. How, then, did Dewey reply to the question regarding the ‘something more’ that the educative process properly aims to achieve beyond the obvious practical benefits associated with career preparation and perhaps social respectability – in the conventional sense of ascending to a higher rung on the socio-economic ladder? His answer turned upon his notion of intellectual growth or what in different contexts he referred to as the ‘spirit of inquiry’, the ‘spirit of curiosity’, and ‘the quality of mental process’ that he distinguished from ‘the production of correct answers’.55 Education aims at producing minds that are not merely capable of entering the workforce or respectable society, or that have amassed a certain body of information, but that possess the capacity and inclination to learn more in the course of future experience. The educated mind is characterized by particular intellectual virtues and by the absence of corresponding vices. What exactly these virtues and vices are is the question to which I now turn. Throughout his writings on education and on some related issues, Dewey made frequent reference to a fundamental attitude of mind or intellectual posture that is the mark of educational success as well as to its antithesis. The following passages are representative: A person who has gained the power of reflective attention, the power to hold problems, questions, before the mind, is in so far, intellectually speaking, educated. He has mental discipline – power of the mind and for the mind. Without this the mind remains at the mercy of custom and external suggestions.56 The best thing that can be said about any special process of education, like that of the formal school period, is that it renders its subject capable of further education: more sensitive to conditions of growth and more able to take advantage of them. Acquisition of skill, possession of knowledge, attainment of culture are not ends: they are marks of growth and means to its continuing.57
78
The Educative Process But intellectual growth means constant expansion of horizons and consequent formation of new purposes and new responses. These are impossible without an active disposition to welcome points of view hitherto alien; an active desire to entertain considerations which modify existing purposes. Retention of capacity to grow is the reward of such intellectual hospitality. The worst thing about stubbornness of mind, about prejudices, is that they arrest development; they shut the mind off from new stimuli. Open-mindedness means retention of the childlike attitude; closed-mindedness means premature intellectual old age.58
The conception of the educated mind that emerges in Dewey’s writings remained consistent throughout his long career and is in many ways an outgrowth of his instrumentalist or pragmatic theory of knowledge. Flexibility, open-mindedness, originality, persistence, and an active curiosity are some of the principal Deweyan virtues. In both his conception of educational success and in his philosophical outlook more broadly, Dewey prized the intellectual disposition that is forward-looking, hospitable to new ideas, undogmatic, and in particular that is given more to constructive problem-solving than to critique in the negative sense of fault finding. Beyond this, the educated mind is reflective in the sense that it is capable of ‘turning a subject over in the mind and giving it serious and consecutive consideration’.59 It is unhurried, contemplative, and would sooner examine a matter in depth than arrive at conclusions quickly and superficially. It is careful, attentive, able to maintain concentration, and self-controlled. It possesses the capacity for good judgment in the sense not only that one is able to follow procedures laid out in advance but that one has a sense of the problem or question before one, an understanding of its larger significance, and is able to ‘grasp the scene or situation before him, ignoring what is irrelevant, or what for the time being is unimportant, who can seize upon the factors which demand attention, and grade them according to their respective claims’.60 The judicious mind is able to estimate degrees of importance and is neither indifferent to what is weighty nor preoccupied by trivia. Additionally, Dewey spoke of the educated mind as capable of ‘reconstructing’ its experiences in the sense of reorganizing and reinterpreting it in ways that infuse it with meaning. To reconstruct one’s experience is to be capable of learning from it and integrating whatever insight one is able to gain from past experience for the future. Having integrated the lessons of the past, be it one’s personal past or the larger lessons of history or previous inquiry, one is able to apply this knowledge in imposing direction and a degree of control over the future rather than remain at the mercy of events. One is capable of anticipating what is to come, planning, fending off disaster, or generally applying what one has learned for the enrichment of the future.
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
79
Successful education fashions a mind that is not overly specialized or narrow in its horizons, that is passionate in its interests and not overly discriminating in the matters in which it takes an interest. Dewey cited with full approval a remark by John Stuart Mill that ‘the cultivated mind . . . finds sources of inexhaustible interest in all that surrounds it; in the objects of nature, the achievements of art, the imaginations of poetry, the incidents of history, the ways of mankind, past, present and their prospects in the future’.61 There is a certain restlessness of mind and passion for questioning that Dewey held in particularly high esteem and certainly displayed himself in his voluminous writings on just about every philosophical subdiscipline and every political issue that he ever encountered. He both prized and exhibited in himself an enthusiasm for ideas in a great many domains and a capacity to develop new interests, whether they be of a narrowly academic or non-academic nature. The matter of desire was of such importance to Dewey that he would speak of its communication from educator to student as ‘the one thing most needful’ in education since it is the passion for ideas themselves, far more than the instilling of information or beliefs, that is the driving force behind the students’ continuing intellectual development beyond their years at the university.62 The virtues of mind that represent, for Dewey, the highest achievement of the educative process also go beyond the narrowly intellectual to include the emotional and, still more, the social. Good judgment and the passion for inquiry itself are at once intellectual, emotional, and social virtues; they are habits of mind that lead one into co-operative discussion with others rather than lock the self within its own inner confines. Curiosity, for instance, draws the self into forms of intellectual exchange that challenge one’s convictions and reveal the nature of ideas as hypotheses rather than dogmatic certainties. We are challenged toward self-reflection and inventiveness precisely through co-operative inquiry and participation in shared undertakings of various kinds and by having our own ideas challenged in conversation.63 By the same token, good judgment is no merely logical operation of thought but includes a certain ‘emotional responsiveness’ that informs our ethical knowledge and ensures the capacity to put into operation whatever judgments we form regarding the good or the true.64 Democracy and the democratic character are terms that Dewey employed with great frequency to express the social dimension of education, where they signify less a political creed than an ethos of co-operative discussion, respect for differences of opinion, and other social virtues associated with democratic citizenship. Democracy and Education, as well as being the title of one of his most important educational works, are completely intertwined notions as they pertain both to the political and to the educational in the narrower, institutional sense of the term – a topic to which I shall return in Chapter 7.
80
The Educative Process
The intellectual vices that for Dewey are the marks of educational failure go well beyond the inability to retain information or understand difficult concepts to include inflexibility of mind, dogmatism, narrowness of horizon, parochialism, inattention, conventionality, and apathy, among others. The over-reliance on custom and deference to authority which the old education had instilled produce a docility of mind that leaves one at the mercy of intellectual fashion and ill-equipped to challenge the orthodoxy of the times. It was a serious worry of Dewey’s that the general populations of America and Europe had become too unresisting to political propaganda in particular, and it is less the politicians than the educational institutions that are the culprit. Rather than instilling the spirit of inquiry, educators in most any field teach the art of acceptance – of received wisdom, information, or the educator’s beliefs – and an unquestioning attitude toward ideas that are presented to students in the guise of facts rather than hypotheses and instruments of analysis. The resulting disposition is one to which it does not occur that there is any need for questioning, one that lacks a capacity to discern what is questionable and what is not. If the ‘natural tendency of man is not to press home a doubt, but to cut inquiry as short as possible’, this tendency is aided and abetted by educational practices that breed intellectual laziness and passive acceptance of controversial hypotheses as orthodox fact.65 Another intellectual failing upon which Dewey frequently remarked is the tendency toward overspecialization and the academic scholasticism and narrowing of perspective that inevitably follow from this. A certain thoughtlessness accompanies the trend that increasingly conscripts students, educators, professionals, and workers alike into narrow specialties beyond which the individual will often know remarkably little. The important matter of the connections between separate fields of inquiry or the relations between different experiential domains is increasingly unlearned, and not only within the sciences in which this may be thought an inevitable consequence of the advancement of knowledge but within the humanities and the arts no less. Dewey was particularly concerned about the trend toward excessive specialization in his own discipline of philosophy and – as I shall discuss in Chapter 4 – the high price that this and any other field of investigation pays when those within it become uncognizant of all that lies outside a narrow field of expertise. A related phenomenon is the remoteness and disconnection of the university from the broader culture and the irrelevance of so much of what takes place there. As Dewey remarked, ‘it would sometimes seem that only athletic exhibitions form a direct line of connection between the college and the average community life’ – an observation hardly less accurate today than in 1901 when Dewey wrote these words.66 The increasingly blinkered nature of research and subject matter in post-secondary institutions
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
81
renders professors and students alike dangerously indifferent to the larger implications of the inquiries they undertake. Related intellectual vices include the doctrinaire turn of mind that holds its opinions in ridiculously high esteem, that is unmoveable and inflexible regarding whatever orthodoxy it holds dear. The ‘cultivation of openness and flexibility of mind’ was of such importance to Dewey that, as he wrote in one of his very earliest essays, ‘If I were asked what is the chief intellectual defect found in pupils, I should answer, judging from my own experience, lack of flexibility, lack of ability to turn the mind towards new ideas, or look at old ones in new lights.’67 The mind that is self-satisfied and self-certain is as much a symptom of educational failure as the one that is indifferent to ideas, apathetic, thoughtless, or whose thoughts are limited to simple formulas and fashionable sentiments. Were the educative process to be rooted in human experience and unfold in an appropriate environment, Dewey fervently believed, these and other intellectual failings which render the life of the mind impoverished and underdeveloped would be replaced by the open and experimental turn of mind that is the mark of intellectual maturity.
From Erlebnis to Erfahrung The logic of education – the basic ground and orientation that, phenomenologically speaking, always already characterizes the learning process – is the logic of experience. This, in short, is the Copernican revolution that Dewey sought to effect. Education rooted not in students’ lived experience but in notions of preparation for later life, economic or technological efficiency, cultural literacy, or indoctrination into particular beliefs distorts the learning process by displacing its own immanent ends with values imported from outside the process itself. The tendency to distort the learning process in this way, essentially by reducing education to a means of manufacturing subjects of a particular kind (those who believe, value, and act as educational authorities wish), is, I would suggest, the principal failing of a great deal of educational theory and practice and is the root of a myriad more specific failings. The temptation to overlook education’s immanent logic in the zeal to import extraneous ends of one kind or another may well be a universal phenomenon, one resisted as seldom by educational liberals as conservatives. Yet resist it is what must be done if we wish to provide education with a proper grounding. Experience is the starting point of thought; it is what arouses curiosity, gives rise to questioning and interpretation, and motivates minds whether young or old to understand what confronts them in some vital way. Education begins with experience ultimately because it must. A parallel may be found in Heidegger’s answer to the question why interpretation properly operates within the contextual, back-and-forth
82
The Educative Process
structure of the hermeneutic circle. One does not decide to enter the hermeneutic circle; phenomenologically, one is always already thinking within it. The choice to be made is not whether to enter this circle but how to negotiate one’s way within it, how to reconcile part with whole and whole with part in a way that brings about coherence and meaning.68 By the same token, students in educational settings have no choice but to bring their experience into the classroom and to learn on this basis. This is the context in which learning takes place, not any purely rational or ‘academic’ (non-) context of information and blackboard exercises. Were students not beingsin-the-world but computers or perhaps gods, no appeal to experience would be necessary. Yet we must take students as we find them, with a point of view that is at once intellectual, psychological, cultural, and existential, and which is summarized in the notion of experience. A question we must ask in coming to critical terms with Dewey’s philosophy of education is how well his experimental conception of experience stands up today. We may well accept his case for a shift in the ‘center of gravity’ of education while having some reservations about his conception of experience itself. While the conception that Dewey articulated is commendably rich and expansive, particularly in comparison with earlier forms of empiricism, I wish to argue for a still more expansive view, the general contours of which roughly accord with Dewey’s position yet without its somewhat reductionist and scientistic tendencies. Dewey was never inclined toward positivism or any uncritical idolatry of science (despite what certain of his critics alleged), yet he did regard scientific experimentation as the paradigm case of intelligently directed experience.69 We may wish to ask, however, why science should hold so central a place in our understanding of experience rather than, say, the encounter with art or literature or history. Is an educational encounter with literature properly understood in terms of scientific inquiry? If we are so enamored with science that we would wish to answer this question in the affirmative, it would seem to me that we are making the phenomenon fit the theory. A work of literature is an object to be experienced, to be sure, but is it to be inquired into in quite the sense that a physicist inquires into the atom or an astronomer investigates black holes? A negative answer need not prompt us to reject Dewey’s account, but it does raise the question of the limits of experience as experimental intelligence and cause us to inquire further into the concept of experience itself. There may be more to the concept than what Dewey has given us. There may indeed be far more, as becomes evident when we examine the history of the concept of experience in more detail than the cursory overview above. Fortunately we find a guide to this in Martin Jay’s Songs of Experience, in which he endeavors to show that philosophical theories of experience both ancient and modern are ‘as much “songs” of passion as sober analyses’.
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
83
Rather than defending any theoretical account as an altogether accurate description of what experience actually is, Jay makes the interesting suggestion that experience ‘is a signifier that unleashes remarkable emotion in many [including Dewey] who put special emphasis on it in their thought’, and more closely approximates ‘lyrical panegyrics’, ‘elegiac laments’, and ‘bitter denunciations’ than philosophical theories in the usual sense. It is certainly questionable whether experience as conceived of by philosophers constitutes a ‘song’ in Wordsworth’s sense of the word, or any other; however Jay may well be correct in his assertion that ‘because of the term’s ubiquity . . . no totalizing account can hope to do justice to its multiple denotations and connotations over time and in different contexts’.70 Experience is not only a technical term in philosophy but a word in everyday language, and theoretical efforts to explain its meaning must do justice to this fact and to the concept’s interpretive richness rather than reduce it to a single dimension which is purported to be essential. It is highly unlikely that experience has an essence of which we could provide an exhaustive theoretical analysis. What we can expect of philosophy is not this but a more modest interpretation of its significance in certain more important respects, an interpretation that makes no claim to exhaustiveness or finality. Whether Dewey proffered his theory of experience in this spirit or in the more usual, reductionist way is a debatable matter; textual support may be found for either reading. Of more importance for our purposes is whether Dewey’s account, attractive as it is, is sufficient. Hans-Georg Gadamer has noted that ‘the concept of experience seems to me one of the most obscure we have’, an observation with which it is difficult to disagree. In making the word into a technical term, modern epistemology ‘truncates its original meaning’, orienting it too exclusively toward the scientific at the expense of the historical. As Gadamer further noted, In its methodology modern science thus simply proceeds further toward a goal that experience has always striven after. Experience is valid only if it is confirmed; hence its dignity depends on its being in principle repeatable. But this means that by its very nature, experience abolishes its history and thus itself.71 This critique would appear to apply to Dewey as well, although Gadamer himself did not so apply it – presumably for the reason that, like so many other continental philosophers of the twentieth century, he did not read Dewey or the other American pragmatists. Be that as it may, the truncating of the concept of experience that we witness in modern epistemology is a serious matter, and not one that we ought to perpetuate yet again by offering an analysis that purports to separate the concept’s essential from its merely
84
The Educative Process
apparent meaning. Ambiguity cannot always be reduced to zero, nor ought philosophers be quite so anxious to dismiss a concept that cannot be so ‘clarified’ as hopelessly vague. Part of the word’s ineliminable ambiguity is due to the variety of concepts to which it has long been contrasted; reason, theoretical knowledge, naivety, and hope are just a few, and they do not appear to have much in common to which a single concept could stand in opposition. Another complicating factor is of course the history of the word, and not only as it functions within philosophical discourse or for that matter in the English language. The German language includes a rather important distinction between two senses of experience – a distinction, curiously, that never attracted Dewey’s attention. German philosophy of the late nineteenth and twentieth centuries, increasingly dissatisfied with the reduction of experience to an epistemological matter excessively beholden to natural science, began to speak of experience in terms of the distinction between Erlebnis and Erfahrung, where the former connotes a ‘lived experience’ that is pretheoretical and immediate while the latter signifies a larger integration of perceptions and judgments over time. Erlebnis must be understood in terms of its connection with life (Leben); it is an experience of the world that is vital, conceptually undifferentiated, personal, and more than occasionally emotional. Often associated with the sensational and unique, Erlebnis is typically spoken of in its singularity as it arises in the course of everyday life or as an interruption of that life and of the larger projects and habits that comprise it. Experience in this sense is a discrete and intimate possession of the self, an individual occurrence that often leads to no larger configuration of meaning or to any social realities beyond the interiority of consciousness. Gadamer has noted a distinction between two senses of this ambiguous word. Erlebnis, he observed, refers at once to the act of experiencing as well as its object or content: This content is like a yield or result that achieves permanence, weight, and significance from out of the transience of experiencing. Both meanings obviously lie behind the coinage Erlebnis: both the immediacy, which precedes all interpretation, reworking, and communication, and merely offers a starting point for interpretation – material to be shaped – and its discovered yield, its lasting result.72 Experience in this sense, then, must be understood in connection with life rather than in solely epistemological terms. It is an episodic occurrence which, while arising from life, lacks the larger significance and temporal frame that characterizes experience in the second connotation of the word. This is experience as Erfahrung, in the sense that German thinkers such as
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
85
Heidegger and Gadamer would speak of it in twentieth-century phenomenology. Another ambiguous expression, experience in this sense refers to the larger configurations of meaning and temporal duration that Erlebnis is without. Often associated in epistemological terms with perceptions and judgments, Erfahrung took on a less empirical or scientific connotation and a more historical one. It is less concerned with individual happenings than with the larger course of human experience in terms of which those happenings take on meaning. As Jay writes, Erfahrung ‘came to mean a more temporally elongated notion of experience based on a learning process, an integration of discrete moments of experience into a narrative whole or an adventure’.73 The notion of adventure itself exhibits an interesting ambiguity. Gadamer noted: An adventure is by no means just an episode. Episodes are a succession of details which have no inner coherence and for that very reason have no permanent significance. An adventure, however, interrupts the customary course of events, but is positively and significantly related to the context which it interrupts. Thus an adventure lets life be felt as a whole, in its breadth and in its strength. Here lies the fascination of an adventure. It removes the conditions and obligations of everyday life. It ventures out into the uncertain. But at the same time it knows that, as an adventure, it is exceptional and thus remains related to the return of the everyday, into which the adventure cannot be taken. Thus the adventure is ‘undergone’, like a test or trial from which one emerges enriched and more mature. Experience in this sense has a dialectical quality: it exhibits a continual movement back and forth between the particular occurrence and the general context to which that occurrence may be related as either a departure or a continuation but from which it derives whatever meaning is possible for it. Like the dialectical movement of the hermeneutic circle and the basic structure of an adventure as a venturing forth and subsequent return to the everyday, it is from the particular to the universal and vice versa that human experience is played out and understood. Citing Gadamer once more, ‘Every experience is taken out of the continuity of life and at the same time related to the whole of one’s life. . . . Because it is itself within the whole of life, the whole of life is present in it too.’74 Until an individual episode is integrated within a context or larger sequence of experience, it either defies understanding or is intelligible only in an immediate and generally onedimensional way. Experience in the sense of Erfahrung, then, exhibits the temporal continuity and at times progress that individual occurrences do not. It often assumes a larger social significance as well as a narrative structure, incorporating an
86
The Educative Process
ever-increasing number of episodes, social practices, persons, and lessons learned to form a kind of story, albeit one that is likely to be shot through with discordance and contradiction. Insofar as it is understood, experience in this sense resembles a narrative, with a more or less coherent thread of meaning running through it over time and rendering particular happenings significant in view of their contribution to the story. Hermeneutical phenomenologists after Heidegger would often characterize both experience and the human being itself as either having a narrative structure or, more pointedly, as being a narrative. As one understands one’s experience by arranging it into narrative form, or telling a story about it rather than regarding it in its isolated particularity, many in this tradition would also speak of the self as a personal history rather than a stable substance of some kind, be it describable in scientific or metaphysical terms.75 Erfahrung would also be described in this tradition as a transformative experience, in contrast to one that merely is what it is, as it were, or that one undergoes without being in any significant way changed. Experience in this sense is fundamentally a learning experience. It causes a modification in our self-understanding or our understanding of the world in some important respect, transforming old patterns of thinking rather than always confirming them. Gadamer would even maintain that Erfahrung, or experience ‘in the genuine sense’, ‘is initially always experience of negation: something is not what we supposed it to be’.76 Experience either conforms to our expectations or it defies them. In the latter case we are brought up short and compelled to revise whatever anticipations we had brought with us into a given experience, transforming our point of view in large ways or small and causing a reconsideration of what we thought we knew. The negativity of such experience is accordingly productive; it makes possible a more comprehensive knowledge than what we previously had, corrects mistakes, or otherwise makes learning a genuine possibility. Experience that does no more than confirm our anticipations – the perception of the sun rising again this morning, for instance – is not a learning experience, if indeed it is an experience at all. The encounter with art, by contrast, leaves us transformed. It forces a modification in our perceptions, confronts us with what is unexpected or strange, and carries us along in a process that changes us. Here at last we get to the heart of the matter: experience ‘in the genuine sense’, as Gadamer aptly put it, is indeed experimental yet not only in Dewey’s scientific understanding of the word – as investigative, rationally ordered, and solution oriented – but in the sense that it is profoundly transformative. Ultimately it is oneself and one’s point of view that experience transforms, in the sense not only that one has resolved a problematic situation but that one has become changed in one’s being. ‘I am not the person I was’, we say at the conclusion of an experience that is worthy of the name.
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
87
One emerges from it with new insights and a richer understanding or selfunderstanding; one has learned – and not only where this means gaining information or successfully concluding a course of inquiry, but in the sense that one’s stance toward the world has been altered. Gadamer would speak of experience (Erfahrung) and of ‘being experienced’ in terms that accord roughly with Dewey’s view while in a way going beyond it. ‘The truth of experience’, as he wrote, ‘always implies an orientation toward new experience.’ It is neither simply an outcome of a certain kind – the condition of having amassed a tidy sum of facts and observations – nor a method but a posture toward the future. As a result of what one has learned, one is oriented toward future experience with a disposition of openness and curiosity. That is why a person who is called experienced has become so not only through experiences but is also open to new experiences. The consummation of his experience, the perfection that we call ‘being experienced’, does not consist in the fact that someone already knows everything and knows better than anyone else. Rather, the experienced person proves to be, on the contrary, someone who is radically undogmatic; who, because of the many experiences he has had and the knowledge he has drawn from them, is particularly well equipped to have new experiences and to learn from them. The dialectic of experience has its proper fulfilment not in definitive knowledge but in the openness to experience that is made possible by experience itself.77 One certainly hears echoes of Dewey here. He as well spoke of educative experience as disposing one toward future learning, as opening up new pathways for inquiry and arousing curiosities and decidedly not as a process that reaches a final conclusion. The habits of mind that education properly instills dispose us against intellectual self-satisfaction and self-certainty, Dewey always insisted. Because it is the nature of experience that it ‘lives on in further experiences’ rather than being an altogether discrete happening, the decisive matter for educators is ‘to select the kind of present experiences that live fruitfully and creatively in subsequent experiences’.78 What is essential with respect to experience is that to which it leads: further experience, yet in a sense not of more of the same but more of what is different. While the conceptions of experience that these two philosophers defended are hardly identical, it remains that the intellectual virtues that Dewey prized include the phenomenon of which Gadamer spoke, albeit less explicitly. Gadamer’s accent on openness to experience and the transformation of one’s point of view is more pronounced than in Dewey’s writings and occurs in a context quite different from philosophy of education. Gadamer
88
The Educative Process
would also emphasize the dialectical nature of experience in a more Hegelian way than Dewey, the two being profoundly Hegelian thinkers yet in very different ways. As well, Gadamer would always place considerable emphasis on the most un-Deweyan theme of the limits of methodological, and especially scientific, thinking. To say that experience has an experimental and in some ways dialectical quality means for Dewey that it follows a method, one that is broadly applicable and repeatable in principle by any rational agent. While it connotes a process that is open-ended, its essence, as it were, is its methodology. For Gadamer, one of the principal features of experience, or of ‘being experienced’, is precisely a sense of the limits of technique as well as an understanding of human finitude more generally – a theme that did not escape Dewey’s notice but that never made it to the forefront of his thought. That it belongs in the forefront is Gadamer’s point. Exaggerating only slightly, and to good effect, Gadamer remarked: ‘Thus experience is experience of human finitude. The truly experienced person is one who has taken this to heart, who knows that he is master neither of time nor the future. The experienced man knows that all foresight is limited and all plans uncertain.’79 If experience and education alike can be said to culminate in anything, as for both Dewey and Gadamer they can, they culminate for the latter less in the acquisition of methods or solutions to problems than in a knowledge of the limits of human understanding. Above all, they culminate in what Gadamer would call ‘historically effected consciousness’; this is a consciousness that is at once an effect of history – that is constituted by language, beliefs, evaluations, and prereflective understandings that are passed down to us in tradition – and aware of itself as so effected. The person with historically effected consciousness realizes the contingency of the ground on which he or she stands and thus the limits of human reason. It is an awareness of this kind, more than any possession of factual information or even abstract cognitive skills or methods of inquiry, that makes it optimally possible for us to have new experiences. The realization that what is seemingly natural or self-evident is an historical construction – that our moral sense, for instance, disposes us this way and that not because it has grasped some deep truth about morality but owing to centuries of received judgments and popular conceptions, most of them inspired by religion – makes it possible to ask new questions about how what is might be otherwise and to undertake in a creative way the very kind of experimental inquiry that Dewey recommended. A more radical kind of inquiry thus becomes possible, one that regards as problematic situations that had appeared altogether unproblematic and unquestionable, which assumes less and questions more, and more deeply, than was hitherto possible. At the same time one’s capacity for having new experiences is enhanced. It becomes possible to have experi-
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
89
ences that were hitherto impossible because unthinkable. What Gadamer called one’s horizon, in the sense of what is perceivable and thinkable from a finite point of view, is modified and broadened in the course of experience, in the process opening up new possibilities of what can become an experience. What the process culminates in, then, is an explicit awareness of one’s own historicity, or of the extent to which one’s perspective and one’s very being are an historical artifact and accordingly might have been otherwise. To be experienced in this sense – still in the sense of Erfahrung – means to stand to tradition in a certain way: neither to accept everything that is passed down to us unquestioningly nor to reject it in its entirety as the dead weight of the past, but to adopt a disposition that is in a sense intermediate between the two. What Gadamer referred to as ‘the inner historicity of experience’ – precisely that which the reduction to epistemology and science overlooks – causes us to ‘belong’ to tradition in the sense of to participate in it. Being open to experience means being open to the claims that our historical tradition makes upon us and replying to such claims with an intelligent yes or no. Historically effected consciousness keeps itself open to such claims and allows tradition to address one as a Thou – which is to say, as an interlocutor with which one may agree or disagree but which may not be ignored. ‘Openness to the other’, Gadamer continued, . . . involves recognizing that I myself must accept some things that are against me, even though no one else forces me to do so. . . . I must allow tradition’s claim to validity, not in the sense of simply acknowledging the past in its otherness, but in such a way that it has something to say to me. This too calls for a fundamental sort of openness.80 It is an openness or disposition of selective appropriation and critical engagement that directly parallels the open-endedness of experience. In both instances the one who is experienced is equally far removed from the dogmatic closed-mindedness that knows all and so has nothing to learn and from the naive conformity that believes everything it is told. Insofar as experience leads to or culminates in anything, in Gadamer’s view, it ‘culminates not in methodological sureness of itself, but in the same readiness for experience that distinguishes the experienced man from the man captivated by dogma’.81 Dewey would also speak of experience as having a consummatory dimension, albeit in very different terms. In Art as Experience Dewey would speak of experience as culminating in the aesthetic while in an educational context he would always characterize the experiential process essentially as an affair of leading: an existing interest, when properly explored, leads to another one, usually one that is more sophisticated,
90
The Educative Process
abstract, or theoretical than the original. It is largely in virtue of that to which an interest or experience can be anticipated to lead that we judge it educational or non-educational, Dewey would always maintain. Like Gadamer, Dewey placed some emphasis on the continuity of experience as well, albeit in less historical and more scientific terms. As Jay has noted, Dewey’s conception of experience is of ‘an open-ended process of cumulative realization’, adding: ‘In the vocabulary of experience that was not his own, aesthetic experience was thus closer to a dialectical, historically maturing Erfahrung than to an unmediated, instantaneous Erlebnis.’82 The same can be said of educative experience. Here as well we may speak of a ‘process of cumulative realization’ and of ‘historically maturing Erfahrung’, to speak a somewhat more continental language than Dewey preferred. But where Gadamer’s position can be regarded as an advance over Dewey’s is in bringing to the forefront both the distinction between Erlebnis and Erfahrung and interpreting the latter as (or as culminating in) historically effected consciousness. The latter idea, it is interesting to note, is indeed one we find important glimpses of in Dewey’s writings, although it would never become a major theme for him in the way that it would for some of his European counterparts. Much the same can be said of Bildung, a concept classically defined by Johann Gottfried Herder as ‘a process of rising up to humanity through culture’. While Dewey never employed the word, the concept of Bildung can be said to be present in nascent form in many of his writings, although certainly not in the prominent way that it is in Gadamer’s work. It is an idea with roots in the Middle Ages and that came into philosophical prominence in the Hegelian tradition which itself had such a profound effect on Dewey in various aspects of his thought. Bildung is closely related to both culture and form, or the gradual process of formation and self-formation which philosophers such as Hegel and Wilhelm von Humboldt would identify as central to both experience and education. It refers to a process of gradual cultivation from within and to the results of this process, a character that has realized its humanity and come into its own by overcoming those elements of its nature that are immediate or merely given. Be it in formal educational settings or ordinary life, ‘every individual’, in Gadamer’s words, ‘is always engaged in the process of Bildung and in getting beyond his naturalness’. This is accomplished by distancing oneself from the immediacy of desire and the particular and finding one’s way toward the universal. The ‘rising to the universal’ of which philosophers in the Bildung tradition speak is no simple negation of nature, practice, or desire in favor of wholly abstract notions of culture, theory, or reason, however the general orientation of this process is in the direction of the latter.83 Bildung is of the nature of a task or project, and a universal one for human beings. It is the task of rising above one’s immediate nature or circumstances for the sake of a higher purpose, one
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
91
that transcends the self while simultaneously forming or transforming it in the image of the universal. An illustration of this is found in the nature of work. As Hegel described it in The Phenomenology of Spirit, ‘working consciousness’ is no mere means toward economic ends but in an important respect is an end in itself. The essence of work is to lend form and meaning to an object: to take something out of its naturalness and transform it with a view to the universal. Otherwise put, In forming the object – that is, in being selflessly active and concerned with a universal – working consciousness raises itself above the immediacy of its existence to universality; or, as Hegel puts it, by forming the thing it forms itself. What he means is that in acquiring a ‘capacity’, a skill, man gains the sense of himself.84 One works not only, and not essentially, to consume the object of one’s labor but to form it and oneself thereby. One comes into one’s own or fashions oneself precisely by putting oneself aside or, at any rate, those aspects of one’s being that are immediately given and unformed. Following Hegel, Gadamer would also speak of the universal as exacting a demand; one’s commitment to knowledge or justice acts as a restraint on desire and the grosser forms of self-interest, thus imposing a kind of training and order on the self that is difficult and ennobling. This process of inner cultivation – which is to say the process of human experience in general – does not end and has no goals outside of itself. But as much as Bildung refers to the experiential process, it equally refers to its results. The person who is formed in this way has a sense about it: a sense of what is proportionate and important, of what is beautiful or right. Thus the cultivated person has a sense of tact or of the aesthetic which is very different from a technique. One is able to make judgments without following rules and may be quite unable to produce formal arguments to ground them, even as one’s judgments are correct. As Gadamer rather eloquently described the sense of tact, for instance: By ‘tact’ we understand a special sensitivity and sensitiveness to situations and how to behave in them, for which knowledge from general principles does not suffice. Hence an essential part of tact is that it is tacit and unformulable. One can say something tactfully; but that will always mean that one passes over something tactfully and leaves it unsaid, and it is tactless to express what one can only pass over. But to pass over something does not mean to avert one’s gaze from it, but to keep an eye on it in such a way that, rather than knock into it, one slips by it. Thus tact helps one to
92
The Educative Process preserve distance. It avoids the offensive, the intrusive, the violation of the intimate sphere of the person.85
Much the same can be said of the sense of memory. Here too one develops, or fails to develop, a sense of what is memorable. What a good memory is not is an indiscriminate piling up of past experiences in the mind or ability to retrieve them on command. It is a sense of what is worthy of remembrance and a selective retention of this and only this, not of anything and everything. Bildung, then, is marked by the possession of this sense, or senses, and is simultaneously a cultivation of the self and an orientation toward the universal. Experience must therefore be understood dialectically, or in terms of a structural reversal of consciousness. One recognizes oneself – one becomes oneself – in venturing beyond one’s private immediacy and encountering what is other. It is in this encounter that one recognizes oneself, and precisely not by withdrawing into some private sanctum of interiority. One ventures forth in experience and returns a changed being; one has learned, become experienced, and become open to future venturings. Although one has amassed information in the process, this is not what is essential. What is is the transition from one state of being to another. The encounter with what is other transforms one from one’s ‘natural being’ to a state of cultivation and higher sensibility, or as Gadamer, in a Hegelian mood, expressed it, ‘To recognize one’s own in the alien, to become at home in it, is the basic movement of spirit, whose being consists only in returning to itself from what is other.’ If experience, or consciousness, is dialectically structured, and if ‘keeping oneself open to what is other’ is thus ‘the general characteristic of Bildung’, such an openness is as much a necessary condition of experience as its culmination.86 An openness to what is novel and unknown is the very lifeblood of experience. ‘[G]etting beyond his naturalness’ may also describe the transition from the transient immediacy of Erlebnis to the more reflective mode of experience that is Erfahrung.87 If for Dewey the educator’s task in essence is to guide students from an experience that is immature to one that is intellectually differentiated and sophisticated, this process may well be articulated as the transition from Erlebnis to Erfahrung – a characterization that he might well have accepted had the distinction been part of his philosophical vocabulary. Where he spoke of the learning process as proceeding typically from the concrete to the abstract, from the particular to the universal, and from the practical to the theoretical, he might also – and better – have spoken of the transition from the unformed to the formed, from the narrow and parochial to the expansive and open, and from nature to culture, and where these values are not conceived in abstract opposition. The experienced
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
93
person no less than the educated has been cultivated in such a way that they are hospitable to new ideas, curious and restless of mind. They possess the intellectual virtues and the experiential continuity and interaction of which Dewey spoke while also exhibiting qualities of which he did not speak but might have, that is, which are consistent with the spirit of his philosophy of experience and education but not altogether with its letter. The concepts of Bildung and Erfahrung both suggest an experience that is continuous in Dewey’s sense while showing a dialectical and also a narrative quality that is better articulated in phenomenological and hermeneutical philosophy than in radical empiricism and pragmatism. Experience in what Gadamer called ‘the genuine sense’ is temporally elongated, integrated, meaningful, and transformative. Its significance is understood in terms of a story that unfolds over time and decidedly not as a mere succession of happenings disconnected from each other. The experiential continuity that largely distinguishes radical from British empiricism is a narrative continuity since it is this form of interpretation that renders meaningful, or understandable, human experience in general. It is precisely by fitting our experiences together into a followable story that they gain the continuity and interactivity that Dewey identified as the criteria of genuinely educative experience. I wish to add by way of a conclusion a remark or two, to which I shall return in later chapters, regarding Erfahrung and Bildung as they bear upon certain conditions of modern life. It does not appear to me that the present times are well suited to the kind of experience and cultivation that these concepts evoke, whether we are speaking of the realities of education or more generally of the state of modern life as a whole. The realities of the classroom, which directly reflect the condition of social life in general, are such that appeals to theoretical notions such as these can appear hopelessly academic when pressures to get through the material, prepare students for examinations, deal with administrative inanities, and cope with behavioral problems can make ideals of this or any kind seem like castles in the air. Indeed, one may get the impression that a great deal of educational theory is yet another scholasticism whose debates are contemporary equivalents of consubstantiation versus transubstantiation. One may even be right about this, in cases, but in the present case it is worth asking whether the ideals of experiential integration, narrative continuity, and personal cultivation of which I have been speaking are genuine possibilities for educational practices that are beset by conditions of the kind just noted. Educators charged with preparing students for standardized examinations and who have little or no freedom to select the curriculum will find it difficult, to say the least, to identify natural continuities between their particular students’ experience and the standardized curriculum that is imposed on them. Are any ideals
94
The Educative Process
possible under this condition, or does it reduce the whole business so thoroughly to a technical matter of information-bestowing and informationcramming that the discussion we have been having is a perfect irrelevance? To the extent that such conditions continue to prevail, philosophical ideals of every kind – not only the ones spoken of here – are not only unattainable but something far worse: they are beside the point. There is no leading of young minds from Erlebnis to Erfahrung in an institution modeled on Hirsch’s conservatism, for instance, no place for the intellectual virtues at all aside from the most rudimentary, and except by accident no possibility of any ‘rising up to humanity through culture’. When culture itself is flattened out to a mere sum of information, as for Hirsch it is, there is nothing there to which one can rise up; there are only facts to be crammed in, piled up, or plastered on. The sad reality is that this is often what education comes to, and in such a philosophy (or antiphilosophy) there are no ideals to be had but for such singularly empty notions as efficiency and cultural literacy. It often appears as if the times, in which the latter notions are so readily at home, are such that the kind of ideals that a Dewey or a Gadamer recommended are complete no-hopers since they fit so poorly into present ways of thinking and fly in the face even of many approaches that claim them as an influence. It often seems as well that conditions outside of educational institutions render these ideals still more untimely. The frantic pace of modern life combined with the fragmentation of experience, the temporariness of nearly everything, the fleeting and superficial nature of so much of what occupies us and what we care about do not bode well for a conception of experience as enduring, meaningful, and at times profound. Dewey lamented as far back as 1934 the impoverished state of human experience in the twentieth century, a lament far more appropriate at present than when he commented on the extent to which zeal for doing, lust for action, leaves many a person, especially in this hurried and impatient human environment in which we live, with experience of an almost incredible paucity, all on the surface. No one experience has a chance to complete itself because something else is entered upon so speedily. What is called experience is so dispersed and miscellaneous as hardly to deserve the name.88 The consummatory dimension of experience, the unhurried development of events and projects over time, or even the capacity for delayed gratification or sustained attention, appear in increasingly short supply at a time when efficiency and haste have become all-pervasive imperatives. Erfahrung and Bildung both signify a process that unfolds very gradually through the years; there is no standardized examination that can test for their attain-
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
95
ment, they are unquantifiable and unprofitable, there is no science of them, and no technique imparts them. They are also the heart and soul of education and the highest indicators of its success. Education always seeks in some measure to adapt or constitute its subjects in accordance with prevailing norms and a way of life. It prepares them to lead a life of a certain kind, with experiences that are typical of such a life, and works with whatever experiences students bring with them into the classroom. When such experience is inclined toward the immediate, the fleeting, and the fragmented, it falls to educators to swim against the tide in leading students, often against formidable odds, toward a mode of experience that is more integrated and enduring than what they may find in the general society or in the home. An educational environment can still be something of a respite from the daily barrage of information, the disconnected happenings and unrelated episodes that have become commonplace in so many lives, even if the pressures that come to bear on educators would often force them into becoming mere trainers in efficiency and adaptation, brokers of information, or facilitators of social conformity. Beneath many of the slogans of contemporary education, the latter phrases, I believe, reflect rather accurately what much of education has become. Too often it reproduces habits of mind that are a positive hindrance to experience in a richer sense of the word and adapt the young entirely too well to the cult of efficiency that awaits them. In the next chapter I wish to take up a hypothesis of Martin Heidegger, not dissimilar to what I have been arguing, to the effect that the present age is unthinking or so profoundly beholden to a single conceptual framework – ‘science-technology’ – that what he rather ambiguously termed ‘thinking’, in a higher sense of the word, has become something of an impossibility. Whether this is so is clearly an urgent question for education. Before turning to Heidegger’s discussion of this, I shall return to Dewey and ask what exactly he understood thinking to consist in, what his theoretical model for intelligent thought is, what its relevance to education is, and how it stands up to Heidegger’s line of questioning.
Notes 1. ‘Now the change which is coming into our education is the shifting of the center of gravity. It is a change, a revolution, not unlike that introduced by Copernicus when the astronomical center shifted from the earth to the sun. In this case the child becomes the sun about which the appliances of education revolve; he is the center about which they are organized.’ Dewey, The School and Society (1900). MW 1: 23. 2. Dewey, ‘The Need for a Philosophy of Education’ (1934). LW 9: 194. 3. Dewey, ‘The Psychological Aspect of the School Curriculum’ (1897). EW 5: 171. Similar sentiments are found throughout Dewey’s writings on education. 4. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 7.
96
The Educative Process
5. Dewey, ‘Report of Interview with John Dewey’, by Charles W. Wood (1922). MW 13: 427. 6. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 6. 7. Dewey, ‘Current Tendencies in Education’ (1917). MW 10: 120. 8. Dewey, ‘The Psychological Aspect of the School Curriculum’ (1897). EW 5: 166. 9. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 14–15, 14. Dewey continues in the same vein: ‘We also speak of rearing, raising, bringing up – words which express the difference of level which education aims to cover. Etymologically, the word education means just a process of leading or bringing up. When we have the outcome of the process in mind, we speak of education as shaping, forming, molding activity – that is, a shaping into the standard form of social activity.’ 10. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 5. 11. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 194, 193. 12. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 216. 13. Dewey, Moral Principles in Education (1909). MW 4: 284. 14. Dewey, ‘How the Mind Learns’, Educational Lectures Before Brigham Young Academy (1901). LW 17: 214. Elsewhere Dewey wrote: ‘Yet by way of expiation we envy children their love of new experiences, their intentness in extracting the last drop of significance from each situation, their vital seriousness in things that to us are outworn.’ Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (1922). MW 14: 72. 15. The entire paragraph reads: ‘All men by nature desire to know. An indication of this is the delight we take in our senses; for even apart from their usefulness they are loved for themselves; and above all others the sense of sight. For not only with a view to action, but even when we are not going to do anything, we prefer seeing (one might say) to everything else. The reason is that this, most of all the senses, makes us know and brings to light many differences between things.’ Aristotle, Metaphysics in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 980a 22–28. 16. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 194, 194–5. 17. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 29–30. 18. ‘Almost everyone has had occasion to look back upon his school days and wonder what has become of the knowledge he was supposed to have amassed during his years of schooling, and why it is that the technical skills he acquired have to be learned over again in changed form in order to stand him in good stead. Indeed, he is lucky who does not find that in order to make progress, in order to go ahead intellectually, he does not have to unlearn much of what he learned in school. These questions cannot be disposed of by saying that the subjects were not actually learned, for they were learned at least sufficiently to enable a pupil to pass examinations in them.’ Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 28. 19. When I think back on my own adolescence, for example, I can recall virtually nothing of at least half of the courses that I studied in high school, even what subjects they covered, yet can remember the lyrics to just about every song that the Eagles ever recorded and hockey statistics of every imaginable kind. 20. Dewey, ‘Education, Direct and Indirect’ (1904). MW 3: 240. 21. Dewey, The School and Society (1900). MW 1: 24. 22. Ibid., 8. Dewey would express much the same even-handedness in the following remarks from 1932: ‘I remember the village in which stood my grandfather’s house, where in my childhood I went to spend the summer vacation. There in the village was the old-fashioned sawmill, the old-fashioned gristmill, the old-fashioned tannery; and in my grandfather’s house there were still the candles and the soap which had been made in the home itself. At certain times the cobbler would come around to spend a few days in the neighborhood, making and repairing the shoes of the people.
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution
23. 24.
25. 26. 27.
28.
29. 30. 31. 32. 33.
34.
97
Through the very conditions of living, everybody had a pretty direct contact with nature and with the simpler forms of industry. As there were no great accumulations of wealth, the great majority of young people got a very genuine education through a kind of informal apprenticeship. They took part in the home-made duties of the household and farm and activities of the neighborhood. They saw with their eyes, and followed with their imaginations, the very real activities about them. The amount of genuine education, and of training in good habits that were obtained in this way under earlier pioneer conditions, is not easy to overestimate. There was a real education through real contact with actual materials and important social occupations. ‘On the other hand, knowledge in the form of written and printed word then had what economists call a “scarcity value.” Books, newspapers, periodicals, in a word reading matter of all kinds, were much rarer and more expensive than they are today. Libraries were comparatively few. Learning, or rather the mastery of the tools of learning, the ability to read and to write and to figure, had a high value, because the school was the one place where these tools of learning could be mastered.’ Dewey, ‘Monastery, Bargain Counter, or Laboratory in Education?’ (1932). LW 6: 102. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 136, 137. See James A. Good’s A Search for Unity in Diversity: The ‘Permanent Hegelian Deposit’ in the Philosophy of John Dewey (Lanham: Lexington Books, 2006) for a thorough treatment of Dewey’s profound indebtedness to Hegel throughout his lifetime and well beyond his break with the Hegelianism of his youth – which, as Good demonstrates, was far more a break from British Hegelianism than from Hegel himself. William James, Essays in Radical Empiricism (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1996), 42. See James, The Principle of Psychology, vol. 1 (New York: Dover, 1950), especially chapter 9, ‘The Stream of Thought’. Dewey, ‘The Psychological Standpoint’ (1886). EW 1: 123. Dewey reiterated the point on the following page: ‘Now the psychological standpoint is this: nothing shall be admitted into philosophy which does not show itself in experience, and its nature, that is, its place in experience shall be fixed by an account of the process of knowledge – by Psychology.’ Dewey, ‘Experience and Existence: A Comment’ (1949). LW 16: 383. Regarding ‘the influence of William James’ on his thought, Dewey wrote in 1930: ‘As far as I can discover one specifiable philosophic factor which entered my thinking so far as to give it a new direction and quality, it is this one.’ Dewey, ‘From Absolutism to Experimentalism’ (1930). LW 5: 157. Dewey would also endeavor quite frequently to defend James against his often hostile and uncharitable critics such as Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore, among others. The carelessness with which such critics would often dismiss James, and often Dewey as well, was an obvious source of irritation to him. The following passage is typical in this regard: ‘James is an essayist, and he enjoys writing. When he writes about a problem, he uses figurative language, and elaborates his point even to a degree of exaggeration. The fact that James enjoys his use of literary license has made him vulnerable to misinterpretation by unfriendly critics.’ Dewey, ‘Three Contemporary Philosophers’ (1920). MW 12: 219. Dewey, ‘The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy’ (1917). MW 10: 11. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1916). MW 12: 132. Ibid., 131. Dewey, ‘The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy’ (1917). MW 10: 6. See, for example, Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (in MW 14), Freedom and Culture (LW 13), Individualism, Old and New (LW 5), The Public and its Problems (LW 2), and Ethics (LW 7), among others. Dewey, ‘The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy’ (1917). MW 10: 9.
98 35. 36. 37. 38. 39.
40. 41. 42. 43.
44. 45. 46. 47. 48. 49.
50.
51. 52. 53. 54. 55. 56.
The Educative Process Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 141. See especially Dewey, Art as Experience (in LW 10). Dewey, Interest in Relation to Training of the Will (1896). EW 5: 142. Ibid., 143. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 46. Another representative passage from 1901 reads: ‘I used to talk sometimes to teachers about the subject of interest. I found out that the term is getting to be misunderstood. A great many people think that to interest means to make everything easy and amusing, when in reality it means quite the opposite. . . . To put it etymologically, interest is that which comes between the subject and object in attention, between what the man has to give and what the object brings. And wherever there is this sense of contact between the old that is already in the mind, and the new which is yet to be mastered, there will not fail to be interest.’ Dewey, ‘Attention’, Educational Lectures Before Brigham Young Academy (1901). LW 17: 280. Dewey, Interest and Effort in Education (1912). MW 7: 154. Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (1922). MW 14: 70. Dewey, Interest and Effort in Education (1912). MW 7: 171. A few of Dewey’s examples on this point include the following: ‘the direct interest in carpentering or shop work should gradually pass into an interest in geometry and mechanical problems. The interest in cooking should grow into an interest in chemical experimentation and the physiology and hygiene of bodily growth. The original casual making of pictures should pass into an interest in the technique of representation of perspective, the handling of brush, pigments, etc.’ Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 298. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 46. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 174. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 19, 13. Dewey, ‘The Way Out of Educational Confusion’ (1931). LW 6: 88. Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (1922). MW 14: 71. As Dewey remarked in a different context: ‘All habits are demands for certain kinds of activity; and they constitute the self. In any intelligible sense of the word will, they are will. They form our effective desires and they furnish us with our working capacities. They rule our thoughts, determining which shall appear and be strong and which shall pass from light into obscurity. We may think of habits as means, waiting, like tools in a box, to be used by conscious resolve. But they are something more than that. They are active means, means that project themselves, energetic and dominating ways of acting.’ Ibid., 21–2. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 24. The phrase ‘objective conditions’ that Dewey employs here ‘includes what is done by the educator and the way in which it is done, not only words spoken but the tone of voice in which they are spoken. It includes equipment, books, apparatus, toys, games played. It includes the materials with which an individual interacts, and, most important of all, the total social set-up of the conditions in which a person is engaged.’ Ibid., 26. Ibid., 26. Dewey, Interest and Effort in Education (1912). MW 7: 178. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 12. Dewey, ‘How the Mind Learns’, Educational Lectures Before Brigham Young Academy (1901). LW 17: 214. Dewey, The School and Society (1900). MW 1: 48. ‘Education and the Social Order’ (1934). LW 9: 180. Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 183. Dewey, The School and Society (1900). MW 1: 102.
Dewey’s Copernican Revolution 57. 58. 59. 60. 61. 62.
63.
64. 65. 66. 67. 68. 69. 70. 71. 72. 73. 74. 75.
76. 77. 78. 79. 80. 81. 82. 83.
99
Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 185. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 182. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 113. Dewey, Moral Principles in Education (1908). MW 4: 288. Dewey, Ethics (1932). LW 7: 208. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 329. The larger passage reads: ‘He will note that the teachers who left the most enduring impression were those who awakened in him a new intellectual interest, who communicated to him some of their own enthusiasm for a field of knowledge or art, who gave his desire to inquire and find out a momentum of its own. This is the one thing most needful. Given this hunger, the mind will go on; while it may be stuffed to overflowing with information, if this one thing is omitted, little will be gained in the future.’ One of Dewey’s infrequent references to Maria Montessori expressed his partial disagreement with her on the means by which individual creativity is learned: ‘I think we owe a great deal to Madame Montessori, but she has misled herself and others in assuring that there must be isolation or separation in order to get individuality; that each child must be doing something by himself rather than working with others; that it is impossible to combine the two principles of school work with the development of individuality. I think quite the opposite is the case. Children, of course, need a certain amount of isolation. They must get off by themselves and have time to think. This is true; but in the main, the best stimulus to the inventiveness and the ingenuity of the child, the calling out of his own individuality, is found when the individual is working with others, where there is a common project, something of interest to them all, but where each has his own part.’ Dewey, ‘Individuality in Education’ (1923). MW 15: 176. Dewey, Moral Principles in Education (1908). MW 4: 288. Dewey, ‘Some Stages of Logical Thought’ (1900). MW 1: 151. Dewey, The Educational Situation (1901). MW 1: 290. Dewey, ‘Psychology in High-Schools from the Standpoint of the College’ (1886). EW 1: 85–6. See Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson (New York: Harper and Row, 1962). James Scott Johnston has done an admirable job of documenting and replying to these allegations in his Inquiry and Education. Martin Jay, Songs of Experience (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 2005), 1, 4. Gadamer, Truth and Method, 346–7. Ibid., 61. Jay, Songs of Experience, 11. Gadamer, Truth and Method, 69. For a few examples of this, see Paul Ricoeur, Oneself As Another, trans. K. Blamey (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992); Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989); Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984); and Anthony Kerby, Narrative and the Self (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1991). Gadamer, Truth and Method, 353, 354. Ibid., 355. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 13. Gadamer, Truth and Method, 357. Ibid., 346, 361. Ibid., 362. Jay, Songs of Experience, 162–3. Gadamer, Truth and Method, 10, 14, 12.
100 84. 85. 86. 87. 88.
The Educative Process Ibid., 13. Ibid., 16. Ibid., 14, 17. Ibid., 14. Dewey, Art as Experience (1934). LW 10: 51.
Chapter 3
What Is Called Thinking?
Theorists of all persuasions agree that whatever the true business of education is, it crucially bears on what is rather ambiguously termed thought or thinking. Disagreements most often center on the proper objects of thought – which subject matters are of relative importance at which stages in the learning process – and the methodology by which particular curricula are most effectively taught and learned. Other disagreements pertain to whether it is the content of thought, in the sense of which items of knowledge or belief are to be instilled and what students are to accept as the truth or the good, or the capacity to think independently that matters most and is the true mark of educational success. Beneath these and the many other disagreements that have long occupied theorists is the shared conviction that thought, whatever it is, is the central concern of education. Logically prior to questions of the what and the how of education is the question in the title of this chapter. Since Plato, the more ambitious philosophers of education have often posed this question directly along with related questions concerning what is knowledge, reason, and truth. If the educative process involves a transition of some description from ignorance to knowledge, of which Plato’s allegory of the cave affords the classical model, how are we to theorize this transition? It is a transition from a state of not knowing or ignorance, something that requires no elaborate philosophical account, to something that manifestly does: knowing, understanding, thinking. What, then, are these? For that matter, is this one question or three? While Dewey regarded the three questions as distinct in principle, answering them requires fashioning a unified account of mental life which highlights the organic connections between the philosophically distinct categories of thinking, knowledge, truth, experience, and understanding. The specific question of what thought itself is, for Dewey the Jamesian empiricist, is of course an empirical, or better phenomenological, matter, as the title of one of his major works, How We Think, rather matter-of-factly suggests. The phenomenological question of what thinking is and the logic by which, as a matter of fact, it unfolds in various fields of inquiry has primacy over the epistemological or methodological question of how we ought to think, as if the latter could be answered in an a priori fashion. 101
102
The Educative Process
Thinking, or the practice of intelligent inquiry, already contains an immanent method which it is the task of logic and epistemology to render explicit rather than replace with a method derived in abstraction from the practice itself. Today no less than in Dewey’s time, educators commonly speak of the need for students at all levels to learn how to think, or to think critically, where it is supposed that the faculty of thought is separable in principle from the particular subject matters that it takes up, rather like the capacity for strength is distinct from the heavy lifting that it makes possible. Thus departments of philosophy now invariably offer undergraduate courses both in formal logic and in critical thinking on the premise that thinking may be taught and learned apart from subject matter, or that it is a subject matter unto itself, and that it is essentially a technical matter of following rules of inference and avoiding fallacies. Once committed to memory and dutifully heeded, the rules of thought can be counted upon to lead the mind in the direction of truth on any occasion that calls for inferences to be made or for critical thinking. It is, of course, a thoroughly laudable goal of the university to see to it that its graduates emerge from their years of study not only with a body of knowledge or information at their disposal but also with a capacity to think, even as many of the professors charged with teaching the technique itself view the task with some consternation. Exactly how does one teach another how to think? they can be forgiven for asking, that is, to think in the abstract and apart, in principle at least, from something to think about, an object or subject matter. The usual solution is to supply the students in a course on critical thinking with a somewhat watered-down version of symbolic logic. Since thinking is a matter of following rules, the curriculum in such a course consists of the rules themselves along with some exercises in which the rules can be applied, rather in the fashion of a course in mathematics or accounting. Once students have mastered the technique, they are henceforth able to think. When one surveys the history of thought, one may legitimately wonder whether any of the thinkers whose works continue to be studied decades or centuries after they are written ever learned how to think in this manner, or whether the reason that we continue to regard the great thinkers of history as great lies in their singular capacity to follow the rules such as we find them in textbooks on formal and informal logic. We may wonder as well whether the eminent thinkers of the present are one and the same individuals as those who we may presume have most thoroughly mastered the technique of thought itself: the logicians. Whatever this highly interpretable notion is taken to mean, it is no more likely to be reducible to technique or simple rule-following than participating in a conversation or playing a game, although, as with the latter practices,
What Is Called Thinking?
103
rules or principles may well play a role. If being a good conversationalist or hockey player involves observing certain very general principles or rules that can be spelled out in advance, so as well does the art of thinking, yet as with these other cases becoming adept at thinking is no mere conformity to rules but is more the nature of making skilful or creative moves within the rules and occasionally changing the rules themselves or intelligently departing from them. There is an important element of creativity and freedom – precisely that which is irreducible to technique – that gets us to the heart of the matter that is thinking. If critical and intelligent thought sometimes makes use of logical inferences, as it undoubtedly does, it also involves that which no method can teach: the art of asking questions and of seeing what is questionable, of reflecting and contemplating, slowly weighing the strength or force of an argument, detecting what is salient, cultivating the intellectual virtues in general, and other elements that go far beyond the following of rules. I shall discuss this further in due course. First, I wish to examine in some detail Dewey’s replies to the questions before us. If education crucially bears on developing students’ ability to think, as well as the content of such thought, in what sense is this the case? What is this ability itself and can it be taught and learned in the abstract or apart from inquiry into some particular subject matter? Is it what students think or whether they are able to think independently that matters most in education? Which pedagogical methods are best suited to teaching the art of thinking, if we determine that it is indeed an art or a skill rather than a formal technique? Dewey’s first contention in this matter was that there is no separation to be made between thought and its object, a view that, apparently unbeknown to Dewey, directly parallels Edmund Husserl’s phenomenological doctrine of the intentionality of consciousness. All thought is a thinking about some particular object or other, and is not, in Dewey’s words, ‘something cut off from experience’ or from an intentional object, and accordingly is not ‘capable of being cultivated in isolation’.1 Thinking is not a faculty or capacity of mind that may be trained in isolation from particular fields of inquiry or that is such a field in its own right. Thinking, on Dewey’s view, is precisely an ‘ordering of subject matter with reference to discovering what it signifies or indicates’, and thus ‘no more exists apart from this arranging of subject matter than digestion occurs apart from the assimilating of food’.2 It is a popular but mistaken conception of the mind as consisting of separate faculties of reasoning, perception, memory, and so on, as if each were a kind of muscle that could be exercised apart from the others and without the necessity of accomplishing some work. While Dewey firmly maintained that ‘the prime need of every person at present is capacity to think’, it is a capacity that can be trained neither in a vacuum, directly, nor easily, on the contrary being ‘the most difficult occupation in which man engages’.3
104
The Educative Process
On the question of what thinking itself is, Dewey defined this rather concisely as a ‘response to the doubtful as such’.4 It is essentially the practice of experimental inquiry into a given problem, the aim of which consists in ‘the directed or controlled transformation of an indeterminate situation into a determinately unified one’.5 Thinking responds to a doubtful or problematic situation – the unknown, anomalous, or perplexing – by posing questions, advancing interpretations and hypotheses, following the course of a given hypothesis to its conclusion, testing it against the available evidence, and looking for specific experiential consequences. It is a process that never loses connection with experience, arising from a doubtful situation within it and ultimately returning to it with an enhanced knowledge of the connections between events or ideas and the significance of the original situation. ‘Thinking is thus equivalent’, in Dewey’s words, ‘to an explicit rendering of the intelligent element in our experience. It makes it possible to act with an end in view.’6 What thinking is not is precisely what it is so often taken to be by educators: in essence an affair either of following rules or of amassing information in the largest possible quantity combined with the capacity for recall. What this ‘cold-storage ideal of knowledge’ overlooks is the active and creative dimension of thought. While it is not to be doubted that an education in thinking necessarily involves gaining information about a given field of study, and often a great deal of it, thinking itself refers to what is done with such information or the purposes to which it is turned. The cold-storage conception, no less than traditional notions of education in which the art of thinking is a far less urgent matter than the content of what students know and believe, is positively inimical to thought for the reason that the mind that is overladen with ill-digested facts is effectively smothered and unable to put such information to meaningful use. Not only are opportunities for intelligent inquiry not taken advantage of, but ‘it swamps thinking’ by piling on information that exceeds the students’ capacity to interrogate or integrate constructively into their experience.7 Learning in the popular sense of absorbing information more or less passively which may be retrieved at a later time should the occasion arise is a stage on the way to thinking, but it is not itself the genuine article or the ultimate aim of education. Rather, it is a secondary matter – not unimportant, as Dewey’s critics sometimes alleged, but secondary and instrumental to the development of intellectual capacity. In 1937 Dewey illustrated this point with respect to the study of civics as follows: There is, I think, considerable danger that this phase of social study will get submerged in a great flood of miscellaneous social study. When the subject was first introduced, I think there was a good deal of evidence of
What Is Called Thinking?
105
faith in the truly miraculous power of information. If the students would only learn their federal and state Constitutions, the names and duties of all the officers and all the rest of the anatomy of the government, they would be prepared to be good citizens. And many of them – many of us, I fear – having learned these facts went out into adult life and became the easy prey of skillful politicians and the political machines; the victims of political misrepresentation, say, on the part of the newspapers we happened to read.8 Much the same can be said of how at the present time we often teach in the arts, humanities, and social sciences on the premise that if only students become informed about philosophy, history, or anthropology they will become philosophers, historians, or anthropologists by some automatic process, perhaps at some point during their doctoral studies. That this is not so is readily observable when we consider the innumerable instances of students graduating from the university with an impressive array of facts at their disposal yet unable to turn them to creative use. Nothing ‘simulates knowledge’ or thought, Dewey observed, ‘and thereby develops the poison of conceit’ quite as effectively as information piled high in memory and available to be showcased upon the occasion of an examination or social gathering.9 What thinking also is not is what would better go under the name of inculcation or indoctrination, for which it is also frequently mistaken. When educators set about prescribing what students shall believe, particularly as it concerns controversial opinions and still more when students have not reached an age of intellectual maturity, they are instilling habits not of intelligent thought but of unreasoning submission. Quite apart from the intentions of educators, which in the usual course of things may be entirely beneficent, the practice of instilling a particular set of beliefs on the pretense that they are training the mind is positively miseducative and very nearly the opposite of what it claims to be. Even supposing such beliefs to be true, the mark of an educated mind is not at all the content of one’s convictions – whether one be liberal or conservative, religious or irreligious, egoist or altruist – but rather the manner in which one’s beliefs are arrived at, the reasons one can adduce on their behalf, one’s ability to draw connections between ideas and experience, to defend one’s position against rival views, and so on.10 Thinking pertains to the method, and indeed is the method, by which beliefs are rationally acquired and is thus far less concerned with end states than processes. The process itself, as he would continually emphasize, requires the students’ active participation and thus an overcoming of both the educator’s temptation to indoctrinate and the intellectual laziness and conventionality that, in his view, most often characterize youth.11 Dewey’s
106
The Educative Process
criticism of the practice of instilling or inculcating beliefs is harsh by his standards and is applied equally to opinions with which he himself agreed and disagreed.12 While Dewey’s conception of thinking crucially bears upon method, it is not limited to the methods of deductive and inductive inference that today constitute the focus of undergraduate courses in formal and informal logic. Instead it pertains to the method of intelligent inquiry itself and the spirit of such inquiry. Exactly what is this method is the issue to which I now turn.
