cover
next page >
title: author: publisher: isbn10 | asin: print isbn13: ebook isbn13: language: subject publicatio...
39 downloads
1117 Views
3MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
cover
next page >
title: author: publisher: isbn10 | asin: print isbn13: ebook isbn13: language: subject publication date: lcc: ddc: subject:
Hegel's Concept of God SUNY Series in Hegelian Studies Lauer, Quentin. State University of New York Press 0873955978 9780873955973 9780585078472 English God--History of doctrines--19th century, Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich,--1770-1831--Contributions in theology. 1982 BT101.H423L38 1982eb 231/.092/4 God--History of doctrines--19th century, Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich,--1770-1831--Contributions in theology.
cover
next page >
< previous page
< previous page
cover-0
next page >
Hegel's Concept of God
cover-0
next page >
< previous page
page_ii
next page > Page ii
< previous page
SUNY Series in Hegelian Studies Quentin Lauer, S.J., Editor
page_ii
next page >
< previous page
page_iii
next page > Page iii
Hegel's Concept of God Quentin Lauer, S.J. Department of Philosophy Fordham University
< previous page
State University of New York Press ALBANY
page_iii
next page >
< previous page
page_iv
next page > Page iv
Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 1982 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical articles and reviews. For information, address State University of New York Press, State University Plaza, Albany, N.Y., 12246 Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Lauer, Quentin. Hegel's concept of God. Bibliography: p. 331 Includes index. 1. GodHistory of doctrines19th century. 2. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 17701831Theology. I. Title. BT101.H423L38 231'.092'4 81-21452 ISBN 0-87395-597-8 AACR2 ISBN 0-87395-598-6 (pbk.) 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3
< previous page
page_iv
next page >
< previous page
page_v
next page > Page v
Contents Abbreviations
vii
Introduction
1
1. Religion and Philosophy
21
2. The Concept
57
3. God as Spirit
128
4. The Infinite
162
5. "Proofs" of God
203
6. The Question of Pantheism
243
7. Philosophy and Theology
283
Epilogue
325
Bibliography
331
Index of Names
333
Analytic Index
335
< previous page
page_v
next page >
< previous page
page_vii
next page > Page vii
Abbreviations BDGVorlesungen über die Beweise vom Dasein Gottes, ed. Georg Lasson (Hamburg: Himmelheber, 1966). BS Berliner Schriften, ed. Johannes Hoffmeister (Hamburg: Meiner, 1956). Diff "Differenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen Systems der Philosophie," Jenaer kritische Schriften, edd. Harmut Buchner and Otto Pöggeler (Hamburg: Meiner, 1968). EGP Einleitung in die Geschichte der Philosophie, ed. Johannes Hoffmeister (Hamburg: Meiner, 1940). EpW Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften (1830), edd. Friedhelm Nicolin and Otto Pöggeler (Hamburg: Meiner, 1959). GPR Grundlinien der Philosophie der Rechts, ed. Johannes Hoffmeister (Hamburg: Meiner, 1955). GW Glauben und Wissen, ed. Georg Lasson (Hamburg: Himmelheber, 1962). JL Jenenser Logik, Metaphysik und Naturphilosophie, ed. Georg Lasson (Hamburg: Meiner, 1967). JR Jenaer Realphilosophie, ed. Johannes Hoffmeister (Hamburg: Meiner, 1969). PdG Phänomenologie des Geistes, ed. Johannes Hoffmeister (Hamburg: Meiner, 1952). VA Vorlesungen über die Aesthetik (3 vols., Frankfurt a/M: Suhrkamp, 1970). VGP Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie (3 vols., Frankfurt a/M: Suhrkamp, 1971). VPG Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Geschichte (Frankfurt a/M: Suhrkamp, 1970).
< previous page
page_vii
next page >
< previous page
page_viii
next page > Page viii
VPRVorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion (2 vols., Frankfurt a/M: Suhrkamp, 1969). WG Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte (4 vols.) Vol. I, ed. Johannes Hoffmeister, 1955; Vols. IIIV, ed. Georg Lasson, 1976 (Hamburg: Meiner). WL Wissenschaft der Logik (2 vols.), ed. Georg Lasson (Hamburg: Meiner, 1963).