Pragmatic intelligence Understanding Dewey’s account of thought as inquiry and his philosophy of education more generally requires viewing both in light of the pragmatist or experimentalist (instrumentalist) theory of knowledge that he appropriated primarily from William James. Without going into the details of this epistemology, a pragmatic conception of knowledge accentuates the connection between thought and action or the relation of ideas to problematic situations that arise in the course of human conduct and experience.13 Although Dewey, particularly later in his career, was less fond of the term ‘pragmatism’ itself than James – recommending in 1938 that we ‘avoid its use’ altogether given the widespread and singularly uncharitable misinterpretations that had surrounded this term – and was very mindful of the criticism that had greeted James’ formulation of this in Pragmatism and its ‘sequel’, The Meaning of Truth, the theory of knowledge that Dewey defended throughout his career is thoroughly Jamesian (and to a lesser extent Peircean) in regarding ‘consequences as necessary tests of the validity of propositions, provided these consequences are operationally instituted and are such as to resolve the specific problem evoking the operations’.14 The proviso was Dewey’s supplement to James’ view (or clarification of it, given that even a moderately charitable reading of James would include the proviso and does not lead to the simplistic misreadings of pragmatism formulated by unsympathetic critics like Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore and that have remained widespread until the present day), and forestalls objections to the effect that a pragmatic epistemology provides a philosophical rationalization for wishful thinking or for whatever propositions one happens to hold dear. In Dewey’s pragmatic instrumentalism, as he preferred to call it, the process of inquiry is described phenomenologically in a fashion that overturns what he referred to as the ‘spectator conception of knowledge’ or ‘the idea that knowledge is intrinsically a mere beholding or viewing of reality’, on the model of unconditioned subjectivity on one side and an objective, uninterpreted reality on the other. Against the spectator theory such as we find it in rationalism and British empiricism, Dewey sought to render explicit
What Is Called Thinking?
107
‘the existing practice of knowledge’ as we find it operative in both scientific and humanistic investigation, a practice in which thought and action are ultimately inseparable and ‘knowledge is power to transform the world’, not as an accidental byproduct but essentially.15 The true test of an idea or hypothesis, then, lies in the experiential consequences to which it leads or in its capacity to bring about a more adequate and coherent arrangement of our experience of the world. C. S. Peirce’s dictum that ‘there is no distinction of meaning so fine as to consist in anything but a possible difference of practice’ was taken up by Dewey and given a more explicitly experimental or scientific connotation.16 Whereas older conceptions of science had been misled by classical empiricism into regarding scientists as in essential respects passive recipients of observations and discoveries provided that they direct their attention toward a given object for some period of time, Dewey insisted that the scientist is an active investigator who must ‘do something’ – hazard an hypothesis, perform an experiment, study an object under a variety of conditions, and so on – in order to gain knowledge.17 Thought in general, from the explicitly scientific to philosophical theorizing and reflective understanding, crucially bears upon the pragmatic – ‘how things work and how to do things’ – not as a secondary matter but ultimately.18 It is not thinking but information that is complete unto itself, as it were, and related only contingently and accidentally to action. To be informed is at most to have gained that upon which thought might set to work, but it is not yet to think. For Dewey, the paradigm of thought is scientific experimentation in the sense that here we find the same method of inquiry that is properly followed in any field of study in an explicit and ‘intensified form’.19 While he would never embrace any form of positivism, nor maintain that procedures proper to the natural sciences can be simply transferred to the social sciences and humanities, Dewey did hold a decidedly optimistic view of science and of what the scientific method might accomplish in refashioning thought in general.20 One finds throughout his writings not any simplistic or naive adulation of science – although there are passages that do approach this – but a somewhat more measured optimism that ‘the scientific habit of mind’ is generally applicable to human affairs.21 Dewey’s reading of the general movement of twentieth-century culture was that it is an age of science into which modern civilization has moved, in the sense that empirical and experimental methods of inquiry are rapidly replacing the worldviews of the past, from the philosophical to the religious, political, ethical, and so on. While numerous other theorists of his time were making much the same observation – some with optimism, others (notably Martin Heidegger) with foreboding – Dewey would speak of this new scientific era in his characteristically sober and measured way as neither a Heideggerian dark night of the forgetfulness of
108
The Educative Process
Being nor a positivist’s utopia but as something intermediate between the two. Science is something neither to be idealized dogmatically in the manner of positivism nor brooded over in the fashion of certain existential thinkers but regarded more modestly as a method, and a singularly useful one. It is, moreover, the same method as that pursued with less elaborateness and exactitude in ostensibly non-scientific forms of inquiry. While the promise that this method holds for the transformation of human affairs is nothing short of revolutionary, in Dewey’s view, he stopped short of an uncritical idealization of science of the kind that characterized many of his contemporaries. Science represents an ideal of thought in the sense that here the method of rational investigation that is proper to thought in general is visible in its purest form. Distinguishing between science as a body of knowledge or academic subject matter on one hand and a method on the other, it is the latter that holds potential for liberation and advancement in all realms of human concern. ‘The general adoption of the scientific attitude’ which would effect ‘nothing less than a revolutionary change in morals, religion, politics and industry’ means not that we ought all become physicists or biologists or acquire vast learning about the latest empirical discoveries but that the ‘attitude’ and method of experimental ‘intelligence’ (to use one of Dewey’s favorite expressions) is what is needed to bring about a radical transformation in our ways of thinking and relating, both in liberating us from the absolutes of the past and in supplying us with a positive model for human knowledge.22 Regarding the exact nature of this model, Dewey stated in one of his more concise descriptions: By science is meant . . . that knowledge which is the outcome of methods of observation, reflection, and testing which are deliberately adopted to secure a settled, assured subject matter. It involves an intelligent and persistent endeavor to revise current beliefs so as to weed out what is erroneous, to add to their accuracy, and, above all, to give them such shape that the dependencies of the various facts upon one another may be as obvious as possible. It is, like all knowledge, an outcome of activity bringing about certain changes in the environment.23 Following James, Dewey conceived of the investigative process as one of experimental hypothesizing and empirical testing of ideas in a fashion that proposes and modifies hypotheses with a view to arranging or rearranging phenomena with optimal coherence. As experimental, this procedure calls for a dynamic interaction between inquirer and investigated object which bears no resemblance to the technical application of rules. In the process of experimental inquiry, an hypothesis is proposed by which to account for
What Is Called Thinking?
109
particular phenomena, the progress of which is then followed as it proceeds through various discursive stages until it registers pragmatic consequences of a specific kind. Provided these accord with the consequences anticipated by the original hypothesis, and by this means provide for the organization or reorganization of a given set of phenomena, the hypothesis passes for true until and unless it generates a contradiction in another region of experience. This method integrates experiences with other experiences, phenomena with phenomena, in dialectical fashion, drawing connections between disparate ideas and observations in ways that make it possible to find our way about the world. Knowing and thinking generally constitute an effort to resolve a problematic situation of one kind or another. Thinking indeed ‘is the actual transition from the problematic to the secure, as far as it is intentionally guided’.24 This short definition encapsulates a larger process of methodological investigation that begins with a difficulty, doubt, or confusion that arises in the course of lived experience and leads to a question and the assertion of a provisional hypothesis, a ‘conjectural anticipation’ or a ‘tentative interpretation’ concerning a problematic situation. The basic trajectory of thought is a solution-oriented refinement of this hypothesis in light of a more thorough examination of the relevant facts or evidence surrounding the case. The hypothesis is then tested against competing ideas and against the evidence itself by determining its capacity to accommodate a greater range of phenomena and by ‘doing something overtly to bring about the anticipated result’, whether this be subjecting an empirical object to a variety of experimental conditions in order to determine whether it reacts in the specific ways that the hypothesis predicts, or testing a textual interpretation by checking it against a progressively larger number of passages.25 This is a method of trial and error that if successful resolves the original difficulty without in the process generating more problems than it solves. Speaking generally, then, ‘Anything that may be called knowledge, or a known object, marks a question answered, a difficulty disposed of, a confusion cleared up, an inconsistency reduced to coherence, a perplexity mastered.’26 Dewey’s choice of verbs in this passage is telling: to think – also to know – is to answer, dispose of difficulties, clear up, reduce to coherence, or master a given issue, in essence to solve a problem. Not certainty but ‘warranted assertibility’ is the outcome of successful inquiry, a conception of knowledge and of truth itself as invariably contingent on the course of future research. Dewey stressed that it is the nature of inquiry, be it scientific or philosophical, to be futural, fallible, and ultimately practical in orientation, never allowing us to rest altogether on our conclusions but setting these in operation on the model of scientific experimentation. Truth is never the final outcome of thought in the sense of an end attained once and for all, but is itself a processual notion,
110
The Educative Process
as James before him had maintained. In pragmatic knowledge, ‘the process of growth, of improvement and progress, rather than the static outcome and result, becomes the significant thing’.27 In principle, truth remains always provisional on future inquiry and on the consequences for practice and experience that they engender. While scientific experimentation affords the model for thought in general, it is important to qualify this in a couple of ways. First, the ‘research’ that, according to Dewey, ‘all thinking is’ most often is of a rudimentary variety and involves no sophisticated operation of inference whatever.28 Dewey provided the following example of thinking in its ordinary, everyday meaning: [A] man is walking on a warm day. The sky was clear the last time he observed it; but presently he notes, while occupied primarily with other things, that the air is cooler. It occurs to him that it is probably going to rain; looking up, he sees a dark cloud between him and the sun, and he then quickens his steps. What, if anything, in such a situation can be called thought? Neither the act of walking nor the noting of the cold is a thought. Walking is one direction of activity; looking and noting are other modes of activity. The likelihood that it will rain is, however, something suggested. The pedestrian feels the cold; first he thinks of clouds, then he looks and perceives them, and then he thinks of something he does not see: a storm. This suggested possibility is the idea, the thought. If it is believed in as a genuine possibility which may occur, it is the kind of thought which falls within the scope of knowledge and which requires reflective consideration.29 In the usual course of human experience, this is the typical pattern of ‘research’ or ‘inquiry’ that Dewey had in mind, and differs from scientific or logical investigation only in degree of explicitness and sophistication. The second qualification to add is that thought is not a monological but a dialogical matter. Pragmatic inquiry includes an important social element, as Peirce and James also maintained, albeit in different ways. For Peirce, it is the nature of inquiry to strive for consensus among a community of inquirers rather than, as the older empiricism and rationalism both had it, to occur essentially in the inner sanctum of the mind.30 James and Dewey extended Peirce’s view into a broader theory of knowledge and truth, arguing that while in the first instance both knowledge and truth are predicated of the individual inquirer – are a function of a belief’s pragmatic success within an individual’s experience – the belief in question must be submitted to the general conversation of a community. As the investigative process unfolds, the locus of truth shifts from the individual thinker to a community of
What Is Called Thinking?
111
participants, while one’s own perspective broadens to incorporate an increasing number of inquirers. As the conversation continues and the pool of shared experience enlarges, knowledge becomes less idiosyncratic and increasingly intersubjective, with consensus rather than accuracy of representation being the best (albeit fallible) indication that truth has emerged. So conceived, truth is invariably a social construction that is strictly contingent on human experience and symbolizing practices and is in no sense an ahistorical or purely objective relation that is happened upon in the course of inquiry.31 In pragmatic intelligence, then, it is coherence in both an intra-experiential and intersubjective sense that is the ‘end’ to which thought leads even while never finally attaining it. Regarding ideas themselves, Dewey conceived of these as essentially hypotheses or means of resolving problematic situations. Their instrumental function alone supplies whatever meaning they hold for us, as Peirce and James had argued. This pragmatic conception of ideas poses a direct challenge to standard philosophical views according to which ideas, whether they be mind-dependent or mind-independent, have an essential nature and proper meaning which it is the business of philosophical reflection to capture theoretically, be it in the form of contemporary ‘analysis’ – in which ideas, despite their apparent ambiguity, can be counted upon to sit still long enough for us to pronounce a definitive account of their meaning, and ideally one that reduces their ambiguity to zero – or ancient efforts to answer the Socratic ‘What is x?’ question by discovering a Platonic Form or Aristotelian essence. Ideas in general, on the pragmatic view, are not ‘rigidly fixed’ in their meaning but are contingent upon their use-value in resolving difficulties in human experience and facilitating our commerce with a lifeworld. They never rise above the status of ‘intellectual instruments to be tested and confirmed – and altered – through consequences effected by acting upon them’. Ideas therefore ‘lose all pretense of finality – the ulterior source of dogmatism’. Dewey’s remark about dogmatism is no mere afterthought but is fundamental to the instrumentalist conception of ideas and to its justification. Part of the basis for the instrumentalist theory of ideas and of thinking lies precisely in its promotion of the intellectual virtues discussed in Chapter 2 and in its capacity to unseat the dogmatic frame of mind of which Dewey was a lifelong critic. If so many human efforts throughout history have been invested in the war of ideas and creeds tenaciously clung to without regard for their consequences for human life, a better idea would be to transform how we view ideas themselves. Regarding ideas as hypotheses and means of solving problems, Dewey maintained, ‘would do away with the intolerance and fanaticism that attend the notion that beliefs and judgments are capable of inherent truth and authority; inherent in the sense of being independent of what they lead to when used as directive principles’.32
112
The Educative Process
Nothing is more fatal to inquiry than conceiving of ideas as fixed verities that must be adhered to regardless of where the investigative process leads or that are above the fray of criticism and justification. Once Peirce had proposed that the meaning of a given idea lies in the consequences to which it leads for human practices, James and Dewey saw no reason not to extend this to include the idea’s purpose and truth-value as well (an extension that Peirce himself vehemently opposed, to the point of renaming his theory of meaning ‘pragmaticism’ to distinguish it from the ‘pragmatism’ of James).
Reflective thinking From the beginning, pragmatism’s critics have charged it with lacking a certain reflective quality or even with anti-intellectualism, as if it constitutes a counterpart within epistemology to a crude form of ethical utilitarianism. Any association of truth-value with use-value for many represents a betrayal of philosophy’s age-old promise of gaining an accurate knowledge of reality in its true dimension, one that forswears all prejudice and enables us to separate knowledge from mere opinion, reason from rhetoric, and the truth itself from what merely passes for it in ordinary discourse. At first glance – which many such critics never advanced beyond – it may indeed appear that the pragmatic view of ideas as hypotheses and instruments of research rather than fixed verities misses something essential to the life of the mind: something like reflection, contemplation, or understanding for its own sake rather than as a means to a practical end. To many, it appeared as if pragmatism was denying this and putting forward a crass and simplistic, even antiphilosophical, conception of thought. The inaccuracy of this impression is easily seen when one brackets the reputation that pragmatism received a century ago and which remains widespread to this day and actually reads Dewey’s works, in which he repeatedly addressed the numerous misinterpretations of James’ and his own position that continually appeared throughout the first half of the twentieth century. An important case in point concerns the nature of reflective thought, contemplation, and understanding in the sense of these terms that common sense distinguishes from the pragmatic. The connotation of ‘pragmatic’ and ‘instrumental’ that James and Dewey invoked is not the narrow one of common parlance. So far was Dewey from separating the practical from the theoretical or the instrumental from the reflective that for this profoundly dialectical thinker such dichotomies are renounced entirely along with the everyday connotation of the pragmatic as lacking the depth dimension associated with the contemplative and philosophical. Indeed, one of Dewey’s most enduring concerns as both an education theorist and cultural critic was precisely the manner in which traditional pedagogy and the general society
What Is Called Thinking?
113
of his time had become dangerously superficial and fascinated by outward things at the expense of depth and reflectiveness. As a social observer, for instance, Dewey frequently lamented the manner in which the leisure time of Americans had become consumed by amusements devoid of meaning but inexpensive and generally available to an increasingly urbanized population. The fascination with amusements combined with declining taste in the arts and science constituted ‘a very serious situation for thousands of people whose industrial and economic life does not have either soul or spirit’, as Dewey would remark in 1923.33 The remedy for the cultural deterioration he believed he was witnessing must come from educational institutions whose social duty includes instilling capacities of reflectiveness and taste which will allow their graduates to make better use of leisure time throughout life.34 Moreover, as I discussed in Chapter 2, Dewey’s notion of the intellectual virtues and the educated mind includes a central place for reflectiveness and the turn of mind that is ‘slow but sure’, in contrast to the ‘brightness’ that ‘may be but a flash in the pan’. The student who is genuinely thoughtful ‘is one in whom impressions sink and accumulate, so that thinking is done at a deeper level of value than by those with a lighter load’. The reflective intellect is precisely the one with an advanced capacity for contemplation and for the ‘wisdom’ that tradition has long distinguished from mere information. Retaining this distinction, Dewey considered it an important matter for educators to separate the accumulation of factual knowledge from the higher ideal of wisdom in the sense of ‘knowledge operating in the direction of powers to the better living of life’.35 If education crucially bears upon the training of thought, this includes encouraging habits of mind that far transcend being pragmatic or solution oriented in the colloquial sense of these terms to include cultivating ‘a deep personal sense of the problem to be dealt with’. Reflective thought begins with this ‘sense of the problem’ which, in an unhurried way and before proposing a solution, searches for clarification regarding the proper dimensions of the problem or question itself, including the critical issue of ‘why it is a problem’. Is it an ostensibly perennial question that simply falls from the sky, as so many academic problems are customarily presented to students, or does it arise from some vital experience of life which the student can be made to see? If the former, the course of thought that ensues is more likely to resemble ‘mere debating’ and ‘sophistry’ than the ‘reasoning together’ and ‘process of cooperative search’ that characterizes genuinely reflective inquiry.36 It is precisely the depth dimension of thought that is among the most vital matters in education, as Dewey would so often argue against his conservative critics. The depth to which a sense of the problem, of the difficulty, sinks, determines the quality of the thinking that follows; and any habit of teaching
114
The Educative Process
that encourages the pupil for the sake of a successful recitation or of a display of memorized information to glide over the thin ice of genuine problems reverses the true method of mind-training.37 Dewey all but defined the condition of being educated as the capacity for reflective thought in a sense that includes the power to articulate and pursue questions to their depths and to ‘go below the surface’ of appearances in the way that philosophy has always prized, to reject the premature answer and the facile conclusion in favor of slow and rigorous investigation.38 The term ‘reflective thought’ itself he defined as the ‘[a]ctive, persistent, and careful consideration of any belief or supposed form of knowledge in the light of the grounds that support it and the further conclusions to which it tends’, thus as an explicitly philosophical or scientific search for the basis of human knowledge.39 It searches as well for the connecting links in human experience between one problematic situation and another, between different lines of inquiry or whole fields of study, and between a particular subject matter and its larger significance for human life. As mentioned in Chapter 2, an important part of what distinguishes radical empiricism from its predecessor in British thought is the accent placed by the former on relations or connections within experience in contrast to the experiential atomism of the older tradition. Since it is experience that constitutes the proper object of reflective thought, such thought pays particular attention to these connections rather than studying objects or ideas apart from the context that supplies them with meaning. Philosophical concepts, for instance, are properly studied not as a god might view them, as acontextual essences which are what they are apart from the uses to which they are put, but as terms within a larger train of thought or discursive vocabulary, and which, to be understood, must be so regarded. Whether it is the philosopher theorizing on the nature of time or justice, or the philosophy professor providing instruction on the same, reflective thought that proceeds by removing the concept from all context and connections with other concepts, with its history, etymology, and variety of uses in different fields of inquiry and experience – except perhaps as a secondary matter or for purposes of illustration – is a project destined for failure. We neither experience nor reflect upon intentional objects of any kind – philosophical concepts, scientific hypotheses, empirical objects, or what have you – as disconnected atoms but by regarding an object in organic relation to a context of thought and experience. In Dewey’s view it is the ‘neglect of context’ that constitutes ‘the most pervasive fallacy of philosophical thinking’, a habit of thought that is as old as the Greeks and as contemporary as certain forms of ‘analysis’.40 Reflection upon an idea, then, involves locating it within a train of thought or argumentative sequence that importantly includes a ‘con-sequence – a
What Is Called Thinking?
115
consecutive ordering [of ideas] in such a way that each determines the next as its proper outcome’. In reflective thinking, as in the experience with which it is concerned, one thing leads to another; an idea or object is comprehended by relating it to a purpose, a history, a different idea or object, by identifying that to which it leads, or otherwise by drawing it into association with something else, and not simply providing an inventory of its properties or component parts. This of course includes a critical examination of its justificatory rationale, yet in a sense that is not limited to formal reasoning. In How We Think, Dewey identified three differences between formal reasoning in the sense of logical deduction and ‘thinking as it actually goes on in the mind of any person’.41 Whereas the former is as perfectly impersonal as mathematics, the latter is contingent on the intellectual habits of the thinker – whether the individual is attentive or inattentive, careful or careless, disciplined or undisciplined. Second, while logical argument forms are unchanging and unconcerned with the content that fills them, thought is a process that changes with some regularity and is forever taking account of its object and trying to resolve difficulties without creating new ones. As well, formal reasoning is indifferent to context while for reflective thought the larger context of resolving problematic situations must remain uppermost in view. These differences notwithstanding, reflective intelligence as Dewey conceived of it is as concerned with the rational basis of belief as what conventionally goes under the name of logical inference. Dewey’s conception of reflective thought also includes the notion of understanding, and in a sense of this term that anticipates developments in the phenomenological hermeneutics of Martin Heidegger and later German and French thinkers working under his influence (as I shall discuss later in this chapter). If pragmatic inquiry as Dewey described it is a properly social undertaking, so too is the practice of understanding which is intimately related to reflection. Although Dewey would not write at great length about the concept of understanding itself – certainly not providing the elaborate phenomenological account of the kind articulated by Heidegger or Gadamer – he did speak of understanding and its synonym, comprehension, in a very short essay of 1929 as an inclusive word – it signifies coming together, bringing things together; and when we say that human beings have come to an understanding, we mean that they have come to an agreement, that they have reached a common mind, a common outlook from which they see the same things and feel the same way about them.42 A few years later he would again describe understanding as ‘an agreement or settlement of some affair’ between persons, hence in an explicitly intersubjective
116
The Educative Process
connotation, as well as in more straightforwardly cognitive terms as the capacity ‘to grasp meaning’ in context. To understand an expression is to locate it within the context that is afforded by a sentence, conversation, or discourse, and thus to grasp it in relation to what surrounds it. Taken out of context, the expression permits of only a narrow, definitional understanding. Without mentioning the concept of the hermeneutic circle by name – the idea, that is, that understanding has a circular structure and operates by relating the parts to the whole and vice versa – Dewey did make mention of ‘the constant spiral movement of knowledge’, and wrote that all understanding and all knowing ‘proceeds by taking the thing inquired into out of its isolation’ and placing it in a context ‘until the thing is discovered to be a related part in some larger whole’.43 The process of contextualization applies as much to grasping the significance of the first robin in March as marking the beginning of spring as to understanding the meaning of a sentence by relating it to the paragraph of which it is a part or to the text as a whole – although textual hermeneutics itself would never be a preoccupation of Dewey’s. Understanding an object also involves comprehending the uses to which the object can be put, and in a sense that pertains to the gaining of control. If meaning consists, as Peirce argued, in consequences for practice, then the object must be understood in terms of the consequences that it brings about or that for which it is a means. Thus, we may understand an historical event – a battle, let us say – as the decisive turning point in a war, as bringing about the eventual victory of one side over the other, or as the defining moment of the war, which allowed lessons to be learned or a larger meaning to be grasped. If understanding is one part of a larger reflective process that involves the resolution of problematic situations generally conceived, it is the part that bears directly on the connection between means and consequences. From the means or instrumental side of the equation, an object such as a chair is comprehended in being seen as something on which to sit, while from the side of consequences we can see in examples of invention how a desire to produce a certain outcome requires us to understand the means that will produce it. In either event, ‘[t]he relation of meansconsequence is the center and heart of all understanding’.44 If Dewey’s insistence on the inseparability of understanding and action differs in important respects from other phenomenological accounts of the nature of understanding and interpretation, the accent on context remains very much in line with such accounts, as do Dewey’s remarks concerning the pervasiveness of language in understanding. At around the time that Heidegger would speak of the ‘as-structure’ of interpretive understanding (that all understanding involves interpreting an object as belonging to this or that linguistic category), Dewey emphasized that it is by means of concepts and
What Is Called Thinking?
117
language that we comprehend meaning, that ‘[c]oncepts enable us to generalize, to extend and carry over our understanding from one thing to another’. Thus if one is familiar with the concept of an ‘island’ and is informed that a particular object is such, one gains a general understanding of the object. Should one want more detailed knowledge concerning this particular island, one would then inquire into what distinguishes it from other islands – hence its relations by way of similarity and difference to other objects of the same linguistic kind – even if ‘for practical purposes it is often enough to know what kind of thing it is’.45 From elementary perception to the higher reaches of thought, knowledge is no purely objective or immediate beholding of reality, but is invariably mediated by prior understanding and by language, as Heideggerian phenomenology would also maintain and explicate in far more detail. Simple perception is mediated by the linguistic categories that allow us to interpret an object and is thus an ‘active outgoing construction of mind’, as Dewey remarked as early as 1887.46 Nearly a half-century later he spoke of a ‘peculiarly intimate connection’ between language and thought in general, noting (as would Heidegger) that the word from which logic itself derives – logos – ‘means indifferently both word or speech and thought or reason’.47 Dewey and Heidegger both regarded this fact as no mere accident of etymology but as a philosophically interesting indication of the fundamental inseparability of word and object along with language and reflection. Language is no mere tool for communicating wordless intuitions, a kind of accidental garb that is added to thought which in essence is an alinguistic ‘private soliloquy or solipsistic observation’.48 Thought in general does not occur apart from language, and where Dewey intended by language not only ‘oral and written speech’ but ‘[g]estures, pictures, monuments, visual images, finger movements – anything deliberately and artificially employed as a sign’. Thinking occurs in signs and its object is not wordless things but their meaning or pragmatic significance. Reflective thought also transpires within a context afforded not only by language but by tradition and culture. Another frequent theme in phenomenology and hermeneutics, the facticity of thought is a matter with which Dewey was also well familiar both in his earlier Hegelian (or AngloAmerican neohegelian) period and in his later (still Hegelian) period. The life of the mind in general, for Dewey, is occupied with signs that are social inventions and works with ‘acquired habitual modes of understanding’, with ‘a certain store of previously evolved meanings or at least of experiences from which meanings may be educed’.49 To understand is at its core to communicate and to participate in ongoing discursive practices which constitute a culture. If its object is a particular experience or meaning, it is an object that is always already (as phenomenologists would say) imbued with culturally inherited understandings and tradition that constitute the point of view
118
The Educative Process
of the thinker while remaining largely in the background of thought. The philosopher, the artist, and the scientist all ‘derive their substance from the stream of culture’ and exhibit the same ‘dependence upon tradition’ that characterizes thought in general, including its most creative forms.50 Dewey’s model here is once again biological: thinking represents an inheritance as well as a carrying forward of the accumulated thought and experience of the past. Our most innovative ideas are themselves ‘already overlaid and saturated with the products of the reflection of past generations and by-gone ages’, and constitute so many learned habits of mind, responses, and departures from what has been transmitted to us by virtue of our participation in a cultural tradition.51 Creative and critical thinking, then, no more divests itself of tradition than of language itself. In maintaining this view, Dewey never reverted to any kind of traditionalism or intellectual conservatism. A thinker whose habitual turn of mind was consistently progressive and futural, Dewey would speak of the creative and imaginative dimension of thought no less than its embeddedness in language and tradition. Reflection is continually finding new uses for received ideas, whether it is new technological applications of an old scientific hypothesis or artistic innovations within old styles and genres. That originality arises from a context that is determined by familiar ways of thinking rather than out of thin air implies only that it is contingent and limited, not that it is unattainable or a rarity. Indeed, thought in general and ‘all conscious experience has of necessity some degree of imaginative quality’, some ‘conscious adjustment of the new and the old’. As the living organism interacts with its environment and is never its mere product, human thought as well represents a vital interaction with the knowledge and meanings that are passed down to it, whether this involves a wholesale appropriation of received truths or a conscious departure from the old ways. Either way, the inventiveness that is proper to thought is fundamentally a new reply in a conversation that began long ago. Regarding the concept of imagination itself, Dewey would sometimes speak of this in a general way as ‘a way of seeing and feeling things as they compose an integral whole’ and as a novel configuration of the old and the new, while in other contexts he defined it in a narrower and more conventional way as a ‘power of forming mental pictures’ or images in a sense more or less synonymous with fantasy.52 When writing as a social critic he would more than occasionally decry the unimaginativeness of twentieth-century culture in the sense of its conservatism and lack of creativity, and the incapacity of its educational institutions to instill more forward-looking habits of mind.53 The poverty of the modern imagination is a pervasive cultural phenomenon, in Dewey’s view, the remedy for which lies in educational reform that encourages a facility with ideas that far surpasses cultural transmission or social reproduction in the sense of simple
What Is Called Thinking?
119
conservation. Traditional education has positively hampered reflective thought not only by failing to take opportunities for creativity in studying received ideas but by actively blocking this through instilling beliefs as readymade certainties or authoritative pronouncements. Both a symptom and contributing cause of the unimaginativeness of the present, Dewey fervently believed, was the scholasticism that increasingly characterized the thought of the twentieth century. Across the disciplines, the trend has long been toward increasing specialization, partly no doubt due to the nature of inquiry itself and its inherent tendency to branch out into smaller and narrower avenues, but partly due to other factors. The latter include what Dewey perceived as a growing unconcern among scholars in all fields for matters that fall outside their own narrow specialty, whether it be the broader implications of knowledge gained in a specific area of inquiry for other disciplines or subdisciplines or, more especially, the consequences for human life in a larger sense. That knowledge in general exists for the purpose of furthering human interests is increasingly lost sight of by specialists whose focus can become so narrow that all contact with the pragmatic and the social disappears. Overspecialization tends to create indifference toward social questions that are the ultimate end of inquiry in general, and to give rise to theoretical discourses that lack any vital connection to practice. In Dewey’s own discipline of philosophy, for instance, the compartmentalization of knowledge that he observed in the early decades of the twentieth century had become so extreme in his view that the discipline itself had become largely irrelevant to the pressing social issues of the day if not to human life more generally, as I shall discuss further in Chapter 4. Rather than broadening horizons and fashioning theories that facilitate our commerce with the world, philosophy of the contemporary period most often has a narrowing effect on the mind and generates theoretical discourses that are dangerously scholastic, formalistic, and conservative. The professor of philosophy, Dewey lamented, is a technical specialist concerned increasingly with ‘form . . . for its own sake’, and indeed with a ‘form of forms, not forms of subject matter’; the twentieth-century philosopher speaks a highly technical language inaccessible to non-specialists and engages in hair-splitting minutiae to which the outside world is understandably indifferent. Dewey was unusually severe in his criticism of the retreat of philosophy in particular from ‘the facts of human life into purely formal issues’, adding: ‘I hesitate to call them issues because nothing ever issues except more form! It’s harmless for everyone except philosophers. This retreat accounts for the growing disinterest of the general public in the problems of philosophy.’54 In addition to its formalism and departmentalization – which of course have increased dramatically since Dewey’s time – philosophy has become ‘unusually conservative’, less for the solutions it
120
The Educative Process
offers than for ‘clinging to problems’ of old and often merely translating centuries-old problems into new vocabularies rather than resolving or dissolving them. Meanwhile the ‘[d]irect preoccupation with contemporary difficulties is left to literature and politics’.55 Other disciplines received a similar assessment from Dewey, the common denominator being that the ‘[s]cholastic specialization’ and compartmentalization of research in all fields ‘breed indifference to larger social issues and objects’ and produce scholars who are ‘socially isolated and socially irresponsible’, and who exhibit ‘more than usually poor judgment in matters not closely allied’ to their field of expertise.56 The weddedness of research to the university produces educational practices that reproduce such traits within students more often than instilling the intellectual virtues and habits of mind that for Dewey are the marks of an educated mind. Reflective thought in particular is hampered by overspecialization, its orientation being toward precisely that which all scholasticism overlooks: the connections between different domains of experience, the consequences of ideas and theoretical constructions for our practices, the larger contextuality of understanding, and the inventive quality at the heart of all inquiry.
Pedagogical matters We thus arrive at an answer to the question posed in the title of this chapter. The defining features of thinking in Dewey’s expansive sense of the term include an orientation toward the experiential and the problematic, an experimental frame of mind that is modeled on scientific inquiry while also being reflective, imaginative, and hospitable to new ideas, which seeks depth of understanding and a breadth of interests, and above all that demonstrates a concern for resolving difficulties within human affairs rather than theorizing in the spirit of scholastic formalism. What thinking is not includes amassing information in the largest possible quantity, following rules or formalist methods, an inculcation of beliefs, or a faculty of mind that is isolated from subject matter. Thought is a methodological enterprise, yet one that more closely resembles ordinary trial and error than formal logic in the non-pragmatic connotation of the term. Accordingly, if the business of education crucially bears upon the art of thinking or what is called ‘critical thinking’, as so many currently profess and as Dewey himself maintained, what pedagogical recommendations did he provide for educators charged with teaching this art? How does one teach another to think, recognizing that the answer will depend significantly on the students’ level of intellectual maturity as well as the subject matter? Clearly, if pragmatic intelligence is an essentially social and co-operative form of inquiry, a fair proportion of class time will be occupied with informal
What Is Called Thinking?
121
discussion, most obviously in disciplines within the arts, humanities, and social sciences. Rejecting the customary habit of educators intent upon arriving at the ‘right answer’ by the shortest possible route of ‘getting things under discussion settled’ quickly – most often by educators supplying their own answers to their own questions – Dewey recommended an unhurried approach to discussion that leaves students free to propose ideas while requiring them to clarify and justify whatever views they propose.57 Having argued that education requires a certain kind of environment in order to succeed, an important dimension of this concerns the spirit of open-ended conversation that ought to prevail, most especially in the university setting where a level of intellectual maturity has been attained. Here it is the testing of ideas against other ideas that is decisive and the adoption by students of the role of active participants in the process of inquiry in combination with the demands of intellectual rigor. In particular, Dewey urged that the investigative or conversational process that historically unfolded between individuals in a given field be transferred to the student’s own thought process, that the dispute between Plato and the sophists, for example, or between Galileo and the Roman church be engaged in the student’s private reflection. ‘No process is more recurrent in history’, he wrote, ‘than the transfer of operations carried on between different persons into the arena of the individual’s own consciousness.’58 Ever mindful of the connection between the fate of education and the fate of democracy, Dewey argued that while free discussion in the classroom can easily get off track or deteriorate into the pointless, it is essential to the training of democratic citizens to answer to their peers for the opinions they hold and to ‘share in joint conference and consultation on social questions and issues’.59 The free classroom discussion that Dewey advocated requires a degree of forbearance on the part of the educator, beginning with the conscious refusal to instill one’s own controversial beliefs in students’ minds on the pretense of authority or special insight, while including as well the practice of directing discussion along fruitful avenues and instilling intellectual discipline without insisting that to every question there is a single correct answer or, equally problematically, that all answers are equal, that ideas are merely subjective or arbitrary ‘biases’. A pedagogical offshoot of the dichotomy between objectivism and relativism that Dewey categorically rejected and that remains widespread among students and educators today is the notion that the purpose of classroom discussion is either to discover the single right answer quickly or to allow one and all to air their arational prejudices. Dewey held out hope for an intermediate ground where the conversation approximates experimental intelligence under the direction of the educator. In order that the spirit of inquiry prevail, a considerable measure of freedom to propose and debate ideas is an indispensable principle of
122
The Educative Process
classroom discussion and of education generally, as Dewey often had occasion to argue. Students must have the freedom to determine their own purposes and to pursue them since ‘the formation of purposes and the organization of means to execute them are the work of intelligence’.60 As I discussed in Chapter 2, the educative process takes the students’ extracurricular experience as its point of departure and requires their active participation in deciding which interests will guide subsequent activity. Accordingly, the principal form of freedom in education is what Dewey called the ‘freedom of work’, by which he meant not only academic freedom in the familiar sense of the term but a certain intangible quality as well – ‘something which is in the atmosphere and operates as a continuous and unconscious stimulus’ – the freedom essentially to pursue knowledge without undue institutional constraints and in the true spirit of inquiry itself.61 Academic freedom in its usual connotation is virtually axiomatic in Dewey’s view, there being nothing more fundamental to the very meaning of education than the right to advance and debate any and all hypotheses. As he wrote, ‘Freedom of mind, freedom of thought, freedom of inquiry, freedom of discussion is education, and there is no education, no real education, without these elements of freedom.’62 Consequently no idea or field of belief is properly immune from critical examination, and no concessions may rightfully be made to public opinion or to the intellectual fashions of the day. Thus in an essay of 1902 Dewey would defend the teaching of the biological doctrine of evolution irrespective of popular views on the subject: ‘It is safe to say that no university worthy of the name would put any limitation upon instruction in this theory, or upon its use as an agency of research and classification. Very little sympathy could be secured for an attack upon a university for encouraging the use of this theory.’ Noting public pressure and also internal pressure within religious colleges in particular to limit or forbid the teaching of this hypothesis, Dewey continued: There are still, however, large portions of society which have not come to recognize that biology is an established science, and which, therefore, cannot concede to it the right to determine belief in regions that conflict with received opinions, and with the emotions that cluster about them.63 Twenty years later Dewey would speak in similarly critical terms of the Lusk laws in New York state which required teachers to take loyalty oaths in light of the red scare of the day. Speaking in an interview, Dewey remarked: The moment we stipulate what a child shall think, we make it impossible for him to think at all. Dealing with human intelligence as though it were mostly a matter of animal training constitutes the real viciousness of such
What Is Called Thinking?
123
measures as the Lusk laws. However such laws may be defended from the standpoint of public comfort, they do not permit us to educate our children. Their tendency is to make of them a lot of well-trained apes.64 While no formal method teaches the art of thinking, there are conditions that educators must guard against, from indoctrination to prohibitions on certain ideas or regimes of belief, an undue compartmentalization of thought, directionless activity, intellectual irresponsibility, and also excessive formality in the classroom.65 As for more precise pedagogical recommendations regarding how thought or the intellectual virtues that Dewey esteemed are best taught and learned, Dewey was often surprisingly circumspect apart from some very general remarks. On the subject of lecturing, for example, Dewey stated very briefly that while he regarded lecturing as indispensable, where the question of ‘the best method of lecturing’ is concerned, ‘I can only say that I have been wrestling with the problem for some years, and have been regretfully forced to the conclusion that the best way a man can, is the best way for him to lecture.’ Providing direct instruction is far superior, in his view, to ‘the text-book fetish’ and ‘superstition’ according to which human knowledge may be presented to students in ready-made form as so much information to be amassed.66 Lecturing being an art rather than a technique, there is little by way of positive guidance or formalizable rules that can be devised. What it is essentially is a skill in presenting information or ideas regarding a given field of inquiry in a fashion that leads the students into engaging the inquiry in their own consciousness and in common discussion. What lecturing is not is a method of ‘pouring knowledge into a mental and moral hole which awaits filling’.67 Its aim, as with educational practices in general, is to contribute to the students’ intellectual growth, and thus must be thought of more as a processual matter than the achievement of a specific end-state. Much the same applies to the issue of assigning grades. The ‘evil’ that marks represent is owing to their intrinsic nature of imposing quantitative measure on what is a properly qualitative matter – the students’ acquisition of intellectual habits that approximate thinking.68 While the straightforward acquisition of information may be easily quantified, with grades determined by means of traditional examination, the ‘things of the spirit’, as Dewey expressed it, ‘do not lend themselves easily to exact quantitative measure’.69 Where they are unavoidable, grades should be regarded as something of a necessary evil or, in any event, ‘a minor matter’ rather than the ultimate goal of learning, as they are so often regarded today. What education ultimately demands of students is no different from what experience itself requires of us all: very simply that the student ‘do absolutely the best that he can under all circumstances’ and let the grades be what they will. Since there is no telos
124
The Educative Process
in the educative process save for more education, the only measure of success is whether students have developed a facility with the subject matter which allows them to pursue further study, to carry a line of thought further, or in general whether they have derived from a course what is derivable from it. To substitute for this the standard of passing or of achieving a certain grade, such as the ‘false and demoralizing standard’ that is the class average, sets the bar entirely too low and over time accustoms students to expect little of themselves in other areas of life as well.70 Dewey’s assessment of the importance or ultimate unimportance of grades, as he pointed out, is often faulted for itself setting too low a standard and for promoting a ‘soft pedagogy’ that fails both to reward achievement and to discourage undesirable intellectual habits. His reply that ‘the exact contrary holds’ stems from his belief that stressing the qualitative over the quantitative and process over end-states, while unusual in modern culture, better captures the meaning of education while also being a more demanding task for educators and students alike.71 Students who achieve a relatively high grade are given to believe that they are where they need to be and may therefore rest on their laurels while it is those at the bottom end who have more learning to do. Where the art of thinking is concerned, one is never entirely where one needs to be.
Dewey and the continent The dialectical and synthetic conception of thought that the early pragmatists defended shows such obvious affinity with strains in the German and French thought of the same period that one might have expected a productive dialogue to ensue between a James or a Dewey on one side and a Husserl or a Heidegger on the other, yet pragmatic instrumentalism and phenomenological hermeneutics developed largely in isolation from each other. While the founder of phenomenology himself was well acquainted with James’ writings and profoundly influenced by The Principles of Psychology, the influence was not mutual, nor did Husserl instill much interest in the American movement among his German students of the time. The European reception of pragmatism was undoubtedly influenced by politics and by a certain Old World arrogance that refused to view America as a possible home for philosophical innovation, a prejudice confirmed by such early and influential critics as Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore who dismissed the pragmatic movement with a wave of the hand as so much superficiality and crass Americanism. When pragmatism was not ignored completely it was saddled from the beginning with a reputation for superficiality, materialism, and naive optimism. Worse still, it became widely regarded as an apology for intellectual license, owing mostly to a merely
What Is Called Thinking?
125
passing familiarity with a few hypotheses – particularly as represented in James’ widely misread Pragmatism – and in part to James’ sometimes careless use of language. A text originally written for oral presentation, Pragmatism contains numerous formulations of the pragmatic theory of inquiry and truth, several (by no means most) of which lack the desired clarity and some of which demonstrate more regarding his fondness for pithy remarks than his considered view. His references to the concept of truth, for instance, as ‘only the expedient in the way of our thinking’, or ‘the name for whatever proves itself to be good in the way of belief’, stuck in the minds of many while doing nothing whatever to clarify the pragmatic conception of truth. James’ artful yet occasionally careless manner of writing in places led him to state that truth is the ‘expedient in almost any fashion’, a view taken by his critics as opening the door to irrationality and intellectual license, a suspicion seemingly confirmed by the argument of The Will to Believe.72 It is unfortunate that language of this kind, which does not begin to do justice to James’ considered position, much less that of Peirce or Dewey, would profoundly influence pragmatism’s early reception and occasion its immediate dismissal by many in Europe as well as in North America. Indeed, critics of pragmatism to this day continue to labor under standard misconceptions rooted in over-attention to pithy phrases of the kind cited above and under-attention to James’ and Dewey’s more precise exposition. In more careful moments, James emphasized that the ‘cash value’ of an idea, in which its truth consists, is to be understood strictly ‘in experiential terms’ or with respect to its phenomenological verifiability: ‘True ideas are those that we can assimilate, validate, corroborate, and verify. False ideas are those that we cannot. That is the practical difference it makes to us to have true ideas; that, therefore, is the meaning of truth, for it is all that truth is known-as.’73 The ‘satisfaction’ that truth affords is neither identified with the emotional satisfaction a belief may bring about nor as broad in meaning as his critics routinely suppose. For James, a statement passes for true for the reason that it produces experiential coherence which in turn may create a measure of consensus and makes it possible to negotiate our way about the phenomena, and not on the grounds that it produces an emotional or material payoff. While fond of economic metaphors which may at first glance support the crassly utilitarian reading of pragmatism, James in less casual moments clearly rejected the crass view for the coherentist one. In phenomenological terms, it is ‘the circumpressure of experience itself’ that is ‘the only real guarantee we have against licentious thinking’.74 A cognitive being that makes its way about a lifeworld by fashioning coherence and identifying connections between disparate phenomena does not ‘succeed’ in realizing its ‘practical interests’ by selecting beliefs that produce pleasure while doing violence to the phenomena as they present themselves. True ideas are those that save the
126
The Educative Process
phenomena and account for our various experiences, ideas that may be revised should a new experience contradict a previous conviction. Dewey was still clearer in this regard, carefully avoiding James’ occasional casualness of expression while insisting on the circumscription of terms such as ‘satisfaction’ and ‘practical interests’ to the immediate object of inquiry: Too often . . . when truth has been thought of as satisfaction, it has been thought of as merely emotional satisfaction, a private comfort, a meeting of purely personal need. But the satisfaction in question means a satisfaction of the needs and conditions of the problem out of which the idea, the purpose and method of action, arises. . . . Again when truth is defined as utility, it is often thought to mean utility for some purely personal end, some profit upon which a particular individual has set his heart. . . . As a matter of fact, truth as utility means service in making just that contribution to reorganization in experience that the idea or theory claims to be able to make. The usefulness of a road is not measured by the degree in which it lends itself to the purposes of a highwayman. It is measured by whether it actually functions as a road, as a means of easy and effective public transportation and communication. And so with the serviceableness of an idea or hypothesis as a measure of its truth.75 The satisfactoriness of an empirical belief consists exclusively in its capacity to predict future experience, account for present perceptions, and cohere with other relevant beliefs just as a true understanding reconciles the elements that belong to a given context and so allows us to grasp meaning. The ‘utility’ that is promoted by a hypothesis consists not in any extraneous psychological satisfaction on the part of the believer or community of believers, but in its ability to account coherently for, or save, all the relevant phenomena and allow for a resolution of the original difficulty. The problem that a true belief resolves is solely that which originally occasioned a given line of inquiry, and decidedly not any utilities merely supervening on that belief. Despite James’ and Dewey’s repeated clarifications, the reception of pragmatic thought in Europe would remain marred by misunderstanding and wilful ignorance, effectively preventing any meaningful exchange between pragmatism and phenomenology from taking place and leaving both to develop as separate traditions on separate continents. (Only in recent decades has pragmatism begun to receive a serious hearing in continental thought, owing largely to the efforts of such philosophers as Richard Rorty and Jürgen Habermas, among others.) Such disregard, however, was not one-sided. Dewey himself, despite being a voracious reader his entire life, and despite the fact that his early ‘acquaintance with Hegel’, as he stated in
What Is Called Thinking?
127
1930, ‘has left a permanent deposit in my thinking’, would turn his back resolutely on German thought in particular – partly, again, for obvious political reasons but partly for reasons more philosophical.76 Like so many Anglo-American assessments of German thought in the early decades of the twentieth century, Dewey’s assessment emphasized the connections that he believed he saw between German philosophy from Immanuel Kant onward and German culture more generally, including in particular the political culture that culminated in Hitler. Already in 1915, Dewey would write in a short book titled German Philosophy and Politics (undoubtedly not one of his more impressive achievements) that ‘there is no people so hostile to the spirit of a pragmatic philosophy’ as the Germans and that ‘supreme regard for the inner meaning of things, reverence for inner truth in disregard of external consequences of advantage or disadvantage, is the distinguishing mark of the German spirit’.77 Well prior to Hitler and indeed to the First World War, Dewey would adopt such a dim view of German philosophy’s antipragmatic bent toward the spiritual, the transcendental, the romantic, and the a priori, and away from the practical and political consequences of ideas that the German thinkers of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries with whom Dewey had a good deal in common would remain ignored and usually unread by him (and he did possess reading knowledge of German). The 38 volumes that comprise Dewey’s collected works contain not a single reference, for instance, to either Husserl or Heidegger, and it does appear that he did not read them. Even Dewey’s acquaintance with Nietzsche’s thought was surprisingly superficial and largely second-hand, the references to his works very few and passing. Still more surprising perhaps is the thesis of German Philosophy and Politics that it is none other than Kant who bore ultimate responsibility for the lamentable state of German political consciousness at the outbreak of the First World War due to his rigid separation of nature from the higher realm of spirit, the things in themselves, the will, and moral duty, and due as well to his dichotomy of reason and experience and his anti-consequentialist fanaticism regarding the categorical imperative. By the early twentieth century Dewey had come to view European culture ever more as ‘the Old World’ – more especially continental Europe, ‘and Germany in particular’ – in contrast to which American culture and American philosophy needed to assert itself. Two world wars, of course, did nothing to reverse his view, such that by 1944 he would remark that America must regard itself no longer as ‘an offshoot of Europe, culturally speaking’, but ‘as a New World in other than a geographical sense’. If the New World did not yet rival the Old in terms of artistic achievement, it was rapidly gaining ground in scientific advancement and in philosophical thought still more. ‘Philosophy’, he now asserted, ‘needed to be taken out of the hands
128
The Educative Process
of those who have identified it with barren intellectual gymnastic exercise and purely verbal analyses’ – which is to say the rationalists, the idealists, and their contemporary offspring.78 If Dewey never made common cause with the American isolationists of this period (and he did not), he may well have fallen into its philosophical counterpart. He was hardly alone in this, of course, yet his case is made especially unfortunate by the missed opportunity for exchange with his German colleagues who at the same time were engaged in equally radical and at times interestingly similar efforts to reconceive the nature of human thought.
Thinking in the pre-eminent sense Foremost among these is Martin Heidegger, with whose works Dewey’s often show interesting affinities. While the differences between their respective traditions and vocabularies of course run deep, both theorists sought to reconceive in an essentially phenomenological way the basic nature of human thought, identifying its intimate connection with practice, language, and culture as well as its relation to science. Both philosophers would remark upon the thoughtlessness of twentieth-century culture and speak of thinking in a higher sense of the word than what ordinarily passes for it. Thinking as rule-following, a matter of formally demonstrating the truth-value of propositions with reference to a foundation and abstract technique, would be replaced with a fundamentally creative conception, one that Dewey believed finds its highest expression in science and that Heidegger would contrast with science. What the latter would refer to as thinking in the pre-eminent sense surpasses method, including evidently the method of experimental inquiry that Dewey regarded as a model of thought in general. Thinking for Heidegger and the tradition of hermeneutics that he decisively transformed is not only experimental, in search of solutions, but interpretive, in search of meaning. That the process of inquiry includes interpretation and understanding was certainly not lost on Dewey, as we have seen, yet Heidegger would have undoubtedly regarded the former’s analysis of these terms as insufficient if we are intent upon overcoming the rationalistic excesses of Enlightenment foundationalism and doing justice to how, as a matter of phenomenological fact, we think. Dewey’s scientific model undoubtedly succeeds in capturing a good part of what one might call thinking, yet that it captures the whole of this phenomenon is somewhat more doubtful, as Heidegger’s work helps us to see. Particularly relevant here is the distinction the latter would draw between calculative and meditative thinking as well as his phenomenological investigations in Being and Time into the structures and conditions that are always already in play in the process of interpretation. The latter includes the
What Is Called Thinking?
129
as-structure of interpretation – that all perceiving is a perceiving-as this or that kind of thing – along with the hermeneutic circle, the thoroughgoing embeddedness of understanding within an historically conditioned horizon of language, practices, and prereflective interpretations. Interpreting particular objects invariably occurs against the background of an encompassing understanding of Being, one that constitutes one’s historical inheritance as a being-in-the-world or participant in a cultural tradition. Consciousness inhabits a lifeworld in the sense of a meaningful totality of relations that precede all explicit knowing and inferring, a world that we never stand apart from, as subject to object, nor grasp in its totality. Reflective thought in general is preceded, made possible, and also limited by prereflective and often unconscious background judgments against which particular interpretations are made. Heidegger’s influential hermeneutics of facticity shares much with Dewey’s view while also surpassing it in important respects. Dewey would often anticipate hypotheses that later received more explicit treatment in phenomenology and hermeneutics, including the contextual, historical, and linguistic nature of understanding. But where Dewey regarded scientific experimentation as a model for thinking in general, Heidegger considered it vital in an age increasingly dominated by science to draw attention to its limits and the dangers of a culture in which non-scientific modes of thought had become eclipsed. For all its merits, ‘science’, as Heidegger concisely put it, ‘does not think’.79 On the face of it, this is a preposterous claim, surely one that would have aroused the ire not only of Dewey and the pragmatists but of virtually all of twentieth-century intellectual culture. On closer inspection, it is a view that must be taken very seriously indeed. Two texts in particular – What Is Called Thinking? (1954, a text that coincidentally bears the same title as the present chapter) and Discourse on Thinking (1959) – find Heidegger remarking repeatedly upon the ‘growing thoughtlessness’ or the ‘flight from thinking’ that characterizes a scientifictechnological age.80 ‘[W]e are still not thinking’, Heidegger stated and restated. What could this conceivably mean, and moreover did Heidegger include himself in this ‘we’? He did indeed, or so he said: ‘we are still not thinking; none of us, including me who speaks to you, me first of all’. This ‘[m]ost thought-provoking’ of thoughts – that we are not thinking, ‘not yet capable of thinking’, nor even ‘ready to learn thinking’ – is surely one of Heidegger’s darker sayings, yet one that warrants no less attention for that reason. To grasp his meaning we must understand what he does and does not mean by thinking. To think is not to philosophize: But how dare anyone assert today that we are still not thinking, today when there is everywhere a lively and constantly more audible interest in
130
The Educative Process
philosophy, when almost everybody claims to know what philosophy is all about! Philosophers are the thinkers par excellence. They are called thinkers precisely because thinking properly takes place in philosophy. . . . But even if we have devoted many years to the intensive study of the treatises and writings of the great thinkers, that fact is still no guarantee that we ourselves are thinking. . . . On the contrary – preoccupation with philosophy more than anything else may give us the stubborn illusion that we are thinking just because we are incessantly ‘philosophizing’.81 The thoughtlessness of which Heidegger spoke extends to modern culture in general, including the intellectual culture of science and philosophy and was not merely a bit of social criticism or rebuke against the popular culture of the times. What passed for thinking in philosophy had become a technique of calculation far removed from thinking in its most ultimate sense. This reduction of thinking to technique would include not only the positivism and formalism that Dewey would also criticize but the latter’s experimental model no less. Here as well we are presented with a model of thought ‘that plans and investigates’; while indispensable in its sphere, it ‘always reckon[s] with conditions that are given’ and serves purposes that are conceived in advance. Thinking as calculation or problem-solving ‘is not meditative thinking, not thinking which contemplates the meaning which reigns in everything that is’.82 This ‘flight from thinking’ includes scientific inquiry no less than thought in its more popular forms. If in ordinary experience ‘we take in everything in the quickest and cheapest way, only to forget it just as quickly, instantly’ – an observation far more true today than in 1959 – a similar unreflectiveness is visible in science and technology as well.83 While ‘in themselves positively essential’, the sciences nonetheless possess a limited capacity to reveal that which is, and it is these limits of which the modern world had lost sight, Heidegger believed.84 It is science’s totalizing pretensions that is the main object of Heidegger’s critique, including the naive overestimation of its ability to know the world as it is in itself together with its lack of historical consciousness and the common tendency to regard science as a model of what philosophy should be. For Heidegger, as for Nietzsche before him, science cannot be more than a perspective and an interpretation of the world, a way of revealing beings that is both precise in its methods and singularly useful in its applications, yet an interpretation all the same. Like all interpretations, it reveals and conceals in the same gesture, there being no unconditioned perspective on what is, but partial and limited ways of revealing only. Heidegger’s distinction between thinking and the sciences is often mistaken as a disparagement of the latter in spite of his clarifications to the
What Is Called Thinking?
131
contrary, not unlike popular misconceptions of Dewey running in the opposite direction. Neither figure resorted to a naive adulation of science, nor was either inclined to disparage it in its own right. It was the dogmatic over-reach of science and technology, and the consequent delegitimation of non-technological modes of understanding, that greatly troubled Heidegger and which ought to trouble us still. A mode of thought that reduces nature to so many objects of planning and calculation or human beings to resources of a certain kind or a ‘standing-reserve’, something therefore to be used and used up, is ominous when countervailing ways of knowing are stripped of their legitimacy or appear out of step with the times. The twentieth century had become an age of ‘science-technology’ (for Heidegger a unified phenomenon), of calculation and control, and of the very kind of rational planning and problem-solving that Dewey held up as an ideal, as definitive of thought itself. That a single ‘way of revealing’ or mode of understanding the world could become totalized is the danger of which Heidegger warned, ‘that calculative thinking may someday come to be accepted and practiced as the only way of thinking’.85 It is a warning that applies far less to Dewey himself than to the positivists and rationalists whom Dewey himself criticized harshly, yet there can be no doubt that Heidegger would have included Dewey in his critique. Of special relevance in this critique is Heidegger’s distinction between calculative and meditative thinking. Calculative thought, which reaches its highest expression in science-technology, plans, manipulates, and predicts with a view ultimately to achieving a kind of mastery over everything that is, including human beings. While [n]o one can foresee the radical changes to come . . . technological advance will move faster and faster and can never be stopped. In all areas of his existence, man will be encircled ever more tightly by the forces of technology. These forces, which everywhere and every minute claim, enchain, drag along, press and impose upon man under the form of some technical contrivance or other – these forces, since man has not made them, have moved long since beyond his will and have outgrown his capacity for decision.86 Calculative rationality deduces and plans while understanding neither its limits nor the meaning of its object nor the very act of calculation itself. As it outstrips our will it transforms our relation to and perceptions of the world as a set of usable objects set over against ‘inner’ subjectivity. Whether it be theoretical or practical, scientific or philosophical, calculative thought is governed by a method that in principle anyone can follow and repeat; it purports to be free of subjectivity and bias, of partiality and prejudice, and to
132
The Educative Process
be an essentially technical affair of ascertaining an object’s nature and use value. It prizes efficiency and organization, clarity and precision in its methods, and certainty in its conclusions. Meditative thinking, by contrast, seeks depth of understanding over certainty and may be applied not only to learned discourses but to ordinary human experience no less. It follows no method and requires no special expertise. Thus, ‘anyone can follow the path of meditative thinking in his own manner and within his own limits’. If the human being ‘is a thinking, that is, a meditating being’, it falls to each one of us to take up this mode of thought and direct it particularly toward that which concerns us intimately. It is a mode of thought that produces no certainty, employs no technique, and gets no results apart from the understanding that it makes possible. Importantly, it is a way of thinking for which there is no model; it may or may not begin with a problematic situation and may or may not lead to its solution. Nor did Heidegger offer us a formal definition, there being a certain interpretive richness about the term that eludes straightforward analysis. What is clear, however, is that meditative thinking possesses a depth dimension that calculative thought does not, content as the latter is to remain at a surface level where technical precision and definite outcomes are sought rather than any deeper dimension of meaning. Meditative thought, in its orientation toward the meaning and uniqueness of beings rather than that about them that can be generalized, measured, or used, resists philosophical abstraction or formal modeling and possesses an openended and transformative quality that is consistent with experience as Erfahrung. It aims to reveal or ‘un-conceal’ particular beings in a manner closer to the artistic than the scientific, yet synonymous with neither. Thus in thinking about the eventuality of one’s own death, for example, one is not only, and not primarily, inquiring into a problem to be solved or reckoning with technicalities but reflecting without method or the possibility of a solution upon the meaning of an experience. Likewise one reflects upon an event in one’s past with an eye to interpreting its significance, understanding how it fashioned the person one has become or changed one in some particular way. One thinks about an historical event similarly in terms of what it meant for later generations or for a nation’s self-understanding, quite apart from any measurable generalities in terms of which that event can be known. One contemplates a work of art in similar terms: precisely not by squeezing it into a scientific or technical set of concepts but by allowing the work to speak to us as a unique work, one that conveys meaning and opens up a world for us. In such cases there is no problem to be solved, no causal relations to ascertain, nothing to quantify or represent, unless perhaps as a secondary matter. The point rather is to understand, to grasp a meaning that is singular and unrepeatable.
What Is Called Thinking?