< previous page
page_viii
next page >
< previous page
page_1
next page > Page 1
Introduction It could well seem that I am being facetious if I refer to this study as "a book in search of a title," but many an author will recognize that the expression designates an experience which is not unfamiliar. I had already completed the first draft of this volume before coming to a decision as to just what title it should bear. What is a title, after all, but a concise symbol of what one hopes one has said? As I looked back, then, over what I had saidor tried to saythe rather obvious title that suggested itself was "Hegel's Idea of Philosophy," but that title had already been preempted by a book I had published ten years previously. The question then became: Is there another way of saying virtually the same thing? If one takes a panoramic view of Hegel's entire philosophical endeavorthe endeavor to come to grips with and to be committed to reality in the concreteone is struck by one inescapable idea: The Hegelian enterprise is an extraordinarily unified and grandiose attempt to elaborate one concept, which Hegel sees as the root of all intelligibilitythe concept of God, whatever that term is going to turn out to mean. Hence, the title Hegel's Concept of God represents an attempt to encompass the global character of the Hegelian philosophical enterprise. To those, of course, who are at all familiar with the enormous body of secondary literature that surrounds Hegela body of literature which has been expanding rapidly in recent yearsit will be immediately evident that Hegel's "God" has come under fire from a number of directions both among his own contemporaries and in subsequent generations. In the course of this study it will be necessary to take into consideration the various facets of opposition to Hegel's "God-language." Here it should be sufficient to indicate the main directions this opposition has taken. (1) There are, first of all, those who claim that Hegel has no business bringing Godparticularly the God of Christian religioninto a philosophical
< previous page
page_1
next page >
< previous page
page_2
next page > Page 2
discussion at all, either because (a) there is no such God to bring into the discussion, other than negatively (Feuerbach, Marx); or (b) because the only God there is is beyond the capacity of rational thinking to comprehendGod is defined most adequately as the "incomprehensible," the "transcendent," the "mysterious" (Kierkegaard, Barth). (2) Then there are those who contend that regardless of the terminology he employs, Hegel is not really talking about God but only about the "absoluteness,'' the "infinity" of the human spirit, a sort of overarching "Spirit," which at once transcends and embraces all its finite instantiations, but which bears no resemblance whatsoever to the God of any religion, least of all the God of Christian religion (Kojève, Findlay, Kaufmann). (3) There are those, too, who take Hegel seriously enough but assert that, by "logicizing" God, Hegel has deformed him and has put in his place Hegel's own questionable concept of "infinite reason," the "logic" of which is Hegel's own invention (Maréchal, Küng, Ricoeur). (4) Finally, there are those who contendand in a sense this contention is common to all the objectionsthat there is only one reason, an essentially finite human reason, and that therefore God is simply beyond reason, either (a) as irrational and therefore nonexistent (Nietzsche, Sartre), or (b) as suprarational and therefore only to be believed in, not to be known (Kant, Fichte, Jacobi). There is no need at this point to seek answers to the objections that have been raised. The question with which we are facedand this will be true in all of what followsis neither whether Hegel is correct in what he says nor whether his interpreters are justified in what they say of him. Rather the question is one of finding out just what Hegel does say and of determining what impact that can have on our own thinking. The point is, however, that it is enormously difficult to determine exactly what Hegel is saying. There are two reasons for this: (1) The language he employs is frequently that of the Christian religious and theological tradition, a language which those who do not share the tradition will decipher only with great difficulty and which those who do share the tradition may feel Hegel is using in such a way as to make its meaning hopelessly obscure; and (2) only in the framework of an elaborate philosophical "system," which no one claims to have unraveled adequately, is the meaning of all that Hegel says intelligible. When Hegel employs such terms as "God," "revelation," "elevation," "infinite (or absolute) Spirit," "trinity," "creation," and "incarnation," it is clear that the vocabulary is borrowed from Christian theology. Yet the terms, as he employs them, have a peculiarly philosophical significance, and it is questionable whether turning to the theological tradition will make their meaning clear, precisely because Hegel is quite definitely trying to make what is initially the content of faith rationally comprehensible. To put all this in another way, we might say this: There can be no question in anyone's mind that Hegel repeatedly employs the term "God"; nor
< previous page
page_2
next page >
< previous page
page_3
next page > Page 3
should there be any question that, when he uses the term, he intends it not to refer to some unknown or unknowable being, but to have a conceptual content with which human reason can come to grips. It is here that the objections we have seen come in. Has Hegel simply made God too comprehensible? Is the God who is the content of finite human conceptual thinking really God at all? Has Hegel, perhaps, rationalized God out of existence? has he finitized infinite Being by making it the object of finite thought? or has he illegitimately infinitized a human thinking which is essentially finite? When the questions are put in this way, we can, perhaps, see that the questions themselves may well be illegitimate, since they are based on three unverified (or unverifiable) presuppositions: (1) that rational thought is finite and only finite; (2) that the questioner knows precisely what Hegel means by "infinite"; and (3) that the questioner has drawn an intelligible distinction between "finite" and "infinite." If rational thought is finite and only finite, then of course it cannot know infinite Being; it can only, as did Kant, "postulate" infinite Being and resign itself to not knowing what it has postulatedunless, of course, it is not infinity at all that has been postulated, but only indeterminacy. The human mind can come to grips with mathematical infinity, with the infinity of time or space, or with the infinity of endless repetition, but this would seem to run up against an equally grave problem, namely, the intelligibility of indeterminacyunless what is being said is that indeterminacy is preferable to intelligibility. Perhaps Hegel too is postulating what he has no right to postulate, the intelligibility of reality, a necessary condition of which is an intelligible God. The Intelligibility of Reality Perhaps, then, the trouble is that Hegel is too optimistic about the intelligibility of reality, even finite reality. Because he simply will not accept an unintelligible realitywhich may very well be a nonphilosophical (or prephilosophical) refusalhe will presuppose that intelligibility and then spell out in detail the necessary conditions for the conceivability of an intelligible reality. That, after all, is where his logic takes him. But it takes him further than that: As he sees it, a condition for the reality of the real is that it be intelligible, susceptible of rational comprehension; and by the same token a condition of the intelligibility of the real is that it be actual, a determinate object of rational comprehension. Here, then, philosophy and theology come together again. According to Hegelian logic, being is intelligibleand it must be, since being is the foundation of all intelligibilityonly if being is both finite and infinite. By the same token thought can comprehend beingand it must, or else nothing is comprehensibleonly if thought is both finite and infinite. To say that reality is intelligible, however, or that the thinking mind
< previous page
page_3
next page >
< previous page
page_4
next page > Page 4
knows reality, is not to say that the mind imposes a form on reality and thus renders it intelligible, known. Hegel is content to let reality speak for itself, and he is convinced that it does speak, not only to the mind but also through the mind, in the mind's thinking. If we can go this far with Hegel, there seems to be no "logical" reason why we cannot go further and say that knowledge of being is being's self-revelation both to thinking spirit and in thought. Nor does it require a "logical" leap to move from this to the conviction that the ultimate principle of all being, intelligibility, and knowledge reveals itself to thinking spirit in thought. Thus, when Hegel says that God is comprehensible (or better, perhaps, not incomprehensible) to the human mind, Hegel is not saying that the human mind can know all that there is to know about God ("comprehension" does not signify that sort of all-embracing grasp). What he is saying is that God, who is infinitely self-knowing Spirit, reveals himself to man, to the human mind, and that this revelation, indispensable as it is to any knowing of reality, is comprehended. If not, it is no revelation; comprehension of the revelation is part and parcel of the revelation, whether of finite or of infinite being. The very being of spirit is self-revelation, but self-revelation is, in fact, revelation only if comprehended. The Intelligibility of Divine Reality It must be admitted at this point, however, that it is not difficult to see why both nonbelievers and believers might balk at Hegel's contention. Has he not overlogicized God? Does a logic of infinite Being really make sense? Can the infinite being to which Science of Logic ineluctably leads, identified as it is with "absolute Idea," legitimately be identified with the infinite Spirit of which faith speaks? To the nonbeliever, obviously not. What about the believer? Without going into the argumentation with which this entire volume will be concerned, we can let Paul Ricoeur be the spokesman for the many believers who fear that the God of whom a Hegelian "logic" speaks cannot fail to be a degradation of the "transcendent" God who is the object of religous faith. A teleology carried out in Hegelian style does not have as eschaton, as final term, the sacred delivered in myth, cult, belief. Of itself what this teleology envisions is absolute knowing, not faith; and absolute knowing bespeaks no transcendence, only the subsumption of all transcendence in a thoroughly mediated self-knowledge.1 Ricoeur, of course, is not alone in fearing that a Hegelian "logic" makes