133
Dewey’s model of thought as experimental inquiry here encounters its limits. Thinking does not follow a single track, or when it does – as for Heidegger it had – thought itself becomes dangerously narrowed and surface-level. That which resists problem-solving, representation in concepts, calculation, or control becomes literally unthinkable; we are reduced to silence before it or perhaps to speculation or unreasoning guesswork. The mode of thought that Heidegger somewhat ambiguously gestured toward is non-linear and transformative in the manner of experience itself. It changes one and leads one not toward any reassuring solution but to where one already stands, only transformed. We see this most obviously in the encounter with art: we emerge from the experience changed in a manner that we could not have predicted and that is not readily repeatable in others. We have understood something anew, or emerged from the experience with a new outlook or set of questions. Such thinking, as Heidegger would often say, is a ‘way’ rather than a technique, one that must be traveled to be understood. A method can be represented in the abstract while the thinking that is or that ‘builds a way’ cannot.87 Instead he likens it to traversing a path in the wood – one of uncertain destination, that is without a map but that contains the occasional ‘clearing’ in which something comes into view. Metaphors abound in Heidegger’s description of thinking: building, dwelling, clearing, the fourfold of earth and sky, gods and mortals. While I shall not undertake a detailed analysis of Heidegger’s metaphors, what they call attention to is the inexhaustibility of meditative thinking, its breadth and depth, and its capacity to bring into focus the meaningful dimension of its object without linearity or empty circularity. Dewey himself was certainly alive to this depth dimension of thinking and understanding while invariably insisting that it be brought under the umbrella of pragmatic inquiry. The difficulty to which Heidegger pointed, correctly in my view, is that not everything can be so described. Consider as a case in point the experience of wonder. The experimental model would regard this as a felt difficulty or perception of a problematic situation, thus as the starting point of investigation. This partially describes the experience, yet that it captures the whole of it is doubtful. Wonder has an open-ended quality to it and belongs still more at the conclusion of thinking than at its origin, if indeed thought can be said to have an origin at all. When reflective thinking, or a given line of it, culminates not in a definitive answer but in a heightened sense of wonder or awe in the face of the unknown, Dewey’s model would seem to deem this a failure of inquiry; the sense of wonder logically belongs to the beginning of the investigative process, not its end. Yet that it so often characterizes the end can hardly be counted a failing or a mark of incompleteness. It might fairly be said that thinking in general is
134
The Educative Process
incomplete, and in a few senses. It has neither an absolute point of origin – rather, it emerges from previous inquiries and is embedded in historically contingent understandings and symbolizing practices – nor an altogether settled conclusion. But for the more rigidly technical modes of calculative thought, intelligent thinking typically culminates in no final solution but in something far less definitive: a judgment, decision, or interpretation that is not dogmatically held but regarded as the best idea to emerge thus far. Here we recognize that thinking is of the nature not only of inquiry but of conversation. The conclusion that we settle upon is that which emerges from the conversation relatively unscathed, which withstands criticism with some success, provides more illumination than shadow, or creates fewer problems than it solves. Yet it is not final. This is illustrated dramatically in many of Plato’s dialogues, in which Socrates’ interlocutors, intent upon ascertaining the truth, in the end must settle for the idea that has withstood challenges with relative success, and the dialogue ends without the note of finality that Socrates’ line of questioning had led us to expect. The same point is illustrated in many a classroom discussion, including the most productive, in which once again no final determination is made and no consensus reached, yet a heightened sense of wonder has been aroused and a false self-certainty shaken. This experience of wonder may well lead to further inquiry, but the point that warrants emphasis is that it belongs no less at the conclusion of thought, and where this is not properly a conclusion at all but a thinking forward into a sort of expanse. Open-endedness, expansiveness, and undecidability belong to the structure of wonder, and it is an undecidability that must not be counted a failing. The best and most educative conversations may end this way, with more questions than answers, more possibilities than determinate conclusions. In Being and Time Heidegger would speak of the human being itself as more of the nature of a possibility of what it might become than a present actuality, and much the same can be said of our thinking; it never reaches a state of finality but presses onward in the manner of any growing thing. Its conclusions are at most temporary resting places while thought itself moves ever forward into what is unknown and possibly unknowable. Dewey himself was fond of organic and naturalist metaphors and often characterized education and thinking as a lifelong process, yet the model of inquiry itself captures very imperfectly the open-ended quality of thought that Heidegger drew to our attention. The notion of mystery warrants attention here as well. On a scientific model of thought, mystery is either banished altogether or consists in what is not known as of yet. Science rarely tells us what it does not know; it tells us what it does not know yet. The qualification is important for what it suggests about the limits of human knowledge. The notion of mystery has no place in
What Is Called Thinking?
135
a scientific vocabulary and can only translate as what remains to be discovered or explained, a problem yet to be solved, which of course is not what a mystery signifies at all. Like wonder, mystery is in principle open-ended. It signifies what is unknowable and yet that with which our thinking must nonetheless engage, and in a way that more closely approximates meditative thinking than experimental inquiry. As Gabriel Marcel would point out, in the encounter with mystery there is no space between the questioner and the question or the matter that is to be thought about, be it the nature of freedom, love, or life itself. It is not experienced as a problem – as an obstacle in my path, which requires a technique to resolve – but as a matter that concerns me in my existence.88 Other examples from everyday life of a thinking that can only very awkwardly be characterized as inquiry in Dewey’s sense are not difficult to find: the remembrance of personal experiences of joy or suffering may well occasion inquiry into the causes or consequences of such events, but fundamentally a remembrance of this kind involves an interpretation of their meaning and an appreciation of their emotional overtones; the experience of grief is not essentially an inquiry into a problematic situation but again an interpretive meditation upon the significance of a life now at an end and an equally important sense of loss; indeed many of the events in our lives that we look back upon as learning experiences have this character of forming us this way or that, perhaps deepening our experience or character yet without having solved a problem, unless we stretch the problem-solving model beyond Dewey’s meaning or truncate the experience itself. A history lesson on the Second World War certainly inquires into a wide variety of problems, but learning the lessons of the Holocaust or simply understanding the enormity of this occurrence does not comfortably fit within Dewey’s model. It can of course be made to fit, as theorists are wont to do, but not without a considerable loss of meaning. The student in this case must be transported in imagination into the point of view of the victims and witness the moral outrage of this event; thus do they begin to appreciate its significance in addition to any problems they may solve. Dewey may have wished to characterize this as developing a ‘sense of the problem’ – thus as an important preliminary stage within a larger investigative process – yet it would genuinely seem that the development of this sense belongs still more to the end of the process than to the beginning. Understanding an historical event and learning the lessons it teaches importantly involves a resonance of emotionally charged meaning in addition to and more fundamentally than any solutions reached. The same can be said of a work of literature. An educative experience of literature can mean any number of things, including Deweyan inquiry, but here again the model does not capture the full richness of the experience. A theoretical model of any kind would have difficulty capturing at once the
136
The Educative Process
imparting of information, the cultivation of aesthetic sensibility or taste, the art of interpretation and literary criticism, and the application of lessons learned to one’s own life. Interpretation of meaning once again seems a better umbrella term than experimental inquiry, but even this term is unlikely to include everything that is involved in thinking about or having an educative experience of literature. Theoretical models always have their limits, yet Dewey insisted that thought as inquiry is sufficient to cover all the various phenomena, including the less linear ones, that we associate with this word. Such phenomena would include such intangible matters as suggestiveness, intimations, provocations, and the art of asking questions and of seeing what is questionable – something that, as Gadamer has remarked, no method can teach.89 The questioning act often falls within Dewey’s model, as either the articulation of a problem or the formation of an hypothesis, yet not every question advances an hypothesis, describes a problem, or even permits of a definite answer. Some of the most important questions are precisely those that remain open-ended and leave us in a state of wonder while also, but perhaps less essentially, leading us to hazard opinions of one kind or another. The human sciences are replete with questions that provoke us this way and that, and which appear to prepare us for ensuing inquiry complete with the promise of an answer. The answer sometimes comes, yet rather often it does not, sometimes because the question is badly formulated or contains a false assumption and at other times because of the matter itself that we are questioning. What is the meaning of the French Revolution? What did the collapse of the Soviet Union teach us about a wide variety of social issues? What does War and Peace teach us about human nature or war? What is the good life for human beings? What is the meaning of Being? These questions give rise to thought certainly, and not merely to empty speculation. Perhaps we have comprehended a meaning, become attuned in a certain way, let go of our dogmatism, or become open to possibilities we had not seen. Perhaps we have replaced an old and fruitless line of questioning with new questions, ones better articulated or more likely to shed light on a certain phenomenon even while remaining unanswered. This is precisely the form that intellectual advances often take: abandoning old questions for new ones, where the answers are something of a secondary matter. The more eminent thinkers are known not only or even primarily for the arguments and theories that they advance in answer to the questions they pose but for the questions themselves, questions that others may take up and refine. This accent upon apparent preliminaries – formulating the question, distinguishing what is from what is not worthy of being called into question, an openness to possibilities of one kind or another – is part of what we may learn from Heidegger together with the manner in which our thinking has always already been pre-formed by an ontological preunderstanding that is
What Is Called Thinking?
137
our historical inheritance. It is typical of Heidegger’s own works, as one recent commentator points out, that ‘[t]hey are all more or less preparatory, with some having more of the character of a leap into a radically different way of thinking in their attempt to bring “be-ing itself” to language’.90 How many times, for instance, would Heidegger formulate and reformulate the question of thinking in What Is Called Thinking? or of being in Being and Time? Not one to reach for the quick answer, Heidegger in some ways provides a model for the unhurried meditative thinking for which he called, including at times the poetic thinking of which he spoke in his later period. Thinking in the pre-eminent sense includes some encroachment into the poetic, and for Heidegger has quite as much to do with mythos as logos. The thinking that transforms us partakes of the poetic and mythical, in spite of the Western tradition’s repeated attempts to sanitize thought by abolishing the poetic, mythical, and rhetorical. Greek philosophy, as the story goes, undertook a profound transformation in thought ‘from mythos to logos’, and elevated reason decisively above these now ill-reputed modes of utterance. By Nietzsche’s time the rational or Apollonian dimension of thought had won such a decisive victory over the Dionysian that it had led thought into a lamentable condition of dogmatic rationalism and beyond this to a larger cultural enervation and decline of the instincts. The rights of the Dionysian had to be rehabilitated, which Nietzsche sought to effect through such devices as the eternal return, the Übermensch, amor fati, the will to power, and a variety of critiques and provocations that, while experimental, do not conform to Dewey’s scientific model of experimentation. While Heidegger himself would not take up Nietzsche’s conception of philosophy as a gay science, he did call for a reconnection of logos and mythos, particularly at the level of language. As Heidegger expressed it, Myth means the telling word. For the Greeks, to tell is to lay bare and make appear. . . . Mythos is what has its essence in its telling – what is apparent in the unconcealedness of its appeal. The mythos is that appeal of foremost and radical concern to all human beings which makes man think of what appears, what is in being. Logos says the same; mythos and logos are not, as our current historians of philosophy claim, placed into opposition by philosophy as such; on the contrary, the early Greek thinkers are precisely the ones to use mythos and logos in the same sense.91 To think is to say what is telling, to make the object of thought apparent in language – an achievement of poetry and art no less than of philosophy and of mythos no less than logos, if indeed there is a meaningful distinction to be drawn here. Heidegger’s efforts, or Nietzsche’s, to remythologize thinking after a fashion have little to do with scientific inquiry, yet in an age that is so
138
The Educative Process
thoroughly dominated by science and technology we would do well to take such efforts seriously. Thought that travels only by tried and true avenues or that conforms to a single model is in a precarious condition indeed. Under this condition a thinking that is ‘outside the box’, as the current expression has it, or tolerably original becomes difficult, to say the least. When even the experimental is beholden to method, and a single method at that, a way of thinking that is genuinely transformative and that allows something radically new to be said becomes ever more improbable, something to be debarred as so much subjective opinion. If to think for Heidegger is to pronounce the telling word upon a certain object or theme – the word that brings a being into a state of unconcealedness – it also signifies a certain mode of relating to the object. Heidegger illustrated this point with the example of the cabinet-maker’s apprentice and the kind of learning or thinking that is undertaken in the course of apprenticeship. The apprentice must learn in the straightforward sense of acquiring useful facts about wood, tool usage, and what not, but beyond this he must develop a rather less tangible way of thinking. One learns the cabinetmaker’s art by learning to think like a cabinet-maker, which means learning how to relate to the object of one’s craft: ‘If he is to become a true cabinetmaker, he makes himself answer and respond above all to the different kinds of wood and to the shapes slumbering within wood – to wood as it enters into man’s dwelling with all the hidden riches of its nature.’ It is a deeper ‘relatedness to wood’ that ‘maintains the whole craft’, an attunement that transcends the purely practical and economic without falling into mysticism.92 One might say the same about the musician or the writer: one learns to think like a musician by acquiring a certain mode of relatedness – ambiguous, intangible, but essential – to one’s instrument, a relatedness that is likewise removed from the mystical and the merely technical. The advanced musician knows how to distinguish the master from the technician, and it is not a distinction that turns on any ability to play notes. The same can be said of the writer and of the relation to language that the novice must learn. Could we not apply the point quite generally and say that learning to think like an artist, a chef, or an athlete transcends both informational knowledge and an ability to solve problems in Dewey’s sense, that what is decisive in all such cases is the matter of how one relates and responds to the object of one’s labors, whether these are material things or ideas? There is nothing mystical in this; while it is ambiguous to speak of thinking as a ‘way’, as incessantly preparatory, open-ended, and transformative, and as ‘a craft, a “handicraft”’, ‘something like building a cabinet’, this general characterization captures a dimension of thinking that Dewey’s model does not and that simplistic contemporary notions of critical thinking do not. Like experience in the sense of Erfahrung, such thinking is neither altogether active nor passive. It
What Is Called Thinking?
139
demands much of us or even has its way with us, so to speak, even as it remains our own thought, one that does not think itself. In a sense it is perfectly true that the cabinet-maker responds to the wood and the poet responds to language. It is equally true that wood and language do not form themselves. But what Heidegger’s phenomenological account adds to Dewey’s is that were we less beholden to science and technology we might better understand the simultaneously active, experimental or form-bestowing as well as the passive, responsive, or transformative dimension of thinking. To think is not to preside over being. I would like to conclude this chapter with a few remarks concerning thought in either Dewey’s or Heidegger’s sense of the word, and certain conditions of the present time, both social and educational, that are less than conducive to the manner of thinking of which these philosophers spoke. Heidegger’s ominous-sounding words, ‘we are still not thinking’, ring about as true today as they did when he pronounced them, and not only in the sense that he intended but in Dewey’s sense and some others. Our classrooms are still not inquiring, nor are they imparting habits of mind that lead students into a deeper examination of their experience. After decades of research into curriculum, the psychology of the young, and pedagogical methodology, students of today appear no more inclined toward reflectiveness, in whatever sense of the word one prefers, than they ever did, if indeed they are not still more fascinated by the outward and superficial. A mind that is fashioned within an order of technology, calculation, and performativity, of standardized information and standardized testing, learns to follow rules. According to widespread belief, it was in the olden days – whenever we imagine these to be – that students were conscripted into ways of thinking that were conformist and oppressive while today students are thinking for themselves, critically and scientifically. Educational research has made this possible, and but for the interference of the unlearned it would produce a generation of critical thinkers with profitable careers and enviable selfesteem. Science too has its mythology. When thought in general is reduced to a single form, abolishing the remainder, the educated mind becomes adapted to techniques and expects to find rules and methods governing all aspects of its existence. It looks to, and readily finds, a special class of experts who are the guardians of such techniques, and it submits to their instruction as fervently as in any olden days of educational authoritarianism. The authorities and the rules of thought may both have changed, but this matters less than the thoughtlessness that remains the outcome of contemporary education. The thoughtlessness of our times undoubtedly assumes a different form than in the past. The variety of this that was the focus of Dewey’s criticism has been replaced by standardization and an inauthentic scientification of the
140
The Educative Process
learning process. In spite of contemporary catchwords of empowerment, of skills and critical thinking, and of cognitive, social, and psychological development, students of today are trained to take their place in the economy as ever they were, to heed economic and technological imperatives, to defer to expertise, and to adjust themselves to rules of thought and action so ubiquitous and seemingly without alternative as to take on an appearance of perfect naturalness. It is only natural and progressive, we now think, to look to technology or to some method that either is grounded in or exhibits the trappings of scientific knowledge should the need for thinking arise. What this view continues to overlook is that thinking is an art. No scientific or logical model, whether Dewey’s or more recent ones, can capture the complexity of human knowing and understanding. At most, such models succeed in formalizing one aspect of a larger process, and in the usual course of things mistake the part for the whole. A fact we shall not escape is that the intelligent mind, whatever it is, is too multifarious to be captured in a theoretical model or technique; its reasonings and imaginings, its ways of knowing and experiencing defy reduction to a method. Dewey’s efforts to theorize intelligence succeed in some measure in describing phenomenologically ‘how we think’ yet overlook the limits of the experimental model. More recent efforts to the same end commit the same error, and we shall continue to err as long as we suppose that what is by its nature an art might be put on the secure path of a science. Like experience, thinking is an interpretively rich notion; it includes understanding and critique, analysis and synthesis, interrogation and explanation, narrative and metaphor, inference, judgment, taste, discrimination, remembering, information, and a good deal else – most of which have little to do with technique. Understanding and interpretation, for instance, conform to no methods but the hermeneutic circle; they strive for coherence and consensus, however these are not formal rules but very rough guidelines only. No technique instructs us on how to read Plato, how to respond to the meaning that emerges, or how to critique what we read or apply it to our own circumstances. Nor is there a method of constructing a narrative or fashioning a good metaphor – if a good metaphor is one that brings into sudden proximity two items that had appeared entirely disparate, and in such a way that something new comes to light. Recent trends toward standardization and technologization are a veritable recipe for unreflectiveness. Standardized information presages standardized beliefs and values, as the advocates of cultural literacy well realize. Technologization facilitates the acquisition of information while subtly transforming thought itself or even removing the need for it. It simplifies and orders matters for our convenience while dumbing down nearly everything it touches. Internet research, to take an obvious case in point, creates the illusion that the student is inquiring in a way no different from the old-
What Is Called Thinking?
141
fashioned reading of books signed out from a library but for its superior efficiency. Thinking as gaining quick access to highly simplified, abbreviated, and predigested information coupled with a bit of computerized cutting and pasting – a process that for many a student passes quite satisfactorily for thinking – is, I would suggest, not the genuine article. If Heidegger had good cause to remark in 1959 that ‘[t]he world now appears as an object open to the attacks of calculative thought, attacks that nothing is believed able any longer to resist’, it may now appear as so much information on a computer screen, purified of unnecessary detail, complexity, precision, imagination, and style.93 Why go to the trouble, many now reason, of plowing through Being and Time, with its difficult prose and complex argumentation, when one can access websites that have boiled down all the necessary information to a paragraph in plain English? Why read War and Peace with its long-winded chapters in which nothing happens, when one can find plot summaries with thematic analysis sufficient for any examination? Questions of this kind are now asked in earnest, not embarrassment, and not only by the lean-minded. Were thinking one day to disappear from the face of the earth it would be due far less to intellectual laziness than to a want of opportunities for its exercise, to the simple lack of need for it due to an iron cage of calculative rationality, performativity, and standardization containing one and all. This day is not at hand, yet deeply rooted social and educational conditions of our times are reducing rather than increasing opportunities for the kind of thinking of which Dewey and Heidegger both spoke, trends that see thinking in the classroom either as a simple matter of being informed or as an idle luxury, thinking in the workplace as an obstacle to efficiency, thinking in ordinary conversation as an affectation, and thinking in solitude as evidence of mental disturbance. Heidegger was correct: ‘We are still not thinking.’ He did exaggerate the point; we are thinking, but in too restricted a capacity, and we are losing sight of the need or even the possibility of thinking differently. Dewey was correct as well: thought is experimental. Yet it is experimental in a way or to a degree that Dewey did not see. Experimentation includes the incalculable, the metaphorical and the questioning, the mysterious and open-ended. Not everything that counts as thinking can be made to fit a single model, nor is every intelligent course of thought a problem to be solved. Much as we have always sought, and will no doubt continue seeking, to codify thinking, to reduce it to a system of rules and thus call it to order, it remains that thinking itself, most especially in its higher reaches and its inventive capacity, has a way of leaving the rules behind. Our impatient culture may long for the ready solution and the measurable outcome, for the self-certainty and ease of mind that technical models often promise, but much of this is an illusion. There is not always a code to be cracked, and if we would speak of thinking
142
The Educative Process
as it is, then we must speak of it as an art that sometimes draws upon abstract methods of one kind or another and sometimes does not.
Notes 1. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 160. 2. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 315. 3. Dewey, ‘The Need for Orientation’ (1935). LW 11: 164. ‘Philosophies of Freedom’ (1928). LW 3: 112. 4. Dewey, The Quest for Certainty (1929). LW 4: 179. 5. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938). LW 12: 121. 6. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 152. 7. Ibid., 165. 8. Dewey, ‘The Challenge of Democracy to Education’ (1937). LW 11: 185. 9. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 159. 10. As Dewey expressed this point: ‘Thus the tenets of political and economic liberal faith are made the criterion of a liberal education and mind. And here also it may be stated that even if these views are sound, the mark of a liberal mind is not that they are held, but is the way in which they are reached and accepted.’ Dewey, ‘The Prospects of the Liberal College’ (1924). MW 15: 203. 11. See, for instance, Dewey, ‘Bankruptcy of Modern Education’ (1927). LW 3: 277. 12. One representative passage reads: ‘But the child who has been most perfectly trained as to conduct, the one who acts in every way as he is told to act and even holds the opinions which he is told to hold, is quite apt not to be educated at all. He may make a good soldier, he may make a “good citizen”, in the sense that he may be depended upon not to murder or steal, not to drink, swear, gamble, or get married too often: but such a person may only be trained; he may not be educated at all. It is quite possible that he cannot think.’ Charles W. Wood, ‘Report of Interview with John Dewey’ (1922). MW 13: 428. 13. For an analysis of the pragmatist theory of truth, see Chapter 2 in my Theorizing Praxis: Studies in Hermeneutical Pragmatism (New York: Peter Lang, 2000), in which I defend this theory in its Jamesian and Deweyan formulations and bring it into conversation with the hermeneutical conception of truth articulated by Martin Heidegger and Hans-Georg Gadamer. 14. Dewey, ‘Preface’ to Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938). LW 12: 4. See William James, Pragmatism and The Meaning of Truth (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975). 15. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 144. 16. C. S. Peirce, Collected Papers, vol. 5 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1931–1958), 400. 17. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 144. 18. Dewey, ‘The Challenge of Democracy to Education’ (1937). LW 11: 184. 19. Dewey, The Quest for Certainty (1929). LW 4: 200. 20. Dewey made explicit the point concerning the methods of the natural sciences not being transferrable to humanistic inquiry in a footnote to an essay from 1949: ‘The word “methods” is italicized as a precaution against a possible misunderstanding which would be contrary to what is intended. What is needed is not the carrying over of procedures that have approved themselves in physical science, but new methods as adapted to human issues and problems, as methods already in scientific use have shown themselves to be in physical subject matter.’ Dewey, ‘Philosophy’s Future in our Scientific Age: Never Was Its Role More Crucial’ (1949). LW 16: 379. 21. Dewey, ‘Science as Subject Matter and as Method’ (1910). MW 6: 78. A few passages
What Is Called Thinking?
22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30.
31.
32. 33. 34.
35. 36. 37. 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45. 46.
143
that do approach a thoroughgoing scientific idealism may be found in MW 6: 78; MW 9: 196; LW 3: 101; LW 5: 115; LW 13: 279–80. Dewey, Individualism, Old and New (1929). LW 5: 115. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 227. Dewey, The Quest for Certainty (1929). LW 4: 181. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 157. Dewey, The Quest for Certainty (1929). LW 4: 181. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 181. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 155. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 118–19. As Peirce expressed the point: ‘In sciences in which men come to agreement, when a theory has been broached, it is considered to be on probation until this agreement is reached. After it is reached, the question of certainty becomes an idle one, because there is no one left who doubts it. We individually cannot reasonably hope to attain the ultimate philosophy which we pursue; we can only seek it, therefore, for the community of philosophers. Hence, if disciplined and candid minds carefully examine a theory and refuse to accept it, this ought to create doubts in the mind of the author of the theory himself.’ C. S. Peirce, ‘Some Consequences of Four Incapacities’. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, vol. 2, 1868, 140. James repeatedly emphasized this point, perhaps most eloquently in the following text: ‘The trail of the human serpent is thus over everything. Truth independent; truth that we find merely; truth no longer malleable to human need; truth incorrigible, in a word; such truth exists indeed superabundantly – or is supposed to exist by rationalistically minded thinkers; but then it means only the dead heart of the living tree, and its being there means only that truth also has its paleontology and its “prescription”, and may grow stiff with years of veteran service and petrified in men’s regard by sheer antiquity. But how plastic even our oldest truths nevertheless really are has been vividly shown in our day by the transformation of logical and mathematical ideas, a transformation which seems even to be invading physics.’ James, Pragmatism, 37. Dewey, The Quest for Certainty (1929). LW 4: 221. Dewey, ‘Social Purposes in Education’ (1923). MW 15: 167–8. As Dewey wrote in the same essay, ‘We must develop a taste in science or art, not only for those who are going to be scientists or artists, but also for those who, when leisure time comes, will be interested in reading or hearing something of nature, or literature, or have a capacity to enjoy music and the drama. This will create an active demand for the better things instead of the poorer things. These, I repeat, seem to me to be the three general phases of the problem of realizing the social purpose of the school which teachers, and especially those who are training other teachers, have to deal with.’ Dewey, ‘Social Purposes in Education’ (1923). MW 15: 169. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 148, 163. Dewey, ‘Foreword to Argumentation and Public Discussion’ (1936). LW 11: 515. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 148. Dewey, ‘John Dewey Responds’ (1950). LW 17: 85. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 118. Dewey, ‘Context and Thought’ (1931). LW 6: 5. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 114, 171–2. Dewey, ‘Understanding and Prejudice’ (1929). LW 5: 396. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 225, 237, 226–7. Ibid., 233. Ibid., 236. Dewey, Psychology (1887). EW 2: 180.
144 47. 48. 49. 50. 51. 52. 53.
54. 55. 56. 57. 58. 59. 60. 61. 62. 63. 64. 65.
66. 67. 68. 69. 70. 71. 72. 73. 74. 75. 76.
77. 78. 79. 80. 81. 82.
The Educative Process Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 301. Dewey, ‘The Inclusive Philosophic Idea’ (1928). LW 3: 51. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 301, 214–15. Dewey, Art as Experience (1934). LW 10: 270. On this point, also see MW 9: 7; LW 2: 57; LW 6: 11–13; and LW 10: 274–5. Dewey, Experience and Nature (1925). LW 1: 40. Dewey, Art as Experience (1934). LW 10: 276, 271; ‘Imagination’ (1902). LW 17: 242. Also see EW 2: 168. In an essay from 1928, for example, he would write: ‘If one looks at the overt and outer phenomena, at what I may call the public and official, the externally organized, side of our life, my own feeling about it would be one of discouragement. We seem to find everywhere a hardness, a tightness, a clamping down of the lid, a regimentation and standardization, a devotion to efficiency and prosperity of a mechanical and quantitative sort.’ Dewey, ‘A Critique of American Civilization’ (1928). LW 3: 134. Dewey, ‘The Future of Philosophy’ (1947). LW 17: 469. Dewey, ‘The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy’ (1917). MW 10: 3, 4. Dewey, ‘Bankruptcy of Modern Education’ (1927). LW 3: 278; Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 178; Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 71. Dewey, Education and the Social Order (1934). LW 9: 180. Dewey, ‘Some Stages of Logical Thought’ (1900). MW 1: 158. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 335. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 43. Dewey, ‘Academic Freedom’ (1902). MW 2: 61. Dewey, ‘Freedom in Workers’ Education’ (1929). LW 5: 332. Dewey, ‘Academic Freedom’ (1902). MW 2: 56. Charles W. Wood, ‘Report of Interview with Dewey’ (1922). MW 13: 428. On this last point, Dewey recommended ‘a certain atmosphere of informality, because experience has proven that formalization is hostile to genuine mental activity and to sincere emotional expression and growth’. Dewey, ‘Progressive Education and the Science of Education’ (1928). LW 3: 258. Dewey, ‘Lectures vs. Recitations: A Symposium’ (1891). EW 3: 147. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 56. Dewey, ‘Education, Direct and Indirect’ (1909). MW 3: 244. Dewey, The Educational Situation (1901). MW 1: 271. Dewey, ‘Education, Direct and Indirect’ (1909). MW 3: 245, 244. Ibid., 244. James, Pragmatism, 106, 42, 106. Ibid., 97. James, The Meaning of Truth, 47. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 170. Dewey, ‘From Absolutism to Experimentalism’ (1930). LW 5: 154. Dewey’s early Hegelianism was heavily influenced by the Anglo-American idealism of figures such as T. H. Green in Britain and Dewey’s own doctoral adviser at Johns Hopkins University, George Sylvester Morris. Dewey, German Philosophy and Politics (1915). MW 8: 152, 153. Dewey, ‘Challenge to Liberal Thought’ (1944). LW 15: 274, 272. Heidegger, What Is Called Thinking? trans. J. G. Gray (New York: Harper and Row, 1968), 8. Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking, trans. J. Anderson and E. H. Freund (New York: Harper and Row, 1966), 45. Heidegger, What Is Called Thinking?, 4, 14, 4, 3, 5, 4–5. Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking, 46.
What Is Called Thinking? 83. 84. 85. 86. 87. 88. 89. 90. 91. 92. 93.
145
Ibid., 45. Heidegger, What Is Called Thinking?, 14. Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking, 56. Ibid., 51. Heidegger, ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, trans. W. Lovitt, in Basic Writings, ed. David Farrell Krell (New York: HarperCollins, 1993), 311. See especially Gabriel Marcel, Man Against Mass Society, trans. G. S. Fraser (South Bend: St Augustine’s Press, 2008). Gadamer, Truth and Method, 365. Gail Stenstad, Transformations: Thinking After Heidegger (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2006), 52. Heidegger, What Is Called Thinking?, 10. Ibid., 14–15. Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking, 50.
This page intentionally left blank
PA RT 2
Education in the Human Sciences
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 4
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker From the time in the early modern era when philosophers became gradually absorbed into the university to become the new breed of academic professional that is the secular professor of philosophy, there is no area of practice with which philosophers have been more intimately acquainted in our nine-to-five existences than the practice of education. Since roughly the eighteenth century, philosophers in the main have been university educators, a consideration that one might expect would cause more of us to inquire into the principles and conditions of this practice than has in fact been the case. Like other matters of social philosophy, the question of education is a topic on which philosophy professors, irrespective of our field of specialization, believe ourselves eminently qualified to pronounce an opinion, yet beyond the bounds of university politics and our own classroom we typically elect to hold our peace and to leave the matter for administrators and education department faculties to sort out among themselves. Historically speaking, this is a recent phenomenon. Prior to the era of professionalization, and especially prior to the twentieth century, the great philosophers of the Western tradition have typically had a great deal to say on the subject, quite apart from whether they were educators themselves or not. Thus Plato and Aristotle, Augustine and Aquinas, Descartes, Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke, Leibniz, Rousseau, Kant, Hegel, Mill, Nietzsche, and a great many others all made important contributions to the philosophy of education, while in more recent times philosophers have been somewhat more reticent on this matter than might have been expected. So much so, in fact, that in the educational literature of the past century the philosophers of note who stand out as exceptions do so rather prominently: Alfred North Whitehead, Bertrand Russell, and – a philosopher never known for reticence – Dewey stand out notably among major philosophers of the twentieth century for their writings in the philosophy of education. When we look back to the Greeks, of course, we find the connection between the love of wisdom and a preoccupation with education to be far from accidental. Plato’s lengthy discussion in the Republic of the kind of education that the guardian class and the philosopher-king should receive is hardly a secondary issue in Plato’s conception of the just state, nor is the 149
150
Education in the Human Sciences
question of education ultimately separable for Aristotle and many other classical thinkers from one of philosophy’s most basic concerns: the nature of the good life. If the human being’s essential nature is its rationality – its possession of the logos – then the good life is the life that is proper to a rational being: the life of disinterested contemplation, of scientific, mathematical, or philosophical study. From the beginning, then, the fate of philosophy was inseparable from the fate of education, while the ‘educational enterprise’, in Dewey’s words, ‘was regarded as the systematic means by which the good life was to be arrived at and maintained: the life full, excellent, rich, for the individual center of that life, and the life good for the community of which the individual was a member’.1 Philosophy’s original connection with education was indeed part of a broader association of the love of wisdom with the conduct of life, with a wider outlook on the natural and human world, and ultimately with social aims, as the example of Plato well illustrates. It is not an accident of history that Plato founded the Academy or Aristotle the Lyceum, nor were these schools created as a secondary or unphilosophical undertaking. Instead they were to form the proper abode of philosophy itself and to put into practice the cultivation of wisdom and the intellectual virtues that defined both education and the best way of life for rational beings. Dewey’s philosophy of education in many ways represents a continuation of this Greek ideal, modified of course to suit modern conditions but continuing the idea that the ultimate aims of education transcend the acquisition of information or technical skill to include the business of thinking itself – the cultivation of intellectual capacity, the fashioning of ideas, and the resolution of whatever problems beset a society. Where there is genuine education, and genuine philosophy, the two are vitally connected not only to each other but to the urgent social questions of the day, to the fate of democracy and the condition of the culture of which one is a part. Today, however, in the era of professionalization and specialization the philosophy of education has become a relatively marginal subdiscipline within what is termed ‘applied’ or ‘social philosophy’, where ‘applied’ and ‘social’ are contrasted with the ostensibly ‘core’ branches of philosophy – metaphysics, logic, epistemology, and philosophy of language – while within social philosophy itself the theory of education most often takes a back seat to ethics and political theory. Despite its impressive pedigree in Greek thought and the ensuing tradition, and despite the burgeoning literature in the field that has emerged in recent decades, the theory of education has been effectively demoted to a minor specialty within the contemporary philosophy profession. This is reflected in the course offerings of philosophy departments at the present time, where seminars at the graduate level are seldom offered in this field while at the undergraduate level perhaps as many as a single course is taught, most often as a ‘service’ course attended mainly
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
151
by students in other disciplines. Eyebrows are seldom raised when philosophy departments offer no courses whatever on the subject or defer the matter to educational departments wherein the philosophy of education again takes a back seat, this time to specific empirical inquiries or technical issues rather more in the spirit of social science than philosophy. How did it come to pass that the philosophy of education has become a minor specialty within rather than a vital and essential part of philosophy, and at a time when philosophers are most all of us professional educators? What does it signify for philosophy itself when this field of inquiry is held to be far removed from the ‘core’ areas of thought? These are questions that greatly concerned Dewey, as indeed they may concern us all. It is a topic to which he would return again and again, from the beginning of his career to the end, and on which he would write with unusual passion. His answer took the form of a surprisingly scathing indictment of a great deal of the philosophy of his time as it was undertaken by academic specialists. The ultimate concerns of both education and philosophy, for Dewey, are the fundamental problems that affect a culture at a given time and the articulation of intelligent solutions, to look beneath the surface of events, and to think, in the most expansive sense of the word, of how things might be otherwise. As Dewey would write as late as 1947, ‘The principal task of philosophy is to get below the turmoil that is particularly conspicuous in times of rapid cultural change, to get behind what appears on the surface, to get to the soil in which a given culture has its roots.’2 It is to attain a degree of wisdom in the conduct of life, including both the life of the individual and the broader life of the society, and to turn human knowledge in the direction of the practical, the social, and the experiential. The principal task of education is to render students capable of precisely this, not in the sense of transforming them into specialists in whatever degree is optimally possible but in the sense of cultivating habits that render them no longer ‘at the mercy of every intellectual breeze that happens to blow’, that eliminate the gullibility, the parochialism, and the docility of mind that Dewey viewed as commonplace in modern culture.3 What Dewey found, however, when he surveyed the professional philosophical scene toward the end of the nineteenth century and in the first half of the twentieth, was both the end of the historical connection of philosophy and education and the decline of the Greek ideal of philosophy itself. So often did Dewey express disdain for what philosophy had become in the hands of the professors that it is difficult to select for the purpose of brief citation among the innumerable remarks he would express over the decades to the effect that the classical love of wisdom is ‘becoming a form of Busywork for a few professionals’.4 A good place to begin – and I shall endeavor to keep this brief, despite both the eloquence of many such remarks and my
152
Education in the Human Sciences
complete agreement with the sentiments they express – is a short essay from 1891 entitled ‘The Scholastic and the Speculator’. This remarkable text finds Dewey comparing the philosophical specialists of the day with the scholastics of the Middle Ages. Where the medieval schoolmen had abstracted Aristotle from any living connection with Greek culture and in the zeal for a system treated his texts in a purely formal and contextless fashion, when the scholastics ‘had suffocated Aristotle by removing him from the conditions of life’ and then ‘proceeded to dismember the remains’, so the philosopher of the present inquires into an object by tearing it out of its context and analyzing it, proffering cut-and-dried definitions, drawing razor-thin distinctions, and engaging in what appears to all the world to be purely formal and verbal exercises. Dewey continued: Even the miser, I suppose, has to do something with his gold, or else he wouldn’t know he had it. He must count it over, he must jingle it together, he must bury his fingers in it and roll the coins about. So the Scholastic had to use his learning in some way. He pulled it this way and pulled it that until he pulled it all to pieces. When anything is abstracted, when it is taken off by itself, having lost its connections, all that remains is to go over and over the same thing, dissecting, dividing, analyzing, and then sorting out and piling up the fragments. Distinction-making and collecting always accompany the scholastic habit. The reflective object’s very life consists in its contextuality and organic connections with other objects and processes, yet this is precisely what is lost sight of when the primary business of thinking consists of an abstraction and analysis that at the end of the day fails to return to the world of experience and the object’s ‘place in the movement of life’. Modern philosophy, far from putting an end to the scholastics’ ways, instead gives them different form and a far broader range of application. Where the schoolmen were limited to the texts of Aristotle and the Scriptures, the specialists of modern times may turn their gaze in any direction, toward the entire domain of thought and language. As he continued, The monastic cell has become a professional lecture hall; an endless mass of ‘authorities’ have taken the place of Aristotle. Jahresberichte, monographs, journals without end occupy the void left by the commentators upon Aristotle. If the older Scholastic spent his laborious time in erasing the writing from old manuscripts in order to indite thereon something of his own, the new Scholastic has also his palimpsest. He criticizes the criticisms with which some other Scholastic has criticized other criticisms, and the writing upon writings goes on till the substructure of reality is long obscured.5
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
153
These sentiments from Dewey’s early period were repeated frequently throughout his career. While applying them very generally to the condition of contemporary inquiry across the disciplines, he continually singled out philosophy as ‘the chief wrong-doer in this matter’.6 Philosophical thought, in Dewey’s estimation of it, had become ‘reduced . . . to a show of elaborate terminology, a hair-splitting logic, and a fictitious devotion to the mere external forms of comprehensive and minute demonstration’. It exhibited ‘an overdeveloped attachment to system for its own sake’, ‘an over-pretentious claim to certainty’, ‘a hateful division of theory and practice’, and an ‘aloofness’ from the world which represents an ‘unconscious protective reaction’ compelling philosophers to retreat into increasingly narrow avenues of thought.7 Philosophers had become a socially isolated and inward-looking class of professionals, a new cultural elite who regarded themselves as above the fray of what Dewey often called ‘the problems of men’, whose ‘problems’ are strictly their own, and who criticize the Deweyan pragmatist ‘on the ground that concern with the needs, troubles, and problems of man is not “philosophical”’.8 Later in his career Dewey would direct this criticism toward the logical positivism and analytic philosophy that had emerged in the Anglo-American world. One example of this is his critique of his younger British associate and sometime friend Bertrand Russell, whose philosophy, Dewey would write, ‘smacks of authoritarianism appropriate to an aristocracy’. While applauding the liberal-democratic spirit of many of Russell’s writings on social issues, Dewey took a decidedly dim view of Russell’s ‘aristocratic’ rationalism: Why do we compare this attitude with that of the aristocracy? It is simply that some people are impatient with the practical affairs of life, and seek to raise themselves above mundane considerations and enter a sphere of pure reflection. Such people feel that they are ‘artistic’, and that they belong to a higher order of being than the run of common man. It is not difficult to see that the theoretical aspects of Russell’s philosophy are characterized by this tendency.9 Russell’s logical atomism and the new logical positivism that had its beginnings in the Vienna Circle both placed philosophical thought within such narrow confines as to lose connection with the vital world of human concerns and became a purely formal exercise. As philosophy turns its back on the world, the latter responds in kind or looks with bewildered incomprehension upon the ‘barren intellectual gymnastic exercise and purely verbal analyses’ that are passed off as problems.10 The new analytic rationalism’s propensity for technicality, formality, and hair-splitting was, in Dewey’s estimation, so remote from philosophy’s proper purpose and grounding in
154
Education in the Human Sciences
experience as to constitute an irrelevance in most respects and a contributing cause of the ‘decline of liberality of mind’.11 The combination of analytic formalism and overspecialization in the person of the professional philosopher creates a turn of mind that retreats in the face of worldly concerns and that is socially irresponsible, a basic conviction being that ‘certain matters of fundamental import to humanity are none of my concern because outside of my Fach’.12 These are harsh statements, particularly by the standards of this unusually mild-mannered philosopher, yet the sentiments that they express would inform Dewey’s own practice as a theorist. Hardly a narrow specialist himself, his writings included major contributions to nearly every philosophical subdiscipline, while he would also serve for decades in the role of America’s foremost public intellectual. This description, of course, fits few other philosophers of Dewey’s time or our own. Indeed, the trends in scholarship that so concerned Dewey have continued to the present day, while signs of their imminent reversal are nowhere to be seen. With few exceptions, philosophers of the present day are not only specialists but technicians, analysts, or scholarly readers of the great thinkers. The Deweyan public intellectual is largely a thing of the past, and where the role is occasionally taken up by a few brave souls it is typically frowned upon by one’s fellow professionals. University professors of today receive no academic credit by way of tenure and promotion, research grants, and so on, for non-peer-reviewed publications if indeed their reputations do not take a sizeable hit for their efforts. If Socrates remains the patron saint of philosophers, few any longer follow him into the public marketplace or venture to pose the variety of questions that he, and Dewey, did. This unfavorable review of the condition of philosophy in the twentieth century would inform Dewey’s assessment of the education that students of philosophy currently receive. Although Dewey would not address the specific issue of the aims of education in philosophy at either the undergraduate or graduate level in the direct and sustained way that one would wish and perhaps expect, given the many years he would teach in several of America’s better philosophy departments, his writings provide ample evidence of his views on the subject. What the aims of a philosophical education are not, on his account, are to provide the technical training and preparation for a career in the academic profession which we are easily tempted into regarding as the highest mark of educational success. Particularly at the undergraduate level, students of philosophy are not to be regarded as aspiring professors or prospective members of the cultural elite. The traditional notion of education in general as a preparation for later life, including especially the students’ entry into the economic life of the society, is an idea that Dewey would often have occasion to criticize, as we have seen. Without
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
155
directing this critique in the direction of any specific field, Dewey argued that education in general prepares students for future life only ‘in a certain sense’ and that preparation for a specialized profession is not its central purpose: Now ‘preparation’ is a treacherous idea. In a certain sense every experience should do something to prepare a person for later experiences of a deeper and more expansive quality. That is the very meaning of growth, continuity, reconstruction of experience. But it is a mistake to suppose that the mere acquisition of a certain amount of arithmetic, geography, history, etc., which is taught and studied because it may be useful at some time in the future, has this effect, and it is a mistake to suppose that acquisition of skills in reading and figuring will automatically constitute preparation for their right and effective use under conditions very unlike those in which they were acquired.13 While the educator in philosophy or in any discipline must take the students’ future into account, this must not be interpreted in a narrow or purely instrumental way, as happens when undergraduate education is regarded as the training that is a necessary prelude to becoming a specialist, be it as an academic philosopher or in another field of professional life. The conventional and still prevalent view that an education in philosophy or in anything must be good for some end outside of the educative process itself is, of course, a view that Dewey rejected, even while acknowledging the obvious practical value of a university education. He rejected as well the notion of higher learning as a preparation for entry into a cultural aristocracy of sorts. The ‘theoretic type of education’ that philosophy provides and which its ‘upholders always defend . . . on the ground of “culture” and “liberal,” “humanistic” education’, Dewey remarked, ‘has prevailed almost entirely in the schools aiming to produce “gentlemen” in the English conventional sense – that is, members of the ruling and leisure class’.14 To maintain that a theoretical education, while a good, is ‘not good for anything’ – a preparation for a career as a specialist, an initiation into the elite, a stepping stone to law school – is to assert that its instrumental value is not its ultimate end but is subordinate to ends of a less tangible nature.15 Insofar as an education in philosophy prepares students for anything, what it prepares them for is to be competent democratic citizens and to possess the intellectual virtues that are needed to participate in forms of community life that transcend economic labor. Ever mindful of the properly democratic spirit of education, Dewey adamantly opposed the division of students into those destined for ‘an academic life of leisure and culture’ and those who are being prepared for the ‘somewhat passive and dulled participation in unidealized labor’.16
156
Education in the Human Sciences
This class-based conception breeds docility of mind in the latter group and an Old World elitism in the former. Perhaps Dewey’s most direct answer to the question of the aims of an undergraduate education in philosophy is one that he outlined in a very brief essay of 1893, appropriately entitled ‘Why Study Philosophy?’ Addressing a student audience, he answered his own question by stating the importance of knowing the origins and basis of current ideas, a knowledge that enables students to gain facility with ideas and at times to ‘free ourselves from them’. If ideas are instruments for resolving problematic situations rather than components of a creed, the educated mind must be proficient in their use rather than uncritical or deferential. In his words, I am not here to magnify my calling unduly, but I feel that one who has done what is termed ‘completing his education’ without an insight on his own behalf into the processes historical, logical, psychological, by which the present structure of ideas and of emotions and volitional attitudes, has been brought into existence has an outlook, at once narrow and rigid, upon a field monotonous, of hard and fast perspective, of fixed horizon, while he might, relatively at least, be looking with wide and flexible vision upon a scene of melting hues, of playing lights, shifting limits. While harboring no illusions that the formal study of philosophy at an American university in 1893 was likely to instill to an appreciable degree the intellectual virtues that Dewey prized, he did hold out as an ideal a conception of the educated mind as possessing an advanced capacity to think. Whether departments of philosophy in fact have any special insight into how to impart this capacity is a matter on which he would express some misgivings, yet a laudable ideal it remains. Dewey’s essay concludes on the note that studying philosophy serves ends more ultimate than the instrumental, including the sense of wonder that is ‘the feeling of a philosopher’ and the instinct to pursue knowledge simply because one must.17 It is a familiar idea that a philosophical education teaches students how to think. Additional to the knowledge of intellectual history that it imparts, the formal study of philosophy trains minds in the art of rational thought, an art or technique conventionally regarded in its purest form as the study of formal logic and in its popular form as what is called ‘critical thinking’. As Chapter 3 discussed, rational thought is most often regarded in both its pure and vulgar forms as a technique that may be taught and learned apart from a concrete subject matter, or that is a subject matter unto itself. Dewey’s rejoinder, as we know, is that thought is not an isolated faculty that may be trained in isolation from ideas, texts, or some other object. The intentional structure of thought – the fact that it is invariably about something or other
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
157
– prevents us from conceiving of logical studies as a purely formal operation, empty of content, or of thinking itself as occurring on the near side of a chasm opposite of which lies the world of experience. The ‘mental faculties’ in general, he wrote, ‘are not powers in themselves, but are such only with reference to the ends to which they are put, the services which they have to perform’.18 This, of course, flies in the face of received views during Dewey’s time and our own that rational thought in essence is a formal and methodological affair and that only as a secondary matter need the method be applied to an item of experience, perhaps to serve the purpose of illustration or practical exercise. On this view, the rules of logical inference are the only essential subject matter, while if one is teaching critical thinking, one may need to supplement these with the informal argument fallacies and perhaps some rules of thumb. What these views overlook is not only the intentional and pragmatic orientation of thought but also the important issue of its inventiveness. The vital business of all philosophical thinking is not forms that are empty of content but the content itself, intelligently formed. Dewey rejected the dichotomy of form and content as he rejected that between reason and experience. What is called ‘critical thinking’ can only be a thinking that is critical of this or that idea, not something – a faculty, a capacity – that is separate unto itself and that may be trained in isolation from a curriculum. By the same token, philosophical reflection is a reflection upon the texts of this or that philosopher or upon the questions that arise in the course of lived experience. Where rationalism in its older and newer forms errs is not only in its abiding tendency to separate reason from experience and to denigrate the latter but in advancing a strictly formalistic conception of rational thought in which creativity or inventiveness plays at most a minor role. For Dewey, it is not only the higher reaches of thought that go beyond the following of rules. Thought in general requires some creativity and itself constitutes ‘an incursion into the novel’.19 Aside from the purely mechanical, mental acts of thinking and knowing require a posing of questions, a grasping of meaning, a placing in context, an ‘emotionalized thinking’, and the carrying over of a received idea to a new field of experience, all of which well surpass rulefollowing.20 Accordingly, if an education in philosophy involves learning not only what the great philosophers of the past have maintained but in a general sense how to think philosophically, this entails something more than avoiding fallacies and following the rules of logical inference. It requires a reconnection of reason and experience and an understanding of how philosophers do in fact think rather than an abstract idealization of how they supposedly ought to. If the great thinkers of the Western tradition did not devise arguments in an experiential vacuum, as surely they did not, nor does the philosophy
158
Education in the Human Sciences
student of today assess their arguments or create new ones through the straightforward application of technique. The error of many a philosophy professor, Dewey believed, is to reproduce in students’ minds the traditional series of binary oppositions – between reason and experience, the a priori and the a posteriori, theory and practice, thought and emotion, form and content, knowledge and opinion, certainty and probability, and so on – and to insist that the serious business of the intellectual is the former value in each of these polarities while the latter values represent so much watering down of the ideal. The consequences of this include the distorted view that students receive regarding how philosophers think and ought to think, as well as a dangerous disconnection between ‘logical thought, as something abstract and remote, and the specific and concrete demands of everyday events’. More ultimately, these consequences go beyond the narrowly intellectual to encompass the practical and the ethical: ‘The gullibility of specialized scholars when out of their own lines, their extravagant habits of inference and speech, their ineptness in reaching conclusions in practical matters, their egotistical engrossment in their own subjects’ are a few of the effects that the severing of thought from experience produces, and among students quite as much as their educators.21 One of the vital matters in a philosophical education, as in philosophy itself, is the set of problems with which it deals and the origin of these problems. When the professor of epistemology informs his or her students that there is a problem regarding the existence of the world, or of other minds, the students quite possibly require convincing as to the genuineness of the problem. How, they might be forgiven for asking, does this problem arise? Why is this a problem? Before inquiry into solutions gets under way, these elementary questions must be answered, yet unanswered or even unaddressed they often remain. The zeal for answers easily inclines us to overlook the worthiness of the question, however as Dewey pointed out, this seemingly elementary matter is all-important for the inquiry that follows. Learning requires a motivation, a degree of curiosity or desire, as does thinking itself. If an educator can often instill this simply through the force of his or her own enthusiasm for the subject, it remains that for education to succeed, students must have a sense that the problems they are studying are not pseudo-problems or puzzles on which to sharpen their wits. The ‘great questions’ with which they are presented must be regarded by the students themselves as living and urgent questions rather than ostensibly perennial ones which, as the professor informs them, simply arise whenever the human mind sets about to think, or that perhaps fall from the sky. When Dewey wrote in Democracy and Education that ‘a peculiar artificiality attaches to much of what is learned in schools’, he may well have had in mind a great deal of the curriculum that is offered by departments of
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
159
philosophy (if ‘schools’ may include post-secondary institutions), especially in light of what he would often write on the issue of philosophical problems and pseudo-problems.22 In Knowing and the Known, for instance, Dewey remarked upon the artificiality of a great many of the problems with which philosophy has long been concerned: What has been completely divided in philosophical discourse into man and the world, inner and outer, self and not-self, subject and object, individual and social, private and public, etc., are in actuality parties in lifetransactions. The philosophical ‘problem’ of how to get them together is artificial. On the basis of fact, it needs to be replaced by consideration of the conditions under which they occur as distinctions, and of the special uses served by the distinctions.23 A distinction that arises in the course of practical experience becomes in the hands of many a philosopher a grand either–or, an abstract polarity that has been uprooted from experience and that must now be examined as a theoretical matter without the benefit of context. When this occurs within philosophical inquiry itself, it typically gives rise to arguments and theoretical positions that fail to satisfy the pragmatic maxim, while when it happens in the classroom it creates an atmosphere of unreality in which students come to think of philosophical problems as a kind of parlor game. To be genuine, a philosophical problem must originate in human experience while its eventual resolution must be brought back to the original problematic situation for verification. Theoretical reflection in general, be it philosophical, scientific, or what have you, both arises from and returns to the realm of the practical and the experiential. Otherwise thinking is so much castle-building in the air. This, in short, is the pragmatic view of what constitutes a philosophical problem. Its implication for education is that students must be able to see the true dimensions of a problem and develop a sense of what the problem is, how it arises, and what is at stake in resolving it. Too often, however, all of this is thought to go without saying or even to be unphilosophical or anti-intellectual. When students are presented with the ‘fundamental problems’ of philosophy, followed in quick succession by a series of theoretical proposals without developing a sense of the problem before them, education becomes a losing cause of passing examinations and memorizing information. Students learn not to expect philosophical reflection to touch down in any meaningful way to what is practical or academic study in general to have any vital connection to life outside of the classroom, and to equate this with intellectual sophistication. In further consequence, ‘[o]rdinary experience does not receive the enrichment which it should; it is not fertilized by school learning. And the attitudes which spring from
160
Education in the Human Sciences
getting used to and accepting half-understood and ill-digested material weaken vigor and efficiency of thought.’24 As I discussed in Chapter 2, the educative process in general must have its basis in the students’ out-of-school experience, yet in the case of a discipline that so often is far removed from such experience and to many a student appears utterly disconnected from it, a special difficulty presents itself for the educator. How might the professor connect a purely conceptual subject matter to ordinary experience without oversimplification or lowering the level of discourse? Dewey firmly held that in order to awaken interest in an area of study among students for whom no prior interest exists, it is imperative that the educator appeal to an existing impulse or curiosity of one kind or another. How is this done when the subject matter is entirely theoretical? If the conventional answer is to ‘make it interesting’ either through some clever pedagogical technique or through the infectious influence of the educator’s own passion for the subject matter, Dewey’s view remained that the students’ own experience must be looked to as the ground of interest and the motivation for inquiry. Thus an interest in political philosophy may be awakened if a student is not indifferent to social injustice and can be persuaded of the benefit of inquiry into possible remedies. An interest in epistemology may be awakened by relating – or better still, reading about – Descartes’ experience of doubt regarding all that he had previously believed, an experience without which the argument of the Meditations would have little point. In the event that an ostensible problem cannot be so grounded, Dewey would sooner question the genuineness of the problem itself than fault the students for their lack of interest. Without denying that a student’s interest in theoretical matters may, and often does, take on a momentum of its own and eventually outgrow the impulse that originally inspired that interest – indeed, at an advanced level of study this will hopefully be the norm – Dewey emphasized ‘the importance of seeing to it that the preliminary period – that in which the form or means is kept in organic relationship to real ends and values – is adequately lived through’.25 As students attain intellectual maturity and develop some reasonable degree of specialization, that original impulse or curiosity will have been long since outgrown and replaced with a succession of further interests, in the manner of any growing thing. If what Dewey called the ‘organic connection between education and personal experience’ is often thought to be tenuous or unsophisticated in a discipline as theoretical as philosophy, that it need not be so may be seen in a couple of examples.26 An undergraduate course in moral issues most often attracts far more students than one in moral theory, critical thinking more than formal logic, and so on. As for why this is so, the conventional wisdom is that in both cases the former is less advanced and perhaps less intellectually challenging, particularly for students not majoring in philosophy. A
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
161
course with the word ‘issues’ in its title rather than ‘theory’ is thought by many students looking for an easy elective to be a promising candidate and perhaps to have a more immediate appeal than the theoretical course. There may be more to the story, however, than what the conventional wisdom captures. A course in moral issues or in a branch of applied ethics will often connect with a student’s experience and existing interests far more readily than a course in ethical theory. Students will often bring a high level of interest to such a course, and an interest that is sustained even after it becomes apparent that the course is not as easy as they had anticipated. If a majority of such students are reluctant subsequently to study ethical theory, this is more likely due to its perceived irrelevance to practical issues than its advanced level of difficulty or sophistication. The demand for ‘relevance’ so often heard from students may not (or not only) be the symptom of misguided anti-intellectualism that their educators often take it to be, but in part a legitimate expectation that the theoretical will help us to cope with the practical and also a complaint about the disconnection between experience and education that they so often perceive. Is ‘making it relevant’ a legitimate expectation when so much of the philosophical curriculum consists essentially of intellectual history? If one is teaching Plato’s Republic or Hobbes’ Leviathan, does it not suffice to teach the argument of the text, to elucidate its meaning in the traditional manner, and perhaps engage in some critical analysis? Must one relate the text to the students’ personal experience – a matter that is customarily regarded as pedestrian or at best a preliminary issue to be dispensed with as quickly as possible in order to get to the essential business of the argument? For that matter, under what conditions is teaching the history of ideas properly educative at all? What is the point of this, and is it ever mis-educative? Dewey’s response to this line of questioning is that connecting the great works of the past to the students’ present-day experience is both a legitimate expectation and a necessary condition of it having educational value at all. Reading such works does not resemble a visit to a museum in which priceless antiques are carefully roped off by the educator while students are compelled to gaze in appreciative passivity at the wonders within the roped-off area. On the contrary, learning the great works means engaging with them, and in a sense that is not limited to inspecting the logic of their arguments or engaging in what philosophers in a certain tradition call ‘analysis’. Genuinely to engage with the Republic is to have one’s horizon widened and one’s convictions tested, to comprehend one of the sources of Western culture not as an end in itself but, as Dewey put it, ‘in order that the current may receive a new direction’.27 Ultimately, the justification and relevance of studying intellectual history is no different from the study of history in its other forms: to enable us the better to cope with the present and the future.