1. Paul Ricoeur, De L'interprétation (Paris: Seuil, 1965), pp. 505506.
< previous page
page_4
next page >
< previous page
page_5
next page > Page 5
God too comprehensible, thus doing away with the "sacred," the "numinous," the "transcendent"in short, the "mysterious." What does not seem to bother such thinkers, however, is that their own logic may well run the risk of making God not only logically incomprehensible, but logically reprehensible. What needs to be said here is that in a certain sense, perhaps, Feuerbach, Marx, and Engels,2 were right: the thought of Hegel does mark the "end" of philosophy, that is, of a rationalism which tries to retain its theism. Hegel would be the first to agree with thathe sees in "rationalism" (particularly "Enlightenment" rationalism) the enemy of both philosophy and religion.3 Whether, as marking the end of that sort of rationalism, Hegel's thought marks the beginning of a rationalism which is nontheistic, is at least debatable. It will be the argument of this volume that Hegel's philosophy is theistic, but in a new sort of way. That what he has to say in Phenomenology of Spirit (Chap. VII, section C, "Revealed Religion") and in Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion (part III, ''Absolute Religion") does much to discredit belief in God who is only "transcendent," that Hegel bids us seek God elsewhere than "outthere," and that he would turn our gaze to the overarching "spirit" of man if we are to find a God who makes sense, can well be admitted. This, however, makes Hegel neither an "atheist" nor a "pantheist"; it makes him one who does not think that saying "God" necessarily involves knowing what one is saying and one who does think that knowing what one is saying is indispensable to saying anything. On the other hand, it would be foolish to deny that the "humanist" approach (say, of Feuerbach and Marx)according to which when one says "God" one is not saying anything but merely projecting a mental constructreceives more than merely moral support from Hegel's argumentation. Hegel is in the position of having to say that the term "God" does have a very determinate meaning which the mind can both grasp and see the necessary reality of, if it is to be able to assert the reality of any object of thought whatever. One can at least understand the fear of those who feel that this sort of argumentation downgrades God to the level of human self-conscious knowing. The real problem, howeverand this is where the philosophy of Hegel must meet the crucial testdoes not come with the assertion that the mind must affirm the reality of infinite being if it is going to affirm any reality whatever, nor with the assertion that any spirit, absolute Spirit, can be infinite, but rather with the contention that the God (ultimately the God of the Judaeo-Christian tradition) whom religious consciousness believes in can in no way be other than the God whom "speculative thinking"
2. See F. Engels, L. Feuerbach und der Ausgang der klassischen deutschen Philosophie. (Berlin: Dietz, 1951.) 3. See the section "God and Philosophy" in this introduction.
< previous page
page_5
next page >
< previous page
page_6
next page > Page 6
recognizes as a logical necessity. But here a caution is in order. It would simply be a mistake to claim that Hegel anywhere contends that "speculative thinking" can dispense with religious consciousness in asserting the real existence of the "infinite Spirit" it affirms. Even more obviously, this sort of thinking cannot dispense with religion in affirming the identity of its own God and the God of religion. The problem, then, is that of holding on to religion and at the same time affirming the thorough-going rationality of religion's God, such that there simply can be no essential difference between the God religion believes in and the God whom reason comprehends. If God be real, there can be no abstract "God of the philosophers," who would be other than the God of faith. The key concept here, it would seem, is that of "transcendence." In relation to this concept, those who attack Hegel from opposing sides are in agreement: either God is immanent or God is transcendenthe cannot be both. For Feuerbach and Marx there cannot be a "transcendent" God as that would be an insult to human dignity. Therefore, Hegel's God must be immanent, and this is no God at all in any intelligible sense, only a projection of human needs and aspirations. As we have already seen, for Paul Ricoeur the only God who can truly be God is the "transcendent" God of faith; and thus, because Hegel's God is immanent "in thoroughly mediated selfconsciousness," he cannot be truly God. From a slightly different point of view Emil Fackenheim says much the same. "There is no greater attempt than the Hegelian to unite the God of the philosophers with the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob. The 'result' of its failure is that the two fall radically apart.''4 For Fackenheim a God whose inner logic of "love" demands a world in which God can reveal himself is a God in whom faith cannot believe, because faith and logic, belief in God and knowledge of God, are incompatible. Philosophic knowledge of God is more hostile to faith than is an out-and-out atheism which wages open war against faith5to affirm the reality of a non-God is worse than to deny the reality of God. Object of Reason vs. Object of Understanding These objections from both sides bring us to the very heart of Hegel's "speculative logic." It has so often been asserted that Hegel denies the principle of noncontradiction, that the assertion has taken on the air of a commonplace which needs neither proof nor explanation. The fact is that Hegel affirms over and over again that noncontradiction is an indispensable principle of formal logic, of abstract understanding (Verstand); to ignore it on
4. Emil Fackenheim, The Religious Dimension in Hegel's Thought (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967), p. 240. 5. See ibid., p. 204.
< previous page
page_6
next page >
< previous page
page_7
next page > Page 7
this level can lead to nothing but confusion. What is a necessary principle of abstract understanding, however, need not be a principle of concrete reason (Vernunft). This is not to say that reason violates the rules of understanding, nor, worse still, that reason dispenses with understanding. It is to say that reason, whose standpoint is that of totality, infinity, is not compelled, as is understanding, to fight shy of contradiction. In the light of infinity, contradictories call each other forth and are continuous with each other, and contradiction can be allowed to resolve itself. If to abstract understanding infinity means nonfinitude and only that, and if finitude means noninfinity and only that, then "never the twain shall meet." If, on the other hand, to concrete reason the finite (concrete) and the infinite (concrete) are continuous, such that the finite implies the infinite and the infinite implies the finite, their contradictoriness is resolved in their necessary relationship to each other. The same applies, in the light of infinity, to freedom and necessity, individuality and universality, possibility and actuality, faith and knowledge, immanence and transcendence, and so on. A parade example for Hegel, then, of the continuity of contradictories is that of immanence and transcendence. If immanence is nontranscendence and only that, if transcendence is nonimmanence and only that, they are clearly incompatible, and that is the end of the line, as it is for abstract thinkingwhich is inadequate to reality if it does not move on to concrete thought. It would clearly be going too far to claim that what we have thus far seen answers all the objections that Hegel's opponents raise against him. Nor is it the function of an introduction to do that. We might ask ourselves, however, whether the atmosphere has been cleared with regard to the charges which have been brought against Hegel from the standpoint of "orthodoxy." That these charges were brought against him even during his own lifetime we know, if from no other source, from the preface to the third edition of Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences and from numerous references in Berliner Schriften. One thing does seem to be clear; he was convinced that his thinking, as striking as it might appear, was orthodox. Along with that went the conviction that only adequate philosophical thinking could legitimate theological reflection on the content of faith, and that neither Wolffian "metaphysics," Kantian "criticism," exegetical "erudition,'' nor romantic "intuitionism" could accomplish the task of making "orthodoxy" intellectually respectable. One might still find it debatable whether Hegel's "speculative thinking" succeeds in accomplishing the task; it will be the task of the present study to examine in detail the degree to which Hegel can be looked upon as successful in his endeavor. The only point here is to see whether, in fact, Hegel's endeavor was to make orthodoxy intellectually respectable by making it speak intelligibly to the enquiring mind. Does a "logic of concept" prove to be at once philosophically satisfying and theologically (or, perhaps, religiously)
< previous page
page_7
next page >
< previous page
page_8
next page > Page 8
acceptable, or has Hegel opted for philosophical satisfaction at the expense of religious acceptability? More pointedly, perhaps, was Hegel serious in trying to come to grips philosophically with the self-revealing God of Christianity? A hint as to the answer to this last question may be found in Hegel's conviction that a revelation must be intelligible if it is to be a revelation at all. To put it more bluntly, Hegel is convinced that God has told us nothing of himself if what he has told us is unintelligible to human reason. He is also convinced, however, that philosophical knowledge of the infinite Spirit who is God is just as much divine self-revelation as is the word of God in scripture or in the teaching of the Christian religion. Opposed as he was to "rationalism," considering it a kind of abstract burlesque of reason, he was a vigorous advocate of supremely rational thinking, to which he would assign no limits. That there should have been opposition to this attitude can come as no surprise, but the grounds of the opposition would seem to be more emotional than rational. This, of course, his "theologian" opponents would not deny, since in religious matters they considered emotion more reliable than reason. But, it is not difficult to see that, precisely from the point of view of his supreme confidence in reason, Hegel should sense the danger of such a reliance on emotion. Can one honestly be religious and at the same time be satisfied with an unknown or unknowable God? Is not a non-God preferable? Hegel's endeavor, then, can be looked on as a mighty effort to avoid the second conclusion. One wonders, in fact, whether his "theologian" opponents were opposed to him on truly religious grounds or merely fearful of the conclusion to which rational thinking would lead them. Since the reason of "rationalism" does not permit them to know God, and since they cannot conceive of a reason which is not rationalistic, they must resist Hegel's claim that reason can know God. ''Mystery"and therefore unknowingis much more comforting. Since it is not rational either to affirm or deny God, it would seem imperative to drop reason, if one is not to drop God. Hegel's contention is diametrically opposed to this; as he sees it, relinquishing reason is tantamount to relinquishing religion, and both relinquishments are unworthy of the human. If man alone is capable of religion, it is through that which is most characteristic of man, that is reason.