162
Education in the Human Sciences
For any experience to be educative, it must exhibit continuity with other experiences. As Dewey expressed this principle in Experience and Education, ‘when and only when development in a particular line conduces to continuing growth does it answer to the criterion of education as growing’. By the same token, an ‘experience is mis-educative that has the effect of arresting or distorting the growth of further experience’.28 Applying this principle to the history of ideas, we would say that the educational value of the Republic lies not in any of the text’s intrinsic qualities but in conditions both prior to and following the students’ encounter with it. Long experience has shown that exposing students who have reached an age of intellectual maturity to great works such as the Republic or Leviathan, if competently taught, is typically very well conducive to further intellectual growth, directs existing interests along new and fruitful lines, and deepens the capacity for intelligent thought. From the example of Socrates, students learn something about the intellectual virtues which they can apply in other areas of inquiry. Then again, their encounter with this or any text can be mis-educative if students become callous to ideas or anti-intellectual, if they retreat into dogmatism or become disdainful of philosophy in general, whether on account of poor instruction or other factors. Simply knowing the argument of the Republic or committing it to memory is not in itself an indication of educational success but is a means of opening up avenues of further experience. This view clashes directly with educational conservatives for whom a knowledge of intellectual history is considered to be inherently educational. Indeed it clashes not only with the conservatism of a Harold Bloom or an E. D. Hirsch, for whom it is the possession of information, not the cultivation of intellectual capacities, that is the vital matter, but with views that have long been defended by the mainstream of philosophy professors – or, at any rate, that are often implicit to their practice as educators. If many profess allegiance to the idea that in teaching the Republic they are not only imparting information about an ancient philosopher’s views but teaching students to engage critically with the text, and beyond this to think philosophically, common practice tends to overlook this idea and settle for students ‘knowing the material’ in a sense that may be quantified by an examination, including even the multiple-choice examination which actively prevents thought and any manner of intelligent engagement with the text. That the amassing of information is a necessary part of the learning process is sufficiently evident as to go without saying, for Dewey, and indeed he was surprised when in Experience and Education he was forced to state this explicitly. What does not go without saying is that ‘knowing the material’ is a non-ultimate value, that it places second to the cultivation of intellectual habits and attitudes: ‘For these attitudes are fundamentally what count in the future. The most important attitude that can be formed is that of desire to go on learning.’29 It is
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
163
entirely possible, for instance, for students of philosophy to acquire a wealth of knowledge about intellectual history or about this or that area of inquiry while at the same time adopting an intellectual arrogance that renders them virtually unteachable. This is not an uncommon phenomenon among students of philosophy, and is especially prevalent when their educators are themselves dogmatic in their views or regard themselves as members of an intellectual aristocracy. Students are often highly mindful not only of their professors’ opinions on the subject matter but, more important perhaps, of their attitudes toward ideas in general, including those that they may know little about – whether they are flexible or inflexible in their beliefs, open to new ideas or closed-minded, tolerant or intolerant, and so on. Such attitudes are often quickly adopted by students and can be far more enduring than any knowledge acquired in the course of formal study. If the highest aim of a philosophical education is for students to learn how to think philosophically, and if the art of thinking is taught and learned not in a curricular vacuum but through critical engagement with texts and ideas, then a major portion of such an education will necessarily involve studying the great texts of the past and gaining a thorough grounding in the history of philosophy – not, again, as an end in itself or as an exercise in conservation but because encountering the works of a Plato or an Aristotle, a Hobbes or a Nietzsche, constitutes the best training ground for thought that we have yet discovered. If one would learn to think, one would best study the great thinkers of history, just as if one would be an artist, one would do well to study the masters, not to imitate them but to learn from and ultimately to surpass them. Dewey made this point in speaking of the importance in scientific studies of students receiving the ‘proper nutriment’ by actively engaging in laboratory experimentation – in the practice of inquiry – rather than merely absorbing information about the content of prior discoveries. ‘The real value of the laboratory method’, he stated, ‘. . . is not really that a person can discover truths over again . . . ; but the mere handling of the thing, the mere going through the operation originally gone through with in finding that truth, gives a natural outlet of expression which makes the idea his own.’ Applying the same principle to philosophy, we may say that as students retrace the operations of thought of the great thinkers of history, they are learning to think far more genuinely than when they are supplied with an abstract method. If it is true, for instance, that ‘we are at the end of one historical epoch and at the beginning of another’, as Dewey and so many other twentieth-century thinkers believed, and if one of the aims of philosophical reflection is to understand ‘what sort of change is taking place’, students’ ability to engage in this sort of reflection is informed by ‘the mere going through the operation originally gone through with’ by thinkers of the past who also stood at the threshold of a new era.30 What better reason do we
164
Education in the Human Sciences
have for studying the writings of Descartes or Hobbes, for example, than to see how philosophers have previously negotiated in thought the transition from one age to the next? Many of the philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, of course, as many of more recent times, were well aware of the historical transition in which they stood and regarded it as the philosopher’s task both to interpret what this new era fundamentally signifies and to provide it with intelligent direction. The capacity of students to take up a similar reflection is likely doomed to failure or superficiality if they lack adequate knowledge of such efforts and of intellectual history more generally. Dewey defended a few additional principles that readily apply to the teaching of philosophy, although once again his own applications usually focused on education at more elementary levels than the university. As we have seen, a basic principle of Dewey’s is that the classroom constitutes a ‘special environment’ which is distinguished from other environments in that everything within it is purposefully arranged with a view to promoting intellectual growth. Dewey went so far as to argue that ‘we never educate directly’ but rather ‘indirectly by means of the environment’.31 We can readily imagine how this applies in the primary school, where activities and materials in general are ordered with an educative purpose in mind, but how does the same principle apply at the post-secondary level to philosophy? What are the conditions of a proper ‘learning environment’ in the seminar room or lecture theater of the modern university? Again without ever asking this specific question, Dewey did provide a general direction by speaking of an educational environment as one that leaves students and educators at liberty to propose and test ideas in free discussion, that widens horizons, challenges received beliefs, and practices inquiry without fear of repercussions that often follow outside of an academic environment from challenging orthodoxy or established taboos of thought. The ideal of freedom is so central to any properly educational environment that, as Dewey put it, the ‘one great obstacle’ to intellectual growth, widespread during Dewey’s time and our own, is ‘that there is a region of beliefs, social, religious, and political, which is reserved for sheer acceptance and where unbiased inquiry should not intrude’.32 In the philosophy classroom of today we continue to have our intellectual orthodoxies which students are forbidden to challenge, whether it be the political correctness orthodoxy of recent decades or the professor’s own views, both of which students are often keenly aware and by which they are often intimidated. It remains a common occurrence for students who allude in class discussion or written work to a philosopher to whom the professor is not well disposed to be informed with an air of authority that the philosopher in question ‘is not a philosopher’, but perhaps a sophist or a charlatan. An equally common phenomenon is, of course, the
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
165
teaching of philosophy within religious colleges where students may have less than free reign to pursue rational inquiry into theological questions or to study the works of atheist philosophers. On one occasion when Dewey addressed a student audience, he responded to the question of what students at the university may expect from their studies by accentuating the broadening of intellectual horizons that free inquiry brings about: One thing, then, that a University should do for a man is to rid him of his provincialisms. We all – or almost all – of us come out from a sphere of life somewhat narrower than that into which we come. The question is whether in this emergence we come out of our shells, or bring them with us. Certainly the boy or girl who comes to college judging all things from the standpoint of the way they think and do ‘in my place’, ought to have his horizon of outlook pushed out a little further, and his standard of measurement lengthened.33 This principle is commonly professed in theory and commonly negated in practice by a classroom environment in which orthodoxy reigns and the freedom to consider any hypothesis that is relevant to the subject matter is denied. The practice of classroom discussion, Dewey often argued, is properly regarded as a form of shared inquiry, and it is when the spirit of inquiry prevails that an environment is appropriately educational. If it is the nature of experience to be actively experimental and inquisitive, it is imperative that in an academic environment students do more than receive information but themselves engage in the practice of inquiry, whether it be in writing essays or in discussion. Students must do something with the ideas about which they learn; they must interpret an idea’s meaning and implications, debate its justification, compare it to competing hypotheses, and view it within its proper context rather than passively register the professor’s views regarding its meaning and truth-value. This requires free discussion that takes the student out of the comfortable role of spectator and into that of philosophical inquirer, while the professor falls out of the role of ‘external boss or dictator’ and becomes a ‘leader of group activities’.34 In the case of studying philosophy at the university, the only group activity of which we can speak is, of course, class discussion. Often regarded as a secondary matter in philosophy, as in so many other fields of intellectual study, class discussion’s fundamental purpose, on the Deweyan view, is not merely to provide students with an opportunity to express their opinions in the fashion of a television talk-show but to challenge them to articulate and justify their views in confrontation with other ideas, whether the latter views are proffered by other students, the instructor, or the text that orients the
166
Education in the Human Sciences
discussion. The educator’s role here is neither to play the expert, and so close off the conversation, nor merely to pass the microphone from one talkshow spectator to the next, but is rather something intermediate between the two or, better still, that represents a higher synthesis. Their role, as Dewey would often insist, is to direct the conversation along fruitful avenues, allowing it neither to deteriorate in level or tone, lose focus, or to become one-sided or dominated by too few students. The educator’s task also includes giving direction to class discussion and ensuring that what Dewey called ‘the spirit of inquiry’ prevails. How this is done in terms of pedagogical technique is decidedly secondary to the intellectual frame of mind that the educator brings to the subject matter and to the discussion, since this attitude so often becomes infectious, for better or worse, among the students. For Dewey, one of the main features that distinguishes the highly competent educator from the ordinary one, entirely aside from their level of expertise or ability to apply the latest findings of pedagogical science, is the less tangible matter of their comportment toward inquiry itself. As he expressed this point, We have here, I think, the explanation of the success of some teachers who violate every law known to and laid down by pedagogical science. They are themselves so full of the spirit of inquiry, so sensitive to every sign of its presence and absence, that no matter what they do, nor how they do it, they succeed in awakening and inspiring like alert and intense mental activity in those with whom they come in contact.35 If this is not good news for pedagogical science, it is well familiar to anyone who recalls from their own student days those, perhaps few, educators who embodied this ‘spirit of inquiry’ to an optimal degree and inspired our own intellectual efforts or guided our interests in a new direction. The professor’s role in the classroom, of course, is not limited to inspiration or embodying the intellectual virtues that he or she would instill, but also involves direct instruction and lecturing on the subject matter, more or less in the traditional manner, while also ensuring that the general discussion remains faithful to standards of rational discourse. It is not a conversational free-for-all that Dewey advocated, but the very practice of pragmatic inquiry and social intelligence that he described in his logical and epistemological writings carried over to the classroom. Since class discussion exhibits a certain ‘haphazard’ quality which, as Dewey remarked, ‘gives it the devious tendency indicated in Plato’s remark that it needs to be tied to the post of reason’, it falls to the professor to keep matters on the rails and direct attention toward the philosophical basis of whatever assertions are made.36 If students do not arrive at the university as blank slates, but possess a wide
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
167
range of beliefs which they have acquired this way or that and which they may or may not have explicitly articulated, classroom discussion provides perhaps the most effective means of drawing out the students’ ideas, and where this involves not only giving such ideas public expression but subjecting them to scrutiny by their peers. Ultimately, the purpose of a philosophical education on Dewey’s view is to teach the art of thinking and to instill the intellectual virtues of flexibility and open-mindedness, creativity, argumentative rigor, reflectiveness, curiosity, and so on. If it is the case, as Dewey believed, that ‘there is no such thing as genuine knowledge and fruitful understanding except as the offspring of doing ’, then the understanding that students gain or the enlarging of horizons that takes place appropriately occurs in the give and take of discursive inquiry.37 The ‘doing’ to which he referred signifies more than an absorption of ideas but their active rearrangement, critical examination, and synthesis with other ideas, an active process of thought that occurs both in the privacy of inner reflection and, more important for Dewey, in the public form of co-operative discussion. The accent that Dewey placed on education as inquiry and on teaching as the nurturing of the students’ intellectual capacity and habits of mind carries important implications regarding the issue of instilling beliefs. In the field of philosophy, as in many others, educators often see their role in the classroom as that of authoritative judge of what is true. A long-standing tradition has it that the professor is something of a venerable figure, particularly in his or her own classroom, a member of the intellectual elite perhaps and in virtue of whose expertise one’s role includes instilling particular beliefs of one’s own into the minds of the students. To teach and to learn, after all, is to teach and learn what is true, and who is the most competent judge of this but the esteemed personage at the front of the room? If, for instance, an idea emerges from the general discussion that passes for true while the professor knows better, or believes otherwise, then it is the professor’s role to instruct students in their errors and to profess the truth. This conventional and still widespread view undoubtedly contains some plausibility, however Dewey would often express the need for caution on the issue of instilling debatable views in students’ minds on the pretense of authority or special expertise. If the knowledge that one is teaching in a course on political philosophy, for instance, concerns the struggle between classes in a market economy rather than a point of incontrovertible truth, then ‘education becomes simply a matter of inculcation – in short, of agitation and propaganda’.38 Competent educators, from elementary schoolteachers to university professors, realize the influence they exert on the minds of the young, and in the case of philosophy professors and their students how credulous the latter can be in the face of opinions confidently asserted by the former. Such credulity, even
168
Education in the Human Sciences
in the intellectual make-up of the advanced student, easily makes for a blurring of the line between instruction and inculcation or between education and indoctrination. Insofar as education involves the art of thinking, and insofar as ‘passivity is the opposite of thought’, the students’ passive deference to the professor’s philosophical views is mis-educative and easily shades into indoctrination. An analogous phenomenon in the elementary grades is what Dewey referred to as ‘satisfying the teacher instead of the problem’. As he wrote, The operation of the teacher’s own mental habit tends, unless carefully watched and guided, to make the child a student of the teacher’s peculiarities rather than of the subjects that he is supposed to study. His chief concern is to accommodate himself to what the teacher expects of him, rather than to devote himself energetically to the problems of subject matter. ‘Is this right?’ comes to mean ‘Will this answer or this process satisfy the teacher?’ – instead of meaning ‘Does it satisfy the inherent conditions of the problem?’39 Any university professor knows how common it is for students presumed to be intellectually mature to be more urgently concerned with satisfying the professor than the problem, and it is a matter that is more urgent still when the professor intimates that the students would do well to agree with his or her philosophical position. This intimation, to which students are often carefully attuned, effectively brings thinking to a halt. If it is the art of thinking that a philosophical education would foster, over and above information about the great philosophical systems of the past and present, what this requires is ‘the active participation of students in reaching conclusions and forming attitudes’, while from professors it requires a measure of forbearance in propagating their own beliefs.40 The latter entails not that they remain silent in their views but that they express them in the spirit of pragmatic inquiry rather than as the incontestable facts for which students can often mistake them. Further, it requires cultivating the intellectual virtues that will enable the learning process to continue long after the period of formal education ends and that make it possible for students to engage intelligently both with the problems of philosophy and with what Dewey called ‘the problems of men’. Philosophy must not lose contact with the culture of which it is a part and the problems that belong to it. Philosophers must not retreat into new forms of scholasticism while training students to follow suit, but must reverse the trend toward hyper-specialization and technification that lead to the disconnection that Dewey saw between much of the philosophical discourse of the twentieth century and the actual modes of practice and problematic situations that beset present society.
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
169
What calls for thinking, argued Dewey the philosopher and public intellectual, is the state of the culture as we presently find it no less than the conceptual and formal issues of academic philosophy. An education in this field must therefore equip students with the knowledge and capacities of mind that allow them no longer to be ‘silent partners in the intellectual life of humanity’. While a philosophical education hardly affords a guarantee of success in this regard, ‘it does acquaint the student’, as Dewey expressed it, ‘with the forces that create ideas and make them potent, and it should give some increase of expertness in the use of the tools by which the leading ideas of humanity are worked out and tested’. Education will always serve a practical function in helping students to make a living, yet as he continued, ‘to have some part in the making of ideas is a necessary part in the making of a living that is worth living, and the chief justification of philosophical study is that it renders the student more apt at this particular kind of making’.41 This is an ambitious view of what the formal study of philosophy can achieve, one premised on an equally ambitious view of philosophy itself and the role that the philosopher can play in the general culture. If such views are out of step with Dewey’s time and our own, they remain continuous with the Greek ideal of bringing the classical love of wisdom to bear on the living of life and the search for the good.
Nietzsche and the philosopher’s education These views show an interesting affinity with a philosopher whose name is rarely mentioned in the same breath as Dewey and with whose works it appears Dewey had at most a passing acquaintance: Friedrich Nietzsche. The condition of philosophy and the role of the thinker were major preoccupations of both figures, and the assessments that they offered were similar in both tone and substance. On the question of the state of philosophy during his day, Nietzsche was characteristically harsh in his opinion and, like Dewey, brought this assessment to bear on his conception of a philosophical education. Nietzsche’s assessment is not surprising given his love of criticism both moderate and immoderate, yet what is surprising is the similar note on which both the American and the German thinker pronounced their critiques of the philosophy of their day and the manner in which these critiques informed their educational views. While the differences between their philosophical positions clearly run deep, their views on the questions that are before us exhibit sufficient similarities to warrant some creative rapprochement. I wish therefore to return to Nietzsche’s critique and to ask a few slightly awkward questions about its contemporary relevance as well as its educational implications. What is the self-image under which philosophy has labored from Nietzsche’s and Dewey’s times to our own, what ultimately is
170
Education in the Human Sciences
the role of the philosopher in a culture, and what relevance does this have to a philosophical education? I shall argue not that Nietzsche surpassed Dewey on any of these issues but that the former offered insights that the latter might well have drawn upon while violating neither the letter nor the spirit of his own position, insights that we would do well to recall. Let us begin by outlining Nietzsche’s rather broad-ranging critique of the philosophy and philosophers of his day before turning to the educational consequences of this critique. Nietzsche would cast his net still wider than Dewey, applying his assessment not only to his contemporaries but to the entire tradition stemming from Socrates. The philosophers of the nineteenth century and prior, Nietzsche held, had committed errors so numerous and profound that documenting their full extent is a daunting and perhaps impossible task. I shall focus therefore on several of the major critiques from which many of the smaller and more specific criticisms are derived, beginning with the general enervation of philosophy that he believed to be something of an epidemic by his time. The roots of this phenomenon, Nietzsche believed, extend many centuries prior to the nineteenth, in the philosophical systems of Plato and Aristotle as well as in the person of Socrates. What this period represents, for Nietzsche, is not a transition from mythos to logos but ‘a decline of the instincts’ and the decisive triumph of the Apollonian over the Dionysian.42 Philosophical thinking invariably constitutes an instinctive activity of sorts, a form of selfexpression not unlike the artistic. If Greek tragedy represented, in Nietzsche’s view, the supreme achievement of ancient culture, it was because of its power to synthesize the rational spirit of the Apollonian with the instinctive drive of the Dionysian, a synthesis that would not be duplicated by the greatest of the Greek philosophers or by any who would follow. Philosophy from this point forward would be dominated by dichotomies of reason or passion, theory or practice, reality or appearance, necessity or contingency, and so on, all of which both Nietzsche and Dewey would decisively reject. The enervation of philosophy of which Nietzsche spoke was a symptom of this ancient decline of the instincts and along with them the only ground from which philosophy could emerge. ‘The history of philosophy’ then became ‘a secret raging against the preconditions of life, against the value feelings of life, against partisanship in favor of life.’43 With Socrates began the renunciation of the instincts, of the body and the senses, of appearance and experience in favor of the rational and other-worldly, creating a trajectory that would orient all later philosophers in one way or another. The loss of the Dionysian instincts in philosophy led directly to its decline or perhaps its stillbirth, since for Nietzsche there was no time either prior to Socrates or later in which philosophy would synthesize the Apollonian and Dionysian in the manner of the ancient tragedians.
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
171
By Nietzsche’s own time, philosophers had become very much as Dewey later described them: university men, scholastics, specialists, decidedly not what Nietzsche or Dewey regarded as the philosopher’s proper calling. As Nietzsche would write in Beyond Good and Evil, ‘I insist that people should finally stop confounding philosophical laborers, and scientific men generally, with philosophers; precisely at this point we should be strict about giving “each his due,” and not far too much to those and far too little to these.’44 Nietzsche would often demarcate rather carefully philosophers from a range of academic professionals that included scholars, critics, historians, scientists, and philosophical laborers, all of whom far outnumbered the former. A typical expression of this point from the notes to The Will to Power reads as follows: Superstition about philosophers: confusion with scholars and scientists. As if values were inherent in things and all one had to do was grasp them! To what extent they study under the direction of given values (their hatred of appearance, the body, etc.). . . . At last, confusion goes so far that one regards Darwinism as philosophy: and now the scholars and scientists dominate.45 The philosopher, for Nietzsche, is a fundamentally creative and free spirit, beholden to no values or judgments that are not of one’s own explicit fashioning. The academics from whom he distinguished the philosopher follow a trajectory of someone else’s design and values that they neither created nor chose. Of scholars and specialists Nietzsche would write with palpable disdain: . . . they are all losers who have been brought back under the hegemony of science, after having desired more of themselves at some time without having had the right to this ‘more’ and its responsibilities – and who now represent, in word and deed, honorably, resentfully, and vengefully, the unbelief in the masterly task and masterfulness of philosophy.46 Countless such remarks may be found in Nietzsche’s works, and what they clearly signify is a lament for philosophy itself and the disappearance of an ideal among those who were calling themselves philosophers. The note of contempt in such remarks is consistent and unmistakable: ‘For this is the truth [says Zarathustra]: I have left the house of scholars and slammed the door behind me.’47 Why this note of contempt, we might ask? Is this merely symptomatic of an unusually cantankerous personality or is there a properly philosophical point to this? To answer this we must understand Nietzsche’s rather elevated conception
172
Education in the Human Sciences
of philosophy and the philosopher and how the thought of his day quite obviously fell short not only of this ideal but of philosophy’s original selfunderstanding as the love of wisdom. I shall discuss Nietzsche’s positive conception of the philosopher in more detail in due course. For now, it will suffice to note that its principal themes include value-creation, inventiveness, critical questioning, depth of understanding, breadth of vision, and responsibility for one’s culture. The academic laborer of the nineteenth century lacked not one but all of these qualities, Nietzsche fervently believed; their business requires a narrowing of vision, a focused and limited range of knowledge, and a self-restraint that is antithetical to free-spirited questioning. Fundamentally, they are servants of received thought: analysts and systematizers, commentators, followers and managers of ideas not their own. ‘It is for these investigators to make everything that has happened and been esteemed so far easy to look over, easy to think over, intelligible and manageable, to abbreviate everything long, even “time,” and to overcome the entire past.’ He continues: ‘Genuine philosophers, however, are commanders and legislators: they say, “thus it shall be!” They first determine the Whither and For What of man, and in so doing have at their disposal the preliminary labor of all philosophical laborers, all who have overcome the past.’48 The philosophers of Nietzsche’s time were scholastic in Dewey’s sense, ‘mere spectators in everything’, as Zarathustra put it: ‘Like those who stand in the street and stare at the people passing by, so they too wait and stare at thoughts that others have thought.’ Such scholars ‘crack knowledge as one cracks nuts’ – again not a complimentary description, even while Nietzsche would occasionally qualify this by suggesting that the philosopher’s education must include a certain quantity of scholarly labor as a precondition for thought.49 Yet a precondition is all that it is, and it is this fact of which the philosophers of Nietzsche’s time had lost sight. For this advocate of perspectivism it was necessary to a philosopher’s development that they master the skills of the scholar, critic, historian, and what have you, ‘to be able to see with many different eyes and consciences, from a height and into every distance’.50 Creative thought undoubtedly requires that we stand on others’ shoulders, but as a means of finding a voice of our own, not in order to become lifelong scribes and disciples. For Nietzsche, even the greatest of German thinkers – Kant and Hegel – had been but great critics and schematizers, not philosophers in this sense. Anyone following their lead could at best remain at their level while a vast majority of their number would of course fall far below. One implication of this is that ‘the philosopher should be a rare plant’, above all not one to be confused with the academics of the nineteenth-century university.51 The failure of the professors to rise above the condition of laborer creates further problems when the judgments and evaluations of the past are
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
173
adopted as a kind of faith. This is a faith, of course, that does not realize it is a faith and that indeed regards itself as at the furthest remove from this: it represents a call to rational order, to certain truth and justice. It is a rejection of appearances and uncertainty, of unreasoning faith and prejudice of any kind. Nietzsche’s rejoinder is that the philosophers are one and all believers in ‘the faith in opposite values’, in an endless series of dichotomies whose values are hierarchically ordered and unquestioned.52 Reality and appearance, truth and falsehood, objectivity and subjectivity, good and evil, and so on remain incontrovertible polarities between which we are compelled to choose, and where there is no choice to be made but for how to articulate the meaning of the former in each of these pairings. In failing to question the dichotomies themselves, philosophers fall victim to historical forgetfulness and transform evaluations and interpretations into an orthodoxy. Concepts that are historical contingencies, symbols, and expressions of a particular form of life or will to power become transcendental deliverances to be analyzed and systematized but not questioned. Here we arrive at the heart of Nietzsche’s critique: You ask me about the idiosyncrasies of philosophers? . . . There is their lack of historical sense, their hatred of even the idea of becoming, their Egyptianism. They think they are doing a thing honour when they dehistoricize it, sub specie aeterni – when they make a mummy of it. All that philosophers have handled for millennia has been conceptual mummies; nothing actual has escaped from their hands alive. Such philosophers are ‘conceptual idolaters’; ‘they have trusted in concepts as completely as they have mistrusted the senses: they have not stopped to consider that concepts and words are our inheritance from ages in which thinking was very modest and unclear’.53 It is the tendency toward historical forgetfulness above all that causes philosophy to deteriorate into scholasticism and idolatry. If the classical love of wisdom had by Nietzsche’s time been transformed into an orthodoxy of received concepts and values it was the thinker’s task to philosophize with a hammer, which always means not to demolish such values but to question them in a radically undogmatic way. Yet this is precisely what his contemporaries had failed to do, leaving philosophy with an altogether false objectivism of reified symbols and unquestioned values. This lack of historical consciousness contributed to philosophy’s reduction in the modern period to the theory of knowledge, with its erroneous notions of objectivity, certainty, and epistemic foundations. Philosophical thought that conceived of itself as a quest for incontrovertible grounds amounted, as Nietzsche put it, to a ‘doctrine of abstinence – a philosophy that never gets beyond the
174
Education in the Human Sciences
threshold and takes pains to deny itself the right to enter – that is philosophy in its last throes’.54 A thinking that was free-spirited and questioning had no quarter under these conditions and on the pretense of objective reason succumbed to what Zarathustra would call the ‘spirit of gravity’. A philosophy that was beholden to science and that idolized received concepts was a solemn business indeed; it required from the scholar a painstaking sobriety and a seriousness of purpose not unlike the priests of old to whom Nietzsche would compare modern philosophers. It required as well an increasingly minute division of intellectual labor which again had the effect of narrowing vision and hemming thought within ever smaller specialties. Nietzsche’s critique of his contemporaries, again like Dewey’s, did not exclude the personal foibles of philosophers. Ever the psychologist, Nietzsche would often remark upon ‘the self-glorification and self-exaltation of scholars [which] now stand in full bloom, in their finest spring, everywhere’. If philosophy during the long period of the Middle Ages had been the handmaid of theology, forcing the thinker to adopt the ways of the scholastic, its modern transformation into the handmaid of science changed nothing essential and left entirely intact the ‘Jesuitism of mediocrity’ that prevailed among scholars prior to the Enlightenment, including its characteristic preoccupations and ostensible virtues. Respectability and reputation remain uppermost here, whether we are speaking of the medieval schoolmen or modern philosophers, scholars, or scientists: Let us look more closely: what is the scientific man? To begin with, a type of man that is not noble, with the virtues of a type of man that is not noble, which is to say, a type that does not dominate and is neither authoritative nor self-sufficient: he has industriousness, patient acceptance of his place in rank and file, evenness and moderation in his abilities and needs, an instinct for his equals and for what they need; for example, that bit of independence and green pasture without which there is no quiet work, that claim to honor and recognition . . . , that sunshine of a good name, that constant attestation of his value and utility which is needed to overcome again and again the internal mistrust which is the sediment in the hearts of all dependent men and herd animals.55 The personal vanity of scholars was a frequent object of his criticism. No modest man himself, of course, Nietzsche’s own brand of immodesty was of a rather different and somehow more forgivable kind than what he so often diagnosed among his contemporaries: a petty egotism rooted in mediocrity and envy of superiors. The psychology of the scholar was one of ressentiment and respectable ordinariness, a character not without ambition and skill in satisfying the requirements of professional life, but uncreative and unin-
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
175
spired. The nineteenth-century philosopher cum university professor desired above all the ‘dignities and respectabilities’ that Zarathustra contrasted with the ‘freedom and the air over fresh soil’ which were the conditions of his own proper existence.56 Little can be expected when the comforts of position and reputation had thoroughly supplanted the free-spirited urgency and untimeliness of the Nietzschean philosopher. For Nietzsche and Dewey alike, the philosopher’s reason for being must still be understood in terms of the classical love of wisdom, where this means neither the division of knowledge into an endless array of specialties nor its altogether secure possession, but rather its unending pursuit. For both figures, philosophy’s proper object is not any merely formal or technical knowledge but a knowledge of what is of ultimate importance to human beings as individuals and as a culture. For this reason the self-image of philosophy must not be what for so many it is today: that of a science or quasi-science, a technical specialty of logical and linguistic analysis or deductive formalism. Philosophy, Dewey and Nietzsche both believed, must retain something of its original self-understanding while aspiring to something rather more difficult and experimental than the norm of their time and, still more, our own. Both figures would also emphasize the responsibility of the philosopher, one that expands far beyond the obligations of the scholar or professional and that takes upon itself a wider responsibility for the culture of which one is a part. Nietzsche’s philosopher, as he would say of himself, is a psychologist of sorts and ‘cultural physician’, responsible for the detection of maladies such as the nihilism that he himself diagnosed as a widespread condition of modern Europe. It is a responsibility that includes pronouncing a verdict on how the general culture is faring and indeed on the value of human life itself. Philosophy does not shy from such questions, but takes them up in the boldest spirit possible, contestable though any judgment we form will inevitably be. Dewey as well would speak of philosophy as an examination of the roots of one’s culture and an interpretation of its undercurrents as they manifest themselves in the arts, religion, politics, language, and so on. Though Dewey would not be given to Nietzschean excess on this point, or any other, their positions here are substantially the same: philosophy properly concerns itself with cultural problems the scope and depth of which transcend all specialized inquiry. No mere technicians, philosophers ‘derive their substance from the stream of culture’ and remain tied to the traditions in which they invariably stand and which supply them with a fundamental orientation.57 They are charged not only with interpreting culture but with getting out front of it and if need be supplying it with a new direction. Philosophy, Dewey would write,
176
Education in the Human Sciences
is a language in which the deepest social problems and aspirations of a given time and a given people are expressed in intellectual and impersonal symbols. It has been well said that philosophy is a reflective selfconsciousness of what first exists spontaneously, effectively, in the feelings, deeds, ideas of a people.58 Philosophy so conceived ‘is a conversion of such culture as exists into consciousness’, a translation of its symbols and aspirations into a coherent way of thinking.59 For related reasons both figures would also emphasize the difficulty of philosophical thinking. Owing to its broad-ranging responsibility, its necessarily creative dimension, and other factors, such thinking ‘is the most difficult occupation in which man engages’, as Dewey put it.60 For Nietzsche, the untimeliness of the thinker, his standing as ‘of necessity a man of tomorrow and the day after tomorrow’, adds to the difficulty of the task. Such a thinker invariably stands opposed to the ideals of his time and is charged with sounding out these ideals for signs of their deterioration into idols as well as with fashioning new ideals. Thinking is an essentially creative, experimental, and also free-spirited activity, one given to adopting a variety of perspectives without becoming dogmatic about any of them. The ‘new philosophers’ or ‘philosophers of the future’ whom Nietzsche believed or hoped to be on the way were ‘men of experiments’, ‘attempters’, ‘very free spirits’, posers of questions and lovers of masks in addition to being ‘friends of “truth”’. Such a philosopher ‘lives “unphilosophically” and “unwisely,” above all imprudently . . . – he risks himself constantly, he plays the wicked game’.61 Above all, Nietzsche’s philosopher of the future is a solitary and inventive spirit, resolute in will and fated invariably to swim against the tide of the present. Good democrat that he was, Dewey would never describe the philosophical enterprise as a solitary endeavor, yet a singularly demanding one it is. Both figures also sought to reconnect thought to life in ways that make philosophy of obvious relevance to the world and to human experience outside of the cloister. Nietzsche’s aim in this respect was to reconnect the Apollonian dimension of thought with the Dionysian, a project that required a rehabilitation of the latter in view of its expulsion from philosophy at the hands of the Greeks. It is a comprehensive outlook for which philosophy properly strives, both thinkers maintained, one that transcends the point of view of the specialist and encompasses within itself an ever-increasing number of ideas and points of view. The possibility of attaining what Dewey called ‘an outlook upon life’ in the sense of ‘a general attitude toward it’, or in Nietzsche’s words ‘the height for a comprehensive look’, belongs to the philosophical non-specialist alone.62 The purpose of serious thought in general, as both figures were keenly aware, is not only to clarify concepts but
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
177
to enhance and often to alter radically the general course of human existence. ‘Whenever philosophy has been taken seriously,’ Dewey wrote, ‘it has always been assumed that it signified achieving a wisdom which would influence the conduct of life.’63 Clearly, these two thinkers did not hold identical views on the questions that are before us, but what their respective critiques and positive views share is of more than historical significance. A philosophy that understands itself as a quasi-science or technical specialty of any kind, Dewey and Nietzsche likewise warned us, inevitably becomes moribund and disconnected from vital human experience. That their warnings have gone largely unheeded by later generations of philosophers will, I trust, be evident to all. Their views on the state of philosophy during their lifetimes are strident, uncompromising, and unfashionable by the standards of their time and, still more, our own. Yet few philosophers at present will have difficulty recognizing something of themselves, or at any rate their profession, in Dewey’s and Nietzsche’s remarks. If not all of us are ‘scholastics’, ‘herd animals’, or some similarly unkind epithet, we nonetheless are all specialists now – technicians or would-be scientists of one kind or another, analysts, critics, disciples, or scholarly interpreters of some Master Thinker. This is how graduate students are trained and how the professional ladder is climbed, even while it is no secret that specialization precludes the more comprehensive outlook for which both of these philosophers called and which they and the greatest of philosophers have always sought to articulate. Today, however, a familiar pattern finds students becoming enamored with philosophy at the undergraduate level and proceeding to graduate school only to find blinkers quickly affixed, often for life. From this point forward, specialists are relieved of having to learn of any other field apart from a few preliminaries, or even of the history of their own specialty. It is now common, for instance, for new PhDs in moral or political philosophy not to have read more than bits and pieces of even the most important historical texts in their own field, to have more than a little knowledge only about the latest technical puzzles that are causing a stir in the journals, and to race from conference to conference for the purpose of building a CV and competing for employment. It is equally common for specialists not to read the literatures of traditions not their own, for liberals or feminists to take seriously the literature of liberalism or feminism alone, or even a narrow strain of this literature, closing off any possibility of conversation across boundaries of any kind. Specialization and ahistoricism have emerged together and have become difficult to untangle. It is a mystifying proposition that one can be expected to advance the conversation when one lacks more than superficial knowledge of its origins and history, and when one is trained to take seriously only one’s fellow travelers in liberalism, feminism, or what have you.
178
Education in the Human Sciences
For as long as philosophy retains the self-image of science it will continue the slide into irrelevance of which students and non-philosophers so often and so rightly complain. The general public largely stopped listening to philosophers long ago, at about the time when the latter began speaking exclusively to and about themselves and within ever smaller circles of insiders and specialists. Were they wrong to do so? Is it a symptom of anti-intellectualism when the general public is perfectly incurious about analytic metaphysics, formal logic, or decision theory? Let me suggest that it is not. Nor are they to be faulted for their failure to make household names of the leading figures in these and many other philosophical subdisciplines. Philosophy as science – meta, aspiring, handmaid to, quasi-, or pseudo– is a recipe for the scholasticism and hyperspecialism of which Dewey and Nietzsche warned. Their warnings may have been in vain and far too late, yet it may at least be hoped that conceptions of philosophy reminiscent of their ideals or even of philosophy’s original signification will emerge, as a corrective perhaps to the technicist and scientistic excesses of the present. A philosophical education that takes Nietzsche’s critique seriously would accentuate a kind of creativity and experimentation that is roughly consistent with Dewey’s view while broadening somewhat the notion of experimentation. Experimental thinking as Nietzsche conceived of it has no model. It is not a science in Dewey’s sense but a ‘gay science’, a thinking that is grounded in the Dionysian no less than the Apollonian, the imaginative and questioning no less than the demonstrative. The creativity of which Nietzsche would speak means in the first instance the creation of values and revaluation of received values and knowledge-claims of whatever kind, in particular the decided refusal of the philosopher’s traditional ‘faith in opposite values’. Nietzsche’s stance on a philosophical education is a direct entailment of his conception of philosophy itself and of the role of the thinker. The aim of this education is clearly not to produce the ‘philosophical laborers’ and priestly types that were the objects of his contempt, but to create the conditions that make creative thinking a genuine possibility. Nietzsche would express this in his characteristic way by declaring the ‘supreme objective’ of this education to be ‘the production of the philosophical genius’, and identified the conditions that would make this possible as follows: . . . free manliness of character, early knowledge of mankind, no scholarly education, no narrow patriotism, no necessity for bread-winning, no ties with the state – in short, freedom and again freedom: that wonderful and perilous element in which the Greek philosophers were able to grow up.
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
179
If it is free thinkers that an education in philosophy would produce, a large dose of freedom – the freedom to inquire in the direction that an intelligent mind wishes and to arrive at opinions that are genuinely one’s own – is its most indispensable condition. Such learning will not be limited to studying the great systems of the past, and certainly not as an end in itself. In his words, And finally, what in the world have our young men to do with the history of philosophy? Is the confusion of opinions supposed to discourage them from having opinions of their own? Are they supposed to learn how to join in the rejoicing at how wonderfully far we ourselves have come? Are they supposed even to learn to hate philosophy or to despise it? One might almost think so when one knows how students have to torment themselves for the sake of their philosophical examinations so as to cram into their poor brain the maddest and most caustic notions of the human spirit together with the greatest and hardest to grasp. The only critique of a philosophy that is possible and that proves something, namely trying to see whether one can live in accordance with it, has never been taught at universities: all that has ever been taught is a critique of words by men of other words. And now imagine a youthful head, not very experienced in living, in which fifty systems in the form of words and fifty critiques of them are preserved side-by-side and intermingled – what a desert, what a return to barbarism, what a mockery of an education in philosophy!64 One who would learn to think philosophically would do well to learn something of the history of philosophy – a history with which Nietzsche himself was well acquainted – yet neither as an end in itself nor to acquire Bloom’s reverence for tradition, but as a training ground for thinking thoughts of one’s own. Ideas and values are what one lives by, and it is in this spirit that Nietzsche would have us teach and learn the history of philosophy – as something to be lived, not entertained as historical antiques or blackboard exercises. Not all of our students will become Nietzsche’s geniuses. Perhaps none of them will, but it remains that an education that is oriented by this aim is more likely to produce competent thinkers than one that serves more pedestrian aims. What is abundantly clear is that the education that Nietzsche and Dewey both criticized – one dominated by intellectual history, the memorization of lifeless ‘words’, and unimaginative testing – produces only a stockpiled memory, and only under the best of circumstances. Under more usual circumstances it produces ennui and a disconnection between the life of the mind and life. A philosophical education that puts a premium on independent thought is informed but not overwhelmed by intellectual
180
Education in the Human Sciences
history. It harks back to Greek philosophy’s marriage of education and the good life while also regarding the relation between education and philosophy itself as far more intimate than it has appeared in recent times. Is it asking too much of students of philosophy and their educators to strive for a thinking that is at once historically informed and rigorous while also experimental and free-spirited? It is a strenuous ideal that asks students to become Nietzsche’s cultural physicians and Deweyan problem-solvers at the same time that they are becoming grounded in the history of ideas, yet anyone who has fallen under the spell of this particular discipline in their youth well knows how attainable this ideal is, how the love of ideas leads the mind from one question, text, or field of inquiry to the next in a process that never ends. This, in short, is what educational success in this field looks like: the mind that is restless, unsatisfied, undogmatic, and unrelenting in questioning itself and its world. If it does not revolutionize the culture in quite the way that Nietzsche wished and himself aspired to do, it might more modestly operationalize the ancient imperative to know thyself.
Notes 1. Dewey, ‘Philosophy and Education’ (1930). LW 5: 290–1. 2. Dewey, ‘The Future of Philosophy’ (1947). LW 17: 466–7. 3. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 31. As Dewey remarked in 1934, ‘There is complaint, and rightly, that the population is too amenable, on the whole, to the influence of propaganda. But why is it? Why are so many people so ready to swallow what is persistently told them, or told them with an air of authority? Why is there so much gullibility? I do not believe that it is mainly from lack of native intelligence. It is because they have acquired the habit of listening and of accepting, instead of that of inquiry, and, if you please, of intelligent scepticism. There are other causes for this mental passivity. Men and women working mechanically all day, tending machines, are not likely to be especially alert. But I think the schools have to accept some responsibility for the prevalence of this habit of mind. While methods of teaching in arithmetic, history, geography, in fact, all school subjects, aid in establishing the mental habit of passive acceptance, while docility at the expense of an inquiring disposition, is too generally cultivated, the evil culminates in the attitudes that are formed in political, social, and economic matters.’ Dewey, ‘Education for a Changing Social Order’ (1934). LW 9: 159–60. 4. Dewey, ‘Modern Philosophy’ (1952). LW 16: 411. 5. Dewey, ‘The Scholastic and the Speculator’ (1891). EW 3: 150–1. 6. Dewey, Knowing and the Known (1949). LW 16: 249. 7. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 91. ‘The Liberal College and its Enemies’ (1924). MW 15: 208. 8. Dewey, ‘Philosophy’s Future in our Scientific Age’ (1949). LW 16: 377. 9. Dewey, ‘Three Contemporary Philosophers’ (1920). MW 12: 239–40. The paragraph immediately following reads: ‘In one of his articles in which he extols the merit of pure mathematics, and deals with the distinction between the practical life of man and his ideal life, Russell avers that the most one can hope for in practical life is some sort of adjustment between the ideal on the one hand, and what is possible on the
Teaching Philosophy: The Scholastic and the Thinker
10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45. 46. 47. 48.
181
other. But in the world of pure reason, no such adjustment is needed; there is nothing to limit development or to stand in the way of continuing increment of creative activity and noble aspiration. This world of pure reason is far above all human desiring; it is immeasurably beyond the impoverished phenomena of nature; there man can construct a systematic universe for himself and dwell therein in perfect peace. There human freedom can be realized, and the sufferings of practical existence be known no more.’ Similar remarks are found in MW 2: 64; MW 3: 77; MW 4: 181–2; MW 9: 91; LW 5: 176; LW 8: 39; LW 14: 324 and 334; LW 15: 272; LW 16: 249 and 361–2. Dewey, ‘Challenge to Liberal Thought’ (1944). LW 15: 272. Dewey, ‘The Liberal College and its Enemies’ (1924). MW 15: 208. Dewey, ‘Academic Freedom’ (1902). MW 2: 64. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 28. Dewey, ‘The Bearings of Pragmatism upon Education’ (1908). MW 4: 182. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 250. Dewey, ‘Culture and Industry in Education’ (1906). MW 3: 289. Dewey, ‘Why Study Philosophy?’ (1893). EW 4: 63, 64, 65. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 61. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 165. Dewey, Art as Experience (1934). LW 10: 80. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 161–2. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 168. Dewey, Knowing and the Known (1949). LW 16: 248. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 168. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 74 note 1. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 11. Dewey, ‘Philosophy and Civilization’ (1927). LW 3: 7. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 20, 11. Ibid., 29. Dewey, ‘How the Mind Learns’, Educational Lectures Before Brigham Young Academy (1901). LW 17: 216, 221. ‘The Future of Philosophy’ (1947). LW 17: 467. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 22, 23. Dewey, ‘The Supreme Intellectual Obligation’ (1934). LW 9: 99. Dewey, ‘A College Course: What Should I Expect From It?’ (1890). EW 3: 52. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 37. Dewey, ‘The Relation of Theory to Practice in Education’ (1904). MW 3: 265. Dewey, ‘Some Stages of Logical Thought’ (1900). MW 1: 161–2. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 284. Dewey, ‘Class Struggle and the Democratic Way’ (1936). LW 11: 384. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 327, 160–1. Dewey, ‘Education and Social Change’ (1937). LW 11: 415. Dewey, ‘The Study of Philosophy’ (1911). MW 6: 137. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale, ed. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1968), sec. 439, p. 242. Ibid., sec. 461, p. 253. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1989), sec. 211, p. 135. Nietzsche, The Will to Power, sec. 422, p. 226. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, sec. 204, p. 123. Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Penguin, 2003), p. 147. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, sec. 211, p. 136.
182 49. 50. 51. 52. 53. 54. 55. 56. 57. 58. 59. 60. 61. 62. 63. 64.
Education in the Human Sciences Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, p.147. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, sec. 211, p. 136. Nietzsche, The Will to Power, sec. 420, p. 226. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, sec. 2, p. 10. Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Penguin, 2003), p. 45. The Will to Power, sec. 409, p. 220. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, sec. 204, p. 123. Ibid., sec. 204, p. 121; sec. 206, pp. 125, 126. Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, p. 147. Dewey, Art as Experience (1934), LW 10: 270. Dewey, ‘Philosophy and American National Life’ (1905). MW 3: 73. Dewey, ‘Philosophy and Civilization’ (1927). LW 3: 9. Dewey, ‘Philosophies of Freedom’ (1928). LW 3: 112. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, sec. 212, p. 137; sec. 210, p. 134; sec. 42, p. 52; sec. 44, p. 53; sec. 43, p. 53; sec. 205, p. 125. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 334. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, sec. 205, p. 124. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 334. Nietzsche, ‘Schopenhauer as Educator’, Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 187, 182, 187.
Chapter 5
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination? When Dewey wrote that ‘too much of traditional education . . . tends to create the closed mind’, there is no doubt that he was referring in part to the instilling of religious beliefs which for ages has been a primary goal of educational institutions of the traditional type.1 Conservatives in particular have long insisted that a vital dimension of education is ‘faith based’ and involves the ‘spiritual training’ of the young and the reproduction of religious tradition. Traditions survive by passing down to the next generation the accumulated experience and wisdom of the past, and one of the mechanisms by which this is effected is education. Spiritual training runs parallel to training of the more purely academic sort and to moral education as well, each element contributing in the conservative’s way of thinking to the true meaning of education. It would be difficult to overstate the influence this idea has had throughout human history to the present day and in a great many, if not indeed all, cultures. It is an idea with which Dewey was, of course, well familiar and one with which his philosophy of education to all appearances clashes rather directly. In view of this, one might have expected Dewey to confront the issue of religious instruction in schools and universities, yet curiously he did not, or not in the direct and sustained fashion that his decidedly non-traditional conception of education would lead us to expect. What provoked his most sustained opposition with respect to ‘the old education’ are its disconnection from experience, its authoritarianism, and its tendency to narrow rather than widen students’ horizons.2 The direct inculcation of religious teachings, however, remained more in the background of Dewey’s critique than in the foreground where one might think it belongs, and nowhere in Dewey’s educational writings would he argue directly and at length against the practice of providing religious instruction in the schools. The grounds that Dewey provided for opposition to religious education are unmistakable and several: religious instruction at an early age severely weakens the capacity for independent thought, creates an often insurmountable prejudice that distorts future inquiry into theological, philosophical, ethical, and related questions, creates deplorable intellectual habits of docility and deference to authority, promotes dogmatism and 183
184
Education in the Human Sciences
parochialism rather than their opposites, and in general furthers the cause of illiberal education. All the arguments that one could wish to make against religious instruction for the young are present and well articulated in Dewey’s works, yet curiously he himself applied these arguments to religious education with some hesitation. Religious education was not treated as a major theme in any of Dewey’s works, yet that it constitutes a major obstacle to the educational reform he advocated there can be no doubt. What I outline in this chapter, accordingly, is a Deweyan position on this issue which is based upon arguments that he provided while applying them to our present theme in the direct and sustained way that Dewey himself did not. My question pertains less to what the proper aims of teaching and learning particular religious doctrines are, be it at the primary, secondary, or post-secondary level, than to whether the practice ought to be undertaken at all. My Deweyan argument is that teaching religion in any manner to the intellectually immature is mis-educative and that what passes for spiritual training in countless institutions of learning today can be nothing other than indoctrination and a distortion of education’s true purpose. To begin, let us recall a few principles that are fundamental to Dewey’s critique of traditional education and to his own positive views. A basic principle of Dewey’s is that when theorizing about the practice of education, as with other practices, we must avoid imposing aims on the educative process that are extraneous to the process itself. Practices always already contain their own immanent ends, and it is the theorist’s task to identify and interpret what these are and to critique the imposition of aims or means that negate the practice’s given purpose. If the ultimate end of education is the art of thinking or the cultivation of intellectual capacity which enables students to negotiate experience intelligently, this requires that educational authorities practice restraint regarding the instilling of beliefs to which the authorities themselves subscribe. It requires an adjustment of pedagogical means to the ends that are immanent to the learning process and a grounding of that process in the students’ own experience. Where traditional education errs is in its tendency to ground the process in goals that are externally imposed and that effectively undermine its true purpose. Regarding the sources and consequences of these extraneous aims, Dewey wrote the following: The vice of externally imposed ends has deep roots. Teachers receive them from superior authorities; these authorities accept them from what is current in the community. The teachers impose them upon children. As a first consequence, the intelligence of the teacher is not free; it is confined to receiving the aims laid down from above. Too rarely is the individual teacher so free from the dictation of authoritative supervisor,
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
185
textbook on methods, prescribed course of study, etc., that he can let his mind come to close quarters with the pupil’s mind and the subject matter. This distrust of the teacher’s experience is then reflected in lack of confidence in the responses of pupils. The latter receive their aims through a double or treble external imposition, and are constantly confused by the conflict between the aims which are natural to their own experience at the time and those in which they are taught to acquiesce. Until the democratic criterion of the intrinsic significance of every growing experience is recognized, we shall be intellectually confused by the demand for adaptation to external aims. The external aims to which Dewey here refers include a particular body of doctrine, be it religious, political, or what have you, that a community expects educational institutions to instill in the minds of the young or that such institutions or individual educators themselves decide to impose. When such ends supplant the aims that are inherent to the educative process itself – ends that, according to Dewey, are ‘always rigid’ and ‘can only be insisted upon’ – education becomes merely a means to an end, and where the end itself is the content of students’ beliefs rather than their ability to fashion beliefs independently.3 If conventional views on education regard the practice as in all essential respects a means to an end – the continuation of a tradition, a preparation for later life, a precondition of gaining a livelihood, etc. – the Deweyan reply takes the form not of a categorical denial of education’s instrumental value but of the assertion of a higher and altogether immanent purpose: ‘the educational process has no need beyond itself; it is its own end’.4 In theorizing about the aims of education we face a choice between regarding the learning process as most fundamentally an end or a means, and where asserting the former does not deny that as a secondary matter (and the qualification is important) it is also a means to any number of ends beyond itself. This basic choice is of special relevance to the question of religious instruction. For its advocates, religious education ultimately serves the purpose of reproducing a particular tradition of belief in the minds of the young or, more innocuously stated, seeing to students’ spiritual and moral training, where such training is taken to be distinct from academic training in the usual sense of the term. Interestingly, Dewey did not reject outright the view that education serves as a means of social continuity and of the passing down of tradition. On the contrary, this fundamentally Hegelian thinker would always remain mindful of the human being’s situatedness in culture and tradition, and was never tempted into adopting a Hobbesian or strongly individualistic conception of the self. Persons are constituted by the social relations that sustain them and the traditions of belief and evaluation that provide them with a
186
Education in the Human Sciences
fundamental orientation – yet another theme in Dewey’s philosophy that he would share with twentieth-century phenomenology. The following passage is representative of Dewey’s view on this matter: The child is an organic whole, intellectually, socially, and morally, as well as physically. We must take the child as a member of society in the broadest sense, and demand for and from the schools whatever is necessary to enable the child intelligently to recognize all his social relations and take his part in sustaining them.5 Further, the entire life of the mind takes its orientation from the traditions in which we stand: ‘There is no thinking which does not present itself on a background of tradition’, Dewey wrote, and where tradition consists far less in ‘blind custom’ than in ideas and interpretations that are passed down to us. ‘Traditions are ways of interpretation and of observation, of valuation, of everything explicitly thought of. They are the circumambient atmosphere which thought must breathe; no one ever had an idea except as he inhaled some of this atmosphere.’6 Well prior to the hermeneutic or interpretive turn in philosophy, Dewey asked: ‘Would we have any intellectual operations without the language which is a social product?’ – a question, of course, to which he replied in the negative while adding that ‘apart from unconditioned reflexes, like the knee-jerk, it may be questioned whether there is a single human activity or experience which is not profoundly affected by the social and cultural environment’.7 Dewey also maintained that education belongs to a larger social undertaking to transmit the accumulated knowledge and experience of a culture to the next generation; however the point that he emphasized concerns the limits of this undertaking and the conditions under which it appropriately occurs. In this respect Dewey stood in a long line of philosophers going back to Plato and Aristotle who warn of the inhibiting effect on rational thought of deference to tradition or past experience. There is a considerable difference between acknowledging the embeddedness of thought in tradition and the kind of traditionalism that is often upheld by advocates of conservative and religious education. Simple repetition of the past is neither rational nor educative, while tradition itself constitutes not simply the dead weight of the past which must be conserved for its own sake but ideas that are often useful in resolving problematic situations of the present. While much of the curriculum in any educational context, in Dewey’s words, ‘represents the enduring experience and thought of the centuries’, the ultimate justification for this is not the conservation or reproduction of tradition as an end in itself but at best as a means: ‘that it [the school or university] may put more effectually the resources of the past at the disposition of the present’. Whereas the
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
187
traditionalist is likely to view the transmission of past experience and culture to the young as an end justifiable on grounds of the inherent value or truth that it contains, and in the case of religious education of the salvation of souls, Dewey insisted that ‘[t]he sole reason for maintaining the continuity of culture is to make that culture operative in the conditions of modern life’.8 Another basic principle of Dewey’s is that the curriculum at all educational levels must connect directly with students’ lived experience rather than be imposed on it from without. The subject matter ought not consist of a body of entirely ready-made knowledge or belief that teachers must actively instill and students passively receive, as the traditional model of religious instruction has it. For experience to be educative, it must unfold organically rather than according to a predetermined plan; otherwise stated, it is the process of expanding development rather than the outcome of students’ religious or other beliefs that is the educator’s proper focus. The mark of an educative experience, for Dewey, is not that it results in anything specific by way of personal convictions but that it exhibits continuity from one experience to another, that it broadens horizons and opens minds without fear of what beliefs students will one day hold. Also relevant here is the simultaneously passive and active dimensions of human experience as Dewey conceived of it. Its active dimension is exemplified in scientific experimentation where again beliefs have the epistemological status of hypotheses which it is the business of inquiry to confirm or disconfirm rather than doctrines to which one clings. While intellectual growth requires an experimental frame of mind regarding ideas in general, Dewey lamented that [m]en still want the crutch of dogma, of beliefs fixed by authority, to relieve them of the trouble of thinking and the responsibility of directing their activity by thought. They tend to confine their own thinking to a consideration of which one among the rival systems of dogma they will accept.9 Even the passive dimension of experience is no simple reception of ideas or suffering of sense impressions but is a witnessing of the consequences that follow upon the provisional acceptance or entertainment of a hypothesis, and is fulfilled in dialectical fashion by an active re-evaluation, again on the model of experimentation. Proponents of religious education will object that the growth in experience that Dewey held out as an ideal is potentially anything but, depending entirely on that into which one grows. The experience of a criminal may unfold continuously from one activity or interest to another. Rather than allow it to culminate where it will, the educator’s obligation is to shape the
188
Education in the Human Sciences
students’ character so that future experience will unfold in the desired direction, Dewey’s critics will urge, and it is here that positive instruction in religious and moral doctrines has a place. Dewey took the objection seriously and replied to it directly in Experience and Education not by denying that one may grow in a direction that is morally unsound but by asking whether growth in the direction of a skilled criminal, for instance, ‘promotes or retards growth in general’. He continued: ‘Does this form of growth create conditions for further growth, or does it set up conditions that shut off the person who has grown in this particular direction from the occasions, stimuli, and opportunities for continuing growth in new directions?’10 Beyond this reply, he expressed considerable reservation on the question of the capacity of educators to shape students’ character by conscious design. This reservation is based on several considerations regarding the conditions that shape character. First, schools are hardly alone in influencing students’ moral character, nor on Dewey’s view is their influence as profound or lasting as the larger configuration of practices and social relations in which they are embedded. Students’ experience outside the classroom typically reaches deeper into who they are than anything that takes place within it, while schools can fundamentally alter a character formed in an out-of-school environment only in a limited degree. Further, a person’s character ‘is something that is formed rather than something that can be taught as geography and arithmetic are taught’. Its formation is contingent upon the habits of thought and action that are ‘the fibre of character’ and upon experience generally. This may and ought to include specific moral instruction about actions approved of and disapproved of, but even here, Dewey maintained, more depends on the spirit than the content of such instruction: Reproof may be given in such a way that dislike of all authority is inculcated. Or a child develops skill in evasion and in covering up things that he knows are disapproved of. Negativism, fear, undue self-consciousness often result. Consequently the net effect of even direct moral instruction cannot be foretold, and its efficacy depends upon its fitting into the mass of conditions which play unconsciously upon the young.11 In short, the roots of character extend deeper than formal religious and moral instruction reaches and pertain more to the imagination, desires, and habits that form conduct than to any doctrines instilled by educators. Dewey’s reservation regarding character formation and religious education more generally extends into his critique of direct efforts by educational institutions to mold the convictions of the young, particularly convictions that are of obvious contestability and that are instilled into the minds of students prior to an age when they are capable of rational criticism. The
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
189
inculcation of controversial beliefs on the pretense of authority, tradition, or spiritual training, for Dewey, is the veritable antithesis of education and is vulnerable to criticism on several grounds, beginning with the docility of mind that indoctrination in any form brings about. The educated mind is above all adept in the art of thinking or of actively inquiring into a given field of belief without a predetermined or dogmatically held conviction regarding what is true. If it is the art of thinking that we would teach, this entails that ‘[w]e must have no misgivings as to what the child shall think. The moment we stipulate what a child shall think, we make it impossible for him to think at all.’12 All genuine inquiry requires the freedom to pursue ideas in the spirit of scientific experimentation and to let whatever conclusions are reached be what they will or what the general course of investigation determines. When certain beliefs are declared by educational authorities to be beyond the scope of such inquiry, students learn not to think but to obey; ‘for thinking’, as Dewey put it, ‘is not the attribute of parrots’, nor of ‘well-trained apes’.13 The outcome this produces is not an intelligent appropriation of tradition but a simple uniformity of beliefs uncritically held. A further argument that Dewey applied specifically to the instilling of religious beliefs bears on the mis-educative effects of imposing, or attempting to impose, adult experiences of spirituality upon children and youth. Children are not small adults, and if they can be said genuinely to have a spiritual life at all it will not be of the same qualitative nature and depth as the adult’s experience of sin, redemption, or what have you. Attempting ‘to force prematurely upon the child either the mature ideas or the spiritual emotions of the adult is to run the risk of a fundamental danger, that of forestalling future deeper experiences which might otherwise in their season become personal realities to him’.14 Recalling Dewey’s definition of a miseducative experience, this is described as one that closes off possibilities of further experience rather than the contrary. This occurs, for instance, by creating an aversion in the student’s mind to a particular domain of ideas or experience, or indeed to learning in general. The adolescent who is compelled to read Shakespeare and feign comprehension is likely to come away from the experience with an aversion to Shakespeare or to literature generally which may remain with them throughout life. By the same token, when the religious experiences of the adult are effectively forced on the consciousness of the young, the latter are more likely to develop a lasting aversion to spirituality than an authentic understanding of it. Regarding the teaching of religion in the public schools, Dewey remarked briefly in an essay from 1908 that one of the primary missions of the public school system is to promote social unity, not in the sense of instilling a particular doctrine but in the sense that by nurturing the intellectual capacity of the young, schools are at the same time and by the same means
190
Education in the Human Sciences
preparing students for democratic citizenship. If democratic politics involves a search for social unity amid difference, as in Dewey’s view it does, the public schools promote this aim ‘in bringing together those of different nationalities, languages, traditions, and creeds, in assimilating them together upon the basis of what is common and public in endeavor and achievement’. Religious instruction effectively undermines this aim by separating students into denominations, ‘each with its private inspiration and outlook’.15 Dividing students at the appointed hour into groups of Protestants and Catholics, Jews and Muslims, promotes an intellectual segregation that is the undoing of democracy while it simultaneously conscripts students into movements of believers rather than educating them for democratic citizenship and the intellectual independence that this requires. On the subject of intellectual conscription, Dewey would also remark on the dangers of this in an essay of 1897, arguing that any form of education in which ‘the child is to be a member of a certain form of social life’, such as a member of a religious denomination, is mis-educative in the ‘mere fact that he is not taken in himself, but as a type of society’. Students are regarded under this condition not in their own right as intelligent agents or citizens but merely as members of a faction or means of carrying on a tradition or organization. In addition to the mis-educative effects of such conscription, modern society has become ‘too complex’ and ‘makes too many demands upon personality to be capable of being based upon custom and routine without the utmost disaster’.16 Modern democratic societies require a population that is educated not for special membership in a faction but to be intellectually competent citizens in a complex social order. Additional arguments that Dewey provided without applying them specifically to religious instruction concern the training of intellectual habits and the central role of the environment in education. The development of the capacities of mind that are the highest achievement of education occurs, as Dewey would often argue, not ‘by direct conveyance of beliefs, emotions, and knowledge’, but ‘through the intermediary of the environment’.17 Only indirectly, through the creation of conditions in which intellectual abilities and habits are called forth in larger processes of inquiry, do such capacities develop rather than through more direct means. As we have seen, the ability to think develops not as a result of direct instruction on how to master a certain method but in the course of thinking about a particular subject matter, thus through the intermediary of a curricular environment as well as a general learning environment that is conducive to free inquiry. Education happens in a social atmosphere in which the individual participates actively in a joint enterprise of one kind or another, not through the passive reception of an educational authority’s beliefs. As we have seen in previous chapters, Dewey regarded intellectual habit
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
191
formation as a crucial educational aim, raising the question in the present context of the habits of mind that religious instruction typically instills together with a certain body of doctrine. Quite apart from educators’ intentions, their practices produce effects in the intellectual makeup of their students, for good or for ill. The intention to enable personal salvation, for instance, often renders future learning in certain directions difficult. Dewey made this observation without applying it to the religious context in one of his earliest essays from 1886: If a student is thoroughly inoculated with a system, his growth in the future is rendered difficult. The cartilaginous portions of the brain are hardened and its sutures closed. One who has been introduced when his mind is most plastic into a system of hard and fast distinctions, cannot lose their impress. All new facts he can classify and comprehend only by their connection with his system. When a new fact appears he does not assimilate it; he takes out his rule and his pigeon-holed box; measures the fact according to his ready-made standard, and tucks it away in its appropriate place.18 This important passage rings true for university professors who teach courses in religious studies, ethics, or philosophy to students who have graduated from religious elementary and secondary schools, and still more perhaps for such graduates themselves. Instructors in such fields are regularly compelled to engage at the outset of a course in unwelcome exercises in intellectual ground-clearing, attempting to remove long-standing prejudices and to pry open minds long closed by years of indoctrination. Minds long habituated to the feeling of certainty and security in convictions for which they are unable to argue but that have been instilled from an early age and believed in by all one’s peers and prior educators can be remarkably resistant to entertaining new ideas, to regarding ideas as hypotheses rather than certainties, and to questioning their convictions in an intellectually honest fashion. When such students are not completely unteachable they are nonetheless so habituated to regarding worldviews as dogmatic systems of belief which can only be insisted upon or fought over that the concept of education as rational and co-operative inquiry in the absence of certainty is registered as a kind of heresy. ‘This professor must be an atheist’, such a student will often think when the professor speaks of argumentative rigor and the need to subject one’s convictions to critical scrutiny. The habits of jumping to conclusions, immunizing certain ideas from serious questioning, and confusing justification with the provision of emotional comfort are a few of the more common miseducative effects of teaching religion to the intellectually immature. Such habits may be
192
Education in the Human Sciences
extended well beyond the religious domain to other areas of intellectual life, such as the ethical and the political, and can prove intractable at later educational stages and throughout life. Indeed, on Dewey’s view so much of human thought and action is a result of habits formed and ingrained at an early age that it is difficult to overstate their significance at all stages of the learning process. The importance of habit consists not only in its resistance to change but in its nature as a disposition or inclination that leads the individual toward certain future experiences and away from others, which actively seeks out the conditions that call for its expression. It shapes future experience through anticipation and expectation and by providing powers by which to negotiate one’s environment and to form purposes. At every stage of education intellectual habits are being formed and re-formed: . . . if not habits of careful looking into things, then habits of hasty, heedless, impatient glancing over the surface; if not habits consecutively following up the suggestions that occur, then habits of haphazard, grasshopper-like guessing; if not habits of suspending judgment til inferences have been tested by the examination of evidence, then habits of credulity alternating with flippant incredulity, belief or unbelief being based, in either case, upon whim, emotion, or accidental circumstances.19 If it is the former habits in each of these pairings that educators would instill, this is accomplished by creating the conditions that call them forth and furnishing the environment that demands their exercise. The student educated into membership in a religious tradition is habituated to regarding certain areas of thought, such as the scientific or the mathematical, as requiring rational investigation and the rigorous justification of conclusions, while other areas, notably the religious and the ethical, are beyond reason’s scope, an attitude of mind that positively inhibits future intellectual development. One of the principal indicators of educational success, quite apart from the quantity of knowledge that is amassed, is the students’ adoption of particular intellectual virtues and the absence of corresponding vices. The reason for their importance lies in the fact that the intellectual virtues constitute the conditions that are necessary for future learning and that make it possible for students to reflect upon their experience long after their formal education is at an end. Dewey’s list of intellectual vices includes several that are relevant to the present discussion, none more so than the dogmatism that he would decry throughout his career. The ‘over-positive and dogmatic habit of mind’ that is so often associated with religious education is fatal to intelligent thought.20 ‘To be bound to a given conclusion is the exact opposite of being required to inquire so as to find out the means of reaching a conclusion as a decision that warrants resumption of decisive
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
193
behavior.’21 The habit of regarding ideas not as provisional and fallible methods of interpretation but as eternal verities and absolutes about which one can only be correct or incorrect, saved or unsaved, constitutes the demise of thought itself. Excessive self-certainty, rigidity of outlook, narrowness of perspective, and inflexibility of mind prohibit new ideas from coming forth or simple learning from different traditions of thought. Other intellectual vices Dewey identified include an unimaginative scholasticism, conventionality, parochialism, and deference to authority, none of which are unknown in traditional religious education and all of which are formidable obstacles to future learning. The educated mind is characterized by openness and inquisitiveness, by a hospitality to new ideas and a flexibility that does not equate with indecisiveness or lack of conviction. Its habitual attitudes include a reflectiveness and persistence in thinking matters through to a conclusion, a wide-ranging curiosity and an ‘inclination to learn from life itself’, a preference for depth over breadth, and a critical intelligence that allows one to resist propaganda. For Dewey, the educated mind resolves problematic situations and reaches conclusions in an unhurried way; its beliefs are formed only at the outcome of an investigative process, regardless of whether the belief in question pertains to a scientific, philosophical, theological, or any other issue. It is reflective not only in the sense of being preoccupied with fundamental questions of human existence but in the sense that its chief concern lies in identifying the grounds of belief while it refuses to accept any system of thought without a convincing rationale. In general, then, it is the combination of ‘[o]penmindedness, single-mindedness, sincerity, breadth of outlook, thoroughness, assumption of responsibility for developing the consequences of ideas which are accepted’, and related dispositions that Dewey praised both as properly intellectual virtues as well as ‘intrinsically moral questions’.22 The virtues of mind and character that religious instruction at the elementary and secondary levels most often aims to instill are hardly those described by Dewey. Traditionally, it is the content of students’ thought far more than their capacity to think independently of a particular religious tradition that is the chief aim of ‘spiritual training’, as is regularly testified to by the intellectual habits that one most often finds among the graduates of religious schools. A tendency commonly exhibited by these students upon reaching the university is to combine an often impressive knowledge and astuteness in the realm of science or mathematics with an alarming credulity regarding religion and any matters that relate even tangentially to it – ethics, politics, philosophy. A kind of intellectual schizophrenia is often the result of years of religious education, where the student holds to all the appropriate standards of rigorous thought in some areas of intellectual life while expecting no rational basis whatever in other areas, and indeed regards this
194
Education in the Human Sciences
as a given or a virtue. This might strike us as pathological were it not so commonplace, and not only among the young. Recall as well that for Dewey the very spirit and meaning of education is definable in terms of inquiry, a practice that requires an advanced degree of freedom in order that educators and students may pursue given lines of investigation or argumentation to their logical conclusions without fear of contradicting a creed. The ‘freedom of intelligence’ is a necessary precondition of intellectual growth since such growth takes place only through the cultivation of habits of thought and in the ‘free mental play’ that follows the subject matter wherever it leads and ‘apart from any subservience to a preconceived belief’.23 In view of the strong accent that Dewey placed on academic freedom, one might expect that on the infrequent occasion that he took up the issue of education within denominational schools and colleges he would apply the principle there as well. However, in an essay of 1902, simply entitled ‘Academic Freedom’, Dewey expressed a curious ambivalence on the question of whether the very principle that most essentially defines the mission of the school and the university applies equally to denominational institutions. He began the essay by distinguishing ‘the university proper’ from ‘those teaching bodies, called by whatever name, whose primary business is to inculcate a fixed set of ideas and facts’, among which he explicitly included religious schools and colleges. After noting the obvious conflict an educator at such an institution faces when charged with teaching in a field some of whose conclusions run afoul of the institution’s doctrines, Dewey stopped short of asserting that he or she must challenge these doctrines should the course of inquiry require it, as we would expect in the secular university. As he wrote: ‘An ecclesiastical, political, or even economic corporation holding certain tenets certainly has the right to support an institution to maintain and propagate its creed.’ This surprising statement – surprising since the institution in question is ostensibly an educational institution and Dewey continually insisted that uninhibited inquiry is the very lifeblood of education – is coupled with a second, equally surprising, assertion: that the relevant question here is ‘not so much of freedom of thought as of ability to secure competent teachers willing to work under such conditions, to pay bills, and to have a constituency from which to draw students’.24 Here it appears not to be an issue of principle at all, but a practical problem of finding students for such schools and educators who do not find such conditions odious. It is odd as well that he would speak in this connection of the rights of institutions over against the rights of students to be educated rather than indoctrinated into a creed. Dewey went on in the essay to observe the historical point that the line of separation between universities and denominational institutions has become increasingly blurred as the latter have gradually taken upon themselves many
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
195
of the characteristics and functions of the secular university. Insofar, then, as an institution that is formally associated with a religious denomination takes up the functions of the university – and, it seems, only to that extent – it is bound by the principle of freedom of inquiry. ‘[I]n other respects,’ however, ‘while the historical denominational ties are elongated and attenuated, they still remain; and through them the instructor is to some extent bound. Implicit, if not explicit, obligations are assumed.’ Acknowledging the obvious conflict that arises for educators attempting to reconcile fundamentally irreconcilable aims, his suggestion was a meager one: ‘in the confusion of this conflict it is difficult to determine just which way the instructor is morally bound to face. Upon the whole it is clear, however, that the burden falls upon the individual.’ Should such an individual find his or her institution’s doctrinal restrictions unduly burdensome, then ‘there is one liberty which cannot be taken away from him: the liberty of finding a more congenial sphere of work’.25 Dewey’s strange ambivalence on this issue, and his reluctance more generally to proscribe entirely the inculcation of religious beliefs in the classroom, stem from a basic conviction of his regarding the ultimate importance of religion in human life. He would even speak in an essay from 1903 of ‘the moral and religious’ as ‘the most fundamental of all educational questions’ – not only a philosophical but an educational question, and indeed a single question. Here he asserted that if the question cannot be ignored in an educational context due to its profound importance, it can nonetheless be taken up ‘in the reverent spirit of science’ rather than in the traditional manner.26 While his account of how this is done is predictably short on detail, he did at least suggest the possibility of providing religious instruction to the young in a fashion that is consistent with his general approach. One might expect that ‘the most fundamental of all educational questions’ would receive the voluminous treatment that typified Dewey’s practice as a philosopher, and while he would never provide one, he did at least provide a few clues, mostly by way of negative description. Thus, as we have seen, such instruction must not amount to straightforward indoctrination or instill mis-educative intellectual habits; it must not undermine the spirit of inquiry by creating too many prohibitions on what may be thought and said in the classroom, yet somehow it must instill a particular set of religious beliefs in students’ minds. The means by which this is done poses an interesting dilemma, to say the least. One principled suggestion Dewey did provide, albeit with uncharacteristic brevity, was to point out that the denominational school and the university are both committed to the truth; the latter’s function straightforwardly pertains to the production and dissemination of knowledge while in the case of the former it is the transmission of tradition that is the primary aim, yet in both kinds of institution ‘[t]he one thing that is inherent and essential is the idea
196
Education in the Human Sciences
of truth’.27 Dewey’s distinction here between the production and the transmission of truth is anything but straightforward for either an educator or a pragmatic experimentalist, both of whom, as he so often argued, must regard received knowledge of all kinds not as absolutes but as hypotheses found useful in the past and that may or may not assist us in resolving problematic situations of the present. If one were teaching biology within a Christian high school, to take an obvious test case, is it the received truth of Genesis or the scientific truth of evolution that one should teach? Were one teaching in a public institution, Dewey’s answer would plainly be the latter, yet what of the institution whose doctrines directly contradict the consensus of modern biologists? While this is undoubtedly a question that Dewey entertained, the only answer he provided – and briefly – is not a principled but a personal one: if one subscribes to evolution, one would do well to find other employment. As I have noted, Dewey also expressed considerable skepticism about the likelihood of direct instruction in religion or ethics producing a profound impression on students’ character. It is the educational environment, habit formation, and the course of experience generally that form character, not straightforward lecturing on religion. ‘It is one thing’, Dewey wrote, ‘to learn words and sentences by heart and another thing to take them to heart so that they influence action.’28 A teacher’s example exercises a far more profound influence on students’ character, including their spiritual character, than lessons learned on doctrinal matters. As well, Dewey always insisted that education never be regarded merely as a means to an end, whether the end is the continuation of a tradition of belief, a preparation for later life, or anything else. Any activity or subject matter that is genuinely educative should be treated as an end in itself, even if as a secondary matter it is also a means to some further end. The same can be said of human experience in general. Dewey expressed considerable discontent with theological worldviews such as the evangelical Christianity on which he himself was raised, and in which he fervently believed as a young man, which regard human experience and life in general essentially as a means to an afterlife, and in the same spirit in which he opposed viewing education as a means only. As Dewey expressed it in an essay from 1893, We have to a considerable extent, given up thinking of this life as merely a preparation for another life. Very largely, however, we think of some parts of this life as merely preparation to other later stages of it. It is so very largely as to the process of education; and if I were asked to name the most needed of all reforms in the spirit of education, I should say: ‘Cease conceiving of education as mere preparation for later life, and make of it the full meaning of the present life.’29
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
197
When writing on religion and education, Dewey generally adopted a liberal attitude, one that was not well disposed to traditional organizations such as the Roman church which depreciate both education and human experience generally by regarding the former as a means of indoctrination and the latter as a means of gaining entrance into the afterlife. He would, for instance, oppose efforts by that church to obtain state funding for its schools, writing in 1947 in opposition to a proposed federal law to extend government subsidies to such schools that the bill expressed ‘encouragement of a powerful reactionary world organization in the most vital realm of democratic life with the resulting promulgation of principles inimical to democracy’.30 Roman Catholic and other religious schools embody the same ethos of authoritarianism that characterizes the hierarchical structure of the churches themselves. The public school system, by contrast, is a vital ingredient of a democratic society and, accordingly, is alone the proper recipient of state funding. If education would serve the cause of religion in any way, Dewey argued, it would most effectively do so not through such direct measures as providing instruction in theology or government subsidies for denominational schools but by ‘serving the cause of social unification’. Education serves an important democratizing function – it is training citizens for democratic participation – and so must never abandon the democratic spirit. Insofar as it approaches religion at all, it must therefore resist the parochialism and dogmatism that are the undoing of a democratic society. ‘[U]nder certain conditions,’ as he would also write, ‘schools are more religious in substance and in promise without any of the conventional badges and machinery of religious instruction than they could be in cultivating these forms at the expense of a state-consciousness.’31 As I remarked at the outset of this chapter, what is most noteworthy about Dewey’s writings on religious education is their uncharacteristic brevity and the clear note of hesitation on which what remarks he would offer on the subject were advanced. It was certainly no lack of courage on Dewey’s part that caused the hesitation to argue directly and forcefully against religious instruction in schools in the manner that he argued against other forms of traditional education, but rather his conviction that religious institutions and traditions have a right to reproduce themselves, and schools are one of the usual means by which this is effected. In what follows I propose to take up this question in a more or less Deweyan spirit while examining how well the views that he provided stand up at the present time.