Given the prejudice of our own time which so separates feeling and thinking, it can be considered a need that they be opposed, even that they be inimical to each other, in such a way that feeling, particularly religious feeling is sullied, even annihilated, by thinking, so that it is essential to religion and religiousness not to be rooted in thinking. To separate in this way is to forget that only man is capable of religion, whereas the brute has no religion, no more than law or morality. [EpW, no. 2]
< previous page
page_8
next page >
< previous page
page_9
next page > Page 9
If to be religious is to be nonrational, then to be religious is to be nonhuman. Such an attitude is indeed grist for the atheist mill! What Is Reason? As one moves through Hegel's writings it becomes more and more clear that he is constantly working out three consistent convictions: (1) that reason both can and must make sense, not nonsense, out of God who is real; (2) that it is an abdication of reason not to make sense out of God, either by claiming that God is not real or by claiming that the human response to the real God is not rational; and (3) that reason cannot make sense of any reality whatever, if it does not make sense of God. One question, however, still remains: Why must it be reason which makes sense of God? or, why is it reason alone that can make sense of God? At this point we must try to make sense out of Hegel's ultimate identification of infinite Being, infinite Thought, and infinite Spirit. Although we shall have to wait until chapter 4 for a detailed exposition of Hegel's thought on the "infinite," we can say here that Hegel sees thinking as a continuous process of self-purification, thought purifying itself of all sensible content whatever. It must be emphasized, however, that Hegel never says that reason does not think what is sensible; rather he says that thought must transform the sensible into the nonsensible if it is to think the sensible adequately. Rational thought, then, can think both the sensible and the nonsensible; butand this is importantonly rational thought can think the nonsensible. Since it is of the essence of the sensible to be finite, if the infinite be it must be non-sensible, and with this only rational thought can come to grips. That the infinite cannot be sensed is clear enough to all; that it cannot be imaged should also be clear. That the infinite cannot be "represented" (vorgestellt) in "understanding'' (Verstand), may not be so clear; but if we follow Hegel's claim that "representation" (Vorstellung) is always at least linked to images, we can see why he makes the claim. Hegel is not claiming that "understanding" does not "represent" the infinite; that is what "understanding" does when it seeks to think the object of religious consciousness. What he does claim is that "understanding" cannot be successful in this, because it cannot dispense with "representations." Only rational thinking can be successful, precisely because only "reason" goes beyond "understanding," beyond "representations," and it is the insistence on identifying "reason" with "understanding" which underlies the claim that the reality of God must be impervious to reason. Here, it would seem, something needs to be saidin a preliminary way, at leastregarding Hegel's notion of the function of "representing" (vorstellen) and "representation" (Vorstellung) in human thinking. A great deal has already been written on this subject, and, it seems to me, much of
< previous page
page_9
next page >
< previous page
page_10
next page > Page 10
what has been written misses the point. When human consciousness is presented with an object, whether the presentation be in the form of sensorial awareness, linguistic communication, or, in the case of religious content, in the teaching, for example, of the Church, Hegel refers to it as "immediate" awareness. It is characteristic of the human to seek to think the content thus "immediately" given. This "thinking" of the content presented to consciousness in "images'' initially takes the form of "representations" (Vorstellungen) which the mind subjectively makes to itself in an effort to come to grips with the content presented. Precisely because this is thinking, the process of vorstellen (Vorstellung) constitutes the beginning of a dynamic movement away from the imagecharacter of what is present. It is important to note that Vorstellung (the form is participial) is itself a process, a progressive movement from image toward thought. So long, however, as the process is still one of subjective "representation," what Hegel frequently calls "one-sided," the link to images has not been superseded. The movement of Vorstellung, then, is oriented to transcending itself in thought, which is no longer merely subjective but objective. It may well be that the counter-claim could be made that it is asking too much to demand, with Hegel, that there be human thought without images. To make this counter-claim, of course, is equivalent to the claim that there is no rational thought in the way Hegel understands it. So be it. It is not the function of an introduction to establish the validity of Hegel's claim, only to assert that he makes it. One thing, however, is clear: If there cannot be human thought without images, then it is the case that the human mind cannot have the infinite as its object; a conclusion which can satisfy atheists but can hardly satisfy the theists. Even religious consciousness, which represents the God of faith in various metaphorical ways, thinks of God as nonimageablean infinite which could in any way be imaged would not be infinite. It is, nevertheless, necessary to admit that the Hegelian logic does make great demands on us, if we are to come to grips with it. One might say that we have to have reached the lofty heights of this sort of "speculative thinking," before we can recognize the conceivability of such thinking. This is one reason why Hegel does not treat us to the luxury of a "proof" in the formal-logical sense of the term. His logic is not a theory of "proof" at all; it is a study of the logos in which reality is revealed, or reveals itself, in thought. There is no question of "demonstrating" that the infinite can be grasped in imageless thought, or that there is imageless thought to grasp it; there is question only of following Hegel's thought and "seeing," so to speak, that it does make eminently good sense. It is small wonder that Hegel looked upon Plato's Parmenides (part II) as the profoundest work of ancient philosophy; it nowhere calls upon sensible images to bolster its philosophical dialectic. If we are to think with Hegel we must be both will
< previous page
page_10
next page >
< previous page
page_11
next page > Page 11
ing and able to follow a process of thought which finds no need of touching ground in the images constantly present in our ordinary thinking and which, nevertheless, claims to be more "concrete" (penetrating to the heart of reality as it is in its total interrelatedness) than is a thinking which relies on "representations." Perhaps the difficulty we experience in following this sort of "logic" stems not so much from our inability or unwillingness to think of the infinite as concrete as it does from our inability or unwillingness to accept a thinking which Hegel calls "untrue to itself" if it does not progressively divest itself of reliance on sense. It is not that Hegel denies that thinking begins in sense perceptionthat is too obvious to need discussionrather he contends that only in constantly and consistently moving away from the sensible can thought be the pure spiritual activity which alone can come to grips with "all reality." Reason (spirit) must transform (spiritualize) even nature, because only as thus idealized does nature itself reveal its own "truth" to and in thought. Only if we can do this can we avoid a return either to an indefensible causal metaphysics of cognition or to an equally indefensible Humean scepticism. God and Philosophy All of this brings us around full circle to where we began: Just what can it mean to say that the whole of Hegel's philosophy is wrapped up in his concept of God, that his philosophy stands or falls in the rationality of that concept? Perhaps the problem is not that Hegel has so philosophized theology that he has dispensed with faith, but that he has theologized philosophy to such an extent that, even as purely philosophical thinking, it cannot dispense with faith, that is, with faith's content. Here it might do well to emphasize once more that Hegel nowhere says that we can rationalize faith; what he does say is that if reason takes a long hard look at the content of faith it will find that content not only rationally acceptable but also rationally necessary, and that reason fails as reason if it does not see this. As he sees it, in terms of the overall process of human experience, religious "experience" is not something either to be left out of the rational process as a sort of aberration, nor is it suprarational in the sense that it simply defies the power of reason to come to terms with it. Thus, religion is not to be superseded, in the sense of canceled and only canceled, as it is for Marx, nor is it to supersede reason, in the sense that religion can attain to an object which is opaque to reason. Rather, as Phenomenology of Spirit makes abundantly clear, religious experience is integral to and continuous with the march of experience in the process of becoming "absolute knowing." Nor is "religious experience" to be given the rather narrow interpretation which it has, say, in James; for Hegel, thinking is the experience
< previous page
page_11
next page >
< previous page
page_12
next page > Page 12