Dewey and the postmoderns Here is an unlikely coupling. When it has any chance of succeeding, dialogue presupposes a degree of common ground between interlocutors as
198
Education in the Human Sciences
well as areas of disagreement; the latter gives us something to talk about while the former provides the conditions that make productive dialogue possible. What common ground exists, one will surely ask, between Dewey’s philosophy and the contemporary postmodern/poststructuralist scene, be it on the topic of this chapter or any other? There is no need to provide an account of what these two schools of thought do not have in common (and, of course, postmodernism itself is very far from constituting a unified school of thought, as its proponents will be very quick to point out). Nonetheless, and with all due respect to the many differences that exist between a Jacques Derrida, a Michel Foucault, a Gilles Deleuze, and so on, the subject that is under discussion here provides a possible meeting ground owing to a recent trend in postmodern thought toward the rehabilitation of religion. Jean-Luc Marion, Jacques Derrida, John Caputo, Richard Kearney, Gianni Vattimo, and Calvin Schrag are a few of the key figures in this trend and, once again, the differences between their positions prevent us from speaking of a unified school of thought. What is both interesting and surprising is that some of the basic gestures that we find in the postmodern literature were foreshadowed in Dewey’s own contribution to the philosophy of religion. I should like therefore to put two texts ever so carefully into speaking terms with each other with a view to seeing what this might contribute to our theme. The texts are Dewey’s A Common Faith, published in 1933, and John Caputo’s On Religion, published in 2001. The latter text contains no references to the former or to Dewey, nor does one find Dewey a frequent topic of discussion in postmodern discourse. A Common Faith is Dewey’s principal contribution to the philosophy of religion, and in it he did not take up the question of religious education. Nor is education a major theme in Caputo’s On Religion or some other of his texts in this field.32 My aim in this section is not to provide a simple comparison between these two texts or thinkers as an end in itself but to question whether an examination of their views on religion can shed light on the educational question: is there any sense of religious education that is, properly speaking, educational, or is everything that passes for spiritual training a veneer for miseducation and indoctrination? In the interest of brevity I shall not go into great detail in interpreting these figures’ positions on religion and the philosophy of religion. Both of their views emerge from their philosophies as a whole, Dewey’s being fully consistent with his theory of experience and Caputo’s with his ‘radical hermeneutics’. Dewey’s text begins with a key distinction between religion and ‘the religious’, which is where the similarity to later postmodern thought begins. By the former term, Dewey intended ‘a special body of beliefs pertaining especially to the supernatural and practices having some kind of institutional organization’. There being in his view ‘no such thing as religion in general’, only religions in the plural, each can be thought of as a world-
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
199
view comprising a set of doctrines, rituals, and so on. The adjectival expression, by contrast, refers to nothing in the way of a specifiable entity, either institutional or as a system of beliefs. It does not denote anything to which one can specifically point as one can point to this and that historic religion or existing church. For it does not denote anything that can exist by itself or that can be organized into a particular and distinctive form of existence. It denotes attitudes that may be taken toward every object and every proposed end or ideal.33 Dewey’s preference for ‘the religious’ over religion reflects both his skepticism of religious doctrines insofar as they purport to describe the truth about the world and his interest in religious experience. Dewey viewed religious experience neither as a grounding for any given set of beliefs or practices nor as incommensurable with other dimensions of human experience. The religious, for Dewey, is an aspect of ordinary experience, one that need not commit us to particular beliefs concerning the supernatural. Religious experience can come into its own only when divested of doctrines regarding the supernatural. He therefore did not seek to justify any of the confessional faiths, instead preferring to speak in somewhat ambiguous terms of his conception of the religious. It is a conception that does not regard the religious as categorically apart from experience in its other forms, such as the scientific, aesthetic, and so on. The ‘“religious” as a quality of experience signifies something that may belong to all these experiences’ and ‘is the polar opposite of some type of experience that can exist by itself’. It is a dimension or ‘quality of experience’ that religions in their traditional forms actively stand in the way of rather than afford with an authentic outlet. Dewey would speak of religious experience as ‘a certain attitude and outlook, independent of the supernatural’, as a ‘deep-seated harmonizing of the self with the Universe (as a name for the totality of conditions with which the self is connected)’, and ‘a just sense of nature as the whole of which we are the parts’. None of these experiential descriptions would amount to theological doctrines, nor did his somewhat halting use of the word ‘God’ commit him to theism. Dewey would speak of God as a name for a kind of ‘natural piety’ which he believed to be absent in traditional religions and atheism alike, both of which presuppose a view of ‘man in isolation’. As he summarized the point, For in spite of supernaturalism’s reference to something beyond nature, it conceives of this earth as the moral center of the universe and of man as the apex of the whole scheme of things. It regards the drama of sin and redemption enacted within the isolated and lonely soul of man as the one
200
Education in the Human Sciences
thing of ultimate importance. Apart from man, nature is held either accursed or negligible. Militant atheism is also affected by lack of natural piety. The ties binding man to nature that poets have always celebrated are passed over lightly. The attitude taken is often that of man living in an indifferent and hostile world and issuing blasts of defiance. A religious attitude, however, needs the sense of a connection of man, in the way of both dependence and support, with the enveloping world that the imagination feels is the universe. Use of the words ‘God’ or ‘divine’ to convey the union of actual with ideal may protect man from a sense of isolation from consequent despair or defiance.34 Dewey’s sense of religiosity was centered on the connections between human beings and the natural world, on that which takes the individual out of isolation and binds it to conditions and ideals by which it lives. Dewey’s God is thoroughly naturalized in naming the ends to which we are ultimately devoted and the union of these ideals with the actual. God is not a supreme being, for Dewey, but a description of experience. Whether he was speaking of God, religious experience, or religious knowledge, Dewey insisted in each instance against regarding these in isolation from their ostensible opposites. Should we speak of religious knowledge, for instance, we are not referring to a special domain of truths inaccessible by the usual means of knowing. In this text as well Dewey would repeat that ‘[t]here is but one sure road of access to the truth – the road of patient, cooperative inquiry operating by means of observation, experiment, record and controlled reflection’. Religious faith is not an exception to this and in no sense transcends ordinary ways of knowing. The ‘whole notion of special truths that are religious by their own nature’ must be emphatically rejected ‘together with the idea of peculiar avenues of access to such truths’. The only conception of faith that Dewey believed permissible is the kind of ‘natural piety’ just alluded to – a this-worldly faith in ideals and in ‘the unification of the self’ that may be accomplished through their actualization. Any conception of religious education that would be compatible with this view would need to abandon the old practice of compartmentalizing truth, declaring some off limits to rational inquiry and utterly sacrosanct while other domains of knowledge or belief require intellectually rigorous justification. It would need to conceive of the religious in its continuity with the rest of human experience and as no less intelligent, in the pragmatic sense of the word, than experience in its other dimensions. This last point Dewey would qualify by remarking that intelligence is not a passionless affair. Passion, including religious passion, must be tied to the post of reason, he would always insist, but this does not give rise to a dichotomy of reason versus passion, intelligence versus faith, or what have you. ‘There is such a thing as passionate
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
201
intelligence, as ardor in behalf of light shining into the murky places of social existence, and as zeal for its refreshing and purifying effect.’35 I shall return to this point in due course. First, I would like to bring Dewey’s views on religion and the religious into connection with John Caputo’s ‘religion without religion’ (a phrase he borrows from Derrida) before turning the discussion back to education. If there are compelling arguments against teaching religion in the usual sense to students prior to an age of intellectual maturity, do such arguments also apply to what Dewey called the religious or to Caputo’s postmodern religion? Several decades after Dewey called for ‘the emancipation of the religious from religion’, a variety of continental – mostly postmodern – philosophers would attempt a rehabilitation of religion of their own, one that does not borrow from Dewey but differs from his account less than one might expect.36 Caputo’s efforts in this regard fall within the tradition of postHeideggerian phenomenology and hermeneutics with a large admixture of Derridean deconstruction. More than a century after Nietzsche pronounced the death of God, many postmoderns who claim Nietzsche as a major influence, Caputo included, now speak of God’s or religion’s return, albeit in much altered form. While Caputo’s formulation of this continues to be ‘parasitic upon the confessional forms’ of religion, most especially Christianity, it is a ‘religiousness without the confessional religions’ – particularly without their theological and metaphysical commitments – that he wishes to salvage after a few centuries of learned skepticism.37 The centerpiece of this religion is what Caputo calls ‘the passion for the impossible’. The ‘mark of a religious sensibility’, as he writes, is far less an intellectual assent to a body of doctrines than what he calls the ‘movement of living on the limit of the possible, in hope for and expectation of the impossible, a reality beyond the real’. Religion is a question of desire, not reason; it ‘is for the unhinged’, not the sober-minded. It is a ‘sense of life [that] awakens when we lose our bearings and let go, when we find ourselves brought up against something that exceeds our powers, that overpowers us and knocks us off our hinges, something impossible vis-à-vis our limited potencies’. To this sense of life he contrasts the rationalistic and narrowly pragmatic, the sort of person who is concerned only with certainties and practicalities of a mundane variety and whose experience is not cognitively deficient so much as unimaginative. While a passion, or passionate mode of experiencing life, religion is not a simple matter of anti-intellectualism. The ‘condition of this passion’, he holds, ‘is non-knowing’, but it is a nonknowing that harks back to ‘what the mystics call a docta ignorantia, a learned or wise ignorance’ rather than ignorance in its more usual forms.38 It is, like the ignorance of Socrates, the knowledge that one does not know and must live in this condition without expectation of deliverance.
202
Education in the Human Sciences
Nor is there deliverance from the flux in which human existence is invariably played out, in Caputo’s view. The religious sense of life is part of a larger openness to mystery and effort to cope with uncertainty that define our existential condition. ‘Religion’, as he writes elsewhere, . . . is a way of coming to grips with the flux, a struggle with the power of darkness, which is ‘authentic’ only so long as it ‘owns up’ to the contingency of its symbols. Faith makes its way in the dark, seeing through a glass darkly, and it is genuine only to the extent that it acknowledges the abyss in which we are all situated, the undecidability and ambiguity which engulfs us all. Religious faith is an effort to live in the ambiguity and to make ourselves at home in a world in which our concepts constitute so many ‘thin membranes of structures which we stretch across the flux’.39 If we cannot know the truth about the world with certainty, the best we can hope for is to learn to cope with mystery the best way we can. If we cannot know who we ourselves are, we can at least engage in interpretation and self-interpretation in the face of what we do not know. If in addition we cannot know exactly what it is that we love when we love God, as for Caputo we cannot, we can at least strive to keep the question open and to love whatever it is that we love with passionate urgency. In places Caputo defines religion itself very simply as ‘the love of God’, while acknowledging that the phrase ‘needs more work’. The work that he later does in this text does little to clarify matters, remarking in several places, for instance, that ‘what we really mean by “God” is love’ rather than any kind of supreme being, and that ‘God is a name we confer on things we love very dearly, like peace or justice or the messianic age’.40 God names love or the object of love, regardless of what that object may be. It is a love marked by excess, unconditionality, and a loss of self-possession. In saying this, Caputo is engaging in some phenomenological description of religious experience that is not unlike Dewey’s own efforts. Neither thinker is a theologian in the sense of an expounder of doctrines asserted to represent the truth about the deity or the afterlife. It is an experience that both are interpreting, a sense of life that goes beyond, and for Caputo that has little to do with, knowledge. Both insist upon preserving the ambiguity and open-endedness of this experience, upon resisting the metaphysical urge to reduce this to some determinate form which can be known or debated as an intellectual proposition. As a sensibility, Caputo writes that it is analogous to an aesthetic or political sense, a capacity for affective interpretation that anyone should have. Those who do not, or who conceive of the religious as a propositional matter, Caputo chides as people who are not
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
203
‘worth their salt’, an expression that he uses rather often. One who lacks a religious sense of life also lacks love, he insists, along with passion, depth, and a few other things. Their experience of life is impoverished and onedimensional. Religiosity is ‘a basic structure of human experience’ and indeed ‘the very thing that most constitutes human experience as experience’.41 It is a structure that impels us beyond ourselves, beyond what is known or securely possessed, and toward the impossible. It partakes of the Dionysian far more than the Apollonian. Yet religion also partakes of truth, Caputo argues. It is, to be sure, an unusual notion of truth of which he speaks – a truth without knowledge, or Knowledge in the upper case. Religious truth ‘is of a different sort than scientific truth’; it is not epistemologically rigorous or demonstrable. It is neither a relation of correspondence between a proposition and objective reality nor is it experimental inquiry. Instead it is analogous to the truth that we find in art. A novel, for instance, ‘lies’ only in the sense that it reports fiction rather than facts, in a way that is antithetical to scientific truth. Works of art say what is true in a different and deeper sense; they disclose meanings and open up possible avenues of thinking in ways that resonate and transform our lives. Religious experience as well reveals truth, yet not in the sense that it provides access to knowledge of a specific kind. He does, however, retain a notion of special religious truth. It is a truth that is non-propositional, unscientific, and unknowing; it is not something possessed but made and enacted in the course of loving whatever it is that we love. Since we love many things and enact this love in many ways, religious truth is not one but many. Caputo draws the obvious conclusion: ‘unlike a scientific theory, there is not a reason on earth (or in heaven) why many different religious narratives cannot all be true. “The one true religion” in that sense makes no more sense than “the one true language” or the “one true poetry,” “the one true story” or “the one true culture”.’ All religions are true – equally so, such that there is no religious conversion that can be understood as a transformation from ignorance to knowledge. It is accordingly an undogmatic and, it seems, relativistic religion that Caputo defends, albeit he does qualify this somewhat. ‘We may and need to have many religions, and many “sacred scriptures,” so long as all of them are true’, he writes. However, in discussing certain religious movements and persons, particularly fundamentalists, he takes a somewhat different line. Here indeed are movements that enthusiastically proclaim their love of God and make a rather strong claim to the truth. Where do they go wrong, as for Caputo they decidedly do? His answer is that fundamentalism typically deteriorates into idolatry of a creed, a ‘passion for God gone mad’ which inclines the faithful toward hatred and violence for those who are not of like mind.42 A group that speaks of itself as the chosen people or in any way special in the eyes of God is likely to become
204
Education in the Human Sciences
sectarian and oppressive, he argues. The fundamentalist or dogmatist of whatever kind insists that since there is only one true religion, all others are mistaken in their beliefs and quite possibly damned. Religiosity deteriorates into intolerance only when its truths are alleged to be exclusive. It is the nature of religion to exist in a state of tension, but in the sense of being at odds with itself, not in competition with rival creeds. Caputo is equally critical of newer forms of spirituality of the kind that fill the shelves of popular bookstores. If fundamentalism makes the mistake of reducing the love of God to a single body of beliefs and practices which is idolized and sectarian, religious nonsense in its flashier forms is simple ‘poppycock’. Exactly what makes New Age spirituality, enthusiasm about angels, channelings, and so on daft while religion in its older forms is not, is unclear on Caputo’s account. Religion, he maintains, has to do with the ‘transformability of our lives’ and is not to be trivialized, yet believers in these newer forms of religious nonsense would be likely to agree with him.43 Even the fanatic – especially the fanatic – has been transformed and loves his or her God with all the abandon that Caputo would want. It is here that Dewey provides a bit of a corrective: religious passion that is untied to the post of reason is a dangerous proposition if not the definition of stupidity. The same can be said of religious truth without knowledge, or experience without intelligent inquiry. Caputo and other postmodern religionists wish to reject the Enlightenment’s (not only Kant’s) ‘religion within the limits of reason alone’ and to inject religion with some passionate free-spiritedness, yet in ways that can border on frivolity. Dewey, a singularly unfrivolous thinker, also wished to emphasize the passionate and openended quality of religious experience, but in a decidedly measured way. The religious, both figures agree, is an experiential and passionate business, not a matter of intellectual propositions or theological doctrines. It is about the love of ideals above all. But even love, Dewey warned, even passion must take intelligent form. Otherwise we have no answer to the ‘poppycock’ that Caputo rightly rejects. Let us now return to the question of religious education. Should religion be conceived not as a doctrinal matter – as essentially an issue of participation in a particular tradition of belief and ritual – but a question of experience – a sense of life involving passionate ideals and longing for the impossible, as either Dewey or Caputo speak of it – then is this a fitting matter for educational institutions to take upon themselves? Is there a spiritual training that involves the same kind of broadening of horizons or experiential growth that we examined in Chapter 2, one that does not degenerate into an uncritical inculcation of beliefs? The possibility is intriguing, not least because the passionate mode of experience that both philosophers describe might inject some much-needed vitality into an education
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
205
that is often lifeless. That their schooling is dull is the most frequently heard complaint among students, and nowhere is it duller or more oppressive than when the subject matter is religion. A lamentable business is religious education. Yet might it rise above all this and inspire students with a more passionate sense of life, one hopefully that remains tied to the post of reason or that at least can find its way back after the occasional day trip? If there is one thing needful in education it is the ‘passionate intelligence’ that Dewey spoke of – not intelligence alone or passion alone but the two in permanent combination. For intelligence without passion, and indeed a passion for the impossible and the unknowable, is lifeless, and passion without intelligence is besotted. Successful educators know the importance of infusing some passion into their teaching and expressing not only their knowledge but their love of ideas and ideals. Educators may well exemplify a sense of life over and above teaching in its more usual sense. If one is teaching art or politics, for instance, it is perfectly appropriate to try to instill a love of art or a sense of justice that transcends the information the curriculum contains. In the case of religion, however, there are grounds for skepticism even in the case of Dewey’s and Caputo’s unconventional conceptions of this. First, religious education is customarily provided in institutions that are beholden to a specific tradition of belief. The mission of these institutions is to perpetuate that tradition, in addition of course to providing an education of a less sectarian kind. Instilling a passion for the impossible without any doctrinal commitments does not fit such a mission. Educating students’ religious experience is well and good, they will say, so long as this means instilling commitment to a creed and remaining scrupulously on the straight and narrow path. Divesting religion of religion, as Caputo wants, is easier said than done, and in an educational setting it is likely impossible. In the case of actually existing religious institutions, as Dewey noted, they have all ‘retained a certain indispensable minimum of intellectual content’, and it is futile to wish it otherwise. All religions . . . involve specific intellectual beliefs, and they attach – some greater, some less – importance to assent to these doctrines as true, true in the intellectual sense. They have literatures held especially sacred, containing historical material with which the validity of the religions is connected. They have developed a doctrinal apparatus it is incumbent upon ‘believers’ (with varying degrees of strictness in different religions) to accept. They also insist that there is some special and isolated channel of access to the truths they hold.44 This is the sense of religion with which Caputo parts company, and as a matter of private religious sensibility this may be commendable, but as an educational matter it is singularly unlikely. Individual educators in sectarian
206
Education in the Human Sciences
(‘faith based’) institutions may be able to get away with this on occasion, if their employers are unusually broad minded, but it is improbable that this could be undertaken on a large scale. Second, we have been speaking of religious experience in its higher reaches. It is an adult’s experience of God – an unusual God and an unusual adult – that Dewey and Caputo are describing. Dewey was correct to warn against trying to impose adult experiences on the young; it is their experience, not ours, that is the starting point of education. While educators properly seek to lead the young toward a more mature quality of experience, they must not have an entirely preconceived notion of where the students should end up, be it in Dewey’s sense of harmony with the universe, Caputo’s sense of being unhinged, or what have you. Mature religious experience, if there is any such thing and if either of these thinkers has succeeded in describing it, cannot be plastered on from the outside but, if it is to take shape at all, must arise from within in the manner of any growing thing. How this is to be accomplished in educational institutions is difficult to see. Instilling a passion for the impossible may be accomplished by educating the imagination, but this is more likely to bear fruit when the subject matter is not religion but literature and the arts, history, politics, or what have you. Third, Dewey would emphasize the limits of educators’ ability to shape the character of their students by conscious design, especially as this concerns ethics. Character is a result of out-of-school experience far more than inschool. The same point is relevant in the present context. If we wish our students to be worth their salt in Caputo’s sense, to love their God or whatever it is they love with passionate devotion and to enact a religious sensibility in their lives, it is not an educator’s efforts alone that will bring this about but their larger experience of life over the course of years or decades. Have educators ever succeeded in producing a mature religious sensibility in their students through conscious planning? What technique would bring about this particular ‘learning outcome’? I believe it is inevitable that when educators maintain this as a goal, indoctrination into a creed or another form of miseducation is the result. Those who practice religious indoctrination, of course, never believe that they are indoctrinators; they are providers of character education, spiritual training, or some other misnomer. They are saving souls and preserving a sacred tradition. The reality is that they are conscripting the young into a worldview before they reach an age at which they might evaluate it rationally, a worldview that will usually remain with them for life without ever being properly examined. By the time they reach an age of intellectual maturity their beliefs are set, their habits of mind, values, and passions highly resistant to intelligent modification. Finally, regarding both Dewey’s and Caputo’s uses of the words ‘God’, ‘religion’, and the ‘religious’, I would say the following: when we take up a
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination?
207
word, we are taking up a tradition of usage, and we are not perfectly free in how we may do this. ‘God’, to take an obvious example, is a word with a very long and very troubled history. Redefining or reinterpreting words may be a philosopher’s prerogative, at least on some occasions, however their histories are not so easily left behind. Dewey and Caputo both wish to speak of God no longer in the language of theology or substance ontology, as the biblical deity or a supreme being of some kind, but as a name for whatever ideals that we hold, for that which we love with passionate intensity and which rules our lives. These uses of the word leave tradition almost completely behind, and while I am not one to insist upon preserving traditional usage simply for tradition’s sake – language is after all a living thing, and old usages are not necessarily to be preferred over new ones – these usages appear to border on the cavalier. Caputo in particular, although he is given to frequent appropriations of Augustine and Aquinas, may be a little too freewheeling here. Phenomenological redescriptions of religious experience are always welcome, but reinterpretations of words can be expected to show at least some historical continuity. As a postmodernist he wants to leave behind the tradition of onto-theology, as Dewey also wished to do; again this is unobjectionable, but disentangling God from that tradition seems to me an impossible task. As improbable a coupling as Dewey and the postmoderns may appear, on the question of religious experience and religious education the two may be put on speaking terms. Doing so changes the question of religious education in interesting ways. It may not, however, change the answer. These two figures have suggested non-metaphysical and undogmatic conceptions of the religious; as interpretations of private religiosity they may even succeed, however importing them into the practice of the classroom, for the reasons I have suggested, will not.
Notes 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7.
Dewey, ‘Between Two Worlds’ (1944). LW 17: 463. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 8. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 115–16, 111. Ibid., 54. Dewey, Moral Principles in Education (1908). MW 4: 270. Dewey, ‘Context and Thought’ (1931). LW 6: 12. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 329. Dewey would return to this theme quite often in his writings and in a wide variety of contexts. In Art as Experience, for instance, he wrote: ‘Any psychology that isolates the human being from the environment also shuts him off, save for external contacts, from his fellows. But an individual’s desires take shape under the influence of the human environment. The materials of his thought and belief come to him from others with whom he lives. He would be poorer than a beast of the fields were it not for traditions that become a part
208
8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32.
33. 34. 35.
Education in the Human Sciences of his mind and for institutions that penetrate below his outward actions into his purposes and satisfactions. Expression of experience is public and communicating because the experiences expressed are what they are because of experiences of the living and the dead that have shaped them.’ Dewey, Art as Experience (1934). LW 10: 274–5. A similar thought is expressed in an essay from 1931: ‘We cannot explain why we believe the things which we most firmly hold to because those things are a part of ourselves. We can no more completely escape them when we try to examine into them than we can get outside our physical skins so as to view them from without. Call these regulative traditions apperceptive organs or mental habits or whatever you will, there is no thinking without them. I do not mean, that a philosopher can take account of this context in the sense of making it a complete object of reflection. But he might realize the existence of such a context, and in doing so he would learn humility and would be debarred from a too limited and dogmatic universalization of his conclusions. He would not freeze the quotidian truths relevant to the problems that emerge in his own background of culture into eternal truths inherent in the very nature of things.’ Dewey, ‘Context and Thought’ (1931). LW 6: 13. Dewey, The Educational Situation (1901). MW 1: 301–2. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 348. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 19. Dewey, ‘Character Training for Youth’ (1934). LW 9: 187–8, 186, 188. Charles W. Wood, ‘Report of Interview with Dewey’ (1922). MW 13: 428. Dewey, ‘Context and Thought’ (1931). LW 6: 15. Charles W. Wood, ‘Report of Interview with Dewey’ (1922). MW 13: 428. Dewey, ‘Religious Education as Conditioned by Modern Psychology and Pedagogy’ (1903). MW 3: 212. Dewey, ‘Religion and Our Schools’ (1908). MW 4: 175. Dewey, ‘The Interpretation Side of Child-Study’ (1897). EW 5: 214, 215, 220. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 26. Dewey, ‘Psychology in High-Schools from the Standpoint of the College’ (1886). EW 1: 85. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 185–6. Ibid., 124. Dewey, ‘Importance, Significance, and Meaning’ (1950). LW 16: 325. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 56, 366. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 39. How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 347. Dewey, ‘Academic Freedom’ (1902). MW 2: 53. Ibid., 54. Dewey, ‘Religious Education as Conditioned by Modern Psychology and Pedagogy’ (1903). MW 3: 215. Dewey, ‘Academic Freedom’ (1902). MW 2: 55. Dewey, ‘Character Training for Youth’ (1934). LW 9: 189. Dewey, ‘Self-Realization as the Moral Ideal’ (1893). EW 4: 49–50. Dewey, ‘Implications of S. 2499’ (1947). LW 15: 285. Dewey, ‘Religion and our Schools’ (1908). MW 4: 175. See John Caputo, The Prayers and Tears of Jacques Derrida: Religion Without Religion (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997); The Weakness of God: A Theology of the Event (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2006); What Would Jesus Deconstruct? The Good News of Postmodernism for the Church (Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2007). Dewey, A Common Faith (1933). LW 9: 23, 52. Ibid., 19. Ibid., 23, 52.
Teaching Religion: Spiritual Training or Indoctrination? 36. 37. 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44.
209
Ibid., 19. Caputo, On Religion (New York: Routledge, 2001), 33. Ibid., 67, 13, 19. Caputo, Radical Hermeneutics: Repetition, Deconstruction, and the Hermeneutic Project (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1987), 281, 269. Caputo, On Religion, 1, 25, 126. Ibid., 9. Ibid., 111, 110, 107. Ibid., 136. Dewey, A Common Faith (1933). LW 9: 22, 21.
Chapter 6
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism Like religious education, some form of ethical training has long been thought, more or less universally, to be an essential part of the educative process. Whether it is the direct instilling of values of a particular kind in students in the primary and secondary grades or the presentation of ethics as a properly academic subject matter at the university, teaching ethics in one form or another is traditionally regarded as fundamental and indeed indispensable. As Dewey noted in an essay from 1893, ‘there has never been such a widespread interest in teaching ethics in the schools as at present’, while in our own time the interest in ethics in education as in so many other areas of public and private life is widespread indeed. It is now common practice, for instance, for university students intent on pursuing a career in the professions to receive mandatory instruction in biomedical ethics, business ethics, engineering ethics, or whatever field of professional life one wishes to pursue. At the primary and secondary levels as well, the idea has long been that students should be taught to accept certain values or social norms which educational authorities or the larger community deem important. At the same time, however, and as Dewey also remarked, there is the ‘pretty widespread conviction that conscious moralizing in the schoolroom has had its day – if it ever had any’.1 In public schools in particular, we have come to expect teachers to refrain from instilling at least controversial values and those that extend beyond the requirements of discipline, civility, and ordinary decency. If religious schools continue the traditional practice of providing a ‘moral education’ in the sense of instilling a comprehensive and theologically based conception of right and wrong, most often we take a dim view of such ‘conscious moralizing’ in public institutions at the very least and to regard it as a throwback to the past. The kind of arguments that Dewey presented against traditional forms of moral education have carried much influence, of course, yet the questions that his critique would generate for Dewey himself over a century ago remain very much with us: what are the aims of teaching ethics at the different stages of the learning process? Is it to instill a particular configuration of values – and if so, which values, in what spirit, and by what means – or to teach students how to think about ethics on their own terms? What, for instance, is 210
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
211
the aim of teaching ethics in the university, whether in the form of a course in ethical theory or in one of the increasingly numerous branches of professional or applied ethics? Should we teach ethics at all in the primary and secondary school, or do the arguments presented in Chapter 5 against teaching controversial religious doctrines to the intellectually immature apply as well to the teaching of equally debatable moral doctrines? Let us begin with an overview of Dewey’s critical assessment of traditional views regarding the kind of moral education that may be undertaken in the schools. The conventional model is one of direct instruction in ethical conduct and the precepts that underlie it, precepts that are most often rooted either in a religious worldview or in the prevailing ethical norms of a community. The goal of such instruction is to see to it that students hold to a particular set of values and become habituated to applying them to their actions – that they become respectful and caring of others, generous and altruistic, or what have you. Dewey’s critique begins, as would his assessment of traditional education in general, with the disconnection between students’ lived experience and the moral lessons that are presented to them as a ready-made body of doctrine for them to absorb and retain. When moral instruction takes the form of old-fashioned lecturing on the virtues combined with practical measures to instill these in the conduct and character of the young, such education can amount to little more than ‘sheer obedience to the will of an adult’, not least when obedience itself is seen as a virtue of childhood.2 Students come to conceive of the ethical as ‘certain special acts which are labelled virtues and set off from the mass of other acts’, or as a set of rules that they must follow for no other reason than that an authority demands it. Ethics loses contact with the realities of everyday life and becomes a kind of transcendent deliverance raining down from on high. On the traditional model, ‘[t]he ethical has been conceived in too goody-goody a way’, as a matter of naive compliance with a set of authoritative pronouncements without any connection to the ordinary motivations of the young. Moral education so conceived has little permanent effect on students’ character, Dewey believed, and remains at a surface level: ‘it does not reach down into the depths of the character-making agency’.3 When it does leave a lasting impression, it is as likely to be mis-educative as the reverse, as for instance when students acquire an aversion to any mention of ‘morality’ due to its association in their minds with moralistic preaching or simple authoritarianism. An equally mis-educative effect is the common impression of ethics as a body of dogma that is inscrutable to reason or that is not placed in the service of human life and happiness. Traditional moral instruction furthermore ‘is pretty sure to be formal and perfunctory, and to result rather in hardening the mind of the child with a lot of half-understood precepts than in helpful development’. A strictly
212
Education in the Human Sciences
rule-governed conception of ethics instilled from an early age creates in many a morbid self-consciousness, ever scrutinizing its interiors for signs of ungodliness, while in others it creates ‘offensive prigs, possibly hypocrites’.4 The basic idea that moral character is formed by having a system of rules continually drummed into one’s being is a distortion of ethics and of moral education alike, while it also exhibits a basic misunderstanding of human psychology and character formation. However ethical dispositions are formed, Dewey argued, it is not through an external imposition of rules or duties upon an acquiescent mind. With the possible exception of Dewey’s views on religious instruction, he would always argue against measures that have the effect of reducing education to a purpose that lies beyond the learning process. Where conventional views most fundamentally err is in substituting extraneous ends for aims that are immanent to education itself. This includes traditional notions of ethical instruction where again the goal of imposing upon the young an external and altogether debatable conception of the good, which may or may not be religiously tinged, supplants the kind of education that Dewey supported. The old methods habituate students to looking beyond experience and this world for their highest values and to a disparagement of human experience rather than training students to deal with ethical problems in a more pragmatic and reflective spirit. ‘A narrow and moralistic view of morals’ causes educators to overlook the more genuine moral education that the learning process itself brings about, as we shall see.5 It fosters dogmatic habits of mind in regard to fashioning moral judgments and makes it difficult for students at a later stage of intellectual development to think intelligently about ethics, their basic orientation in moral matters having long since been carved in stone. The kind of authoritarianism that is associated with traditional moral education, Dewey maintained, is not an accidental by-product of such an approach but an inevitable consequence. When the source of ethics lies beyond the students’ experience and activities in the classroom and is presented in the form of an externally imposed set of requirements, students lack any motivation to heed such requirements and so must be compelled to do so by the personal commands of the teacher and by a system of rewards and punishments. The problem of creating order necessarily becomes one of command and obedience when it does not arise, as Dewey would have it, out of common activities in which students take a genuine interest. In the traditional school, then, the motives for what passes for ethical conduct are chiefly the desire to please authority and the fear of punishment for disobedience, a motivation that often takes religious form. Thus while all may agree, as Dewey put it, that ‘the question of the moral attitude and tendencies induced in youth by the motives for conduct habitually brought to bear
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
213
is the ultimate question in all education whatever’, it remains that ‘moral education is the most haphazard of all things’; efforts to induce particular moral attitudes and dispositions through direct instruction are more likely to fail than to succeed for the reason that when such attitudes take lasting form they arise under conditions that are less direct and top-down than indirect and bottom-up.6 If we wish students to acquire certain ethical dispositions, Dewey argued, it is imperative that we reject traditional moralism and look to the educational environment as an indirect but ultimately more effective means of fostering such attitudes. Dewey would always maintain that it is the school environment that is ultimately decisive in creating educative and miseducative experience alike, and that if it is ethics that we wish to teach, then again it is not primarily direct instruction on the virtues that will bring this about but a larger set of environmental conditions that draw students out in particular directions and elicit responses of the desired kind. Using an organic metaphor, Dewey spoke of the essential business of the educator as ‘supply[ing] the proper nutriment’ or the ‘intellectual and spiritual food’ that naturally gives rise to a certain kind of character formation.7 Such nutriment takes the form of an educational environment in which ‘a spirit of social cooperation and community life’ prevails.8 The school itself ought to have no moral purpose aside from participation in common activities and the values that are necessary to that end. It is not the mission of educational institutions to instill a particular conception of the good life or attitudes widely approved of in the general community, any more than it is to inculcate a controversial political ideology. While Dewey would often speak of education as preparing students for participation in democratic life, he did not mean by this that teachers are to indoctrinate the young in a debatable political philosophy but that the kind of shared activities in which students engage will under appropriate conditions promote the same habits and virtues that will later be brought to bear in democratic activity. The school, for Dewey, is to be thought of as a small-scale community in the sense that the relationships and activities that students take up in the school are precursors of later forms of social and political involvement. The ethics that is appropriately taught and learned in this setting is an ethics that is implicit in the educational environment: not a set of transcendent rules and duties but an ethos of civility and co-operation in joint undertakings. Students are preparing themselves for social life only in the sense that they are engaged in it from the start; they are forming habits of co-operation and respect by virtue of involvement in shared projects and social situations that elicit a moral response. When the school is conceived as a community, ethical principles such as respect and non-conformity arise not as authoritative commands but out of the conditions of community life itself. The need
214
Education in the Human Sciences
to articulate the value of non-conformity or individuality, for instance, arises only in social situations in which this value becomes necessary and is experienced as a felt need. It is only in such a social setting, moreover, that one has an opportunity to cultivate this value. By the same token, the principle of respect for differences arises only in forms of social life in which differences of belief or identity exist and are brought into mutual engagement. Accordingly, if there is a conception of moral education that is immanent to the educative process itself, it is one that regards the school environment not as a mere training ground for later social life or for the ethical relations of adulthood but as a small-scale community unto itself, one wherein shared activities and relationships give rise to particular ethical imperatives. Moral education arises out of the ethos of the social life of the school and is a matter of habit and character formation within this environment. As Dewey expressed it, The only way to prepare for social life is to engage in social life. To form habits of social usefulness and serviceableness apart from any direct social need and motive, apart from any existing social situation, is, to the letter, teaching the child to swim by going through motions outside of the water.9 The activity of inquiry, as Dewey often remarked, is a properly social enterprise and as such gives rise to a particular set of ethical requirements. To engage in inquiry is to participate in a joint undertaking which, if it is to be successful, requires co-operation, civility, discipline, and respect from each of the participants. It is accordingly a moral, not merely intellectual, activity – that is, on the condition that knowledge is gained through active investigation rather than passive reception of information. Under this condition, the moral glue that holds the community together is nothing imposed by authority but is rather the work of co-operative inquiry itself and the conditions that make it possible. To the extent, then, that the formation of moral character is a possible and appropriate educational aim – and, again, Dewey emphasized the limits of the educator’s ability to shape such character – it is an aim that is not pursued apart from properly intellectual goals. Indeed, for Dewey the ethical and the intellectual are ultimately inseparable in the sense that habits formed in one sphere naturally spill over into the other. If we would educate the moral character of students, insofar as this is possible at all, how would we go about it and what would be the indicators of success? On the first question, as we have seen, we must look to the classroom environment to do a good deal of the work, with the educator serving less in the role of moral lecturer than leader of group activities and inquiry, keeper of discipline, and so on. Accordingly, if, as Dewey put it, ‘upon its intellectual side education
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
215
consists in the formation of wide-awake, careful, thorough habits of thinking’, and if such habits of thinking draw us by necessity into forms of social participation, then upon its ethical side education includes the fashioning of social attitudes and habits no less, or an ethical orientation that is modelled on co-operative investigation and dialogue.10 The intellectual virtue of good judgment, for instance, in the sense of the ability to discriminate between relative degrees of importance and value, and thus to form a perspective that is one’s own, is not acquired apart from the practice of testing judgments against others’ views and being drawn into forms of social life that are co-operative and experimental. Good judgment is simultaneously an intellectual virtue as well as ‘an integral factor of good character’.11 Indeed, one further criticism that Dewey would direct against many of the educational institutions of his time is that they fail to develop this capacity in the young by limiting the opportunities to fashion and test judgments of their own and instead overprescribe predigested subject matter. Should we desire students to develop the capacity for good and independent judgment – intellectual and moral – then one learns to judge by judging, and not merely, as traditional views have it, by having students passively adopt the judgments of others. A couple of other examples of which Dewey spoke in this connection are good manners, or what he would refer to as ‘minor morals’, and good taste. Both are imparted far less by direct instruction than through the indirect influence of environment and example. In the case of manners, for instance, these are ‘acquired by habitual action, in response to habitual stimuli, not by conveying information’. By the same token, good taste arises only when ‘the eye is constantly greeted by harmonious objects, having elegance of form and color. . . . The effect of a tawdry, unarranged, and over-decorated environment works for the deterioration of taste, just as meagre and barren surroundings starve out the desire for beauty.’12 Both manners and taste, then, are habits formed in a social environment and are dependent on the examples that it provides. In arguing that moral character is fashioned through habit formation and in combination with the intellectual virtues, Dewey was of course drawing upon an Aristotelian principle while adapting it to a pragmatic or experimentalist point of view. This can be seen as well in his analysis of discipline and freedom in the classroom, a matter that is simultaneously intellectual and ethical. How, Dewey asked, is discipline properly achieved in the school and how much freedom should educators allow, and where freedom encompasses both behavioral liberty and the freedom of students to form plans and choose their own activities? As we have seen, he was severely critical of conventional approaches that prize discipline so highly as to sacrifice any meaningful freedom for students whatever and to reduce them to a condition of intellectual and moral docility. The questions this then raises include
216
Education in the Human Sciences
how much and what kind of freedom should educators permit and by what means is order or discipline to be attained if not in the traditional, schoolmasterish way? The progressive schools that Dewey inspired were often faulted for their apparent lack of order, with students free to walk about the classroom rather than silently working at their desks. To visitors the ostensibly Deweyan classroom often appeared to be a chaotic scene of children engaged in boisterous activity and conversation while the teacher would look on with shocking approval. Discipline and order, it seemed, had been sacrificed to libertarianism. Yet how, Dewey asked, is genuine discipline maintained and in what does it consist? His answer was that ethical or social discipline must be comprehended together with intellectual discipline, and that the order that properly prevails is not one imposed by an authority but ‘is the kind of order that exists in a roomful of people, each one of whom is working at a common task. There will be talking, consulting, moving about in such a group whether the workers are adults or children.’13 The ‘controlling motive in discipline’, then, is ‘the social spirit’ that prevails when students are engaged in a joint undertaking.14 The work of inquiry itself requires as an enabling condition the maintenance of a certain level of social order as well as the freedom to participate, to suggest activities and ideas, to refine hypotheses, and so on. Such work equally requires intellectual discipline in order that inquiry will arrive at a satisfactory conclusion rather than deteriorate into pointlessness. As an educator of many years himself, of course, as well as a parent of eight children, Dewey was not naive in regard to the maintenance of discipline among the young. As naive or idealistic as it sounds, he would always insist that both intellectual and social discipline are effectively brought about not by the traditional means but through free participation in joint undertakings. As he wrote, ‘No experienced and successful teacher has any doubt that right instruction is the primary means of maintaining discipline. Students who are interested in their work and in doing their work well are not students who are a menace to the well-being of the school.’ If a certain degree of disorder and carelessness is an inevitable feature of youth, it is effectively checked less through a ‘system [of] more or less constant espionage’ by the teacher than by means of students voluntarily undertaking forms of inquiry in which they take a genuine interest.15 The work itself makes demands upon students in the same way and for the same reasons that advanced research exacts demands upon investigators in every field which prevent them from making statements that they cannot justify. These demands, when they arise in the environment of the classroom, are as much social and ethical as intellectual or rational. The principle of freedom arises in the same way, whether it applies to children in the elementary school or to the academic freedom associated
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
217
more particularly with the university. In both instances, intellectual work requires the freedom to devise plans and to pursue ideas wherever they lead, while the notion of academic freedom itself is equally a rational and an ethical imperative. The freedom that rightly prevails in either setting, Dewey held, is no merely Hobbesian absence of constraint upon activity or speech but consists in the imperative of offering one’s own contribution to work undertaken in common; ‘it means’, as he wrote, ‘intellectual initiative, independence in observation, judicious invention, foresight of consequences, and ingenuity of adaptation to them’.16 Such freedom is not incompatible with either discipline or planning, and indeed requires both if it is to lead in a direction that is genuinely educative. In his usual dialectical way, Dewey regarded freedom and order as equally vital and mutually entailed principles of education. Free inquiry – if it is indeed to be inquiry rather than unintelligent chatter – requires not only the liberty to form purposes and to speak one’s mind but the discipline to pursue a given line of questioning, to endure frustration and difficulty, and to work on a co-operative basis. If the planning is provided by the educator, then such ‘planning must be flexible enough to permit free play for individuality of experience and yet form enough to give direction towards continuous development of power’.17 The ‘spirit of social cooperation and community life’ that prevails in such an environment includes as well ‘a certain disorder’ that closely resembles that of ‘any busy workshop’; if the classroom is to be a place of work then it must realize the conditions, both intellectual and ethical, that such work requires.18 Dewey would also speak of moral education in a more direct connotation, however. While never losing sight of its connection with intellectual work and of his critique of traditional moralism, he did discuss the possibility of teaching ethics as a subject matter in the university as well as in the higher secondary grades. In a couple of essays from the early 1890s, for instance, he would defend a conception of ethics that may be taught directly to students who have attained a degree of intellectual maturity, a view that he would develop further in later years. This is the examination of ethics not as a system of hard and fast rules, nor even, interestingly, the study of ethical theory and its history, but instead ‘the study of ethical relationships, the study, that is, of this complex world of which we are members’. Ethics, as an academic subject matter, investigates the essential relatedness of human beings to each other and to the larger community. The ethical instruction that is not preaching is conducted in a concrete, matter-of-fact way and aims, through the study of human relations, at the cultivation of students’ moral imagination. The spirit of such instruction is profoundly important, Dewey held, and must never deteriorate into doctrinaire moralizing. Instead it ought to remain primarily a practical matter of deciding how to go about
218
Education in the Human Sciences
remedying social ills if it is agreed upon that a remedy is required. As he wrote, Let the teacher, at the outset, ask the pupils how they would decide, if a case of seeming misery were presented to them, whether to relieve it and, if so, how to relieve. This should be done without any preliminary dwelling upon the question as a ‘moral’ one; rather, it should be pointed out that the question is simply a practical one, and that ready-made moral considerations are to be put one side. Above all, however, it should be made clear that the question is not what to do, but how to decide what to do.19 This last idea refers to his notion of social or moral imagination that is at the center of Dewey’s conceptions both of ethics and of moral education. The ultimate aim of such education is the cultivation of an imagination that is at once sympathetic and ‘intelligent’ in the pragmatic sense of being skilled in problem-solving. It is ‘the power of observing and comprehending social relations – and social power’ that an education in ethics seeks to instill, not a particular set of beliefs or values.20 Terms such as ‘social intelligence’ and ‘moral imagination’ would always remain slightly ambiguous in Dewey’s writings, but in general terms what these expressions connote is an ethical counterpart to his pragmatic experimentalism. If it is the art of thinking that is the ultimate goal of education in general, then moral education as well aims to develop students’ capacity to think about human relations with an orientation toward remedying injustice in ways that avoid traditional moralism. Dewey remarked in an essay of 1894 upon the tendency of university students merely to say what appears edifying or what they believe is expected of them when moral questions arise, an observation that is likely no less accurate today. The professor must endeavor to get beyond this and to inquire in an intellectually honest fashion into how students and others actually engage ethical questions under real-world conditions. He or she must resist the purely formal and theoretical and make the focus of study ‘the actual behavior, motives, and conduct’ of human beings.21 This orientation away from the theoretical and toward concrete social relations makes the study of ethics as an academic subject matter more scientific, Dewey maintained, and less doctrinaire. It gets students away from thinking of ethics as a set of transcendent laws or a system of principles at some remove from actual human practices and motivations and substitutes a more case-specific approach that once again stresses ‘how to decide what to do’. Without renouncing principles altogether, this approach concentrates on their applications rather than their theoretical grounds divorced from practice. It construes principles, moreover, not as hard and fast rules or formal decision procedures, in the manner of the categorical imperative or
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
219
the utilitarian calculus, but as instruments for the analysis of problematic situations. Ethical principles are hypotheses that, like all hypotheses, succeed or fail based on that to which they lead in the process of inquiry, whether they remedy a given social ill or moral difficulty or fail to do so, and not on purely theoretical grounds. When principles are not brought down to earth, morality takes on the appearance of ‘a special region or portion of life’, a system of absolutes that fall from the sky, and particularly when coupled with traditional methods of moral instruction.22 It is imperative, Dewey maintained, that in teaching ethics, students come to regard this area of study as indeed an area of inquiry, of experimental analysis of particular human relations and practices, the aim of which is not to uphold a creed but to improve such relations. Accordingly, as he wrote in Reconstruction in Philosophy, moral ‘[r]ules are softened into principles, and principles are modified into methods of understanding’. Principles are ‘intellectual instruments for analyzing individual or unique situations’.23 Their application requires careful perception of the contingencies of a given case as well as flexibility in application. The need for flexibility is based on the nature of experimentation itself, where an initial hypothesis or judgment is proposed, followed through successive stages of application, refined and tested by the consequences for good or ill that it generates, and ultimately accepted or rejected in light of its success in resolving the original problem. This is ethics in the scientific spirit, Dewey argued, and it may be imported into the university classroom so long as it is taught and learned in this spirit. Its principles remain subject to revision or refinement according to the issues they confront and their success as tools of understanding and resolving such issues, and without a general, theoretical conception of that in which a proper resolution consists. Dewey proposed no equivalent of the utilitarian’s greatest happiness principle, for instance, nor did he reduce ethics in Kantian fashion to the cultivation of a good will and dutiful adherence to the categorical imperative. All ethical principles are closer to what Kant termed hypothetical imperatives in the sense that they are mindful of the practical consequences to which they lead, allow for exceptions, and are not hard and fast rules to be heeded for duty’s sake alone. In fact, Kantian ethics represents the veritable antithesis of the experimentalist view Dewey defended, a conception of ethics that makes no appeal to the a priori or the transcendent, and that requires imaginative understanding and flexibility rather than formalism and rule following. The only ‘virtues’ this ethics includes are as much intellectual as moral: ‘[w]ide sympathy, keen sensitiveness, persistence in the face of the disagreeable, balance of interests enabling us to undertake the work of analysis and decision intelligently’. These are essentially virtues of experimental inquiry rather than the kind of ethical virtues that one would find in an Aristotelian catalog. While such
220
Education in the Human Sciences
inquiry, as an imaginative and pragmatic enterprise, conforms to no formal technique, Dewey did provide a very general description of the course that it follows in understanding specific moral contexts: A moral situation is one in which judgment and choice are required antecedently to overt action. The practical meaning of the situation – that is to say the action needed to satisfy it – is not self-evident. It has to be searched for. There are conflicting desires and alternative apparent goods. What is needed is to find the right course of action, the right good. Hence, inquiry is exacted: observation of the detailed makeup of the situation, analysis into its diverse factors; clarification of what is obscure; discounting of the more insistent and vivid traits; tracing the consequences of the various modes of action that suggest themselves; regarding the decision reached as hypothetical and tentative until the anticipated or supposed consequences which led to its adoption have been squared with actual consequences. This inquiry is intelligence.24 So long as ethics is conceived in this general spirit rather than along more conventional lines, it may well be taken up as an academic subject matter in the university and high school without the danger of it deteriorating into yet another orthodoxy to which students are expected to conform. They are expected, on the contrary, to think for themselves about the social ills of their time and the possible remedies that suggest themselves to the imagination, given a careful analysis of specific moral contexts. The habits and capacities such education fosters include in particular the moral or social imagination in the sense of the ability to apply experimental reasoning to social questions in the same matter-of-fact way that one would approach an issue in the natural sciences. Students are to be presented with specific instances of moral conflict and encouraged to examine the detailed features and circumstances of a case. From here they are to construct a hypothesis regarding its possible resolution, rehearse in imagination what probable consequences the hypothesis will bring about, compare this against alternative hypotheses, and form a judgment about the proper course of action. As befits experimental and imaginative thought in general, it does not search for demonstrative proof for its judgments and remains open to revising these in light of the overall good that such judgments produce or fail to produce in their applications. In a decidedly non-Kantian way, the final judgment one fashions in a case is entirely dependent on its application and whether the consequences envisioned in imagination eventually materialize and resolve the original conflict or generate unanticipated and perhaps exacerbating consequences. The educator’s task in teaching ethics is therefore no different from
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
221
teaching almost any subject matter: ‘the proper method of teaching is to present the facts and to let them be worked up according to the capacity of the minds that work upon them. But in politics, ethics and so-called social sciences, we have not yet learned this lesson.’ Remarking on the common practice of sacrificing intelligent inquiry for moralism, he continued: ‘We still surround these subjects with prohibitions and warnings, and we are still hunting heretics among our school teachers – among the very people whose intellectual freedom is most necessary to all society.’25 Educators and their institutions must practice a good amount of restraint and avoid the temptation to instill particular values or a controversial view of the good life and instead allow students’ capacities of imagination and judgment to develop together with other intellectual habits. If anything at all is to be instilled, it is habits of reflective attention and careful perception of moral conflict. Students must develop an appreciation of the complex texture of human relations and ‘the interrelation of all individuals’ rather than be made to adhere to a fixed set of moral beliefs.26 Ethical principles themselves are neither to be rejected outright nor regarded as ‘in the air’, ‘something set off by themselves’, but instead ‘need to be brought down to the ground through their statement in social and psychological terms’.27 As long as an education in ethics is conceived in this way, it need not be limited to a particular area of study in the high school or university, but crosses disciplinary boundaries into literature, history, psychology, and other areas of inquiry that address the human condition broadly conceived. History is particularly apposite in this connection, being the study not only of what happened in the past but, more important, of the forces that are at work in social relations in general and their consequences for good and for ill. The ultimate aim of teaching and learning history at all educational levels, Dewey argued (and as I shall discuss in Chapter 8), is not to gain an accurate knowledge of what happened in the past for its own sake, as a common view has it. ‘The past’, he wrote, ‘is the past, and the dead may be safely left to bury its dead.’28 The value of studying history as an academic subject matter is ultimately ethical, as it is here especially that students learn about the complexity of human relations and social forces, the motives that underlie conduct and that impel progress and decline, and the consequences of our habitual patterns of behavior. If it is the case, as Dewey believed, that ‘social forces in themselves are always the same – that the same kind of influences were at work 100 and 1,000 years ago that are now’, then understanding the social reality of the present and the forces at work within it benefits significantly from studying the social reality of the past.29 One of the impediments to understanding the present condition of social relations, and so ethical inquiry, is their considerable complexity. The structures, motivations, and ends of human relations and conduct are so mired in
222
Education in the Human Sciences
complexity that the student requires a great deal of distance from the social world of the present in order to gain critical perspective on it, and it is here that a retrospective glance into history can afford a kind of illumination that is very difficult to achieve with respect to the present. Historical events are a kind of moral resource in the sense that the consequences of choices made and actions taken do not have to be anticipated in imagination but are already known, motivations and the driving forces behind social relations may be observed from a distance and so understood, and critical lessons may be learned that apply as well to the present as to the past. Historical inquiry not only imparts information of a sociological nature but in an ethical spirit ‘shows the motives which draw men together and push them apart and depicts what is desirable and what is hurtful’.30 It reveals the consequences of human foibles and generally provides a larger perspective on social life both past and present. It enhances students’ capacities of social analysis and ethical judgment in a manner directly comparable with the study of literature, which has also been long regarded as an important resource in moral education. It is once again in the spirit of experimental inquiry that Dewey conceived of an education in ethics rather than as any kind of dogmatic imposition of belief by an authority. How well this general view stands up over a century after Dewey began writing on the topic is the question to which I now turn.
The art of judgment A couple of decades after Dewey’s time, the theme of ethical-political judgment was taken up in a particularly interesting way by another continental philosopher whose writings demonstrate certain affinities with Dewey without being influenced by him in any identifiable way. Hannah Arendt in many ways practiced the kind of philosophical inquiry and social criticism that Dewey called for, and the connections between their philosophies are significant and under-analyzed. Relevant to our discussion is her simultaneously Kantian and Aristotelian account of the art of judging. It is an account in which she emphasized the political dimension more than the ethical, yet its significance for our theme in this chapter is equally clear. A moral education, as Dewey argued, crucially involves the acquisition of good judgment quite apart from the acceptance of any given set of values. Good judgment, we may well say, is more important than the values we profess, since what ethics is ultimately concerned with is particulars – actions, problems, circumstances – and it is judgments that are particular while values are general and quite meaningless until they are applied in specific actions and judgments. If it is ethics that we would teach, the highest indication of success will consist in the students’ ability to form judgments that are either intelligent
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
223
in Dewey’s sense or otherwise fitting to the case at hand rather than in their professions of faith in this or that system of values. If Dewey was correct that ‘conscious moralizing in the classroom has had its day’, the art of judgment most certainly has not. Indeed, among Arendt’s major concerns in her analysis of twentieth-century Western culture were precisely the importance of this art as well as what she viewed as its decline in the modern world. In a way, Arendt shared Heidegger’s view of the modern age as characterized by a certain thoughtlessness, although she would formulate the idea in different terms. Ours is an age, she maintained, in which ethical-political judgment has become something of a lost art. It has been rendered increasingly difficult by the decline of agreed-upon standards by which value judgments may be grounded or with reference to which the faculty of judgment might gain an orientation. As she wrote in her posthumously published Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, ‘The chief difficulty in judgment is that it is “the faculty of thinking the particular”; but to think means to generalize, hence it is the faculty of mysteriously combining the particular and the general.’ To think in this sense may well be to solve a problem, as Dewey would say, but it is also to judge, where this means not only estimating something’s relative value or importance but bringing a universal to bear on a particular without recourse to rules of any kind. Judgment ‘. . . is relatively easy if the general is given – as a rule, a principle, a law – so that the judgment merely subsumes the particular under it. The difficulty becomes great “if only the particular be given for which the general has to be found”.’31 The latter condition that Kant described is what we are faced with, Arendt maintained, in moral-political judgment. What is immediately before the mind is a particular situation or problem that requires not only a solution but a universal under which it may be properly subsumed. Evaluative judgment thus operates not only on a model of problem-solving but in a dialectic of universal and particular, and a dialectic for which no rules can be found. Dewey certainly had no interest in oversimplifying the moral domain. Indeed he faulted moral philosophers such as Kant and Mill – particularly Kant – for their rigidity and rule fetishism, among other things, and sought to formulate a method of solving moral problems that was far more nuanced than the categorical imperative and the utilitarian calculus. In this he can well be said to have succeeded, yet Arendt’s point is that often methods of all kinds must be left behind and that even the most nuanced of rules will not help us. Good judgment requires that we ‘see the whole’ of a given case or problematic situation, in this sense playing the role of a spectator rather than an actor to whom a particular part is assigned. From this distanced, albeit not completely objective, perspective it becomes possible to adopt an ‘enlarged mentality’ that transcends the partiality of persons directly involved in a
224
Education in the Human Sciences
given case.32 What remains impossible is reaching provable conclusions. Moral thinking is experimental in the sense not only that it proceeds by trial and error and begins with the indeterminate but that it also ends with it. For Arendt the social world is a world of particulars, appearance, action, opinion, and moral-political judgment. It is a realm far more complex than modern normative theories had allowed for, as Dewey also held, yet despite its complexity it is a world that calls upon each of us to opine and to judge the best way we can. To Arendt’s way of thinking, judgment is imperative yet at a time when the act of judging seems to leave us at a loss. How do we proceed when the moral absolutes of the past have been (rightly) rejected and we appear to lack the means of judging in a way that is rationally defensible? By the second half of the twentieth century the very idea of forming value judgments had come to seem not only unscientific but utterly subjective, relativistic, and inscrutable to reason, a simple matter of expressing a preference or an intuition. World events that urgently required the verdict of reason and justice now left us speechless but for those who harked back to the absolutes of the past. It fell to Arendt to attempt to rehabilitate notions of persuasive judgment and opinion that had long ago fallen into disrepute at the hands of philosophers and subsequently the general culture. In doing so she appealed to Aristotle’s concept of practical judgment (phronesis) as outlined in Book Six of the Nicomachean Ethics and also, and especially, to Kant’s Critique of Judgment. Common opinion now has it that no one has the right to make judgments, that doing so is hopelessly dogmatic, intolerant, and out of step with the times. These same times have witnessed some of the most unspeakable events in human history – quite literally unspeakable, since we no longer have the means by which to speak of them in the sense of understanding and judging them. The Holocaust, to take the most obvious example, left social commentators at a loss in the sense not only that no words could measure up to the enormity of this event but that, in Arendt’s words, ‘we have lost our tools of understanding’.33 Twentieth-century totalitarianism in general defies comprehension and judgment and yet demands it urgently. As one scholar writes, The crisis in understanding is identical to a crisis in judgment, for understanding is ‘so closely related to and interrelated with judging that one must describe both as the subsumption’ of something particular under a universal rule. The trouble is that we no longer possess the reliable universal rules required for this subsumption; the inherited wisdom of the past fails us ‘as soon as we try to apply it honestly to the central political experiences of our own time’.34
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
225
Forming opinions and judgments requires an orientation – traditionally a settled moral tradition – that we now lack, yet judge we must. How did we come to this, and how are we to proceed? In addressing the first question, Arendt provided a compelling analysis of the trial and character of Adolph Eichmann, an individual who in her view personified the mentality not only of the Nazi regime but of much of the modern world. Arendt herself attended the trial of Eichmann in 1961, reporting on it for the New Yorker and later publishing the complete account in book form under the title Eichmann in Jerusalem. For Arendt, what made this trial interesting not only from a legal, political, or historical but also from a philosophical point of view were two main factors. The first was the compelling need to understand and judge this man given the role he played in the transportation of millions to the death camps. How is justice to be rendered in such a case, and was it rendered by the Jerusalem court? Second, what is the nature of the grotesque thoughtlessness that the accused man so thoroughly exhibited? Eichmann’s crimes, Arendt stated, were the consequence not of a hateful or psychologically deranged mind but of a mentality that is altogether commonplace. In short it is a mentality that refuses to think and to judge, which lacks intellectual and moral agency of any discernible kind and simply complies with what it is told. Eichmann’s was not a maniacal but a fundamentally docile mind. His self-descriptions of joining the Nazi party, ascending the ranks, following orders, and organizing the delivery of masses of human beings to their deaths were recounted with perfect equanimity, as an accountant might read a ledger. If insanity or simple hatred was not driving this man, what made it possible for him to act in the way that he did and to remain unapologetic years later? The answer for Arendt is moral incompetence in the form of an atrophied faculty of judgment. This was a man with no convictions of his own apart from the duty to follow orders from superiors, who did not know, much less subscribe to, the Nazi program, who was not in favor of the Final Solution, and who at the conclusion of the war, in his words, ‘sensed I would have to live a leaderless and difficult individual life, I would receive no directives from anybody, no orders and commands would any longer be issued to me, no pertinent ordinances would be there to consult – in brief, a life never known lay before me’. The refusal or inability to judge renders us moral non-agents living forever at the mercy of public opinion or political fashion. It was Eichmann’s ‘lack of imagination’, his ‘sheer thoughtlessness’ that led to his crimes. As Arendt observed, ‘such remoteness from reality and such thoughtlessness can wreak more havoc than all the evil instincts taken together’.35 Most disturbing of all in her analysis was precisely Eichmann’s psychological and moral normality. His failings and his character were commonplace; it was the circumstances in which this man was placed that had
226
Education in the Human Sciences
led him to commit his crimes. Arendt was at pains in this text to show that Eichmann was not alone in his failure to think and to resist what the Nazis were doing. German society in general failed utterly to resist this regime, including even many Jewish leaders. What explains this fact but the pervasiveness of a mentality that either refuses or is unable to judge? Arendt’s account of judgment is thus embedded within a larger historical view of twentieth-century Western culture and what she perceived to be the increasing incapacity of persons to think and judge for themselves, a phenomenon of which Eichmann serves as a symbol. This man was and remains a sign of the times, a mind unwilling to resist public opinion or political fashion no matter what it deems. What made this case so compelling for Arendt is precisely the fact that Eichmann was not a stereotypical Nazi but a frighteningly normal individual. His case, together with the public reaction to her book, indicate just ‘[h]ow troubled men of our time are by this question of judgment (or, as is often said, by people who dare “sit in judgment”)’.36 When the very word conjures up associations of self-righteousness and moralistic preaching, its importance is lost sight of and an essential dimension of moral agency is abolished. Nazism and totalitarianism in general needed not only to be understood but judged – harshly – in order that we can make sense of our social reality and not repeat its errors. It is not obvious that this kind of assessment quite fits the Deweyan model. What is the model in this case? When we think back on the Nazi phenomenon we are compelled with some urgency to ask questions and to learn lessons of a great many kinds, but as so many have remarked, the enormity of the task makes this singularly difficult. How can we come to intellectual and moral terms with this? What judgments can we pronounce that do not deteriorate into the trivial or that underestimate dramatically the sheer scale of this event? In pronouncing them, moreover, what problem are we solving and what experiment are we performing? To understand what is involved in the act of judging, Arendt returned to Kant – not, however, to his ethical or political writings but to what she believed to be the unwritten political philosophy implicit to his work on aesthetics, the Critique of Judgment. Arendt shared Dewey’s skepticism regarding Kant’s deontological ethics yet maintained that the third Critique contained a theory of judgment that was without the rigidity of the categorical imperative while being readily transferable from the domain of judgments of taste to moral-political judgments. The centerpiece of this theory is Kant’s distinction between reflective and determinant judgments, which can be briefly summarized as follows. Judgment in general for Kant involves classifying a particular under a universal, whether the universal be a concept, law, principle, or rule. A determinant judgment subsumes the particular under a universal where the latter is given in advance, such as a rule or law that is
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
227
formulated in general terms. A straightforward application of the categorical imperative to a moral case is an example of this. In reflective judgments it is the particular that is given and we are in a position of having to discover or derive through reflection the universal that is appropriate to it. Aesthetic judgments illustrate this phenomenon; we are able to pronounce a particular work of art as beautiful or ugly yet not in a way that is automatic or governed by a rule. No formal method can be appealed to in reflective judgments, although they still involve viewing a particular in light of a general concept. It is judgments of the latter kind that Kant was concerned with in the Critique of Judgment and which Arendt applied to the realm of the moral and political. The art of judgment thus involves a kind of perception of the universal in the particular rather than a straightforward application of rules, the kind of quasi-bureaucratic application that Kant had defended in his writings on ethics. An individual action or case must be classed under a universal since an uncategorized particular simply defies both judgment and understanding. By the twentieth century the universals to which judgment would appeal had lost much of their persuasive force, which on the face of it might spell trouble for the faculty of judgment, yet for Arendt it is under this condition that this faculty achieves its potential. It is precisely when the false absolutes of the past have lost their hold on us that it becomes possible to think and to judge in ways more adequate than in the past. No longer bound by rules that formerly dominated our deliberations, judgment now comes into its own as a capacity of mind that genuinely thinks about a case in its particularity without simply obeying commands or filing things in pigeonholes. This frame of mind may be described as experimental in a sense and also as open-ended in a way that Deweyan experimentation does not quite approximate. In principle, for Dewey a problem has a solution, even if that solution is always subject to ongoing inquiry. Judgment in Arendt’s sense is more indefinite than this, and where the indefiniteness serves not to make us indecisive but to do justice to the case at hand. If the essential concern of ethics is the particular case before us that calls for action then justice must do justice to this rather than simply comply with abstract moral requirements. Doing justice to the particular requires viewing it in light of a universal, but for Arendt it is the particular that has primacy. Kant’s theory of moral judgment of course had asserted the opposite – that the universal is prior to the particular and that the categorical imperative is to be followed for duty’s sake alone – yet it is his theory of aesthetic and reflective judgment that Arendt wished to appropriate. This theory is not fundamentally at odds with Dewey. Both spoke of the primacy of the particular without abandoning principles, of the absence of foundations and formal decision procedures, and also of the social dimension of judgment.
228
Education in the Human Sciences
Again following Kant, Arendt characterized judgment as an inherently social practice. Without explicitly invoking a notion of democracy in the Deweyan manner, Arendt spoke of judgment as oriented toward the persuasion of others in conversation rather than as formally demonstrable. Reflective judgments ‘share with political opinions that they are persuasive; the judging person – as Kant says quite beautifully – can only “woo the consent of everybody else” in the hope of coming to an agreement with him eventually’. It is ‘[f]rom this potential agreement’ with others that ‘judgment derives its specific validity’, in clear contrast to determinant judgments whose validity in the subsumption of particulars under a given universal is governed by a rule.37 The distinction between persuasion and formal proof is rooted in Greek philosophy, as Arendt was well aware. Aristotle’s division of phronesis or practical judgment and sophia or philosophical wisdom similarly distinguished between a knowledge that was grounded in common sense while aiming at informal persuasion and one that compelled universal assent while leaving common sense behind. Moral judgments for Aristotle and Arendt, and of course for Dewey, do not compel agreement in the manner of mathematical reasoning but appeal to the experience and common sense of our interlocutors. Insofar as anything can be said to make such judgments legitimate, this will be found only in the social agreement to which they lead rather than in their conformity with a rule formulated a priori. The social nature of judgment is entailed by the need when thinking about moral questions to imagine oneself in others’ circumstances and not to remain solely occupied with one’s own stake in the matter. One of the indications of Eichmann’s moral incompetence, Arendt noted, was precisely his inability or refusal ever to see his actions from another’s perspective. Good judgments are rational in the sense that they are persuasive to others differently situated without compelling their assent. Their persuasiveness includes the ability to transcend the standpoint of one’s private interests and consider how our judgments appear from various points of view and their consequences for other persons. Moral thinking therefore proceeds on a communal basis, both in the sense that it draws upon common sense and more or less agreed upon social values and in that it aims to persuade others by taking their points of view seriously into account. The principle of impartiality is thus fundamental to good judgment. Just as aesthetic judgments for Kant must justify themselves with reference to a shared culture rather than simply express one’s private subjectivity, moral-political judgments, in Arendt’s view, strive for intersubjective recognition through persuasive reasoning. Part of a judgment’s persuasive force lies in its ability to be communicated to others differently situated and to gain their consent by describing a particular from their point of view no less than one’s own. This is what Kant termed an ‘enlarged mentality’, a leaving behind of purely personal
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
229
advantage and an impartial taking into account of all persons who are affected in a given case. This mentality is a sine qua non of good judgment, Arendt maintained, since the inability or refusal to regard a situation from any other perspective than self-interest is persuasive to no one while also constituting a rejection of common sense. Judgments have a public quality that draws us into discussion without formal methods of adjudication. As she expressed it, . . . this enlarged way of thinking, which as judgment knows how to transcend its own individual limitations . . . cannot function in strict isolation or solitude; it needs the presence of others ‘in whose place’ it must think, whose perspectives it must take into consideration, and without whom it never has the opportunity to operate at all. As logic, to be sound, depends on the presence of the self, so judgment, to be valid, depends on the presence of others. Hence judgment is endowed with a certain specific validity but is never universally valid. Its claims to validity can never extend further than the others in whose place the judging person has put himself for his considerations.38 Traditionally, moral philosophers have insisted that judgments be not only intersubjective but objective, not only impartial but universal, not only persuasive to ordinary reason but rationally unassailable, all of which Arendt and Dewey regarded as an absurd overestimation of moral knowledge. What is possible in this area of inquiry is persuasive judgments and good reasons, not formal proofs of the kind that Kant wanted or a technique of deliberation such as the utilitarian calculus. Techniques of this kind inevitably fail to do justice to the particular and make us into rule fetishists ever mindful of how we stand with respect to the rules rather than to human beings. Dewey was about as severe in his criticism of the doctrinaire kind of moralist who scrupulously follows rules for their own sake as Arendt was in her similar criticisms of Eichmann for his unthinking devotion to orders. The principles that guide reflection, both argued, are not transcendent deliverances but historically emergent values which orient reflection without binding it irrevocably. It is a decidedly undogmatic judgment for which both theorists called, one that aims for consensus without making this a criterion of formal validity. In ethics as in politics, the concept of formal validity has no place. Here, we are in the domain of persuasive reasoning or experimental inquiry not unlike Aristotle’s notion of phronesis or practical judgment, a notion to which Arendt made explicit reference and Dewey did not but might have. Aristotle’s remark at the outset of the Nicomachean Ethics that we must expect from moral philosophy only as much clarity and precision as the object of our
230
Education in the Human Sciences
theorizing allows is one that modern theorists have largely forgotten or dismissed. Dewey and Arendt are important exceptions to this, both endeavoring to articulate a conception of judgment that rejects outmoded dichotomies of objectivism and subjectivism, knowledge and opinion, and so on, and that defends the rights of practical reasoning of a more commonsense variety. Both philosophers were correct in their refusal to regard judgment as soaring over the head of ordinary persuasion and consensusseeking and as an art of one kind or another. Arendt’s strategy of returning to Kant and Aristotle – or to her controversial interpretations of these two, both of whom are usually contrasted on this matter but in whom she believed she had found an important affinity – is intriguing. That she made no effort to bring her views into contact with Dewey is as disappointing as it is unsurprising. She may well have found the language of scientific inquiry simply off-putting, but superficial differences aside, there is at least as much affinity between these two figures on this issue as there is between Arendt and Kant. It is unfortunate as well that Dewey made so little use of Aristotelian phronesis. This maneuver was certainly open to him, as was the appeal to Kant, although given Dewey’s antipathy for the latter on moral matters, such a move was unlikely. Why an appeal to either Aristotle or Kant would have been well advised for Dewey is that, unlike in the natural sciences, where the criteria of successful experimentation are relatively settled, experimental inquiry in ethics has no obvious standards of success. Dewey held that the utilitarian ‘social welfare’ principle came as close as any to such a standard, but this did not satisfy him either.39 How in an ethical context do we determine that a problematic situation has been adequately resolved or that an experiment has met with a satisfactory conclusion? If we inquire experimentally into the issue of abortion, for example, what are the signs that our experiment has been successfully concluded? The question does not permit of a general answer, he insisted, but only specific answers, each of which must do justice to a particular case. This much seems reasonable: the quest for first principles and a formal method by which to solve all moral problems has ended in failure, and Dewey was correct not to provide a successor to the categorical imperative and the principle of utility. Yet it seems that in such inquiry we still require ultimately an appeal to judgment, whether it be Aristotelian phronesis, Kantian reflective judgment, or some other conception. Dewey neither provided such a conception nor saw the need to do so. My suggestion that such an account is necessary is based on the unavoidability of the above questions. Experimental inquiry into an ethical problem, whether it be an abstract question such as where we stand on abortion or one that is case specific, gains orientation from a set of values appropriated from the culture in which one stands. These values are pluralistic, ambiguous, and
Teaching Ethics: From Moralism to Experimentalism
231
often conflicting. Their application to a case does not resemble the simple following of a rule but calls upon the interpretive ability, imagination, and context sensitivity of a competent judge. It requires tailoring a value or principle to a case, viewing a particular in the light of a universal. It requires, in other words, the art of judgment, if by this we understand the capacity to decide how to set up a given line of experimental inquiry, which values come to bear and which are secondary or irrelevant, which aspect of a case is morally salient, which argument is the most persuasive from our own and from all other relevant perspectives, and when a problematic situation has been adequately resolved. None of these questions is avoidable or may be answered in wholly abstract terms. The answer to each is that it depends on the particularities of the case, and this is exactly where judgment is required. An education in ethics involves precisely an habituation to answering questions of this kind. Good judgment is the highest indication of educational success in this field and it is exceedingly difficult – likely impossible – to impart directly. More important than a knowledge of ethical theory or commitment to a given set of values is whether students are able to exercise intelligent judgment of the kind that Eichmann and his cohorts so hopelessly lacked. It is a capacity that is gained through practice above all, in discussing, reading, and writing about social ills of any and all kinds. Simply becoming habituated to asking moral questions and attempting to justify our views in dialogue with others goes a long way toward developing this capacity and undoubtedly further than presenting students with a simple technique, with the educator’s own views, or at the other end of the spectrum encouraging students to express their judgments without any thought of justifying them with reasons. To speak of persuasive judgment does not mean that we are in the land of decisionism, delivered from the need to argue in ways that are capable of changing minds through an appeal to intelligence. The welleducated mind may or may not measure up to Aristotle’s phronimos, but it is able to formulate and defend its judgments with an experimental frame of mind.
Notes 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7.
Dewey, ‘Teaching Ethics in the High School’ (1893). EW 4: 54. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 34. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 75. Dewey, ‘Teaching Ethics in the High School’ (1893). EW 4: 54. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 369. Dewey, ‘The Chaos in Moral Training’ (1894). EW 4: 107, 113. Dewey, ‘How the Mind Learns’, Education Lectures Before Brigham Young Academy (1901). LW 17: 216. 8. Dewey, The School and Society (1900). MW 1: 11. 9. Dewey, Moral Principles in Education (1909). MW 4: 272.
232 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17.
18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31.
32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. 39.
Education in the Human Sciences Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 177. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 82. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 22. Dewey, ‘Why Have Progressive Schools?’ (1933). LW 9: 154. Dewey, ‘Significance of the School of Education’ (1904). MW 3: 282. Ibid., 282–3. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 311. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 36. As Dewey further wrote on the issue of discipline, ‘A person who is trained to consider his actions, to undertake them deliberately, is in so far forth disciplined. Add to this ability a power to endure in an intelligently chosen course in face of distraction, confusion, and difficulty, and you have the essence of discipline. Discipline means power at command; mastery of the resources available for carrying through the action undertaken. To know what one is to do and to move to do it promptly and by use of the requisite means is to be disciplined, whether we are thinking of an army or a mind. Discipline is positive.’ Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 136. Dewey, The School and Society (1900). MW 1: 11. Dewey, ‘Teaching Ethics in the High School’ (1893). EW 4: 60, 56. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 75. Dewey, ‘The Chaos in Moral Training’ (1894). EW 4: 106. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 83. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 172, 173. Ibid., 173–4, 173. Dewey, ‘Report of Interview with Dewey’ by Charles W. Wood (1922). MW 13: 430. Dewey, ‘Teaching Ethics in the High School’ (1893). EW 4: 59. Dewey, Moral Principles in Education (1909). MW 4: 291. Dewey, ‘History for the Educator’ (1909). MW 4: 192. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 71. Dewey, ‘History for the Educator’ (1909). MW 4: 192. Hannah Arendt, Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, ed. R. Beiner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), 76. Arendt is quoting Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, Introduction, section IV. Ibid., 55, 43. Arendt, ‘Understanding and Politics’, Partisan Review 20 (1953), 383. Arendt, Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, 94. Beiner is citing ‘Understanding and Politics’, 383, 379. Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (New York: Penguin, 1994), 32, 287, 288. Ibid., 295. Arendt, Between Past and Future (New York: Viking, 1961), 222, 220. Ibid., 220–1. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 183.
Chapter 7
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship Dewey did not invent the idea – indeed it is an idea as old as the Western tradition itself – that the citizens of a democratic or any well-functioning political order must be educated for citizenship. A competent citizenry is one that has received a certain kind of political training, that has acquired particular habits of thought and action, as well as one that possesses an important measure of knowledge. If Plato’s classic discussion of the kind of education that the guardians and the philosopher-king would receive in his ideal state is the best known example of this in the ancient world, it is also an idea that threads its way throughout much of the modern history of political theory and the philosophy of education. It is no coincidence that until relatively recent times the great political thinkers of the modern age have been advocates of educational reform as well. How one conceives of a just society inevitably raises questions regarding the character of the citizens it comprises and how that character may be educated to assume its role in public life. One might even critique political philosophies from the point of view of the conception of education that they make both possible and necessary, from Plato’s austere and highly regimented view of the guardians’ education to modern liberal conceptions, including Dewey’s, of education as a training for democratic citizenship. Among the aims inherent to the learning process, Dewey maintained, are both the kind of moral education already discussed and a related form of political training. Democracy and education, as well as forming the title of one of his principal works in this field, are themes that Dewey always insisted on theorizing together. While other political doctrines can of course be taught and learned in an educational environment, what distinguishes democracy from other such doctrines is that it need not be instilled in students’ minds in the fashion of an external imposition but is rather immanent to the practice of education itself. A training in democratic citizenship in no way resembles the kind of political training or indoctrination that Dewey observed first hand in communist nations, where from an early age students would be inculcated with state-sanctioned ideology. The kind of democratic education that Dewey advocated involves no direct instilling of political commitments in the minds of the young but very nearly the 233
234
Education in the Human Sciences
antithesis: a training in habits of intellectual independence and experimental intelligence of the kind that make political and all other forms of indoctrination impossible. It is under democratic conditions that the people in general are called upon to participate actively in the political life of the nation and to put forward ideas aimed at creating a more just order. A high level of public participation is a mark of a well-functioning democracy, Dewey held, while indicators of its decline include a susceptibility of the people to state propaganda, a low level of political involvement, and public apathy in the face of the encroachment into politics of commercial interests – all conditions that Dewey observed and lamented in the first half of the twentieth century. The way forward for democracy, then, is a citizenry that is educated not only for political deliberation but more generally in intellectual and moral dispositions that enrich the political life of the society. The line of questioning that this raises for Dewey and for ourselves regarding the political dimension of education concerns, first, from the point of view of politics, what kind of training for citizenship democracy requires – the general answer to which has been intimated in previous chapters – and, second, from the point of view of education, what overriding aims belong to the teaching of politics, be it political history, political science, public policy, or political philosophy? What ends, for example, ultimately govern the teaching and learning of political theory in the university? In what sense are students in the primary school to be educated for democracy? The argument of previous chapters suggests the broad outline of an answer: the mind that is educated for democratic participation is the mind that is educated simpliciter. The educated mind possesses habits of thought and conduct that incline it toward reflectiveness and an intelligence that is at once scientific, pragmatic, and social, habits therefore readily applicable to the domain of politics. This chapter endeavors to spell out in more detail this basic Deweyan hypothesis and, following the structure of previous chapters, to bring this argument into contact with some more recent views on the subject of political education. It will be immediately evident from the course of the argument to this point in our study that a political education emphatically does not consist in any kind of indoctrination in the sense of a direct instilling of contestable political convictions in the minds of the young. Educators are not preachers, Dewey would always insist, and the university professor’s lectern is not a pulpit. While the democratic tradition persists, as with any tradition, in the process of transmission from one generation to the next, educators must be very circumspect in observing their role within this process. Democracy, at the most fundamental level of analysis, is a way of life rather than an ideology or a creed; it refers not only to a body of institutions and procedures but more essentially to the spirit of public life that prevails in a society in which
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
235
the people govern themselves. As an ethos, it calls for the widest possible participation in public life rather than deference to political elites. It calls upon citizens to rule and be ruled in turn, as the Greek ideal had it, and to put forth creative ideas aimed at resolving the social ills of the times. For educators this entails a form of restraint directly comparable to that described in previous chapters regarding controversial philosophical, religious, and moral doctrines. Dewey remarked in an essay from 1924 on the topic of the liberal arts college in what sense an education at the post-secondary level may be said to be genuinely liberal or democratic, and faulted many ostensibly liberal educators for presuming to know in advance of inquiry exactly what commitments and values characterize the properly educated mind: It is held to be certain in advance just what beliefs a truly liberal mind will hold. It is therefore established that the way to create the liberal mind is to instill these beliefs. Quarrel concerns just what set of studies, what ‘curriculum’, methods and beliefs are characteristic of the liberal mind, and are to be employed and inculcated. Now such direct effort to gain specific ends is itself proof of the operation of the illiberal mind. A liberal, also a democratic, education is not characterized by the fact that it instills doctrines of freedom or majority rule in students’ heads rather than a rival political creed but rather by its refusal to instill any doctrines at all. It is not what beliefs students hold that ultimately matters but their ability to fashion rational beliefs independently. As Dewey wrote in the same context, ‘even if these [liberal democratic] views are sound, the mark of a liberal mind is not that they are held, but is the way in which they are reached and accepted’.1 They are to be reached and accepted on the basis of co-operative, experimental inquiry if they are to be accepted at all. This includes, of course, the idea of democracy itself. Like all ideas, it is to be treated as a working hypothesis and not a dogma. This proscription of indoctrination applies across the board for Dewey; it applies to controversial doctrines of all kinds and at all educational levels, from the primary grades to the university. If ‘science’, in the pragmatic sense of the term, is indeed ‘the sole universal method of dealing intellectually with all problems’, this quite obviously includes the political issues of the day and directly challenges teachers and professors who regard their role when the subject matter is political as deciding which political views are most deserving of belief and urging or manipulating students into thinking likewise.2 The latter view of the educator’s role, however widespread in Dewey’s time and our own, is a temptation that must be refused on grounds of the miseducative effects of intellectual ‘conscription’ in general and to
236
Education in the Human Sciences
‘the gratuitous stupidity of measures that defeat their own ends’. When the end in question is ‘social solidarity’ or a democratic way of life, this is not achieved but undermined by fostering habits of ‘intellectual inertness’ and deference to authority. ‘Absence of thought,’ Dewey wrote, ‘apathy of intelligence, is the chief enemy to freedom of mind’, while freedom of mind is the very lifeblood of a democracy.3 As with ideas of a non-political nature, Dewey was not urging educators to refrain from any and all expression of personal convictions. It is again the manner or spirit in which such convictions are expressed in an educational setting that is all important – whether they are expressed with the overt or covert expectation that students will come into agreement with the educator’s opinions or whether they are put forward as hypotheses to be debated on their merits. If the aims of a political education do not include a direct instilling of debatable beliefs deemed valid by an educator, neither are they limited to the narrowly empirical or informational. A great deal of the curriculum in political science consists of empirical information regarding political behavior, the workings of institutions, political economy, and what have you. This is all for the good, of course; not for a moment did Dewey entertain the possibility of striking such informational knowledge from the curriculum in courses in political science or political philosophy. His point is that an education in politics or in anything must go beyond the acquisition of purely informational knowledge to include, as in all education that is worthy of the name, the capacity for intelligent reflection. Informational learning in any discipline, in Dewey’s view, is at once indispensable and non-ultimate; it is a means to an end. Regarding information in education generally, Dewey wrote: I do not mean, of course, that students are not expected to get a certain amount of information. They must cover a certain amount of ground and learn a certain number of facts in order to get hold of the data on which to work. But after all that aside – the side of pure knowledge – ought, in my opinion, to be secondary to developing the child’s [and the adult student’s] sense of ends and aims which are valuable, and to developing his judgment and strength in adapting and adjusting means in order to reach those ends. The possession of information neither constitutes nor leads by any direct path to the kind of knowledge at which a political education properly aims. It is an important preliminary to thought, but thought itself it is not. ‘[A]fter all,’ he continued, ‘the scientist [political or otherwise] is not made by the amount of information he has acquired, but by his ability to use old truths and find out new truths.’4
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
237
Were it the case that political wisdom, good judgment, or social imagination followed automatically upon the accumulation of political facts, then it would stand to reason that the student of politics ought to busy him- or herself in the still conventional way with amassing as much of such information as possible, yet it is plainly evident that the mere possession of facts falls well short of the ability to think or to learn the higher order of cognition that for Dewey is the mark of an educated mind. Indeed, the possession of information may even be counterproductive in this regard; the capacity of intelligent reflection, on political or any other subject matter, ‘is smothered’, Dewey maintained, ‘by accumulation of miscellaneous ill-digested information’.5 Consider, for instance, the undergraduate student majoring in political science whose university education consists mainly or even exclusively in accumulating enormous quantities of facts regarding political forces and behavior, institutional functionings, economic dynamics, and so on, supplemented by additional information regarding the views of particular political theorists. Such a student may excel in his or her studies without ever learning how to critique political ideas or, still less perhaps, to fashion his or her own. The ability to think is ‘smothered’ by too much information in the sense that it is never formed by the student into any kind of meaningful configuration or larger picture of political life, the very quality that makes possible a deeper, contextual understanding of politics. One does not understand a mountain of data without arranging it into some semblance of order or an intelligent frame that allows students to comprehend their meaning and the uses to which they may be put. The educational significance of information is that it is a means to an end, where the end is roughly describable as social intelligence or the possession of good judgment regarding political life. Too often, however, as in so many fields of study, the students’ reflective capacity is underemphasized or even confused by educators themselves with the possession of an array of facts and figures or with what is loosely called being ‘informed’. It is not impossible, nor even unusual, to be very well informed indeed regarding politics and nonetheless incapable of rationally justifying one’s political stance or fashioning and assessing hypotheses for remedying the social ills of our time. The isolation of statistics and factual observations from a larger context of reflective inquiry mistakes a means for an end and so renders that end ever more elusive. The depreciation of the theoretical and reflective in favor of strictly empirical or informational approaches to the study of politics is as inadequate on Dewey’s view as approaches at the opposite end of the spectrum which apply a highly formalized analysis to political life at the expense of any pragmatic sensibility at all. So accustomed have we become to the separation of theory and practice, formal analysis and empirical observation, that educators in the field (or fields) of politics readily fall into one or the other
238
Education in the Human Sciences
side of a dichotomy: either the aim is to ‘inform’ students with an array of facts and figures or to impart a vocabulary of formal, theoretical categories that never quite touch down to the real world of politics. The latter approach, of course, is especially popular among professors of political philosophy who, like educators in other branches of philosophical study, concentrate more or less exclusively on theoretical matters – the thought of a few historical or contemporary political theorists combined with a critique of the logic of their arguments, with perhaps a brief discussion from time to time of the policy implications of certain theoretical principles. Whereas the first approach is strictly empirical, this second approach is decidedly formal and a priori, as it were, and typically provides students with an impressive technical vocabulary which for many represents the true mark of intellectual sophistication and of the well-educated mind. Dewey’s assessment of the latter approach reflects both his conception of political theory and his view of the theory–practice relation. His voluminous political writings are consistently written in a pragmatic spirit, in the sense that theoretical reflection invariably is placed in the service of practice and of resolving ‘the problems of men’ rather than constituting highly formalized analyses of the kind that we often find today in political philosophy. It is the bearing that abstract ideas have upon social issues and the reciprocity of theory and practice that orient Dewey’s own approach to the study of politics, and it is this approach that he favors as well in educational settings. His critique of formalist political analysis in the classroom includes a similar line of argument to what we have seen in previous chapters regarding overly technical and scholastic thought in general – that it is almost wilfully disconnected from the realm of practical life, that it produces a class of overspecialized thinkers ill equipped to move the conversation of democracy forward, and so on. The sole relevance of political, or any, theory is its capacity to help us negotiate problematic situations, and must not lose connection with the practical ground from which it emerges. Yet lose connection with the experiential and pragmatic is precisely what political theory and political education alike very often affect, creating once again a class of thinkers whose formal categories have only the remotest connection with and implications for resolving the injustices of this world. As Dewey would write toward the end of his life in Knowing and the Known, It is, I submit, the growing tendency of ‘philosophy’ [political philosophy not least] to get so far away from vital issues which render its problems not only technical (to some extent a necessity) but such that the more they are discussed the more controversial are they and the further apart are philosophers among themselves: – a pretty sure sign that somewhere on the route a compass has been lost and a chart thrown away.6
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
239
This, as we have seen, is a charge that Dewey throughout his long career leveled against theorists in a great many disciplines, and none more so than philosophy. Political philosophers, political scientists, and others inevitably import into their educational practices basic assumptions regarding the theory–practice relation, the nature of political knowledge, methods of analysis, and so on which orient the learning process and often direct it down avenues that show no signs of returning to the realm of political practice. Among the errors of formalist approaches is the conception of political reason itself as ‘something laid from above upon experience’ rather than as arising from experience and tested by returning to it and providing a better arrangement of the particulars that comprise social reality.7 Formal analysis rejects experimental reasoning in favor of a top-down application of technical categories ranging from the Hobbesian to the Marxian, as if theoretical vocabularies of self-interest or class struggle allow for a simple filing of social phenomena into pigeonholes conceived in advance of inquiry into a given issue or that substitute for inquiry itself. Classifying social realities into conceptual structures originally formulated in an empirical spirit but that in time deteriorate into inflexible dogmas falls into the same error as all forms of rationalism: to separate reason from experience, theory from practice, and to denigrate the latter in favor of a conception of reason that is selfsufficient and requires no corroboration from experience. For Dewey, all inquiry that consists in a ‘search for forms simply as forms’, be it political or otherwise, is empty and at best results only in the ‘acquisition of merely technical skill’ instead of the kind of knowledge that an education in politics might bring about.8 What sort of knowledge, accordingly, might a political education provide? If the aims of education always include a certain kind of knowledge, what knowledge is it that a political education imparts, and where the answer must take up a kind of intermediate position or perhaps constitute a higher synthesis between the narrowly empirical and the rationalistic? Not surprisingly, Dewey insisted that knowledge here as well must have its roots in our lived experience of social life and that the subject matter of political inquiry must draw upon the out-of-school experience of the students themselves. Instead of the political analysis that searches for cut-and-dried definitions of terms and that ‘substitute[s] a bookish, a pseudo-intellectual spirit for a social spirit’, Dewey called for an experimental conception of political reason which rejects the binary oppositions of theory and practice, reason and experience, and so on.9 Experience, in the pragmatic or experimentalist sense of the term, and the existing interests of students, form the ground on which the learning process proceeds, in political and all other areas of education. An experiential and experimental knowledge in the field of politics is in all
240
Education in the Human Sciences
essential respects consistent with that found in a philosophical and a moral education: it enables the student to ‘utilize the experiences he gets outside the school’ rather than isolating the curriculum from the political issues of the day with which students are likely to be concerned; it cultivates the students’ ‘ability to learn from experience’ or ‘power to retain from one experience something which is of avail in coping with the difficulties of a later situation’.10 The reason or reasoning that it brings to bear extracts meaning from the problematic situations that it takes up and aims in the manner of all experimental reasoning to formulate and test hypotheses for resolving such situations. Such reasoning involves the application not of a formal technique such as the utilitarian or contractarian calculus but of a larger set of intellectual capacities and habits of the kind discussed in previous chapters. These capacities and habits include much the same intellectual virtues previously discussed. Open-mindedness, flexibility, persistence, curiosity, reflectiveness, creativity, imagination, intellectual rigor, and so on are of no less relevance to the study of politics than any other branch of investigation. An education in this field, then, aims at once to impart information of the kind familiar to students of political science and political philosophy and, beyond this, to broaden horizons and cultivate the students’ own intellectual powers as they bear upon political questions. It does not prescribe what political convictions they are to accept but gives them the wherewithal to form and apply their own. If it is true, as Dewey maintained, that ‘we are living in a period of applied science’, then the scientific approach to the study of politics must follow the same procedure of experimental inquiry as what we encounter in other fields.11 Political education as inquiry begins with an experienced difficulty or problematic situation that arises in the course of social life (in contrast to the view that political questions are perennial or simply fall from the sky as soon as the human mind turns its attention to politics); this is likely to include either a specific injustice or social ill that requires political remedy or the realization of a general aspiration such as equal rights or a more participatory democracy. In either case, there is a problem to be resolved, and the business of inquiry is to find a possible solution. As the conversation unfolds, alternative hypotheses are suggested, debated, and tested in imagination for the consequences they can be anticipated to bring about and whether a given hypothesis can be expected, by following in imagination its foreseeable course, to resolve the original difficulty more satisfactorily than its alternatives and without simply replacing one social ill with a new and potentially greater one. This ‘method of observation, theory as hypothesis, and experimental test’ is what Dewey meant by ‘intelligence’ in general, be it the social intelligence that is in play in the study of politics and ethics or the form of experimentation undertaken in the natural sciences.12
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
241
For Dewey, all political judgments have the status of revisable hypotheses and never attain the kind of formal certainty that modern political theorists have often thought possible and necessary if we are to transcend the fray of everyday political conversation and rhetoric. The experimentalist is never above the fray in this sense, is never an expert to whom ordinary political agents properly defer, but is at best an intelligent voice in the conversation that a liberal democracy represents. Accordingly, if good political judgment is one of the intellectual skills that an education in this field seeks to bring about, it will be a judgment that cultivates a sense of its own fallibility rather than insisting on the truth of its convictions. Good judgment, in politics as in ethics, Dewey defined as the ability to determine the relative value of things, to estimate degrees of worth and importance without being inflexible or a slave to convention. Should educators wish to instill this capacity in their students – surely no easy task – they must do far more than impart facts of one kind or another but allow students the opportunity to work such facts up into arguments and principles that make up a larger perspective on political life which includes a developed sense of what is important. The student of politics, or of anything, as Dewey expressed it, ‘cannot get power of judgment excepting as he is continually exercised in forming and testing judgments. He must have an opportunity to select for himself, and to attempt to put his selections into execution, that he may submit them to the final test, that of action.’13 The reason why students of politics so often fail to develop this capacity is not that they are ‘uninformed’ but that they are often given too little opportunity to think for themselves and to have their own political stance subjected to critical scrutiny. When students are not invited or obliged to test their convictions in class discussion, for instance, or in written work, their thinking may be very well informed indeed and yet undeveloped in the sense that it cannot defend itself against criticism or rival hypotheses. Like any intellectual capacity, political judgment is acquired through use and is set in motion by the requirements of particular situations or social ills that require political remedy. A political education also calls forth habits of reflectiveness and imagination of the kind discussed in previous chapters. Reflective thinking, for instance, is a search for the philosophical grounds of our convictions and involves ‘(1) a state of doubt, hesitation, perplexity, mental difficulty, in which thinking originates, and (2) an act of searching, hunting, inquiring, to find material that will resolve the doubt, settle and dispose of the perplexity.’14 Because this is not accomplished in a vacuum or solely in the privacy of one’s thought it requires the practice that a social environment affords, a shared inquiry into the basis of our convictions and a questioning of received values. A training for citizenship requires an active and critical mind, an education that ‘develops the power of observation, analysis, and
242
Education in the Human Sciences
inference with respect to what makes up a social situation and agencies through which it is modified’.15 In their concentration upon reflectiveness, the cultivation of judgment and imagination, and the analysis of social situations, an education in politics and in ethics are ultimately inseparable. While the problematic situations that ethics and politics confront are more or less distinct, the intellectual capacities and methods that they call forth are much the same. Because of this, Dewey could well say of the study of politics exactly what he said of ethics: Ethics, rightly conceived, is the statement of human relationships in action. In any right study of ethics, then, the pupil is not studying hard and fast rules for conduct; he is studying the ways in which men are bound together in the complex relations of their interactions. He is not studying, in an introspective way, his own sentiments and moral attitudes; he is studying facts as objective as those of hydrostatics or of the action of dynamos.16 Like ethics, politics as a branch of academic study aims at developing a comprehensive understanding of social life, one that includes both a knowledge of how social relations are fundamentally structured and the forces and circumstances that come to bear upon them as well as an ability to think creatively and critically about how our political institutions might be better designed. While Dewey always cautioned against conceiving either a moral or a political education as involving the direct instilling of particular opinions or values espoused by educators themselves, one possible exception to this is the belief in democracy itself. As we have seen, Dewey insisted that we understand the educative process together not only with experience but with the explicitly political theme of democracy, while his writings on education are rife with references to democracy and the training for democratic citizenship that is a vital part of political, and all, education. On the face of it, it is a strange contention that teachers and professors must not seek to instill particular political views, yet with one prominent exception. Why this exception rather than, for instance, freedom, equality, or human rights generally? If we can theorize education apart from human rights, why not apart from democracy? Is this one political commitment immune from inquiry or criticism while the others are not? What is special about democracy among political values, on Dewey’s view, is that the spirit of a democratic polity is identical to the spirit of education as he conceived of it, and accordingly is not imposed on the learning process from without, in the manner of all indoctrination, but is instead immanent to the process itself. Education as a ‘process of mental development is essentially a social process, a process of participation’ – and
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
243
a participation no different in kind from political participation in a liberal democracy. The Deweyan school is a ‘community-centered’ institution that requires from students far more engagement in co-operative activity than the traditional school prescribes or indeed permits, while also drawing young people from all social classes and backgrounds into a small-scale community.17 Unlike the conventional school, it is not set apart from the rest of the community and conceived as a place in which lessons are taught and learned in isolation from social life and experience but the veritable opposite of this. The school is a nascent democracy – not, obviously, in the sense that students get a vote on whether to learn or not to learn, but in the sense that the mode of participation in shared undertakings and intellectual work that is called forth anticipates the properly political participation that democratic citizenship enjoins. By democracy Dewey intended far more than a particular doctrine regarding the state or a set of political procedures; ‘it is primarily a mode of associated living, of conjoint communicated experience’.18 As he would argue in his more explicitly political writings, democracy is a way of life that prevails in a society characterized by free and broad participation in public life, and not only by a set of political procedures and institutions. It is this same way of life that prevails when academic subject matters are taught and learned, as Dewey put it, ‘as methods of living and learning, not as distinct studies’.19 As a way of living, education is a fundamentally social undertaking, not one that in its ideal form would be essentially individualistic, consisting ideally of an individual student receiving knowledge at the feet of the master, but which for practical reasons must include other students in the classroom. It is only in a social environment that moral and intellectual habits alike are formed, by students of whatever age participating in shared undertakings and debating ideas, in much the same spirit as public policy (ideally) is debated in a democratic community. When Dewey maintained, then, that democracy and education are ultimately inseparable, he was not creating an exception to a general proscription on political indoctrination. He was advocating not that students be force-fed a debatable political philosophy or be made to believe in the principle of popular sovereignty but that the intellectual training that they receive ought to partake of the same social spirit as that which characterizes a well-functioning democracy. Training for citizenship requires no inculcation of political beliefs but habituation to a mode of participation with one’s peers in matters of common concern. In this connection Dewey would also defend the ideal of the public education system as a meeting ground for all the socio-economic classes and identity groups that comprise a democratic society. Since, as he maintained, ‘[e]very expansive era in the history of mankind has coincided with the operation of factors which have tended to eliminate distance between peoples
244
Education in the Human Sciences
and classes previously hemmed off from one another’, and since as well the very idea of democracy includes the notion that persons of all descriptions and backgrounds must converse together on issues of public concern, it is important that a democratic education bring together students from every background and social class.20 The public school is thus conceivable as a small-scale democratic polity in which the kind of social participation noted above comes about in addition, as an indirect but important consequence, to several of the attitudes essential to a moral education. Attitudes of toleration and respect, civility and equality, and so on may be fostered without any need for direct inculcation or sermonizing by bringing students from differing backgrounds into common association, broadening their horizons and experiences of difference, and by this means removing the provinciality and sectarianism that so often give rise to social tensions. The best hope we have of overcoming racial, religious, and other forms of bigotry, Dewey asserted, and so of creating a more civil democracy, is for public schools to admit a diverse student population so that existing social divisions will give way, in part at least, to mutual understanding and good will. It may be hoped that bringing young people into a form of association that is rooted in the achievement of shared tasks will go some way toward eliminating the conditions that give rise to intolerance and enmity. Dewey applied this principle broadly along lines of class, race, religion, age, and also gender. Coeducation, for instance, from the primary grades to the university, is an ideal that Dewey would defend from his very earliest educational writings and throughout his career and on both ethical and intellectual grounds. Educating males and females together along with students of different races, classes, and so on cultivates ‘not merely passive toleration that will put up with people of different racial birth or different colored skin’, but the ‘understanding and goodwill which are essential to democratic society’.21 The racial intolerance that had enveloped Germany and Italy at the time Dewey wrote these words (1938), and which was not unknown on this side of the Atlantic as well, are the undoing of democracy, as are sharp divisions of social class and identity. The remedy to this is the public school that teaches values of respect and equality less through direct instruction than through the indirect but ultimately more effective means of mutual association from an early age. The advantages of this are likewise ethical and intellectual, Dewey maintained. If the moral advantages of overcoming bigotry and a variety of other social ills are evident, the intellectual purpose that is served in bringing together students of diverse descriptions consists in the broadening of horizons and experience and the opportunities for intellectual exchange that it makes possible. The elementary principle of respect for differences is difficult to impart in the absence of real differences of race, gender, or class, or purely intellectual differences of belief. In each case it is
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
245
exposure to what is unfamiliar and the give and take of common association that leads to an expanding of horizons and an enlarging of experience. Dewey further argued that the curriculum itself may serve a democratic purpose, and again without any need for direct inculcation of political beliefs. American history, for instance, may be taught in ways that draw attention to the waves of migration that led over time to the settling and present composition of a nation as well as the contributions that immigrants have made in various dimensions of American life. It may highlight the struggles for emancipation and equal rights that African Americans, women, and other subaltern groups have had to take up, again for purposes not only of conveying knowledge about the nation’s past but of teaching respect, equality, and related values of civil association. The combination of curriculum and diversity of the student population, Dewey hoped, might well succeed in ‘subordinating a local, provincial, sectarian and partisan spirit of mind to aims and interests which are common to all the men and women of the country’.22 Such, in short, is the social mission of public education institutions and the kind of political training that it provides.
Education for liberation That the members of a democratic order must be educated for citizenship is not a view that is unique to Dewey, of course. It is a position that political and educational theorists have often maintained and interpreted in a great many ways, including perhaps the most influential educator of the second half of the twentieth century, Paulo Freire. The growing literature in critical pedagogy that Freire helped to inspire shows interesting affinities with Dewey in some respects. While their political positions diverge notably – Freire being far more indebted to Marx than Dewey ever was – both figures advanced virtually identical critiques of what Freire termed the banking concept of education and sought to replace it with a problem-solving model that would at once cultivate habits of critical reflection and provide a training in democracy. Many of the same moral-political passions that inspired Dewey and the progressives would later find expression in the movement of critical or emancipatory pedagogy that has followed Freire. Such movements are always difficult to characterize in general terms, but despite the variety of opinions these two movements incorporate it can be said that both locate themselves on the political left while the more contemporary movement gravitates rather more toward Freire’s Marxism than Dewey’s liberalism. Indeed for many critical educational theorists and for Freire himself, liberalism or ‘neoliberalism’ – a term often used and seldom defined – has come to represent the very phenomenon from which liberation is ostensibly required. Neoliberalism is a singularly unhelpful term,
246
Education in the Human Sciences
having little to do either with the conception of liberal democracy that Dewey defended or with older or, still less, contemporary conceptions of liberalism. Corporate conservatism is a more accurate term, and it is a stance that most liberals themselves, including Dewey, categorically reject. Nonetheless, ‘neoliberalism’ can be understood very loosely as the political philosophy of Reagan–Bush (senior and junior), its guiding themes being capitalism, Judeo-Christian morality, and a decidedly dated form of individualism. Its social conservatism logically accords with the traditional education that Dewey criticized as well as its contemporary analogues: cultural literacy and the larger movement toward standardization, positivism, and performativity. Ultimately, on such views students are being trained to enter the workforce while preserving tradition in essentially unaltered form. Freire would term this the banking model of education, where teachers are trained as a certain kind of technician and students as the passive recipients of information. Education here ‘becomes an act of depositing, in which the students are the depositories and the teacher is the depositor’, as Freire wrote. ‘Instead of communicating, the teacher issues communiques and makes deposits which the students patiently receive, memorize, and repeat. . . . [T]he scope of action allowed to the students extends only as far as receiving, filing, and storing the deposits.’ Little intellectual agency is called for on this view of education, and in the end ‘it is the people themselves who are filed away through the lack of maturity, transformation, and knowledge in this (at best) misguided system’.23 The banking concept calls for little agency on the part of educators as well, who are essentially reduced to providers of pre-packaged material. Teaching becomes a technical matter of optimizing efficiency in the transmission of information while educators themselves are mere ‘bureaucrats of the mind ’.24 The conservative banking model regards educators as being in the know and students as ignoramuses or blank slates upon which the former straightforwardly inscribe knowledge. Like Dewey, Freire wished to conceive of the teaching process on a model of inquiry or problem-solving rather than a simple accumulation of information, and with a strong accent on critical reflection of a kind readily transferable to democratic politics. Since on both views education is always already political, the kind of political education that is the topic of this chapter must involve carrying such reflection to a higher order of explicitness and sophistication. The student of political science or political philosophy will be a critical thinker of a kind and an inquirer into the social conditions and ills of the times. Where Freire departs from Dewey is in his conception of critical inquiry itself. Whether Freire’s Marxian view represents an advance over Dewey remains to be seen. It is a view that regards such inquiry as a reciprocal dialogue between the educator and the students. Freire’s initial premise is that students are oppressed more or less as Marx
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
247
had described, victims of a false consciousness imposed by the powerful upon the powerless. Writing in the context of his native Brazil, critical pedagogues quickly extended Freire’s basic problematic to the North American setting, a strategy of which the latter readily approved. Capitalism, to this way of thinking, constitutes a scientifically false ideology that blinds the oppressed to the truth of their condition at the bottom of the social order while leaving them ignorant, poor, and uncritical of the system that oppresses them. The ‘pedagogy of the oppressed’ therefore requires an awakening to critical reflection or conscientização which the banking model essentially forbade, a model that itself works to reinforce students’ unfreedom. It falls to the educator to become a political militant of sorts, awakening students to the truth about the social order and their plight within it. Problem-posing and problem-solving education ‘unveils reality’ or sees through the subterfuge that a capitalist order creates.25 This much is not surprising given Freire’s Marxian commitments. More interesting perhaps is his turn toward dialogue as a conception of critical inquiry. Dialogue in this sense is not synonymous with Dewey’s experimental inquiry, although the similarities are sufficient to bring the two into fruitful association. While Dewey would always look to science as an exemplar of rational investigation, Freire looked to social criticism that harks back to Marx while also imparting a notion of Christian love and with a strong accent on dialogical reciprocity. Critical inquiry requires a loving and explicitly egalitarian relationship between educator and students, Freire maintained. In his words, The struggle begins with men’s recognition that they have been destroyed. Propaganda, management, manipulation – all arms of domination – cannot be the instruments of their rehumanization. The only effective instrument is a humanizing pedagogy in which the revolutionary leadership establishes a permanent relationship of dialogue with the oppressed. In a humanizing pedagogy the method ceases to be an instrument by which the teachers (in this instance, the revolutionary leadership) can manipulate the students (in this instance, the oppressed) because it expresses the consciousness of the students themselves. Emancipatory educators lead the students into non-authoritarian conversation regarding a particular problem or reality in which the students can readily take an interest. Being oppressed, their consciousness of this reality will be uncritical and clouded by the ideology that a capitalist order creates. The educator therefore leads the conversation in a critical direction, but without forcing the students into adopting any particular beliefs or values. Any direct inculcation of beliefs would constitute yet another deposit in
248
Education in the Human Sciences
students’ minds, as the banking concept had it, while ‘[a]uthentic liberation . . . is a praxis: The action and reflection of men and women upon their world in order to transform it.’26 It is not only the world that is thus transformed but the students’ consciousness as well. They are raised to a freer humanity and critical awareness in the same dialogical process that seeks a resolution of whatever problems they take up. A political education, then, must be conceived within a vocabulary of domination and oppression, resistance and emancipation, humanization and radical critique, and as an overcoming of false consciousness through the power of dialogue. To an extent this is textbook Marxism of a kind that is surprising given the efforts in recent years by many on the political left to overhaul Marxism, or post-Marxism, in ways far more sophisticated than what Freire has accomplished. Freire’s originality lies far less (indeed not at all) within political theory than in applying it to education, an extension that requires educators to be more egalitarian in their communication with students than his undeconstructed Marxism might lead us to expect. Such dialogue requires the kind of environment that Dewey had also insisted upon, one that avoids the old dichotomization of educator and student, knowledge and ignorance, and that draws teacher and students alike into shared inquiry. Despite the language of ‘revolutionary leadership’ and ‘the oppressed’, Freire sought to downplay or replace this old Marxian dichotomy with an ostensibly egalitarian ethos of loving conversation. Accordingly, he would speak of dialogue as a ‘[r]elation of “empathy” between two “poles” who are engaged in a joint search’, and as at once ‘[l]oving, humble, hopeful, trusting, [and above all] critical’. By contrast, ‘anti-dialogue’ associated with the banking model ‘involves vertical relationships between persons. It lacks love, is therefore acritical, and cannot create a critical attitude. . . . In anti-dialogue the relation of empathy between the “poles” is broken. Thus, anti-dialogue does not communicate, but rather issues communiques.’27 The distinction between the horizontal and the vertical is important in separating genuine dialogue from its counterfeit forms which only reproduce the very relations of power that education should strive to overcome. The related distinction between communication and the issuing of communiques is also intended as a limited critique of Soviet-style Marxism, which Freire would at times criticize for its dogmatism and ‘sloganizing’. ‘The commitment of the revolutionary leaders to the oppressed’, as he expressed it, ‘is at the same time a commitment to freedom. And because of that commitment, the leaders cannot attempt to conquer the oppressed, but must achieve their adherence to liberation.’ Achieving this adherence must not happen by force or manipulation of the kind that Marxists of the old school have often practiced on the conviction that the masses are not only victims of false consciousness but ignorant and
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
249
backward as well. ‘It is not our role’, Freire would argue, ‘to speak to the people about our own view of the world, nor to attempt to impose that view on them, but rather to dialogue with the people about their view and ours.’ The people’s, and the students’, beliefs about their social world are a consequence of their position within that world. Bringing them to critical awareness does not involve forcing them to become Marxian revolutionists but more gently awakening them to the truth of their plight. It is ‘a critical perception of the world’ that a political, or any, education properly instills, not the educator’s values or political stance.28 Freire would often repeat this point, presumably in order to counteract the long-standing tendency of Marxism to seek to impose itself in doctrinaire fashion on the ideologically duped masses, where the assumption was that the latter lacked the intellectual wherewithal to achieve liberation by more peaceable means. ‘Scientific and humanistic revolutionary leaders’, Freire asserted, ‘cannot believe in the myth of the ignorance of the people’, whether such leaders be educators, politicians, or what have you. The people possess knowledge indeed, he argued, although it is a knowledge that is ‘empirical’ rather than ‘critical’.29 For critical knowledge they must look to an education that is enlightened and emancipatory without the ‘inflexibility’ and ‘dogmatism of authoritarian socialism’.30 There is no doubt that the kind of dialogue between educator and students for which Freire called is animated by an egalitarianism more thoroughgoing than what orthodox Marxism allowed, yet that important traces of such orthodoxy remain visible in Freire’s account is equally difficult to doubt. These traces are apparent in the basic problematic that Freire fashioned, and it is important to point them out. While speaking of students as ‘no longer docile listeners’ but ‘searchers’ whose ‘ontological vocation is humanization’ and who gradually become ‘critical co-investigators in dialogue with the teacher’, it remains that dialogue so conceived is rather less egalitarian and reciprocal than Freire often claimed.31 The educational consequences of oppression include the students’ false consciousness, where this means not merely that they are beset by a certain number of false opinions or prejudices but something far more dramatic. They are systematically deceived by their oppressors into misperceiving reality, at least at the outset of emancipatory education. ‘The dominant ideology veils reality; it makes us myopic and prevents us from seeing reality clearly.’32 It encloses minds in a fog that causes them to submit to their own oppression. ‘The dominated consciousness is dual, ambiguous, full of fear and mistrust.’33 It must be brought round to perceiving the truth and ‘develop[ing] a kind of critical reading or critical understanding of society, even in the face of resistance by students and by the dominant class’.34 It is of course the educator, not the students, who possesses this radical knowledge, a knowledge that the latter gradually take
250
Education in the Human Sciences
up if the operation is successful. Should the dialogue arrive at the conclusion that capitalism is not such a bad idea, it would of course fall to the emancipatory educator to instruct the students, albeit gently, in the error of their ways. Dialogical competence is thus something at which the students gradually arrive, on Freire’s account, and at about the same time that they adopt a far-left political stance. In reading Freire’s texts and the body of literature that his work has inspired, it does rather seem as if students (and not only them) who adopt any other stance must be either oppressors themselves or educational failures who have never adopted a critical posture of any kind. This never becomes explicit, of course, but it is never far from the surface. Should a classroom discussion inquire into a particular social problem and generate a consensus that is at odds with the educator’s ostensibly radical knowledge, the possibility is there that the students have it right while the educator does not, yet it is a singularly unlikely proposition. When it is genuine, dialogue requires a renunciation of the claim to expertise or to have a privileged knowledge to which our interlocutors do not have access; it requires an open-minded hospitality to others’ ideas and especially to those that clash with our own. The equality and reciprocity of which Freire spoke are rather more limited than this, and they are limitations that are already implicit in the vocabulary of oppression, domination, false consciousness, and radical knowledge. It is the educator who knows the truth and the students who have had the wool pulled down, not the reverse, and not only before the learning process begins. There are two antithetical strains that run through all of Freire’s texts. One speaks of dialogue and equality, of teacher–students and student– teachers and the evils of authoritarianism in all its forms. The other perpetuates the standard Marxian line: it is the masses who have had their faculties systematically impaired by their oppression, not the revolutionary leaders; it is the leaders who possess critical knowledge about reality and social affairs, not the masses. Freire would do an admirable job of bringing these strains into seeming equilibrium but they remain logically incompatible. When Freire spoke of the antithesis between dialogue and domination, he meant something quite specific by domination or manipulation: Domination is when I say you must believe this because I say it. Manipulation is dominating the students. Manipulating culture makes myths about reality. It denies reality, falsifies reality. Manipulation is when I try to convince you that a table is a chair, when the curriculum makes reality opaque, when school and society present the system of monopoly capitalism as ‘free enterprise’.
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
251
The examples are telling; teaching politics without causing students to see capitalism as ‘the root of domination’ reinforces their oppression and falsifies reality as one would misperceive a piece of furniture.35 The absurdity of this is as clear as it is that there is far more to manipulation than outright demanding that others agree with one based on false authority. Let us suppose that in a class in political theory the philosophy of a John Locke or a Friedrich A. Hayek, or for that matter a John Dewey, were to meet with the general approval of students and their educator, or for that matter any stance that is less far to the left than what Freire prefers. Let us suppose that this stance has been adopted not because the educator has demanded its uncritical acceptance but as a result of unforced dialogue. Freire’s analysis of this must be that this is an a priori impossibility; the non-Marxian consensus can only be a consequence of subterfuge, manipulation, and oppression. The critical pedagogue knows which political conclusions a dialogue may arrive at and which it may not, having beheld reality in its true dimension and having read a good deal of Marx. This form of dogmatism is more muted than what orthodox Marxism exhibited but it is equally objectionable. Morally-politically, the participants in Freire’s dialogical classroom are equal; epistemologically, they are far from it. The antithesis – or at least the distinction – between dialogue and domination is genuine and important, and the ideal of dialogical education is an attractive one which in some ways can be regarded as an advance over or perhaps a further refinement of Dewey’s pragmatic inquiry, yet how we understand dialogue is no less important. When Freire referred to ‘Fidel Castro and his comrades’ as ‘an eminently dialogical leadership group’, we can suspect that dialogue has been misconceived.36 When dialogical education is politicized in the specific and strident way that he advocated, we are compelled to re-examine the conditions that make dialogue the kind of practice that it is or might be, and when domination is reduced to capitalism and its consequences, we have missed the mark. Domination includes efforts by educators, be they on the right or the left, to inculcate their political views in the minds of their students whether overtly or, more likely, covertly. Dialogue requires the freedom to discuss all views openly and to weigh the arguments pro and con without anyone putting themselves above the fray of argumentation or claiming special competence. The latter claim effectively brings dialogue to an end, and while it is not one that Freire explicitly made, it is implicit to his account and hoists that account with its own petard. Declaring one’s interlocutors not only mistaken in their beliefs but victims of a false consciousness from which one does not oneself suffer is dialogical bad faith. It declares one’s interlocutors incompetent until such time as they are critical and radicalized, which means until they come to believe what their educators believe.
252
Education in the Human Sciences
Freire downplayed this and denied its implications, yet he was unequivocal on the question of politicizing education. Students ‘must perceive the reality of oppression’, whether we are speaking of his native Brazil or North America. Students’ ‘perception of themselves as oppressed is impaired by their submersion in the reality of oppression’.37 Their perception must therefore be corrected by those whose faculties are not impaired. Students’ resistance to this must be overcome, and they must not only change their views in a great many ways but act to transform their society in accordance with the radical knowledge they acquire. To bring this about, educators must awaken students to class consciousness, which is a gentle way of saying they must interpret social reality through a Marxian lens, and until they do they are not only mistaken but intellectually impaired. They are not, it is true, the complete ignoramuses and ideological dupes that authoritarian socialism regarded them as, but almost. Educators must therefore be ‘political militants’, and precisely ‘because we are teachers’.38 The imperative of militancy in the classroom is a frequent theme in Freire’s texts. Education, he insisted, quite simply ‘is politics’, and is not a mere aspect of it.39 Educators are not only radical (meaning Marxian) social critics but revolutionary leaders who somehow are not propagandists. How one can square this circle is an utter mystery, although Freire did manage to deflect attention from it by speaking the language of empowerment, resistance, and so on. As mentioned, he also made frequent appeal to the notion of Christian love, further glossing over the dogmatic implications of his argument. ‘Dialogue cannot exist’, he would write, ‘. . . in the absence of a profound love for the world and for people. . . . Love is at the same time the foundation of dialogue and dialogue itself.’ Such love ‘cannot exist in a relation of domination’.40 Love can indeed co-mingle with domination or manipulation, in an educational or non-educational context, as ordinary experience well testifies. When it is thoroughly politicized it is even more likely to do so. What Freire failed to see is that a certain amount of propagandizing is indispensable to his account, that propagandizing in a Marxian vein readily shades into indoctrination – necessarily so when one’s interlocutors’ faculties are declared to be impaired – and that doing so with love in one’s heart does not change that fact. The equality and reciprocity that are indeed indispensable conditions of dialogue are conditions that Freire did and did not believe in, in about equal measure. Freire may be commended for placing dialogue at the center of his conception of educative experience. The relevance of this ideal to a political education is especially important given that training in democratic citizenship crucially involves the ability to justify one’s views in dialogical interactions with others whose ideals or identity are different from one’s own. Ordinary conversation is the lifeblood of a democracy, as Dewey and Freire
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
253
both reminded us, and where it is genuine it involves a renunciation of absolutism and an open-ended quality that the notion of dialogue well captures. Once divested of false certainty and claims of special competence, dialogue better captures the open-ended and processual quality of educative experience than Dewey’s more solution-oriented view. It is process that matters most in education, not outcomes. While Dewey also maintained this, the model of problem-solving captures this somewhat less adequately than the concept of dialogue. Phenomenologically, dialogue indeed involves a search for the answer to a question or the resolution of a problem, but we know from experience that conversation can shed light and awaken the mind without quite solving the problem. The judgments and agreements at which it arrives are never final, but temporary resting places only. The concept of dialogical education recognizes the value of uncertainty and processes of fallibilist interpretation that largely define us as rational beings. Quite apart from the acquisition of factual knowledge, a mark of educational success is the cultivation of intellectual capacities that may or may not produce some determinate results. In the case of a political education these capacities include the power of judgment and a sense of justice, neither of which is a measurable learning outcome. Whether such an education produces emancipation in Freire’s sense is eminently questionable, yet it does give expression to aspirations of a more egalitarian kind than what is implicit to the traditional dichotomization of teacher and student. If it does not eliminate all vestiges of power whatever – and indeed it does not – it does strive for an ethos that at the very least approximates democratic forms of inquiry. It is unfortunate that the current trend that speaks of empowerment and anti-oppression which owes so much to Freire often deteriorates into political correctness. This form of absolutism also makes frequent reference to dialogue, failing to note the fundamental antithesis between the politics of the absolute – be it of the right or the left – and the practice of undogmatic communication, the animating spirit of which is not only egalitarian but fallibilist, non-militant, and intellectually modest. As Dewey’s texts remind us, intelligent inquiry of all kinds is experimental, and the knowledge that it creates, no matter how radical we take it to be, remains contingent on ongoing processes of investigation. No orthodoxy is possible to genuinely dialogical ways of thinking, rendering problematic the habit of some ostensibly dialogical or critical pedagogues of claiming false authority regarding truth or justice. None of us is above the fray of dialogical interpretation, including those who wish to characterize themselves as critical. Freire and many others for whom the catchwords of oppression and liberation, empowerment and critique, and so on, have resonance must tell us from what standpoint the radical educator grasps the truth of the students’ essentially political condition. The diagnosis of oppression and false
254
Education in the Human Sciences
consciousness is pronouncable from the vantage point of truth alone, and a truth to which the educator has special access. The reality of course is that the educator is importing his or her political judgments into the diagnosis and that such judgments are no more or less immune to challenge than any others. If we would teach our students to think critically, as much of the current thinking has it, or indeed to set them free from whatever bondage we believe holds the minds of the young captive, we must train them as active participants in the intellectual and political life of their culture. Dewey would say that education at all levels must initiate the young into the way of life of a democratic society, an initiation that is social both epistemologically – in training students in the practice of experimental inquiry – and politically – in rendering them competent to engage with their peers in debate over the issues of the day. An important indication of success is that one is a politically engaged citizen capable of forming judgments in an intellectually responsible fashion. A political education initiates students into the dialogue that is our culture or tradition, and has far less to do with the content of students’ beliefs (whether they are Marxists or ‘neoliberals’) than with their ability to form their own and to participate as equals in the conversation that a democratic society aims to be. Whatever emancipation or empowerment means in the context of education, it does not mean instilling the political stance of an educator in the minds of the young. If these concepts are to hold any meaning at all, rather than continue to deteriorate into slogans and clichés, they can only signify the capacity of students to participate in dialogical practices on their own terms. It is not uncommon for students or anyone else to be afflicted with blinding prejudices of one kind or another, and the work of education surely involves leading students to see how their apparent certainties are in fact interpretations and judgments that might have been otherwise. The best way this is accomplished is still to expose students to others’ ideas since it is in dialogical encounters with others that one’s prejudices are called into play and can become an object of awareness. These others might be theorists and their texts or one’s fellow students; this much matters little. What matters more is that one risk one’s point of view and often one’s parochialism in encountering unfamiliar ideas. This is how our prejudices are brought to light and potentially seen through, not through an expertocratic bestowing of enlightenment on the part of the educator. Freire may be commended as well for rejecting the trend that finds educators increasingly in the role of technicians and non-professionals of a kind, workers whose role is limited to preparing students to write standardized examinations and administering pre-packaged and ‘teacher-proof’ materials. Dialogical education rehabilitates the notion of the teacher as an educator, meaning a professional who is called upon to exercise judgment in choosing
Teaching Politics: Training for Democratic Citizenship
255
subject matters and tailoring them to students’ interests, in determining methods of education, and so on. When judgment is diminished to the vanishing point, be it in the name of ‘accountability’, rationality, or what have you, one is no longer a professional but a worker of another kind. If university professors remain relatively autonomous in this respect, bureaucrats of the mind are what too many teachers at the primary and secondary level are becoming under the influence of extraneous economic and political imperatives. So long as the learning process aims at the gradual attainment of intellectual maturity, indications of its success will be found in the cultivation of habits and capacities of mind of the kind that are called forth in dialogue. These are largely intangible and qualitative matters of a kind with which policy-makers are often ill at ease or regard as an impractical accessory, yet it is these that enable the young to enter into the intellectual and political life of their society. Becoming competent interlocutors requires practice at all stages of the learning process. One learns to judge, as Aristotle remarked, by judging, and one learns to participate in dialogical inquiry by participating, not only by being informed of whatever consensus or discoveries at which others have arrived. It is an important prerequisite of such participation that one know the history of the conversation to which one will offer a contribution, but it is a prerequisite nonetheless and not an end in itself. It is important as well that dialogue not deteriorate into a platitude, an all-purpose word, or worse, a veil for a certain kind of politicization of which political correctness provides the most egregious, but not the only, example. Whatever falsehoods we believe our students are afflicted by, educators are not crusaders but interlocutors. As such, they are wise to practice a degree of restraint in expressing their views in the classroom and in allowing students to develop their own, including when those views are political and not shared by the professor. In order that dialogical education not become a veneer for something that it manifestly is not, we might well recall Deweyan themes of experimentation, fallibility, and intellectual humility in order to correct the dogmatic excesses of critical pedagogy, even while the latter can indeed be described as an advance of sorts.
Notes 1. 2. 3. 4.
Dewey, ‘The Prospects of the Liberal College’ (1924). MW 15: 201–2, 203. Dewey, ‘Unity of Science as a Social Problem’ (1938). LW 13: 279. Dewey, ‘Conscription of Thought’ (1917). MW 10: 279. Dewey, ‘Period of Technic’, Educational Lectures Before Brigham Young Academy (1902). LW 17: 294. 5. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 57. 6. Dewey, Knowing and the Known (1949). LW 16: 249–50.
256 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. 39. 40.
Education in the Human Sciences Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 134. Dewey, ‘Has Philosophy a Future?’ (1949). LW 16: 361. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 44. Dewey, The School and Society (1900). MW 1: 46. Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 49. Dewey, The Educational Situation (1901). MW 1: 310. Dewey, ‘Introduction: Reconstruction as Seen Twenty-Five Years Later’ (1948). MW 12: 258. Dewey, Moral Principles in Education (1908). MW 4: 290. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 121. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 73. Dewey, ‘Teaching Ethics in the High School’ (1893). EW 4: 56. Dewey, ‘The Dewey School: Appendix 2’ (1936). LW 11: 206. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 93. Dewey, The School and Society (1900). MW 1: 10. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 92. Dewey, ‘Democracy and Education in the World of Today’ (1938). LW 13: 301. Dewey, ‘Nationalizing Education’ (1916). MW 10: 203. Paulo Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, trans. M. B. Ramos (New York: Continuum, 2004), 72. Freire, Teachers as Cultural Workers, trans. D. Macedo, D. Koike and A. Oliveira (Boulder: Westview, 1998), 17. Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 83. Ibid., 68–9, 79. Freire, Education for Critical Consciousness (New York: Continuum, 1973), 45, 46. Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 168, 96, 111. Ibid., 134. Freire, Pedagogy of the Heart, trans. D. Macedo and A. Oliveira (New York: Continuum, 2004), 48. Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 81, 75. Freire, Teachers as Cultural Workers, 6. Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 166. Freire and Ira Shor, A Pedagogy for Liberation (South Hadley, MA: Bergin and Garvey, 1987), 45. Ibid., 172, 47. Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 164. Ibid., 49, 45. Freire, Teachers as Cultural Workers, 58. Freire and Shor, A Pedagogy for Liberation, 61. Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 89.
Chapter 8
Teaching History: The Past and the Present According to an old caricature, Dewey regarded an historical education as an unpragmatic irrelevance, something that belonged to an age of aristocracy.1 Only an Old World man of leisure could concern himself seriously with the past, while in the New World it is the present and its practical problems that command our attention. History can therefore be stricken from the curriculum along with the classics and perhaps the entire Western canon. Nowhere did Dewey write this, of course, although he did have a fondness for saying ‘The past is the past, and the dead may be safely left to bury its dead.’2 Dewey wished the focus of inquiry to be the present and the ‘problems of men’, sure enough, but the popular caricature takes this to be the end of the story. Naturally it is not. Eliminating history from the curriculum for Dewey was an absurdity. The question is not whether history ought to be taught but how and for what reasons. The former question Dewey neither raised nor answered because it answers itself; indeed history ought to be taught and learned, and a good deal of it, but in the right way and with certain aims in view and not others. What the aims of an historical education are is the question that Dewey would have us ask: is a knowledge of our historical past an end in itself or a means toward some more ultimate end? As Dewey wrote in the same paragraph as the sentence just cited, If history be regarded as just the record of the past, it is hard to see any grounds for claiming that it should play any large role in the curriculum of elementary education. . . . There are too many urgent demands in the present, too many calls over the threshold of the future, to permit the child to become deeply immersed in what is forever gone by.3 The first thing to note here is that he was speaking of elementary school education. Students at more advanced levels may regard such knowledge as an end in itself – in the way that students of mathematics may develop a theoretical interest that surpasses its practical origin – but here he was referring to the beginning of the learning process. How is an interest in history originally awakened, one that will supply the level of attention necessary for sustained inquiry? The second point is the conditional tense of the first 257
258
Education in the Human Sciences
sentence cited: if by history we mean so much informational knowledge about names and dates, facts and figures, wars and treaties, which is bestowed upon students as an end in itself, then indeed the value of such an education is eminently questionable. This of course is often what an education in this field becomes. Dewey’s point is not that information of this kind is of no value but that it serves a higher purpose and that it behooves theorists to identify what that purpose is. The question of ends is important in every field of study, but in the case of history it may well assume special importance due to the ingrained habit of not looking up from the particularities of events to gain a larger understanding of history and our own place in it. History is something that we stand within; it is not merely the sum of events that are over and done with but a vital presence in our experience. We must understand how this is so if we wish to answer the question of ends. According to the same caricature, Dewey believed history to be ‘developmentally inappropriate’ at the elementary school level, something again to be eliminated from the curriculum but on psychological rather than pragmatic grounds. Later progressive and many other educators would take this view, sometimes citing Dewey as an authority, but again this was never his belief. A popular view for many years now has been that ‘social studies’ should replace history as the former relates more directly to students’ experience and is more contemporary and local in its orientation. The Deweyan reply to this is that such a policy reduces the students’ understanding not only of the historical past but, more important, of the present. Contemporary social reality, he argued, ‘is both too complex and too close to the child to be studied’, or studied directly. ‘He finds no clues in its labyrinth of detail and can mount no eminence whence to get a perspective of arrangement.’4 If our goal is to understand present social life in more than a superficial way, then it is the past that affords the best point of view from which to do this. The present may best be studied indirectly, by relating historical narratives on how it came to be and the ideas and forces that underlie our present ways of living. Piling detail upon detail without an arrangement or comprehensive view of some kind defies thinking. Setting the caricatures aside, what Dewey was opposed to in the study of history are approaches that present essentially a chronicle of factual information with no interpretive arrangement or significant attempt to relate what happened in the past to the present state of the world. Minds that are culturally literate in Hirsch’s sense may still lack an ability to reflect upon history in the sense of gaining insight into its meaning and learning the lessons that the past teaches. Information alone does not give rise to thought or any of the intellectual virtues that Dewey prized. No matter how skilfully presented, it does not constitute inquiry unless certain conditions are present. He was opposed as well to the same kind of scholasticism in the
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
259
study of history that so often characterizes philosophical, religious, and many other areas of discourse. The scholastic here as well is defined by disconnection from worldly concerns and theoretical disputes that do not touch down sooner or later to the realm of experience. As Dewey would so often point out, ‘[s]cholastic specialization and the departmentalization of knowledge breed indifference to larger social issues and objects’. Overspecialization is ‘the great enemy’ of pragmatic inquiry, whether our interest lies in the theoretical, political, or more factual dimension of history.5 As for historical learning itself, however, Dewey regarded it as of the highest importance. As one scholar has noted, He valued mankind’s accumulated knowledge as much as the most hidebound traditionalist, and he intended that the children in his elementary school be introduced to the riches of science, history, and the arts; here his goals were rather conventional. . . . Only his methods were innovative and radical.6 This last sentence may be overstated. The methods of historical instruction that he advocated were innovative but his view of the ends such methods serve was at least unusual. These ends are neither to preserve tradition nor to stockpile information for their own sake but to provide a perspective on the present. History as Dewey understood it is a kind of ‘concrete sociology’; the ‘immense significance’ of the facts that it studies ‘lies in the insights they give us into the mechanism of human behavior and its functioning under the most diverse conditions!’ As a record of the past, such facts possess little educational value, yet as an interpretive guide for the current ‘structure and functioning of the social mechanism’ they are of supreme importance. While their ‘“past” quality is of no interest’, it remains that ‘so many facts in the past belong not only to the past!’7 They belong to the present in the sense that they shed light on contemporary realities that do not fundamentally differ from past realities. This point is expressed numerous times in Dewey’s writings, including in the following passage from Democracy and Education: But knowledge of the past is the key to understanding the present. History deals with the past, but this past is the history of the present. An intelligent study of the discovery, explorations, colonization of America, of the pioneer movement westward, of immigration, etc., should be a study of the United States as it is to-day: of the country we now live in. Studying it in process of formation makes much that is too complex to be directly grasped open to comprehension.8
260
Education in the Human Sciences
That historical investigation is properly a ‘history of the present’ is about as innovative and radical an assertion as Michel Foucault’s similar claim expressed several decades later in the same words. I shall return to this point in due course. In what sense is history a ‘concrete sociology’ or a matter that is appropriately ‘presented from the sociological standpoint’?9 If it is sociology that we would understand, why not study it directly rather than via the long detour of history? His answer is that social reality in its current state is simply too complex to understand directly, at least by the youthful mind. If it is a deeper understanding that we seek, or one that is profound enough to be educational, we must view present conditions as having been brought about by conditions of the past. The present is essentially an effect of the past, a consequence of factors easily forgotten and extending decades or centuries back in time. History therefore is not merely a record of what has been but an arrangement that differs little from the world in which we now live. It is concrete in the sense that it is ‘a practical study of the structure and functioning of the social mechanism. In teaching us about relatively simple social situations, it leads us to understand better the more complex present.’10 Even when circumstances of the present are not inherently more complex than the past, studying the latter is a simpler matter given temporal distance and less cluttered information, both of which make for a more ordered arrangement of facts. It is far easier to look beneath surfaces of the past than the present, to cut through the details of social reality to grasp its underlying dynamics. Should we wish to understand the nature of war, for example, it is a far simpler matter to study wars of the past than of the present and to derive an understanding of the forces that lead to war and that prevent it. Sociological history brings to light the basic ‘structure and working of society’, not merely what happened in the past but its present and human significance. Past and present are continuous when regarded in these terms. The ‘methods of social progress’, for instance, do not fundamentally change, in Dewey’s view. The forms that progress takes may change but the methods or ‘fundamental forces’ that underlie it do not.11 Human motivations and forms of social life are largely constant, as is ‘the play of forces which make human life what it is’. Those who look upon history as so many disparate epochs are not looking deeply enough into human affairs, Dewey held. From an educational standpoint, ‘If we can make of history a sort of moral telescope through which to view the conditions of past social life, we really make it part of the present, since through what has been we become the better able to understand what is.’12 Dewey always insisted that education must be integrated into the students’ experience no matter what the subject matter, and in the case of history this means drawing connections between past and present experiences of social life. These connections are not difficult to
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
261
draw, provided that we are not skimming surfaces but inquiring more deeply into the meanings, motivations, and consequences of historical events. When the mind grasps not only what happened and when but what it signified, including especially its implications for today, then its perspective is transformed and a light is shed that is difficult to effect by more direct means. Ultimately what the student of history wants to know is not what happened in the past but what is happening today. Many have said that the present era in history is a time of transition of some ambiguous kind. Determining what kind is again very difficult to do, given the bewildering complexity of our times. What is needed is a distanced perspective on the present, the standpoint of a past age that resembles our own in some important respects. As Dewey remarked in 1947, . . . we are at the end of one historical epoch and at the beginning of another. The teacher and student should attempt to tell what sort of change is taking place. . . . [W]e are undergoing the same kind of change, as a change, that happened when the medieval period lost its hold on the people’s beliefs and activities. We recognize this now as the beginning of a new epoch. This new epoch is largely the consequence of the new natural science, which began about the sixteenth century with Galileo and Newton, as the applications of that science revolutionized men’s ways of living and their relations to each other. These have created the characteristics of modern culture and its essential problems.13 Understanding the nature of the transition we are presently witnessing is informed by placing it in historical context, and especially by drawing connections with earlier periods of transformation such as that which followed the long period of the Middle Ages. Whether the twentieth century, or the twenty-first, constitutes an altogether new epoch or something short of this – a further working through of the implications of Enlightenment modernity – requires a great deal of inquiry into the continuities and discontinuities between eras as they pertain to social relations and practices, beliefs and values, and other factors. This is the kind of inquiry that Dewey would have students of history undertake, again with a view to understanding the present state of things. Another aim of an historical education is to develop a critical perspective on the present. Critique always requires a degree of distance from its object, and historical distance is an important factor in perceiving conditions of the present day in an alternative light. Critique often involves seeing how such conditions came into being, thus dissolving the seeming naturalness of present ways of thinking and acting. Issues of politics and economics, to take Dewey’s example, ‘cannot be understood save as we know how they came
262
Education in the Human Sciences
about’.14 Should we wish to critique a given social ill, we must know something of its history – what its causes were or its conditions of possibility – before we are in a position to debate solutions. Resolving such problems in an historical vacuum or on the basis of what we perceive today alone is likely to fail. An illustration of this can be found in Dewey’s own historical reflections. ‘The simple fact’, as he remarked in 1902, ‘is that we are living in an age of applied science. It is impossible to escape the influence, direct and indirect, of the applications.’15 As we have seen, Dewey regarded this primarily as a positive development although he was never inclined toward the kind of scientism to which the positivists of his time subscribed. Science, suitably understood, was a model for intelligent thinking in general, yet he also maintained that the idolatry of science and technology was a grievous error into which a great deal of twentieth-century culture had fallen. Contemporary conceptions of education, for instance, that are utterly wedded to technology and to notions of efficiency and performativity, find no support in Dewey’s writings. The ‘movement for introducing scales, standards, and methods of measurement into teaching and administration’ and the ‘seeping into education of “efficiency” concepts and methods which modern life is making inevitable’, as he noted in 1917, is inevitable only in part.16 Had he lived to see the trend continue as it has, to the point that education is regarded no longer as an art but as a kind of applied science, his reply would be to remind us of the limits of scientific knowledge. Advancing this critique would require some historical reflection on how this trend came into being and the forces that propelled it into its current form. Corporate scientism in education is for many an inevitable consequence of modernity along with the ethos of technology, instrumental rationality, and performativity. It is a symptom of an underlying historical phenomenon, and to gain a critical understanding of it requires precisely this kind of reflection. When technology becomes an all-pervasive way of thinking, one to which all social practices must give an accounting, it has become a dogma that must be placed in historical perspective. A critical understanding of the present also involves learning the innumerable lessons that history teaches. Nothing educates our experience as well as past experience, whether we are speaking of our personal past or of past generations and epochs. As every student of history knows, human experience repeats itself constantly. Beneath the superficial differences, particularities, and appearances, human existence of the past and present revolves around recurring themes of love and hate, joy and suffering, ingenuity and avarice; it involves the playing out of themes in infinite variation. One with an interest in the history of war, for instance, will find behind outward differences of strategy and technology recurrent patterns of moti-
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
263
vation, greed, and power seeking. One finds similar motivations meeting similar consequences and the same mistakes regularly repeated. The history of religion finds similar patterns of love for the impossible co-existing with legitimation, hatred, and again power seeking. The history of government finds the same passion for justice inseparably linked with intrigue, overstepping, and of course power seeking. Whether we are speaking of the ancient world or the moderns, foreign cultures or our own, history recurs. For this reason it also teaches as the discoveries and errors of the past make up a wealth of historical experience that never loses its relevance. The lessons of history may be positive or negative, consisting of the achievements of human intelligence or the blunders, but it is these lessons and our capacity to learn from them on which progress relies. History is always contemporary. The experience with which it provides us is vicarious, oblique, and obscured by time, but its value transcends anything that the individual, bound by the present, may learn on his or her own. A large majority of our experience and knowledge is of this nature; it is undergone or derived by our predecessors, vicarious, and indirect. The lessons learned thereby may resonate in our souls somewhat less than those derived from personal experience, but resonance does not always equate with importance. What we learn, for instance, in studying the history of race relations far exceeds anything we could or would wish to experience today. Unless every generation must have its own experience of genocide, slavery, or segregation, it might be hoped that we could learn from the errors of our predecessors. This is the kind of ‘concrete sociology’ that Dewey was speaking of: ‘We are unfortunately familiar with the tragic racial intolerance of Germany and now of Italy’, as he wrote in 1938. The question to be asked is, Are we entirely free from that racial intolerance, so that we can pride ourselves upon having achieved a complete democracy? Our treatment of the Negroes, anti-Semitism, the growing (at least I fear it is growing) serious opposition to the alien immigrant within our gates, is, I think, a sufficient answer to the question.17 This was not an historical matter in 1938, of course. It is today, yet the questions we are left with are the same. If students now know a good deal about the Holocaust, from who the perpetrators were to the identity and numbers of victims, the events and circumstances of the war, the question remains, what are they really learning? Are they gaining information that might be useful some day, so that when the topic arises in conversation or on television they will know how to follow along? Are they becoming culturally literate in Hirsch’s sense, armed with an impressive array of facts and figures that can be displayed on a multiple-choice test? If this is the extent of their learning
264
Education in the Human Sciences
then they are neither culturally literate in a truer sense of the term (since being literate implies that one understands what one reads) nor educated. The point of what is now called Holocaust studies is to learn from the past, where this means to integrate its lessons with our present experience. The arduous work of inquiry into what happened in the past and how this can be verified serves a larger purpose than mere recollection. This example makes the point especially clear, but in principle the same applies to historical experience in general. Nothing teaches so well as errors of the sort of which history is replete. The record of the past of course includes not only errors but advances and discoveries which also make up our historical experience. History is essentially the record of human experience, its trials and errors, its achievements and failed experiments, a great deal of which is plainly relevant to our own efforts to resolve issues not unlike those encountered by our forebears. Historical lessons are typically more straightforward than what we witness at present, given the advantage of retrospection and its capacity to observe the long-term consequences of particular actions and to see the larger course of experience with greater clarity than the perspective of the present allows. Learning the lessons of history, Dewey held, also involves attending to the sort of characters and motivations that underlie events and the ends to which they lead. If, as he put it, the aim of historical instruction is to enable the child [and presumably the adult] to appreciate the values of social life, [then] . . . [h]istory must be presented, not as an accumulation of results or effects, a mere statement of what happened, but as a forceful, acting thing. The motives – that is, the motors – must stand out. To study history is not to amass information, but to use information in constructing a vivid picture of how and why men did thus and so; achieved their successes and came to their failures.18 Among the marks of educational success is not only that one has learned a certain amount in a given discipline but that one is able to learn. One is able to learn more specifically from experience or life, and it matters little whether that experience is first-hand or vicarious. The capacity and inclination to learn throughout life are contingent on the intellectual virtues and habits that education instills. These include much the same virtues as previous chapters have mentioned: open-mindedness or the hospitality to new ideas, curiosity, reasonableness, tenacity, a sense of intellectual fallibility and finitude, and breadth of perspective. This last quality is especially relevant to the study of history since it is in this field that the mind is permitted to venture far beyond the narrow purview of today and to see what human life has been like in other times and places. Dewey’s description of the ‘mentally active scholar’ applies here quite readily: the
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
265
mind roams far and wide. . . . Yet the mind does not merely roam abroad. It returns with what is found, and there is constant exercise of judgment to detect relations, relevancies, bearings upon the central theme. The outcome is a continuously growing intellectual integration. There is absorption; but it is eager and willing, not reluctant and forced. There is digestion, assimilation, not merely the carrying of a load by memory, a load to be cast off as soon as the day comes when it is safe to throw it off.19 The integration and digestion of knowledge this passage refers to allows for a broadening of the student’s perspective. Breadth in this sense means not only the acquisition of facts about various cultures and ages but a horizon that is wide enough to integrate these facts into a coherent arrangement, to perceive meaning in them, and to draw thematic connections between events from different eras. To be able to compare political or military events, for example, between ages in more than superficial ways is a skill of which the student of history ought to be capable. To be able to stand back from the endless particulars with which history deals and to see their contribution to larger themes, the significance of which only grows with the passage of time, is a primary virtue of this kind of education. No less important than having a broad perspective on history is depth of understanding. Here again is a value that virtually defies objective measurement while its importance is of the first order. What does it mean to possess a deep understanding of history, or of the history of this or that era? It is to have a kind of knowledge that surpasses the informational, but in what way? Dewey answered not the specific question but the general one of what distinguishes depth from superficiality: One man’s thought is profound, while another’s is superficial; one goes to the roots of the matter, and another touches lightly its most external aspects. This phase of thinking is perhaps the most untaught of all, and the least amenable to external influence whether for improvement or harm. Nevertheless, the conditions of the pupil’s contact with subject matter may be such that he is compelled to come to quarters with its more significant features or such that he is encouraged to deal with it upon the basis of what is trivial. The distinction concerns ‘the plane upon which [intellectual responses] occur – the intrinsic quality of their response’.20 A deeper sense of history is had by one who responds to historical particulars with an eye to what is significant in them – their ‘roots’ or the underlying factors that produced them, their important characteristics or implications for the present, and so on. One might compare it to a sense of art or taste; one not only knows a
266
Education in the Human Sciences
certain amount about the relevant facts but makes fine distinctions and responds to particular works on the appropriate ‘plane’. One has a sense of what is important and what is trivial, and of what makes it so. A sense of history, in Dewey’s view, includes an understanding of what is typical or characteristic of an age and in what respects it differs from others. Given the difficulty of comprehending ‘the essential constituents of the existing order’ of our own time and place, an understanding of prior eras is less elusive and can shed light on the distinguishing features of the present. ‘Greece, for example, represents what art and growing power of individual expression stand for; Rome exhibits the elements and forces of political life on a tremendous scale.’21 To elaborate the point, one may speak intelligibly of ‘the Greek mind’ or ‘the political ethos of Rome’, just as one can speak of the spirit of the Renaissance or of the Enlightenment. These are abstractions, but they contribute something important to our historical understanding. Once fleshed out, they offer a sense of what distinguished that age from others and of what made it the historical phenomenon that it was. As Dewey remarked in an essay from 1897, One reason historical teaching is usually not more effective is the fact that the student is set to acquire information in such a way that no epochs or factors stand out to his mind as typical; everything is reduced to the same dead level. The only way of securing the necessary perspective is by relating the past to the present, as if the past were a projected present in which all the elements are enlarged.22 Typically one does not have an explicit sense of what typifies the present and must look for clues to comparisons with other times. Historical selfunderstanding is an elusive value but one that an education in this field properly serves. For Dewey, breadth and depth of understanding are ultimately connected, as are the faculties of imagination, historical memory, and reflection. Only on the surface does the study of history serve the memory over and above reflective thinking, for example, or sociological interpretation. Reflection and recollection are especially hard to separate since ‘[t]o reflect is to look back over what has been done so as to extract the net meanings which are the capital stock for intelligent dealing with further experiences. It is the heart of intellectual organization and of the disciplined mind.’23 Faculties of mind, Dewey would always insist, are not discrete entities but dimensions of a unified experience. Returning to the example of the Holocaust, we find a clear illustration of this phenomenological point: one does not recall with any degree of vividness the atrocities of that time without emotion and the most profound reflection, without one’s sense of justice being called into
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
267
play, and without questioning how this could have come to pass and whether human nature will allow some analogous event to happen in future. One does not simply remember, any more than one remembers one’s personal past without interpretation and affective response. The simple fact is that there is no isolated faculty of observation, or memory, or reasoning, any more than there is an original faculty of blacksmithing, carpentering, or steam engineering. These faculties simply mean that particular impulses and habits have been co-ordinated and framed with reference to accomplishing certain definite kinds of work.24 Historical memory is no more a power unto itself than investigation into the past is isolatable from various other branches of inquiry. Among these branches, as we saw in Chapter 6, is ethics. Moral competence is instilled not by lecturing to the young on values or behavioral reinforcement but through the indirect route of social inquiry. In Dewey’s words, ‘When history is taught as a mode of understanding social life it has positive ethical import.’ Its import consists not in recollection alone but in ‘the formation of habits of social imagination and conception’.25 The student of history is transported in imagination into the past and into the circumstances of various actors and is not engaged in an epistemological enterprise alone. While questions of what happened and how this is known have a certain authority, history that is taught and learned in a sociological spirit calls out moral responses which may become habitual. ‘History’, as he put it, ‘. . . represents doubtless the most effective conscious tool’ in this regard; it is more effective than direct efforts to instill the virtues since it reaches more deeply into the capacities of imagination and responsiveness in which moral competence largely consists.26 Such competence is not ‘plastered on’ from the outside but emerges within experience in the same way that intellectual competence as Dewey conceived it is a product of habits formed in the course of sustained inquiry.27 An example of moral learning to which Dewey referred is the history of toleration. How is such a virtue acquired if not by means of direct exhortation? By means of inquiry into the history of intolerance in its various forms and the consequences to which it has led. In turn this leads the mind to question whether the historical lesson of toleration has indeed been learned, whether by the individual him- or herself or by the larger society. It leads us to see, as he put it, that [t]here is something strange in the history of toleration. Almost all men have learned the lesson of toleration with respect to past heresies and divisions. We wonder how men ever grew so hard and cruel about differences of opinion and faith. . . . But when some affair of our own day demands
268
Education in the Human Sciences
cohesive action and stirs deep feeling, we at once dignify the unpopular cause with persecution; we feed its flame with our excited suspicions; we make it the center of a factitious attention and lend it importance by the conspicuousness of our efforts at suppression.28 The same phenomenon happens today of course and continues to invite historical comparisons of one kind or another. Similarly, one teaches respect by informing the young of the historical struggles and contributions to national life of various groups, without any need for preaching religion or political correctness. The student who is decently knowledgeable of Jewish history, for instance, is an unlikely candidate for antisemitism. So long as our understanding of moral education is rooted in inquiry rather than preaching, the study of history is as effective as any of the social disciplines in instilling this competence. Among the highest educational achievements in almost any branch of the human sciences is the attainment of a certain kind of historical consciousness. Although this was never a major theme in Dewey’s writings, he did give expression on numerous occasions to what would become a major theme of twentieth-century continental philosophy and the various disciplines that it has influenced. This is the view that human thought and experience in general is embedded in a conceptual framework that is an historical inheritance. Our experience of the world is thoroughly mediated by the language and culture that are passed down to us in tradition and that constitute us as historical beings. Since Dewey’s time we have seen a recognition in a growing number of intellectual circles that knowledge in general is a certain kind of historical construction and is contingent on language and the symbolizing practices of a given historical community – that knowledge therefore is not the purely objective matter that most forms of Enlightenment thought believed it to be. Dewey’s way of putting this is that [t]hings come to [the human being] clothed in language, not in physical nakedness, and this garb of communication makes him a sharer in the beliefs of those about him. These beliefs coming to him as so many facts form his mind; they furnish the centers about which his own personal expeditions and perceptions are ordered. Here we have categories of connection and unification as important as those of Kant, but empirical not mythological.29 This hypothesis came to Dewey via not phenomenology but post-Kantian idealism, particularly through his reading of Hegel. Historical consciousness as Dewey conceived of it forms part of his radical empiricism, for which
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
269
experience ‘is already overlaid and saturated with the products of the reflection of past generations and by-gone ages’, including the categories of our language and ‘the intellectual habits we take on and wear when we assimilate the culture of our own time and place’.30 In his typical way Dewey regarded a consciousness of history not only as embedded in the past but as a forward-looking awareness as well. It belongs to reflection to determine the future direction of the culture in which we stand and to participate actively in its future unfolding. Historical consciousness is not a consciousness of the self as a hapless social product but an awareness of history as something that is not over and done with, as entailing a mode of intelligent participation in the life of one’s culture and a search for progress. Finally, on the matter of formal testing to determine in some way the extent to which such aims have been accomplished, Dewey expressed no objection, although the difficulty of assessing historical knowledge beyond the superficialities is clear. Whether it is possible at all to quantify the kind of understanding and intellectual habits of which I have been speaking is as contestable as the idea of quantifying what the student of literature or philosophy has learned at the conclusion of a given course of study. When information alone defines our educational goals there is little difficulty in measuring ‘learning outcomes’, but when we are aiming higher, objective assessment is a difficult matter indeed. Once again Dewey did not address this question specifically, however if we would answer it in a Deweyan spirit we might say that assessment of some kind is indeed possible. What is sometimes called rich knowledge is assessable even while there are limits to its precision. Multiple-choice examinations will surely not do, being the bluntest instrument ever devised by educators, yet formal essays and essaystyle questions in examinations which require relatively long and analytical answers do test a student’s understanding with at least moderate effectiveness. When grades are made to depend directly on reflective thought, and when this has been exhibited to some degree by the educator and the students during the course of study, students are well capable of engaging in this with about as much rigor as is expected of them. The common complaint that grading such matters is subjective is as spurious as the dichotomy between objective and subjective on which the complaint is based. Just as we know what constitutes sound historical scholarship by professionals, we can well distinguish a better interpretation of a given historical occurrence from a worse one when the author is a student. There is nothing mysterious in this, any more than grading is a mysterious matter in any other branch of the human sciences where there is something more than factual knowledge to be had.
270
Education in the Human Sciences
‘The history of the present’ A more contemporary philosopher has also spoken of history – or the only kind of history that holds genuine relevance – as the ‘history of the present’. This is of course Michel Foucault, a thinker who in many respects differs profoundly from Dewey. Hardly a pragmatist, Foucault was often given to saying that it is problems and their histories that interested him most, not solutions. ‘[M]y way of approaching political questions’ in particular ‘. . . is more on the order of “problemization”’ than pragmatic problem-solving, which indeed he resolutely avoided.31 As he would remark in an interview from 1983, for instance, I am not looking for an alternative; you can’t find the solution of a problem in the solution of another problem raised at another moment by other people. You see, what I want to do is not the history of solutions, and that’s the reason why I don’t accept the word ‘alternative’. I would like to do genealogy of problems, or problématiques.32 Dewey’s reply to this would surely have been harsh; what, he or any pragmatist would ask, is the point of recounting the history of a problem if one is not intent on a solution? On the question that is before us, however – the nature and aims of historical inquiry – the positions of these two thinkers are interestingly similar while their differences will turn out to be instructive as well. Let us begin with the similarities. Why should we introduce Foucault’s historical reflections into this discussion when he did not provide a direct answer to the question of the aims of an historical education and when he also appeared to deny the very possibility of looking to the past for intelligent solutions or alternatives to the problems of the present? The answer can be found in Foucault’s descriptions of his own historical investigations, or genealogies as he, following Nietzsche, preferred to call them. The point of genealogy, in his words, is to provide an ‘historical awareness of our present circumstances’, a ‘history of the present’ that serves a critical intent.33 The latter phrase appeared in Discipline and Punish of 1975, an historical–critical account of the modern prison. Foucault concluded the book’s first chapter this way: ‘I would like to write the history of this prison. . . . Why? Simply because I am interested in the past? No, if one means by that writing a history of the past in terms of the present. Yes, if one means writing the history of the present.’34 Foucault of course did not cite Dewey’s use of the same idea and the same phrase, and presumably was unaware of it. Not only the phrase is the same. In all of Foucault’s historical or genealogical writings he insisted that the relevance of the past is solely its connection with the present and the
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
271
light that it sheds on contemporary ways of thinking and acting. In particular, historical inquiry serves the larger purpose of social criticism. It is the conditions of the past that are relevant to present conditions, especially present injustices, that captured Foucault’s interest, not the past as an end in itself. The emphasis on critique may well be said to be an advance on Dewey’s somewhat more restrained view. The purpose of historical investigation and presumably of historical education for Foucault is to critique ‘intolerable’ conditions of the present by tracing the specificities of their development over time, a premise that underlies his writings on the history of the prison, sexuality, madness, and so on. The critical intent of genealogy is more explicit than in Dewey’s work, but so too is its pessimism. Foucault shared much with Dewey: a concentration on the ‘problems of men’ and especially with forms of power and inequality that stand in the way of human freedom; both were dedicated social critics and activists no less than they were theorists; both also wished to reject the metaphysical baggage of the Enlightenment. The two also shared many of the same moral–political passions, yet what they did not share is Dewey’s optimism in the power of human intelligence, in principle at least, to resolve the problematic situations that it confronts in the general direction of progress. An optimist in general, and a pragmatist with respect to social problems in particular, Foucault was not. On these questions I shall not offer an opinion on which figure represents an advance over the other, however on the question of the critical intent that historical inquiry ultimately serves and the nature of such inquiry, Foucault may well be said to have provided an important supplement to the Deweyan position. In what does this supplement consist and on what grounds would one think of it as an advance? The latter question, as I have suggested, is answered in light of genealogy’s critical intent, which carries to a higher order of explicitness an idea that is already implicit in Dewey’s account as I have described it. Historical investigation not only helps us understand the present more thoroughly than sociological inquiry concerned exclusively with contemporary reality, it helps us to understand it critically or with an eye to the conditions of the past that led to present injustices. It is the history of problems, Foucault said, and problems that continue to beset our own times, that defines the genealogist’s sphere of interest, not what happened in the past for its own sake. Genealogy itself, in his words, ‘is gray, meticulous, and patiently documentary. It operates on a field of entangled and confused parchments, on documents that have been scratched over and recopied many times.’ It . . . requires patience and a knowledge of details, and it depends on a vast accumulation of source material. . . . Genealogy does not oppose itself to
272
Education in the Human Sciences
history as the lofty and profound gaze of the philosopher might compare to the molelike perspective of the scholar; on the contrary, it rejects the metahistorical deployment of ideal significations and indefinite teleologies. It opposes itself to the search for ‘origins’.35 Following Nietzsche, whose genealogy of morality was an attempt to trace the history of ethics as a means of revealing the will to power operative within modern standards of evaluation, Foucault’s genealogy is similarly partisan and interpretive, a matter of ‘historical investigation into the events that have led us to constitute ourselves and to recognize ourselves as subjects of what we are doing, thinking, saying’.36 Foucault’s genealogical writings – principally Discipline and Punish and The History of Sexuality volumes – are a collection of inquiries into the history and development of concepts, practices, and institutions that govern modern social reality, inquiries that are never combined into any kind of systematic whole in terms of which that reality may be viewed. Instead the aim of these texts is to reveal the various assumptions and evaluations that underlie present modes of practice and often to remind us of what has been forgotten. Genealogy disturbs what was thought solid and reveals the contingency behind all apparent necessity. It dissolves the self-evident quality of received judgments and reminds us how these judgments and the discourses in which they occur are historical constructions. It historicizes everything from the most everyday perceptions and intuitions to the great questions and problems that philosophers have often taken to be perennial. By placing everything within the rise and fall of history, genealogical inquiry denaturalizes all that we imagine natural or fixed. If it is the nature of power, particularly in its more ominous forms, to present itself as having no alternative or as belonging to an unassailable order, it falls to genealogy to dissolve the dogmatic consciousness that is essential to its operations. Genealogy is distinguished from traditional forms of historical inquiry, first, in its selective attention to events of the past that initiated intolerable conditions of the present and, second, in its refusal to interpret events as forming a continuous line of development from a single point of origin to a culmination in the present or future. While genealogy investigates the origins of various phenomena, it searches for origins in a myriad places, examining a multiplicity of factors that have given rise to present conditions. Foucault was critical of historical research that subordinates the particularity of events to overarching mechanisms and explanatory schemes. There are, in his view, no underlying laws or structural necessities operative behind the particularities of historical development, no fixed patterns or final culminations in terms of which to explain the past. Foucault’s concern was to preserve and ‘record the singularity of events outside of any monotonous finality’, without invoking
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
273
theories of progress or uninterrupted teleology in history.37 In recording the accidents and the errors that gave rise to modern practices, the complexity and contingency of historical events, genealogy undermines the reassuring predictability of traditional historical investigation. For Foucault, there is no standpoint available from which to identify teleological movement in history or to gain a totalized understanding of the past, present, or future. Instead we are left with detailed inquiry into the constitution of modern forms of knowledge and the various ways in which subjectivity has been constituted. Above all, genealogy opposes itself to universalist and quasi-scientific forms of historical analysis such as Marxian historical materialism. Foucault looked with justified suspicion upon Marxists and others who view their method of analysis as bestowing definitive insight into human affairs. Where such theorists seek evidence of continuous development, deep structures, and hidden meanings, the genealogist accentuates historical discontinuity, the accidental character of events, and the superficiality of all ostensibly deep meanings. Historical developments for Foucault represent strategies in the struggle for power and the succession of one form of domination after another. Beneath claims to rational objectivity are found intrigues, conflicts, and treacheries of various kinds. Genealogy documents how objective discourses and subjective motivations emerge together, how practices and institutions embody forms of domination, and how sinister intentions underlie modern standards of evaluation. Foucault characterized genealogy as a method of historical and social critique that involves local and popular forms of knowledge, particularly those that have been demoted to a relatively low position in the scientific hierarchy of knowledges. Foucault famously called for an ‘insurrection of subjugated knowledges’, by which he meant a rehabilitation of local discourses dismissed for their apparent lack of rigor: ‘a whole set of knowledges that have been disqualified as inadequate to their task or insufficiently elaborated: naive knowledges, located low down on the hierarchy, beneath the required level of cognition or scientificity’.38 The genealogist takes up the claims of the participant, the activist, the physician, or the inmate together with other forms of popular and local knowledge. They are rehabilitated not on account of their superior rationality or consensus-generating capacity but precisely for their power to interrupt consensus and destabilize established ‘regimes of truth’. Incapable of fashioning consensus, these subjugated knowledges serve as instruments of critique since they disrupt the selfevident appearance of what passes for truth and remind us how our present practices came to be and, accordingly, may be otherwise. Herein lies genealogy’s claim to radicality: as an iconoclastic form of historical critique, genealogy serves to challenge and destabilize forms of practice that have been imposed upon and have constituted modern subjects.
274
Education in the Human Sciences
The main focus of Foucault’s genealogical writings is the less visible forms of power and the multiple ways in which these are exercised in modern social and discursive practices. Having abandoned the search for a suprahistorical or totalizing standpoint for social criticism, Foucault abandoned as well the ideal of power-free communication at the heart of the Marxian – including Freire’s – theory of critique. Foucault regarded the dichotomy of dialogue and domination and the ideals of power-free discourse and a power-free society as dangerously utopian and proposed to replace them with specific historical inquiries into the workings of power within modern society. Unlike orthodox Marxism again, he did not limit his analysis to the effects of powerful interests or centralized authority. Power is misunderstood as the private possession of an agent, whether individual, state, church, or institution, since this overlooks the multiple ways in which power is exercised without a specific agent of domination. Without minimizing the importance of state power, the principal objects of Foucault’s critique are those exercises of power that are ‘capillary’ and which in a sense make centralized domination possible. Genealogy traces the effects of strategies that, while decipherable, are often without malicious intent and are just as frequently authorless. It reveals how power is exercised not on a top-down basis but from the bottom up, how relations of inequality circulate and pervade a great variety of practices and institutions, and how they constitute the social domain as a totality. In short, genealogy documents how power relations have been able to operate and the specificities of their interconnections. As incisive as Foucault’s analysis of social and political power is, he was no less concerned with epistemic power, particularly within the human sciences. The concept of power/knowledge is central to Foucault’s thought, especially in the genealogical writings. Against those who maintain that statements, in order to be constituted as knowledge, must be emancipated from all vestiges of domination (again, Freire is a fitting example), and who hold out the possibility of objective and rational adjudication, Foucault refused to separate interested from neutral, subjective from objective, discourse. There is, he held, no knowledge outside of power relations, no neutral method of adjudicating competing truth-claims. Knowledge does not presuppose the suspension of power relations but requires the latter as a condition of possibility. Nor are power and knowledge antithetical, such that truth may appear only once the effects of power that conceal the truth are suspended. Rather, knowledge and power are correlative. In addition to being an instrument of domination, power has a productive capacity in the constitution of knowledge. As Foucault put it, ‘We must cease once and for all to describe the effects of power in negative terms: it “excludes”, it “represses”, it “censors”, it “abstracts”, it “masks”, it “conceals”. In fact, power produces; it produces reality; it produces domains of objects and rituals of truth.’ Without collaps-
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
275
ing the distinction between power and knowledge altogether, Foucault maintained that the two ‘directly imply one another; that there is no power relation without the correlative constitution of a field of knowledge, nor any knowledge that does not presuppose and constitute at the same time power relations’.39 Power, then, lies less in outright oppression than in the creation of fields and objects of knowledge and in techniques of epistemic adjudication. It is visible in the establishment of regimes of truth and the suppression of ways of knowing that do not conform to ostensibly rational criteria. Foucault’s genealogical writings also describe the political dimension of identity or the manner in which power reaches into and fashions individual subjectivity. Not only social practices and institutions but relations between physician and patient, confessor and penitent, penitentiary and prisoner, educator and student contain a political dimension. The fundamental manner in which persons are fashioned as subjects is an essentially political phenomenon. Subjectivity is fashioned within a network of subjugations, from the regulation of behavior to the manipulation of desire and the workings of a great many social processes. The human body itself was said by Foucault to be an effect of power, something that is disciplined and modified by everything from economic activity to medical technologies. One of the tasks of genealogy therefore is to interpret the human subject as at once an agent and (especially) an effect of power. Foucault’s interests as a critical historian clearly lay in the domain of dominations, contradictions, and treacheries of various kinds, and decidedly not in the realm of alternatives or solutions to the problems he described. As an iconoclastic thinker, his principal aim was to disturb and to provoke. It was to unseat established regimes of knowledge and to reveal the history and extent of the dangers besetting modern practices. Foucault was without doubt remarkably astute in tracing the development of such practices, in describing them in such a way as to highlight and preserve their complexity, and in cautioning against facile solutions to the dangers associated with them. Herein lies the considerable value that genealogy can claim as a mode of critical–historical thought. It serves an important iconoclastic function by reminding us of the historical contingency of and the dangers inherent to contemporary practices. It undermines the absolutism that can infect our ways of thinking by reminding us that all could have been otherwise. Yet herein also lie the limits of its value. If we wish social or historical criticism to be compelling, it must do more than point out the nature and history of problems and include a more pragmatic dimension. There is no reason to believe that undermining current forms of power/knowledge will of itself bring about a more just state of affairs, any more than recounting the history of a problem will of itself resolve it. For such criticism to be ‘intelligent’ in Dewey’s sense or any other, it must go beyond iconoclasm or
276
Education in the Human Sciences
negation and affirm something. There is no compelling criticism that does not also say something affirmative, no problematization that does not raise the question of alternatives. As Dewey might say, it must do more than demystify and debunk but also propose and resolve. Criticism that lacks a pragmatic sensibility is truncated and of limited usefulness. Returning to our original question, we might say that the aims of an historical education extend beyond factual learning to include the cultivation of what we might call an historical sense. What is the character of this sense? In answering this, I see no reason why we may not draw upon the insights of both of these otherwise very different thinkers. Dewey was correct: history is sufficiently continuous and social forces are sufficiently similar through time that studying past ages is the best way to gain an understanding of the present that sees what is essential and cuts through the rest. Foucault was also correct: an historical sense must be critical and uncover the political dimension of what it investigates. It must be suspicious in some measure and have an eye for what lies beneath the surface of our knowledge and our comforting belief in progress. It is indeed the history of the present, as both figures maintained, that holds ultimate importance, whether from the standpoint of education or social criticism. The past as the past is an irrelevance; the past as a critical perspective on our own times is both relevant and of the highest importance. What an historical sense of this kind looks like may be seen through a couple of examples. As we have seen, Dewey was among those philosophers who regarded science as in a way definitive of the modern age. Understanding the present critically means understanding the myriad ways in which scientific and technological ways of thinking have become pre-eminent in virtually all facets of human existence, from the confrontation with the Roman church and the ensuing scientific revolution down through our own times. For Foucault, we must inquire more thoroughly still: we must trace the effects of this particular form of power/knowledge on the human soul, reveal its productive capacity along with its dangers, and see through its apolitical, value-neutral appearance. We must avoid what he would have surely seen as Dewey’s excessive optimism about science and be alert to its less creditable underside. Studying the present constitution and history of our society requires that we know something of the history of science, which in turn raises questions about the philosophy of science, the limits of science, and so on. All of this contributes to our historical–critical sense of the present and supplements the ‘concrete sociology’ of which Dewey spoke. Another example we have already seen is the study of the Holocaust. Here again we are interested not merely in what happened but in what it signifies today and how this event shapes our own sensibilities. To understand this event at all is to understand it critically, as one of the greatest atrocities of
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
277
history, to be sure, but also as having a great many preconditions and consequences. What social undercurrents made this possible – a question that Dewey confronted directly – and how it continues to form attitudes are questions for the student of history no less than the more straightforward factual questions.40 The same can be said of past events more generally, insofar as they hold genuine historical importance. The point warrants emphasis because of the still prevalent view that historical recollection or the simple conservation of memories is its own end, as if recollection were an isolated faculty of mind unrelated to critique, sociological interpretation of the present, a sense of justice, and so on. It is precisely the memory of historical atrocities and imbecilities, still more perhaps than the great achievements of the past, that directly inform our political sensibilities. The sense of justice is educated by learning the lessons of history, many or most of which are cautionary tales about the consequences of primal stupidity. The recollection of the Holocaust and the moral imperative of ‘Never again’ are from an educational standpoint inseparable. If we are indeed becoming a society that is losing its collective memory along with its attention span, as many fear, what would make this regrettable is not the failure of a conservation project but the lost opportunities for social learning. As with any good narrative, history contains a moral – more likely a remarkably complex set of overlapping and conflicting morals – which it falls to the student of history to interpret no less than the student of ethics or politics. It is an historical sense of this kind that is the highest achievement of education in this field. This is a complex sense that incorporates a good deal of informational knowledge about the past, together with knowledge of a less empirical kind. Dewey called this knowledge sociological while for Foucault it is a more political matter, in a subtler and deeper sense of the word than that which pertains to the state. It is a knowledge that is less tangible, less specialized, and less mundane than the informational. In posing questions of critique it is far removed both from the quasi-value-neutrality of positivistic history and from the conservative preservation for preservation’s sake view. It is a kind of knowledge that does not lend itself to the kind of examination that we find on the SAT and other tests of its kind. Such examinations are far too blunt an instrument to test the capacities that history educates, just as they are too blunt to test the real achievements of learning in all other fields of the human sciences. The SAT – a scam that has far less to do with education than with money and the self-interest of the universities – continues to compress all knowledge of American history, for example, into so many multiple-choice questions that at best skim the surface of historical understanding. While the authors of this test undoubtedly believe they have moved beyond the level of sophistication of tests that dwelled on names, dates, and events, they have succeeded to a very minor extent. Despite
278
Education in the Human Sciences
their assertion that they are testing for contextual and ‘big picture’ understanding, this end is subverted by the choice of means. The multiplechoice question, no matter how cleverly formulated, fails utterly to test real understanding; at best it mimics this and at worst it deteriorates into guesswork. This form of questioning more than any other – with the possible exceptions of the true–false question and ‘Fill in the blank’ – is the death of thinking. It is common knowledge that tests of this kind can be passed with flying colors by students shrewd in the art of test preparation while their level and quality of historical understanding remains rudimentary. This cannot be overcome by better questions but is inherent to the multiple-choice format itself. The format in short is simplistic and shallow. That American students are still subject to this test, in order to feed the marketing machinery and sheer arrogance of the universities, is a travesty. How, then, can such knowledge be tested? I am afraid that the answer to this question will need to be complex, and too much so to be of help in university marketing campaigns. Historical knowledge, like the knowledge of philosophy or literature, is qualitative, interpretive, critical, and some other things that defy psychometrics. It is a sensibility, or set of sensibilities, that can be tested by means of essays and essay-style questions on examinations. Unfortunately these cannot be graded by computer but by educators alone who bring their historical knowledge and professional judgment to bear and who are themselves capable of making qualitative judgments. A good historical interpretation is distinguishable from a poor one if a person has the appropriate knowledge, even if the marker is not able to point to a bubble correctly or incorrectly filled in. Standardized and multiple-choice testing should be seen for what it is: a bad substitute for understanding, an uncritical mode of cognition, and an insult to human intelligence. Why it persists is a question more educators might well ask. Educated students of history possess a great deal of information while being able to discern the meanings of the past and its connections with the present. They possess an historical consciousness that is aware of its own embeddedness in the traditions they study and critical of conditions of the present whose origins and histories they can recount. In a large sense they have an understanding of their culture that is based on how it came to be and a sense of where it may be headed. A knowledge of this kind is elusive and difficult to quantify, yet it is also among the highest achievements of education in the human sciences.
Notes 1. This caricature has been given new life by two recent books, Henry Edmondson’s John Dewey and the Decline of American Education (Wilmington: ISI Books, 2006) and Kieran Egan’s Getting It Wrong From the Beginning (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002).
Teaching History: The Past and the Present
2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32.
33. 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. 39. 40.
279
All the standard misreadings are repeated here, including that on Dewey’s view history ought to be stricken altogether from the curriculum. No textual support for this misinterpretation is provided by either author, presumably because Dewey never wrote this, nor did he imply or believe it. Dewey, ‘History for the Educator’ (1909). MW 4: 192. Ibid., 192. Ibid., 192. Dewey, ‘Bankruptcy of Modern Education’ (1927). LW 3: 278. Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991), 104. Dewey, ‘Education from a Social Perspective’ (1913). MW 7: 125. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 221–2. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 70. Dewey, ‘Education from a Social Perspective’ (1913). MW 7: 125. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 70, 71. Dewey, ‘Social Value of Courses’, Educational Lectures Before Brigham Young Academy (1902). LW 17: 318. Dewey, ‘The Future of Philosophy’ (1947). LW 17: 467–8. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 51. Dewey, ‘The School as Social Center’ (1902). MW 2: 88. Dewey, ‘Current Tendencies in Education’ (1917). MW 10: 118. Dewey, ‘Democracy and Education in the World of Today’ (1938). LW 13: 301. Dewey, ‘History for the Educator’ (1909). MW 4: 192–3. Dewey, ‘The Way Out of Educational Confusion’ (1931). LW 6: 87. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 147–8, 147. Dewey, Moral Principles in Education (1908). MW 4: 282. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 70–1. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 59. Dewey, ‘Ethical Principles Underlying Education’ (1897). EW 5: 60–1. Ibid., 72. Dewey, ‘The Moral Significance of the Common School Studies’ (1909). MW 4: 208. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 15. Dewey, ‘Conscription of Thought’ (1917). MW 10: 277–8. Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920). MW 12: 132. Similar statements are found, for instance, in LW 6: 12, LW 8: 301, LW 12: 159, and LW 13: 329. Dewey, Experience and Nature (1925). LW 1: 40. Michel Foucault, ‘Polemics, Politics, and Problemizations: An Interview with Michel Foucault’, in The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York: Pantheon, 1984), 384. Foucault, ‘On the Genealogy of Ethics: An Overview of Work in Progress’, in Hubert L. Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow, Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983), 231. Foucault, ‘The Subject and Power’, in Dreyfus and Rabinow, Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 208. Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Vintage, 1979), 30–1. Foucault, ‘Nietzsche, Genealogy, History’, in The Foucault Reader, 76–7. Foucault, ‘What Is Enlightenment?’, in The Foucault Reader, 46. Foucault, ‘Nietzsche, Genealogy, History’, 76. Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977, ed. Colin Gordon, trans. C. Gordon et. al. (New York: Pantheon Books, 1972), 81, 82. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 194, 27. See especially Dewey, Freedom and Culture (1938) in LW 13.
Chapter 9
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative It is a curious fact that while Dewey held literature and the arts in very high regard, his educational writings contain remarkably few references to and no sustained discussion of a literary education. Not a single essay is devoted to this theme, leaving us to infer from his writings on some related topics what a Deweyan conception of education in this field would be like. Indeed, one of the more interesting remarks Dewey would offer on the subject, in an early essay of 1898, finds him resisting the trend of that time toward the ‘primary-education fetish’ – a trend that was stressing the importance of learning to read, write, and gain an acquaintance with literature in the first three years of primary school – precisely on grounds of literature’s importance: The plea for the predominance of learning to read in early school life because of the great information attaching to literature seems to me a perversion. Just because literature is so important, it is desirable to postpone the child’s introduction to printed speech until he is capable of appreciating and dealing with its genuine meaning.1 Dewey was well aware of the formative influence of literature and of the extent to which ‘[t]he real child . . . lives in the world of imaginative values and ideas’, yet the implications of this for the teaching and learning of literary works and the aims that properly orient the practice would remain largely unremarked.2 The aim of this chapter, accordingly, is to identify these implications by relating Dewey’s various remarks on this subject and a few related issues, thus articulating a Deweyan philosophy of education as it pertains to literature. Following the structure of the previous chapters, I shall also bring this philosophy into contact with some more recent views on narrative, particularly those of Paul Ricoeur, in an effort to advance a step or two beyond Dewey’s position. I should indicate here that by ‘literature’ I am referring not to the broader connotation of the word – a category that can encompass the written word in general – but to works of fiction in particular: essentially novels, short stories, plays, and poetry. In doing so my intent is neither to resort to 280
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
281
definitional stipulation nor to deny that other senses of the word exist and ought to exist. Literature as we speak of it today is a word that came into common use in the nineteenth century, particularly in educational contexts as the classical canon was beginning to be replaced with texts in the students’ native language. What, the question became, is to replace the great texts of Greece and Rome in the transition from a classical to a national education? A word was needed that would allow us to distinguish those works of one’s native culture that were asserted to be worthy of inclusion in the curriculum from those that were not, and ‘literature’ seemed to fit this purpose. It thus acquired an honorific connotation and one not limited to fictional works. The word, however, has never had an uncontested definition and I have no intention of introducing one here. My purpose in speaking of literature in the narrow sense is to suggest that the aims that properly orient the teaching of fictional texts is a distinct question from the aims of teaching history, philosophy, science, and other disciplines that are often included under the umbrella of literature in its broad sense. If we would not only include works of fiction in the curriculum but, as I shall argue, grant them a more central place than the current fashion prefers – dominated as it is by the sciences and mathematics under the influence of political and economic imperatives – then we must provide a rationale for this view which elucidates what it is about literature that is properly educational. Fictional works impart little by way of informational knowledge that students will find useful in later life, and arguments to the contrary proffered by educational conservatives do a disservice to literature by reducing its importance to practical use-value. Whatever its educational significance consists in, it extends far beyond Hirsch’s cultural literacy or Bloom’s canon for the canon’s sake to include its power to enrich human experience in a way more profound and enduring than we usually believe. Literature forms us, as do the arts in general, and its educational importance can be satisfactorily understood only when we have realized the manner and extent to which this is so. The formative influence of literature is a phenomenon that Plato taught us to see and of which Dewey was also well aware, even if he did not make it a major theme in his writings on education. It is an idea that the Bildung tradition in philosophy would also emphasize, and an idea that accords well with the conception of experience that Dewey defended. Experience and literature, life and narrative, must be thought in their mutuality in order that the educational aim might be made explicit. This is the hypothesis of the present chapter. Encountering literature is indeed a form of inquiry in Dewey’s sense, yet in a manner that surpasses its more straightforward forms. The truth into which we are inquiring here is the truth of the human condition itself, in an expansive sense of the phrase. Literature teaches by informing us, to be sure, and of matters difficult to
282
Education in the Human Sciences
fathom by other means. More important, it teaches by forming and transforming us. As Dewey would write in Democracy and Education, ‘Ideas are not segregated, they do not form an isolated island. They animate and enrich the ordinary course of life.’ These ideas include ‘the cultural products – especially the literary products – of man’s history’.3 The connection of experience and education was Dewey’s constant theme, and the educational importance of literature can be understood in this light. Literature illuminates experience in a richer, more nuanced way than non-literary discourses can achieve; its descriptions of life reveal meaning in ways that are personal and poignant, that relate complex themes to particular characters and situations, and that bring out precisely that which makes our experience humanly significant. Literary language discloses meaning in a way that far transcends informational knowledge, that reaches into the depths of life and leaves the reader a changed being. Experience as Dewey spoke of it ‘means living’; it is not only an abstract philosophical concept and not something that takes place apart from the ‘environing medium’ of social life.4 To be understood concretely, it is best regarded from the inside, as it were, as it is lived by characters real or imagined in their interactions with the world. While Dewey did not develop this argument in the detail for which it calls, he did set down the principles in terms of which this might be done, beginning with the appeal to the students’ existing interests. Nothing (or almost nothing) attracts the interest of both young and old like a good story well told. Whether we are speaking of children’s story time or more mature efforts in literary interpretation, narrative possesses an appeal that is both universal and profound, particularly on the part of the young who are typically more at home in the realm of imagination than those more mature in years. Minds utterly indifferent in the face of mathematics or science can become deeply enamored with literary works, and educators often have no trouble awakening an interest in such works – provided that they connect with students’ experience and not be incompetently taught. Likening an appropriate curriculum to food, Dewey wrote: The child is not waiting passively to take in experience. He is looking for experiences, and in every moment of his waking life, he shows this original and spontaneous eagerness to get more experience, and become acquainted with the world of things and of people about him. . . . What the teacher or parent has to do, is just to supply proper objects and surroundings upon which these impulses may assert themselves, so that the child may get the most out of them. The child supplies the hunger but he does not supply the food.5
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
283
Choosing literary works that satisfy this hunger may have less to do with identifying ‘age-appropriate’ material as educational psychology currently understands the phrase than with texts in which students take a spontaneous interest. Whether we are speaking of children or young adults, all reading is good reading provided that it engages students’ minds (not only their educators) and that there is something in the texts that is worthy of such engagement, something that surpasses entertainment or amusement. The connection with experience is imperative since in the absence of this connection there is very little motivation for students to take genuine interest in what they are studying, and the subject will appear as an external imposition that gets in the way of everything vital in experience. ‘The principle of interest’, as Dewey remarked, ‘is often abused by being reduced to the concept of amusement, or making something interesting.’ That this is a distortion of the principle is important to emphasize given the frequency with which this idea has been mistakenly identified with soft pedagogy. ‘Complete, or organic interest’, he continued, ‘is realized only when the child puts his entire self into his activity. His activity, even if comparatively trivial, objectively considered, must appeal to the child as worth while, as genuine work.’6 It is as futile to teach Shakespeare to the intellectually immature as to expect entertaining but vacuous material to create a love of literature. For this happy result to occur, the students’ capacities must be engaged; they must in a genuine sense be working, and on something of which they can see the relevance – which always means the experiential relevance – themselves. The relevance of literature to life is self-evident to anyone with a basic competence in this area and whose literary education was not marred by poor instruction or ill-chosen material. As Dewey expressed it, the value of literary works for education ‘lies in their use to increase the meaning of the things with which we have actively to do at the present time’, especially as this pertains to the ‘continuous reconstruction of experience’.7 Literature possesses the unique ability both to plumb the depths of human experience and, in the case of the novel, to capture something of its breadth or temporal extension as well. Experience in Dewey’s organic sense of the word extends over a considerable portion of time, in contrast with older empiricist views which had spoken of experiences as discrete units. Experience also has a consummatory nature, as is evident when we speak of having ‘an’ experience. An experience in this sense is contrasted with the inchoate and unfulfilled, that which fails to run its course to completion. Experience that is halting and discordant Dewey contrasted with that which over time achieves a resolution to the felt difficulty from which it arose. A conflict resolved, a difficulty disposed of, a project brought to completion are so many experiences in this sense. It is the dimension of human experience that is ‘a consummation and
284
Education in the Human Sciences
not a cessation’ to which the literary narrative does justice since it is here that the long-term consequences of our actions and the implications of the webs that we weave are depicted in personal and detailed ways. Dewey’s ‘experiential continuum’ derives from James’ ‘stream of consciousness’, as we have seen.8 Phenomenologically speaking, our experience reaches forward in time; it leads from one event to the next while connecting with experiences of the past which provide it with an orientation and purposiveness. An experience may be a means to an end, a result, or a turning point; it may foreshadow future experiences, constitute a beginning or an ending, or otherwise fit into a larger temporal configuration. In any event, it does not stand on its own but ‘flows constantly forward’ and at times culminates in a conclusion or consummation.9 Dewey’s examples include aesthetic experiences as well as resolutions of a more mundane kind: In the hearing of the musical theme, the earlier stages are far from being mere means to the later; they give the mind a certain set and dispose it to anticipate later developments. So the end, the conclusion, is not a mere last thing in time; it completes what has gone before; it settles, so to speak, the character of the theme as a whole. In the ball game, the interest may intensify with every passing stage of the game; the last inning finally settles who wins and who loses, a matter which up to that time has been in suspense or doubt. In the game, the last stage is not only the last in time, but also settles the character of the entire game, and so gives meaning to all that has preceded.10 For Dewey, the idea of culmination points to the essence of aesthetic experience in particular, a theme that he treated explicitly in Art as Experience. These are experiences that are important and stand out from the ordinary course of events in that they constitute a fulfilment of what has gone before and are complete unto themselves. Characterizing every experience as organic means that it presses continually forward, is thoroughly connected with other experiences and with an environment, and is a process that reaches periodic culminations and new beginnings. All of this – the larger swath of human experience in all its connections and significance – is what literature makes apparent, and in ways that resonate within and transform readers. Interpreting a literary work involves precisely the search for connections that for Dewey characterizes experience in general but raised to a higher level. How one passage or episode relates to another, how the significance of the narrative as a whole emerges from the parts, how a theme relates to the reader’s own life, and so on, is the business of the kind of inquiry that is literary interpretation, although it is a kind in which Dewey himself showed far less interest than inquiry in its more overtly
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
285
scientific forms. The experimental frame of mind that Dewey prized is called for in the encounter with literature no less (likely more) than in scientific contexts, while the broadening and deepening of experience that this encounter brings about is the truest indicator of its educational importance. Among the achievements of a literary education is undoubtedly the kind of moral knowledge or social intelligence of which Dewey so often wrote. As I discussed in Chapter 8, Dewey regarded history as having a special importance in the cultivation of this kind of knowledge, yet he was not unaware of literature’s role here as well. If history demonstrates the complexity of human affairs and the successes and failures of our designs, surely literature is capable of doing the same. In my view it even surpasses history in this respect since it is in the works of the great novelists and poets that we come to understand experience from the inside, as it were, rather than from the distanced perspective of the historian. Here the reader is called upon to respond with intelligence and emotion (particularly empathy), to transpose oneself in imagination into the point of view of the characters, to see through their eyes, and to resolve their conflicts in a more immediate and personal way than in historical inquiry. Social intelligence, which Dewey defined as ‘the power of observing and comprehending social situations’ with an eye to resolving conflicts and remedying moral difficulties, is best learned when such situations are described in their full complexity to a reader who does not look on from a distance but identifies in a more intimate way with the characters undergoing them.11 We live out their conflicts, experience their joys and frustrations, and urge them in this direction or that. We draw lessons from their trials, appropriate certain of their ideas and traits, apply the meaning that emerges from their lives to our own, in the process becoming changed in our own way of being. That literature happens in the imagination rather than in real life is no drawback for education. Much that is genuinely educative pertains to the inwardness of the young, to the formation of habits and sensibilities that go beyond the outwardly useful. Indeed, much that is outwardly useful, including the cultivation of moral knowledge, has its basis precisely here: in the realm of inwardness and imagination, in the comprehension of human nature and the intangibles of life to which literature and the arts provide access. How better to learn the skill of moral deliberation than to experience first-hand the conflicts of a Raskolnikov or an Alyosha Karamazov; how better to learn something about personal transformation than to transpose oneself into the point of view of Jean Valjean? As important as history and other branches of the human sciences undoubtedly are in this respect, none surpasses literature in understanding human experience in its manifold richness and complexity. Fundamental to the educative process is that the subject matter lift the
286
Education in the Human Sciences
students out of their immediate circumstances and introduce them to experiences and ways of thinking that connect with their own while also getting them to see farther and to see differently. This is how transformation happens, by getting beyond the parochial and familiar and by leading the mind from what it has known to what it might yet know. If, as Dewey in a Hegelian mood put it, ‘thought lives, moves, and has its being in and through symbols, and, therefore, depends for meaning upon context as do the symbols’, it is in the literary work that symbols and context come into their own, particularly those that touch on the more ultimate questions of human existence.12 Literature, for instance, elicits emotional responses that the young have yet to experience in ordinary life. It initiates them into difficulties and subtleties of an experience more mature than their own and so educates the imagination. The relevance of literature to the imagination may be seen in Dewey’s description of the latter in Art as Experience: Yet if we judge its nature from the creation of works of art, it designates a quality that animates and pervades all processes of making and observation. It is a way of seeing and feeling things as they compose an integral whole. It is the large and generous blending of interests at the point where the mind comes in contact with the world. When old and familiar things are made new in experience, there is imagination.13 It is not difficult to see the manner in which literature educates the imagination and our understanding of the human condition in a more general way. Whether or not literature educates in the narrow sense of imparting informational knowledge – knowledge that is likely communicable in nonliterary language – or in another sense, literature undoubtedly educates. It teaches in ways that are primarily illustrative, indirect, impressionistic, and specific to particular characters in particular situations but that are no less important for that. It is hardly deniable that Dostoyevsky’s Crime and Punishment educates the moral imagination or that Orwell’s 1984 educates the social intelligence of readers, yet less obvious is the precise sense in which this is so. Has Orwell pronounced a valid critique of authoritarianism, a critique that might equally have found expression in a treatise in political theory? Has he resolved one of Dewey’s ‘problems of men’? Likely so, although this understates Orwell’s accomplishment. Has Dostoyevsky advanced a possibly true hypothesis about morality or criminal psychology? Perhaps, yet one senses that this way of formulating the question misses the point. That point is that literature educates the moral imagination, social intelligence, or some similar capacity. It does so by acquainting readers with points of view not their own and with experiences that they might not otherwise have, by undergoing ‘felt difficulties’ from the inside, as it were,
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
287
deliberating about what is to be done, and seeing first hand the consequences of human action. The reader rehearses dramatic situations in imagination while capacities of interpretation, emotional responsiveness, and deliberation are set to work. The relevance for literary studies of the following remarks from Democracy and Education is thus abundantly clear: Just as the senses require sensible objects to stimulate them, so our powers of observation, recollection, and imagination do not work spontaneously, but are set in motion by the demands set up by current social occupations. The main texture of disposition is formed, independently of schooling, by such influences. What conscious, deliberate teaching can do is at most to free the capacities thus formed for fuller exercise, to purge them of some of their grossness, and to furnish objects which make their activity more productive of meaning.14 It is not only the ‘powers of observation, recollection, and imagination’ that the encounter with literature educates but habits of reflection, deliberation, and understanding in a broad sense. Most higher capacities of mind are called into play in the interpretation of literary works, in classroom discussion and written work that elucidates their themes and relates these to the students’ own lives. If understanding the complexities of life is our goal – whether we are speaking of matters of love, social situations, moral deliberation, existential choice, or what have you – no better vehicle exists than great literature, where attention is sustained beyond the range of the moment by complex literary descriptions of experience. The descriptions of a Dostoyevsky or a Tolstoy do far more than convey socially useful information, as E. D. Hirsch would say; they teach us how to see and feel, how to pay attention to human beings and to see more deeply into life. They compel reflection, often for the first time, on the meaning of our experiences. It is this reflection that leaves us transformed and more open to experience. The sustained duration of the literary narrative contributes to what Dewey called the continuity of experience, the criterion – along with the principle of interaction – in virtue of which an experience is properly educative. It is the nature of experience, as we have seen, to lead toward further experiences, to take on a momentum that carries the mind from the familiar to the novel, from the narrow to the broad, and from the concrete to the abstract. Educative experiences are those that lead beyond themselves and hang together with a larger configuration of ideas. The interconnectedness of experience that Dewey brought to our attention is best illustrated in the novel. It is here that connections at once subtle, nuanced, and potentially transformative may be seen in realistic detail, that complex themes are
288
Education in the Human Sciences
played out over a span of time and meaning emerges on the basis of active interrogation of the text. An education that prizes what Dewey called ‘the power of reflective attention’, meaning ‘the power to hold problems, questions, before the mind’ in a thoughtful and unhurried way, and that values ‘depth and slowness’ over hasty superficiality, finds perhaps its most advanced lessons precisely here, where easy answers are nowhere to be found and genuine understanding requires looking beyond surface meanings.15 If ‘the first product of schooling’, as Dewey expressed it, is the ‘inclination to learn from life itself’, where better is life in the sense of lived experience presented in its manifold richness than in the literary work? The fact that such works present us with a fictional world rather than the ‘real world’ of common parlance should not cause us to overlook that it is life that literature and art in general depict, and in a manner that calls upon the reader to abandon the role of spectator or passive recipient of information and to become alive to the connections and meanings of which our experience is replete. Literature does not transport us into a fantasy world of escapism but acquaints us precisely with the real world in ways that the real world itself, studied in scientific and practical ways, often cannot. If it is practical matters with which we are concerned, nothing is more practical than ‘the ability to learn from experience’, if by this we understand ‘the power to retain from our experience something which is of avail in coping with the difficulties of a later situation’.16 In the rage to prepare students for the practical life that awaits them, we cannot overlook that this very preparation includes far more than what goes under the name of useful information, and includes powers of perception and judgment, intellectual habits of reflection and creativity, and the ability – unfortunately rare – to learn from others’ mistakes. This last value, supposing one were to attempt to instill it directly, is not taught and learned through preaching but only by the indirect route of acquainting students with all the foibles of the human character and the consequences to which they lead. By this means, the students’ powers of judgment are enhanced; if one learns to judge by judging then let one judge how this character should have acted in this complex situation, what led to their downfall, and what we might have done in their place. Let them reflect on the lessons learned from the ancient tragedies that are of universal human importance or on modern works that relate more directly to the experience of students. In either case, provided such narratives be of sufficient quality that there is something there to interpret, a degree of worldly understanding might be attained as one becomes habituated to engaging with quality prose, interpreting meaning, drawing conclusions, and forming judgments. Knowing how to negotiate the complexities of life, and to learn from experience itself, is among the highest achievements of a literary education, and it is a knowledge to which great literature is especially well suited.
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
289
If Dewey was correct in his observation that ‘[t]he natural tendency of man is not to press home a doubt, but to cut inquiry as short as possible’, what better means do we have than literature of countering this tendency, of slowing down the mind when need be and sifting ambiguities of perception, negotiating complexities, and allowing a doubt to sink in before we hasten toward a solution?17 Inquiry reaches a bad end when the difficulty that occasioned it is inadequately perceived due to impatience. Literature teaches precisely this kind of patience – in lingering over descriptions and attending to details which modern life, with its propensity for haste, would have us pass over. The classic Russian novel, for instance, which stretches on for hundreds of pages while ‘nothing happens’, instructs the reader in the art of perception and the careful attention to detail that it requires. I can think of no better method of educating perception and moral imagination than reading War and Peace or The Brothers Karamazov, taking up their themes in classroom discussion and writing interpretive essays. Nor has a better method been devised of teaching students to think differently. As Dewey so often pointed out, intelligent thought requires the cultivation of habits – of reflectiveness, patience, open-mindedness, and so on – and the ability to modify habits when necessary. Very often it requires students to re-examine habitual attitudes and to see the world differently than in the received ways of parental and cultural influences. ‘Very early in life,’ as Dewey noted, ‘sets of mind are formed without attentive thought, and these sets persist and control the mature mind.’ These habits can be remarkably resistant to change and ‘unget-at-able’ by educators.18 If they are to be gotten at, it is most likely to be by means of the imagination and by enlisting the senses in the way that literature is able to do rather than in the manner of a frontal assault. Students must at times be taught to see their world differently – with greater flexibility or precision, with attention to historical contingency and without false certainty – and it is here that literature can act as a guide, leading them from familiar experience to what is unfamiliar, more complex or nuanced. Literary education aims as well at educating taste, so that students will be capable of spending their leisure time in more profitable ways than they otherwise might. One of Dewey’s worries was the ways in which the leisure time of young and old alike was becoming increasingly dominated by popular forms of entertainment and mindless amusement, a trend that has of course continued to gain momentum in more recent decades. As he wrote, ‘We must develop a taste in science or art, not only for those who are going to be scientists or artists, but also for those who, when leisure time comes, will be interested in reading or hearing about something of nature, or literature, or have a capacity to enjoy music and the drama.’19 Concerns about an apparent deterioration in taste are nothing new in our time, or in Dewey’s, but it was a concern that he shared. As many have done, he looked
290
Education in the Human Sciences
to education for a remedy, hoping that literature and the other arts, competently taught, would instill taste and interests more refined than what had become the norm. We have had occasion to see throughout this study the manner in which Dewey’s philosophy of education coheres with his pragmatic experimentalism and how he would always insist on connecting the curriculum with students’ experience. Stated in such terms, it can appear that Dewey gave us a conception of education that is excessively practical, one in which an interest in theory or literature for its own sake is misguided and even the cultivation of taste is valued only insofar as it brings about a more profitable use of free time than empty amusement. There may be a grain of truth in this view, but I would suggest not more than a grain. An education in taste and perception undoubtedly serves practical ends, yet Dewey also insisted that education is properly an end in itself. He would also write in How We Think that ‘[t]here is such a thing, even from the common-sense standpoint, as being “too practical”, as being so intent upon the immediately practical as not to see beyond the end of one’s nose or as to cut off the limb upon which one is sitting’. It is an issue of the limits of the practical and its connections with that which appears to transcend it: the theoretical, aesthetic, or intellectual. His point is that there are more such connections than meet the eye, that the art of perception which literature educates has moral consequences, that taste appropriately cultivated does not turn us into aesthetes but gives us a range of vision larger than it might otherwise be. Truly practical men give their minds free play about a subject without asking too closely at every point for any advantage to be gained. Exclusive preoccupation with matters of use and application narrows the horizon and in the long run defeats itself. It does not pay to tether one’s thoughts to the post of use with too short a rope.20 All the habits of mind about which Dewey cared and which an education in any branch of the human sciences aims to impart have their practical uses, even if this is not always self-evident. These uses account in part for their educational value, but it is a mistake to regard education in any of these fields as a mere means to an end. The process of cultivating the mind, Dewey always maintained, requires no justification outside of the process itself. The worldly uses of a literary education are not inconsiderable, but the cultivation of taste or imagination is an end in itself, something vital in the life of the mind, whether one puts it to use in narrowly practical ways (one can always teach) or not. The fact that university English departments have produced their share of useless degrees might well be a mark in their favor. Here, as well as in departments of art, drama, music, and so on, one will still
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
291
find unapologetic spokespersons for the arts who well understand both the practical and impractical dimensions of their field and its contribution to students’ lives. All such disciplines are ill served by spokespersons or marketing pitches that make exaggerated claims about practical use-value, their true value lying in the power of vision and imagination that they cultivate. Indeed, miseducation in its many forms often stems from the view that the curriculum must directly serve practical ends in a sense narrower than what Dewey spoke of, that ultimately its purpose is to prepare students for the life that awaits them upon graduation. Usually of course this means the life of economic production and little besides. Hence the ubiquitous question asked of all students of literature and the arts: ‘What are you going to do with your degree?’ Let us think about this question and what it presupposes. There is the clear assumption that only tangible matters count, that an answer that speaks of the virtues of mind alone – still more as ends in themselves – will not do. There is also the assumption that education not only is a means to an end but that the end in question is gainful employment. These assumptions are readily understandable in courses of study with a clearly practical orientation, but that they apply everywhere is a different proposition. In one fashion or another, what looks from a Deweyan point of view like miseducation typically proceeds on these assumptions – that students who do not retain the right information in the right quantity will have no future in the labor market, or that they will lack the ‘cultural literacy’ that is another name for economic readiness and cultural sameness. That ‘things of the spirit do not lend themselves easily to that kind of external inspection which goes by the name of examination’ – still less standardized examination concerned with memorized information – is an insight of Dewey’s that we would do well to bear in mind.21 Being intangibles, matters of the spirit transcend examination in its more straightforward, quantitative forms at least. The multiple-choice examination, for instance, is a travesty in the study of literature for the same reasons as in other fields of the human sciences: it fails utterly to get beneath the surface of things and to test the students’ understanding of what they read. Things of the spirit likewise transcend informational knowledge and what the excessively practical minded intend by good education. Hirsch is an example of this latter group. What might have given cultural literacy some plausibility is that as a slogan it conjures up images of all that constitutes higher culture and brings them into proximity with literacy in its ordinary connotation – the ability to read and write. The culturally literate, one might think, are those with a broad and perhaps deep understanding of the culture of which they are a part – until we learn what Hirsch intends by the phrase. Where the study of literature is concerned, it should be obvious that the kind of learning that takes place far transcends factual knowledge or
292
Education in the Human Sciences
anything that can be measured by a multiple-choice test. It is a remarkable fact that the founder of cultural literacy was himself a professor of literature, considering that all that makes literature worthy of academic study in the first place and all that makes it of profound human importance is precisely that which cannot be quantified and reduced to the order of informational knowledge. When Walter Scott penned the words ‘Oh what a tangled web we weave . . .’ he was not merely informing us that deception was commonly considered a vice in nineteenth-century Scotland, or for that matter that it actually was or still is such a vice. Nor when Alyosha Karamazov tells a group of children after a funeral they have just attended that ‘we shall certainly rise and we shall certainly all meet again’ was Dostoyevsky merely informing his readers of his personal belief in the immortality of the soul. Reducing the richness and complexity of literary art to chunks of information that may be useful for practical purposes misses the point of literature altogether. Why else would we view with disdain the habit some students have of reading Sparknotes rather than the works themselves? Is this not a more efficient method of gaining information about a literary work than actually reading it? Straightforward plot summaries combined with thematic analysis are more than adequate for purposes of cultural literacy, unless we mean by the phrase something far richer than what Hirsch intended. Were we to devise a formula for miseducation in literature, it would be precisely to reduce the subject matter to so much testable information, the result of which is students believing they have learned what is essential so long as they attain a high grade. It would be to make it possible to achieve outward success while failing to understand what literature actually teaches, how to interpret it, and its power to transform our lives. Miseducation also occurs when students have the wrong kind of experiences with literature, and as a result become put off by the whole business. Even great literature when poorly taught, or taught to minds too young to appreciate it, can be miseducative if it renders students callous to literature in general. Teaching Shakespeare in the ninth grade, for instance, is more likely to create a lasting aversion than genuinely to engage the fourteen-year-old mind. (My own recollections of being force-fed Shakespeare in the ninth grade are perfectly dreadful, as I am sure are those of my former classmates. Likely not one of us understood what we were reading, and not only on account of poor instruction.) Miseducation also occurs when students are given to believe that there is only one way to interpret a literary work – generally the educator’s. This still common practice is objectionable on both hermeneutical and educational grounds. In principle, there is no interpretation of a text that is uniquely and supremely authoritative since meaning is experienced by different readers and generations of readers differently and is contingent on the practical
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
293
interests, point of view, and cultural heritage that readers bring with them in interpretation.22 One can read well or badly, of course, but this never means that in the former case one ascertains the objective truth – perhaps, as Hirsch also believes, by discovering the author’s intention – while in the latter one does not. The Deweyan objection to this practice is less hermeneutical than educational: the nature of education is to inquire, and to do so without presupposing that anyone, be it teacher or student, possesses special insight into the truth. In literary interpretation, for instance, we are inquiring on a common basis into the meaning(s) of a text. As an inquirer, the educator will undoubtedly have a view, and often an eminently well-founded one, yet Dewey’s point is that no matter how much of an expert the educator becomes, he or she does not stand above the fray of inquiry but must submit interpretations in a fallibilist spirit and allow students to examine their merits. Students must never be put in the role of spectators or passive recipients of information that has been altogether predigested. A related form of miseducation finds the teacher in the role of zealot, whether it be in service to a particular literary theory, a political ideology, or what have you. An important example of this is the political correctness phenomenon which has had a ruinous effect on education everywhere it has been practiced, and nowhere more so than in the study of literature. What this movement fails to realize is that from an educational standpoint it matters not at all whether the orthodoxy one would instill is of the left or the right, whether it is political or religious, or for that matter whether it is true or false. Orthodoxy and indoctrination in all their forms are anathema from the standpoint of inquiry. Teaching students to be critical does not mean transforming them into crusaders of ‘anti-oppression’ or disciples of one kind or another. It does not mean seeing to it that students adopt a particular way of thinking but that whatever views they uphold can be backed up with intelligent arguments. The well-educated mind is flexible and searching; no matter the strength of its convictions, it remains resolutely open to any ideas that would challenge them. Political correctness has shown itself to be as heavy-handed and doctrinaire as any of the views that it opposes, and in educational settings has created an atmosphere less of ‘inclusiveness’ than of ideology and absolutism. Overheated debates regarding the politics of the canon have accomplished far less than is often claimed. What matters from an educational point of view is not whether the author of a literary work is male or female, black or white, or what have you, but whether their work speaks to the experience of students and, if properly interpreted, leads them beyond the parochial and mundane into a fictional world that can extend their horizons and leave them transformed. It is not the case that canonical works are inherently educational while non-canonical works are not, or vice versa. ‘There is no such thing’, as Dewey remarked, ‘as educational value in
294
Education in the Human Sciences
the abstract.’23 A text takes on such value when it serves the larger purposes of education, not when it serves the political designs of educators or governments. When the classroom becomes a battlefield in the culture wars and literature a tool of ‘political struggle’ and ‘resistance’, it is fairly certain that education will not be the result. Miseducation can take additional forms as well, of course, but these are a few of the more important forms that a Deweyan view can bring to light. Literary studies can also deteriorate into scholasticism and empty formalism. They can fail to connect with students’ experience and make the world of literature appear as a pompous form of escapism. They can cover too much ground too quickly, instilling habits of skimming and understanding texts only at a surface level. They can ask too little of students by presenting them with ready-made interpretations which students need not question or by not requiring them to develop a command of the language through written work. Other examples could be mentioned, but I shall stop here. What must now be examined, or re-examined, is the connection between life and literature that for Dewey accounts for the latter’s educational importance. There may be grounds for regarding this relation as still more intimate than Dewey believed.
Life as narrative A twentieth-century philosopher with whom Dewey has rather more in common than one might expect is Paul Ricoeur. While references to Dewey in Ricoeur’s writings are nowhere to be found, these two profoundly dialectical thinkers share much in terms not only of their substantive positions on certain issues but of the way in which these two figures habitually approached philosophical questions – by resolutely rejecting the standard dichotomies of modern thought and pursuing an essentially phenomenological inquiry which typically operates in the interstices of binary oppositions. Both thinkers preferred to speak of continuity over discontinuity, and when confronted with some polarity or other typically defended a position of both/and or neither/nor. This holds for both figures on the question of the relation between life and literature – Dewey, as we have seen, emphasizing the fundamental mutuality of the two, and Ricoeur, while arguing much the same, taking the argument a few steps beyond where Dewey left us. I wish therefore to bring Ricoeur’s argument into contact with Dewey’s own views, a line of thought that may render more explicit the connection between experience and narrative and thereby the purpose of a literary education. In what does the relation between the lived experience of students, or for that matter any human being, and narrative consist? A second question may give us a clue to the first: What explains the universal fascination with narra-
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
295
tives, whether they be fictional or non-fictional? In an age of science it should strike us as peculiar that while our ways of thinking and knowing are ever more beholden to the scientific and technological, the fascination with narrative has in no way diminished. Jean-François Lyotard has remarked that modern science has always existed in conflict with narrative, particularly if the latter is regarded as a form of knowledge.24 Literature, one might believe, is a means of entertainment or aesthetic pleasure, but if it is the truth that we would seek then we are going to find this within learned discourses that employ a method of some more or less scientific kind, not in a fantasy world of fiction. Storytelling and literary interpretation alike are not sciences but arts; neither employs a technique or requires special expertise, while both are matters at which some excel. Yet do these arts afford knowledge in the proper sense of the word? Following Ricoeur, I shall defend an affirmative answer to this last question; not only is there truth in literature – in art more generally – but it is a truth that resists translation into non-literary language. What is learned in the encounter with literature is who I myself am. Why this should be so is the question to which I now turn. ‘It has always been known’, as Ricoeur expressed it, ‘and often repeated that life has something to do with narrative.’25 There is no chasm separating the world of literature from that of human experience, or real life as it is called, but a continuity that is often overlooked. A human life, in Ricoeur’s words, is a ‘life in quest of narrative’. Richard Kearney offers a succinct clarification of the point: Every human existence is a life in search of a narrative. This is not simply because it strives to discover a pattern to cope with the experience of chaos and confusion. It is also because each human life is always already an implicit story. Our very finitude constitutes us as beings who, to put it baldly, are born at the beginning and die at the end. And this gives a temporal structure to our lives which seek some kind of significance in terms of referrals back to our past (memory) and forward to our future (projection). So that we might say that our lives are constantly interpreting themselves – pre-reflectively and pre-consciously – in terms of beginnings, middles and ends (though not necessarily in that order).26 Human life, in the language of existential phenomenology, is always already structured temporally and oriented by a set of finite possibilities of the kind of being that one might become. Self-understanding occurs in the manner in which one follows a narrative: by linking together our personal or shared past with an anticipated future, by interpreting present events in terms of larger wholes that supply meaning, by regarding intentions and actions as forming projects that unfold over time, and by configuring our existence as
296
Education in the Human Sciences
a whole as an intelligible succession of experiences. Who I am is the implied subject of what I have done and what has happened to me; it is also who I am in process of becoming, the possibilities and aspirations for which I am continually striving. The narrative theory of the self, as it has come to be called, emphasizes the literary and imaginative dimension of our being over our more ‘thingly’ nature – that which is the object of biological discourse. Without downplaying the latter, the narrative theory insists on the primacy of our lived experience of being subjects of a certain kind. When we wish to understand who someone is – meaning not what kind of entity they are or what distinguishes this from other forms of biological life but who is this human being standing before me – we know from ordinary experience that it is in learning ‘the story of their life’ that we gain an understanding of their identity. The same is true of our self-understanding; insofar as I know who I am – which is never an altogether given matter in experience and may indeed be something that eludes me – I have employed the narrator’s art in relating a life story with a beginning, middle, and anticipated end. Phenomenologically speaking, a narrative history is who I am since it is within this basic structure that the self is invariably understood and that it becomes possible to grasp together everything that one speaks of when one speaks of oneself, be it one’s gender, culture, ethnicity, and other identity markers or actions, experiences, psychological traits, values, beliefs, and so on. The principle of unity that underlies these disparate items is no metaphysical substance or deep core of being but a narrative history that supplies self-understanding and whatever meaning is possible in life. Narrative, accordingly, is not something to be limited to the realm of fiction but pervades our experience of ourselves and others, of history and culture, politics, and a great many areas of human life. It constitutes ‘the very structure of human acting and suffering’, as Ricoeur put it, in the sense that the narrator’s art takes the scattered events of one’s life and arranges them as episodes in a larger temporal sequence, the significance of which lies in their contribution to the whole. An action or experience is understood as in some fashion or other moving the story forward: as a continuation or departure from the past, as foreshadowing later events, as contributing to a project, and thus as more than an isolated occurrence. An action regarded in isolation from narrative is a meaningless unit of behavior, one that defies understanding as anything more than a physical motion of the organism. So conceived, it may be explained within a vocabulary of biology or physiological psychology, but it cannot be understood as a humanly significant occurrence. Ricoeur would speak of action as having a pre-narrative quality in the sense that it is symbolically mediated and gains whatever meaning it holds through its involvement in the larger thread of a story. Not itself a
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
297
narrative, an action can be regarded as a symbol or narrative fragment, and thus as reaching beyond itself. The simple act of looking someone in the eye, for instance, is a ‘quasi-text’ in that it may signify listening, a query, a reproach, a threat, an act of love, or a great many other meanings, depending on the persons involved and the circumstances in which it occurs.27 It therefore calls for interpretation in the manner of any symbol, its significance articulated with reference to norms and signs that allow us to distinguish the action from mere physical behavior. It becomes meaningful when interpreted as a particular narrative unit, in the way that a particular passage in a text gains its meaning from the larger context of the work as a whole and not in isolation. Whether we are speaking of particular actions and experiences or life as a whole, it is narrative that makes understanding possible. It is here that we find an explanation of the fascination, seemingly universal, with the narrative form: if a story is what I myself am, and if it is the form in which I always already understand my experience of the world, then what narratives acquaint me with is the possibilities of who I am and what my life might become. In the experience of literature it is I myself that I encounter, where the self is conceived invariably as a story that has yet to run its course. As a self-interpreting agent, the self is a work in progress every day of its life, suspended between birth and death. The characters about whom one reads are possible selves, whose traits one may selectively appropriate and with whose fate one may or may not relate. In reading a work of fiction one transports oneself in imagination into the world of the text and lives a life not one’s own; the reader sees the world through another’s eyes, and experiences their conflicts as one’s own. Their emotions and perceptions become the reader’s; their fate is regarded not with indifference but as an urgent matter and often a deeply personal one. Reading literature intelligently is not a matter of passive spectatorship but calls forth higher capacities of imaginative interpretation and emotional responsiveness. One must become, in imagination, the characters about whom one is reading, deliberate about their actions, and draw lessons from their lives. The ‘anchorage of the narrative in life’, as Ricoeur expressed it, ‘consists in what could be called the pre-narrative quality of human experience. It is due to this that we are justified in speaking of life as a story in its nascent state, and so of life as an activity and a passion in search of a narrative.’28 It is in search of many narratives in order ultimately to craft a story of one’s own and fashion oneself as at once the narrator and principal character of the story that one is. It has become something of a truism that one does not understand oneself in a social vacuum, yet nor does one do so in a literary vacuum. How many, for instance, continue to understand themselves in terms of a biblical narrative, the basic plot line of their lives being shaped by stories learned in
298
Education in the Human Sciences
childhood while the possibilities of who they might become are informed by a particular cast of ancient characters? Every believer knows which characters on whom they ought to model their lives, which characters not to become, what to aspire toward and what to condemn. The same is true of lovers of literature, popular culture, or narratives in general. Be it in its higher or lower forms, narrative affords the basic structure in which our self-understanding emerges and our lives gain a direction or orientation. It is in this way that we may appropriate Plato’s insight that narrative forms the soul and is a matter for educators and political rulers both to regard with great seriousness. Plato, of course, appealed to this insight in making the classical case for censoring the tales to which the young were to be exposed in his ideal city. The censorship issue is not one I shall take up here, but the insight itself is of enduring importance: the human character is profoundly influenced and indeed formed for good or ill by the narratives to which it is exposed, most obviously at an impressionable age, but not only then. It will not do, Plato reasoned, for guardians of the state to hear stories about heroes and gods acting in reprehensible ways lest they become reprehensible themselves, as they are likely to do. Tales about the gods in particular must depict the latter as virtuous in their deeds not only because they are virtuous in truth but because narratives depicting them as such mold the character in desirable ways. In phenomenological terms, narratives provide the self with possibilities of character and plot-lines that establish a preliminary set to one’s existence. While it overstates the point to say that one becomes what one reads – since there is always freedom in choosing which literary characters one shall emulate, in what ways and to what extent, and also because the human character is not formed by stories alone – it remains that the self is not a raw given but a malleable construction and self-construction of a kind, one that ‘becomes what it is’, as Nietzsche would say. It becomes this in continual interaction with its culture, including not least the products of literary culture by which it learns the various forms that our existence can take. It is a familiar experience, of course, to have one’s life and selfunderstanding profoundly transformed not only by experience but by vicarious experience of the kind that literature provides. Everyone, one might say, ought to have had their life changed profoundly by at least two or three great novels read carefully and at a mature age, rather than remain confined throughout life within storylines encountered in childhood. In important ways life does indeed imitate art, sometimes in reflective ways and sometimes unreflectively, at times by choice and at others through manipulation. Narratives that serve as mere vehicles of political or religious indoctrination for the young remain unfortunately commonplace and can pose as great an obstacle to maturity as the questionable beliefs that they instill. Children’s literature, for instance, that has been chastened by political cor-
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
299
rectness is potentially as harmful as the Cinderella stories it would replace, merely substituting one set of prejudices and force-fed opinions for another. Religious stories do much the same, instilling dogmas at an age when children are without the intellectual means of rejecting them. What Plato brought to our attention is the formative power of such narratives. It is tempting to regard this whole matter as a less than serious issue of child’s play or at most one of elementary moral education, yet the stories on which we are raised play an important role in the formation of personal identity and often remain with us throughout life. This is not an argument for the kind of political micromanagement of children’s stories that is the contemporary offspring of Platonic censorship, but it does give us reason to think twice about the narratives on which the young are raised. The importance of narrative to the formation of the self is made especially apparent in Ricoeur’s theory of subjectivity as temporally structured. In his words, Our own existence cannot be separated from the account we can give of ourselves. It is in telling our own stories that we give ourselves an identity. We recognize ourselves in the stories that we tell about ourselves. It makes very little difference whether these stories are true or false, fiction as well as verifiable history provides us with an identity.29 Following Ricoeur, Anthony Kerby would also defend ‘a model of the human subject that takes acts of self-narration not only as descriptions of the self but, more importantly, as fundamental to the emergence and reality of that subject ’.30 The moral implications of this ontological hypothesis are a matter that Alasdair MacIntyre has taken up, characterizing the good life as one spent in search of a narrative unity rather than the unrelated episodes that our lives can resemble. Moral agency is not a given but a kind of interpretive construction in which by means of the narrator’s art we configure our actions into a followable story for which we are ultimately responsible.31 Others as well have taken up this hypothesis, of course, although it is Ricoeur who provided it with perhaps its most adequate articulation and defense. Part of that defense finds him replying to an important objection regarding the close analogy Ricoeur proffered between narrative and life. The objection goes that there is not much of an analogy here at all for the straightforward reason that stories are told rather than lived and that life is lived rather than told. An ‘unbridgeable gap’ appears to separate the imaginative world of recounted narratives and the real world of human experience. Ricoeur’s response to this has two parts: first, that while narratives are indeed told, they are also in a meaningful sense lived by the reader; second, life is quite obviously lived, but it is also recounted. Let us look at the second
300
Education in the Human Sciences
claim first. In what sense is it true that our lived experience is told or recounted in the fashion of a story rather than simply lived? What the narrative theory of the self proposes is that there is an analogy, not an identity relation, between life and narrative, that our interest in stories is therefore rooted in our ontological condition as beings whose selfunderstanding is mediated by narrative interpretation. To claim that life is recounted, accordingly, is meant not to deny the self-evident truth that life is lived but to describe phenomenologically the manner in which it is lived. It is essentially by understanding itself and its world that the human being lives and copes with its experience. As Heidegger observed, the human being is a being-in-the-world, where the world is the lifeworld of language, culture, and a network of social practices that together represent our historical inheritance and that constitute us as beings of a particular kind. The human being, to this way of thinking, is not only a rational animal but an understanding animal, while its self-understanding takes the form of narrative: I am the person who did and experienced this, that, and the other thing, and who projects a future for myself that consists of a particular set of possibilities and aspirations. I am in short who I have been and who I expect to become. An unnarrated life is a life that is without self-understanding, and is as fully undesirable as what Socrates called the unexamined life, from which it little differs. As Ricoeur put it, ‘fiction contributes to making life, in the biological sense of the word, a human life’. Otherwise stated, ‘A life is no more than a biological phenomenon as long as it has not been interpreted. And in interpretation, fiction plays a mediating role.’32 Whether we are speaking of individual actions or experience as a whole, understanding happens when we are able to situate events within a temporal and narrative sequence which supplies the larger context of our lives. An unnarrated life would consist of a series of unrelated events, resembling more a chronicle than a history, and lacking a sense of direction. It is precisely when our lives are in this unnarrated condition that we complain that we no longer understand ourselves, that our lives have become disconnected and without purpose since there is no followable thread that connects our past with our present and future or that in some fashion draws together the different facets of our lives. The second part of Ricoeur’s reply to the objection is to state that, while narratives are indeed recounted, they are also lived. To see what Ricoeur meant by this we must consider for a moment his notion of emplotment. Fashioning a plot, we commonly think, is the work of the author alone, while the reader’s job is to follow the course of events as the author has arranged them. The error in this view is to underestimate the role of the reader not only in interpretation but in emplotment as well. Plot itself, in Ricoeur’s words, ‘is not a static structure but an operation, an integrating process, which . . . is completed only in the reader or in the spectator, that is to say,
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative
301
in the living receiver of the narrated story’. The operation of integrating events and characters into some meaningful configuration is the common work of the author and the reader, and requires from the latter a rather more active role than is usually supposed. It requires in the first place that the reader actively follow the story by grasping together the sequence of events and forming expectations of what is to come, which are adjusted and readjusted in light of what transpires. The apparently simple act of following a story is already a complex ‘synthesis of heterogeneous elements’, which interprets the many incidents, subplots, and interactions between characters as contributing to a unified story. Following along is thus ‘reactualizing the configuring act which gives [a narrative] its form’, and in this sense ‘completes the work’. Beyond this, reading a narrative requires that we relate the story to our own lives and indeed live vicariously through the characters. To say that literary interpretation calls forth the imagination means that readers must transpose themselves imaginatively into the world of the narrative. In reading Crime and Punishment one must live in nineteenth-century Russia and experience events as if they were happening to oneself. The ‘as if’ is essential here. The voluntary suspension of disbelief that is required of the reader requires not that we believe we are Raskolnikov but that it is as if we so believe and that what is happening to him is happening to ourselves. We do not stand back in imagination and remind ourselves at every turn that none of these events ever happened, this being the veritable antithesis of what is required. In aesthetic experience generally we speak of being transported into an alien world and ‘living in the fictive universe of the text . . . in the mode of the imaginary’.33 Further, the very meaning of the literary work is a product of the mediation that takes place between the text itself and the mind of the reader, and is not solely determined by the author. As with the process of emplotment, the text’s meaning is the joint product of the work of the author and the reader and emerges in the back and forth that takes place between the words on the page and the reader’s experience. Phenomenologically, there is no separation between the significance or sense of the narrative ‘in itself’ and its significance for the interpreter. Notwithstanding objectivist appeals to the author’s intentions, meaning, as Gadamer correctly noted, is not reducible to such intentions and ‘can be experienced even where it is not actually intended’.34 Sharing this view, Ricoeur would speak of a text’s meaning as ‘a mediation between man and the world, between man and man, between man and himself’, and thus as having ‘three dimensions: referentiality, communicability, and self-understanding’. This last value is of particular importance; the understanding that we gain in the experience of literature is at the same time a self-understanding. The insights that literature imparts are not impersonal truths but are related to the reader’s own life in ways that
302
Education in the Human Sciences
are potentially transformative. Fiction, as Ricoeur expressed it, ‘leads us back to life’; by a logic that is seemingly inescapable, what the reader learns in venturing into the world of the narrative is applied upon return to one’s own experience, leaving one in some way or other a changed being.35 One’s point of view or self-interpretation has been refashioned in some degree – provided, that is, the literary work is of some merit and that the reader has given it the attention it is due. The meaning of the work includes precisely its power to speak to the reader or to resonate within their experience in ways that an author may or may not have intended. In this sense narratives are indeed lived by the reader and not simply recounted. They are actively brought to life in imagination, configured and reconfigured, interpreted and applied to the reader’s experience, questioned and critiqued, and so completed by the reader. Herein lies the ultimate source of literature’s universal appeal as well as its educational significance: human experience and subjectivity itself are always already understood in temporal, narrative terms, insofar as they are understood at all. Gaining acquaintance with literature puts us in touch therefore not only with the culture to which we belong but with ourselves, and in ways that enrich our experience far beyond the simple acquisition of information. As Richard Kearney writes, ‘It is because of our belonging to history as storytellers and story-followers that we are interested by stories – in addition to being merely informed by facts.’36 If, as we so often hear, the aims of education include teaching students how to think about their world and about themselves in a sense that includes but also transcends the possession of useful information, no better vehicle for this exists than good stories well told. Here is where thinking in its highest reaches happens, lives are transformed, and education in the sense of Bildung comes into its own.
Notes 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11.
Dewey, ‘The Primary-Education Fetish’ (1898). EW 5: 264. Dewey, The School and Society (1899). MW 1: 37. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 169, 86. Dewey, ‘The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy’ (1917). MW 10: 7. Dewey, ‘How the Mind Learns’, Educational Lectures Before Brigham Young Academy (1901). LW 17: 215. Dewey, ‘Plan of Organization of the University Primary School’ (1895). EW 5: 228. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 86. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 17. Dewey, ‘Three Contemporary Philosophers’ (1920). MW 12: 210. Dewey, Interest and Effort in Education (1913). MW 7: 166–7. Dewey, Ethics (1908). MW 5: 285.
Teaching Literature: Life and Narrative 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24.
25.
26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31.
32. 33. 34.
35. 36.
303
Dewey, ‘Context and Thought’ (1931). LW 6: 5. Dewey, Art as Experience (1934). LW 10: 271. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 21. Dewey, ‘Teaching That Does Not Educate’ (1909). MW 4: 202; Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn, 1933). LW 8: 148. Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916). MW 9: 56, 49. Dewey, ‘Some Stages of Logical Thought’ (1900). MW 1: 151. Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (1922). MW 14: 71. Dewey, ‘Social Purposes in Education’ (1923). MW 15: 169. Dewey, How We Think (rev. edn 1933). LW 8: 296. Dewey, The Educational Situation (1901). MW 1: 271. This is not Dewey’s argument but one expressed in various ways in post-Heideggerian hermeneutics. Dewey, Experience and Education (1938). LW 13: 27. Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans. Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1979), xxiii. Paul Ricoeur, ‘Life in Quest of Narrative’, in On Paul Ricoeur: Narrative and Interpretation, ed. David Wood (New York: Routledge, 1991), 20. See as well Ricoeur’s Time and Narrative, vol. 1, trans. Kathleen McLaughlin and David Pellauer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984) and Oneself As Another, trans. Kathleen Blamey (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992). Richard Kearney, On Stories (New York: Routledge, 2002), 129. Ricoeur, ‘Life in Quest of Narrative’, 28, 29. Ibid., 29. Ricoeur, ‘History as Narrative and Practice’, Philosophy Today 29 (1979), 214. Anthony Kerby, Narrative and the Self (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1991), 4. Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984). Also see Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989) and William Lowell Randall, The Stories We Are: An Essay on Self-Creation (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1995). Ricoeur, ‘Life in Quest of Narrative’, 25, 20, 27. Ibid., 21, 27. Gadamer, ‘On the Scope and Function of Hermeneutical Reflection’, in Philosophical Hermeneutics, ed. and trans. David E. Linge (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1977), 30. Ricoeur, ‘Life in Quest of Narrative’, 27, 26. Kearney, On Stories, 154.
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 8
Index
acculturation, 2, 37, 43, 45, 46. Also see culture. aesthetic experience, 133, 136. Also see literary education. Arendt, Hannah, 222–31 Aristotle, 44, 56, 57, 60, 73, 150, 186, 224, 228, 229–30, 255 autonomy, 2, 3, 15, 21, 25. Also see freedom. Beiner, Ronald, 224 Bildung, 8, 22, 45, 46, 90–5, 281, 302 Bloom, Allan, 5, 16, 27–32, 48, 50n4, 50n20, 162 Bridges, David and Jonathon, Ruth, 24 Briton, Derek, 50n15 Burbules, Nicholas, 48 canon, 16, 28, 31, 32, 38, 47, 49, 281, 293 Caputo, John, 198–207 Carr, David, 15 conservative education, 13–49, 119, 183, 186 continuity and interaction, 72–5, 93, 162, 287–8 Copernican revolution, 52–95 corporate scientism, 20–21, 23, 24, 25, 27, 28, 47, 262 creativity, 5, 27, 157 critical thinking, 4, 16, 21, 30, 31, 37, 38, 44, 102, 118, 120, 140, 156, 157, 254, 261, 262, 271, 276. Also see thinking. culture, 8, 25, 30, 33, 35, 36, 45, 90, 94,
117, 118, 128, 168, 175, 185, 186, 187, 268, 269, 300. Also see acculturation; tradition. curiosity, 43, 44, 77, 78, 79, 160 Darling, John and Nordenbo, Sven Erik, 14, 49n2 Descartes, René, 61, 160 Dewey, John as dialectical thinker, 17, 19, 38, 39, 54, 67, 112 influence of, 19–20, 23 on democracy and education, 46, 79, 121, 150, 155, 190, 197, 213, 233–45 dialogue, 8, 42, 45, 46, 47, 48, 110, 111, 120–1, 134, 165, 166, 167, 197–198, 215, 246–55, 274 difference, 214, 244 discipline, 215–16, 232n17 Dostoyevsky, Fyodor, 285, 286, 287, 289, 292 Edmondson, Henry, 16, 20, 49n1, 50n4, 278n1 education as art, 25, 26, 46, 47 education as end, 26, 28, 44 education as means, 3, 22, 25, 27, 42, 76, 185, 196, 290, 291 education as science, 14, 15, 23, 25, 26, 46, 47 educational theory, 1, 6, 14, 21, 26, 41, 49, 52, 53, 93, 149–151, 184 educative process, 1, 3, 8, 25, 28, 38, 39–49, 52, 81, 233
305
306
Index
Egan, Kieran, 16, 49n1, 50n4, 278n1 empiricism, British, 61–2, 64, 93, 106, 110, 114 empiricism, radical, 62, 63, 64, 65, 93, 114, 268 Erfahrung, 81–95, 132, 138 Erlebnis, 81–95 ethical education, 210–31, 268, 285 experience, 3, 4, 8, 15, 19, 28, 37, 41, 43, 44, 52–95, 114, 118, 133, 159, 160, 203, 239, 262, 281, 283, 284. Also see Erfahrung; Erlebnis; experimental inquiry. experimental inquiry, 4, 8, 19, 40, 42, 43, 45, 59–75, 82, 104, 106, 106–20, 122, 128, 133, 134, 135, 136, 141, 189, 194, 214, 240, 241. Also see experience; thinking. expertise, 5, 23, 43, 132, 139, 241, 293 Foucault, Michel, 23, 260, 270–8 freedom, 25, 34, 71, 93, 103, 121, 122, 164, 165, 178, 179, 189, 194, 195, 215–16, 217, 236, 251. Also see autonomy. Freire, Paulo, 245–55, 274 Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 22–3, 42, 45, 46, 83–95, 136, 301. Also see hermeneutics. Gallagher, Shaun, 16, 51n43 Geertz, Clifford, 36 Good, James A., 51n45, 97n24 grades, 123–4, 269 Green, T. H., 63, 144n76 habit, 46, 62, 73–74, 98n49, 113, 191, 192, 289 Hegel, G. W. F., 8, 45–6, 62, 63, 90, 91, 172, 268 Heidegger, Martin, 5, 23, 28, 31, 50n20, 81–2, 85, 95, 107, 116, 117, 127, 128–42, 300 Herder, Johann Gottfried, 90 hermeneutics, 26, 36, 45, 117, 128,
129, 292. Also see Gadamer; Ricoeur. Hirsch, E. D., 28, 32–8, 48, 49n1, 50n4, 94, 140, 162, 258, 263, 287, 291, 292, 293 historical education, 221–2, 245, 257–78 historical sense, 265–6, 268, 269, 276, 277, 278 historically effected consciousness, 88–90 Hobbes, Thomas, 62 Hook, Sidney, 20 Hugo, Victor, 285 Humboldt, Wilhelm von, 90 Hume, David, 62 Husserl, Edmund, 124, 127 imagination, 118, 217–18, 220, 225, 228, 241, 267, 285–291, 297 inculcation and indoctrination, 2, 105, 123, 167, 184, 189, 191, 197, 206, 234, 235, 252, 293 information, 4, 7, 15, 16, 21, 22, 32, 33, 34, 35, 37, 40, 41, 43, 47, 54, 55, 105, 107, 236, 237, 263, 282, 292 intellectual agency, 5, 7, 8, 25. Also see intellectual virtues. intellectual virtues, 4, 48, 76–81, 111, 113, 167, 192, 193, 240, 264. Also see intellectual agency. interest, 19, 67, 68, 70, 98n39, 122, 239, 283 James, William, 47, 62, 63, 64, 97n28, 106, 108, 110, 111, 112, 124, 125, 126, 143n31, 284 Jaspers, Karl, 48 Jay, Martin, 82–3, 85, 90 Johnston, James Scott, 50n19, 99n69 judgment, 5, 48, 78, 79, 91, 215, 222–31, 237, 241, 253, 255, 288 Kant, Immanuel, 61, 127, 172, 219, 223–31
Index Kearney, Richard, 295, 302 Kerby, Anthony, 299 Kilpatrick, William H., 18, 39 Laboratory School, 18, 58 language, 116, 117, 118, 128, 129, 137, 186, 268, 300 literatary education, 29, 135–136, 280–302 Lyotard, Jean-François, 21–2, 27, 295 MacIntyre, Alasdair, 299 Marcel, Gabriel, 135, 145n88 method, 5, 23, 25, 27, 45, 49, 88, 102, 105, 108, 128, 130–2, 139, 140, 142, 157 Mill, John Stuart, 79, 223 Montessori, Maria, 99n63 Moore, G. E., 97n28, 106, 124 Morris, George Sylvester, 144n76 multiple-choice tests, 162, 269, 277–8, 291 mystery, 134–5, 141, 202 narrative, 86, 93, 280, 294–302 narrative self, 86, 294–302 neoliberalism, 245–6 Nietzsche, Friedrich, 28, 31, 50n20, 54, 127, 130, 137, 169–80, 272, 298 open-mindedness, 43, 46, 78, 81, 87, 89, 167, 293 Orwell, George, 286 outcomes, 21, 24, 26, 47 overspecialization, 79, 80, 119, 120, 154, 158, 168, 177, 259 participation, 4, 25, 31, 37, 43, 45, 46, 49, 89, 105, 121, 243, 254, 255 passion, 79, 200–1, 202, 204, 205 Peirce, C. S., 107, 110, 111, 112, 116, 143n30 performativity, 22, 26, 27, 41, 49, 139, 262 phenomenology, 6, 8, 9, 26, 36, 39, 43,
307
63, 64, 103, 117, 126, 186 philosophical education, 149–80 Plato, 1, 3, 45, 60, 73, 101, 134, 149–50, 166, 186, 233, 281, 298, 299 political correctness, 164, 253–4, 255, 268, 293, 298 political education, 233–55 postmodernism/poststructuralism, 36, 197–207 pragmatism. See experimental inquiry; truth. preparation for later life, 40, 57, 196 process, 105, 123, 124, 134, 253 progressive education, 13–49, 52, 54, 71, 216 psychology, 2, 13, 15, 47 reflection, 5, 6, 37, 46, 49, 77, 103, 112–120, 129, 131–3, 139, 241, 266, 287 religious education, 183–207 Ricoeur, Paul, 294–302 rules, 103, 104, 108, 128, 139, 140, 141, 157, 212, 218–19, 223, 227, 229 Russell, Bertrand, 97n28, 106, 124, 149, 153, 180n9 scholasticism, 80, 152, 178, 258–9, 294 science, 7, 23, 25, 26, 82, 95, 107, 108, 128, 129, 130, 131, 134, 178, 235, 262, 276, 295. Also see technology. Scott, Walter, 292 self-understanding, 43, 44, 45, 86, 295–6, 300, 301 Socrates, 46, 162, 170 standardization, 26, 34, 47, 93 standardized tests, 32, 33, 34, 37, 49, 93, 94, 139, 277–8, 291 Stenstad, Gail, 137 technology, 6, 21, 23, 129, 130, 131, 139, 262. Also see science. thinking, 4–5, 6, 26, 34, 37, 47, 55, 95, 101–42, 156, 163, 169. Also see critical thinking;
308 experimental inquiry; reflection; understanding. thoughtlessness, 130, 225 Tolstoy, Leo, 287, 289 tradition, 2, 29, 30, 31, 32, 36, 37, 38, 40, 117, 118, 129, 175, 183, 185, 186, 268 transformation, 8, 31, 40, 46, 86, 87, 90, 92, 93, 132, 133, 137, 138, 139, 282, 284, 285, 286, 287, 293, 298, 301
Index truth, 109–11, 195–6, 200, 203, 295 understanding, 4, 5, 25, 37, 41, 43, 44, 45, 46, 86, 101, 107, 112, 115–17, 126, 128, 132, 140, 300 Weber, Max, 23, Westbrook, Robert, 17–18, 259 Whitehead, Alfred North, 36, 149 wisdom, 113, 177 wonder, 133, 134, 136, 156