of thinking's object or content. Religious experience, then, is the religious mode of thinking (in Vorstellungen) the absolute content which is God. Religion, however, will not be true to itselfor to its contentif it rests content with not knowing that to which it is oriented. It might be argued, of course, that "the faith of a Breton peasant" could well be superior to that of the philosopher; it would be questionable, however, whether it would be good for the philosopher to have that kind of faith. To insist on a faith which bypasses reason is, according to Hegel, to capitulate to Enlightenment rationalism, which is just as inimical to philosophy as it is to religion. The Enlightenment, that vanity of the understanding, is the most vigorous opponent of philosophy; it is displeased when the latter demonstrates reason in Christian religion, when it shows that the foundation for the testimony of the spirit of truth has been established in religion. In philosophy, which is theology, the only thing that counts is to demonstrate the rationality of religion. [VPR II, p. 341] What Hegel has done, then, is not so much to "theologize" philosophy as to attempt to show, from the philosophical point of view, that philosophy and theology are oriented to one and the same truth, the logos of being in its infinity. Erwin Metzke has expressed this as clearly and succinctly as has anyone. Hegel's world of thought is religiously rooted (cf. the footnotes to the Preface of the second edition of the Encyclopedia). For Hegel, of course, this does not result in surrendering philosophy to theology; rather he seeks to illumine philosophically the profounder common ground of both. Not only for faith but also for philosophical knowing the supreme and unique object, the being of God as the truly absolute Being, includes in a comprehensive way the being of the world: the world is nothing but the unfolding of God himself through the otherness of nature. The world is God's other. Truth is the unity of the infinite and the finite. To see God only as transcendent would be to truncate truth, an abstraction.6 God and Human History We can at this point look at what could at first sight seem a rather implausible source for a confirmation of the present interpretation of the movement of Hegel's thought. Between 1822 and 1831 Hegel presented five times a course of lectures on the philosophy of world history. We now have these lectures in a monumental 938-page edition, Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte, which, it would seem, presents Hegel's
6. Erwin Metzke, Hegels Vorreden (Heidelberg: Kerle, 1949), p. 269.
< previous page
page_12
next page >
< previous page
page_13
next page > Page 13
maturest thought. It is precisely here that he stresses again and again the intimate link between the development of philosophical "culture" (Bildung) and the process of religious experience. "Culture" (Bildung could also be rendered as "cultivation") is that process of development which is unique to the human spirit; a process which is at once the activity and the product of spirit, whereby spirit comes to be what it is to be spirit. What is peculiar to the spirit's process of self-cultivation is that "culture" is inadequate to the task it has to perform until the human spirit is "alienated'' from the merely "natural" in which it is immersed, and that the alienation, as at once a "spiritualization" and a "denaturalization," does not take place independently of the religious consciousness from which emerges into reality a progressively more concrete human spirit (WG, pp. 125, 128, 13132). Thus, in Hegel's view, religion and culture can never be separated in the process of man's becoming human (ibid., pp. 134, 733, 821, 878). The Enlightenment, which, as he sees it, is the last futile attempt to accomplish naturalistically what can be accomplished only spiritually, effectively showed the impossibility of making this separation. The culture of the Enlightenment, like the vast cultural edifices which preceded it, proved to be self-defeating, because it sought to leave out of the picture the only possible integrator of spiritual development, that is, absolute Spirit. When Hegel speaks of Bildung, of course, he speaks of that process of self-cultivation which is proper not so much to the individual as to the spirit of a people, all of whose members share, albeit in varying degrees, in a Bildung which is common to all. By the same token religion is not primarily that which characterizes the orientation of the individual spirit to absolute Spirit; rather it is that which orients the collective spirit. Spiritual activity, then, is not only the activity which most properly characterizes the human; it is the very process of humanizing the human; and this it does by authentically orienting the human to the divine (ibid., pp. 6162, 7273, 530, 554, 576). At this point we may, as has been noted earlier, be brought up short by the objection that it is arbitrary to identify the overarching spirit which unifies the totality of the human, the "absolute Spirit" of which Hegel speaks, with the "divine Spirit" of which religion speaks. The objection, however, has the disadvantage of not appealing to what Hegel does say. It is difficult to see how anyone could read Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte and say that Hegel is not identifying absolute Spirit with Godwhether or not one likes this "God" of whom Hegel speaks (see WG, pp. 12526, 131, 745). Perhaps, however, it would be better to approach this question from another angle. It may be that one could interpret what Hegel says regarding the humanizing of the human in terms of an orientation of human spirit to absolute Spirit as no more than an absolutizing of human spirit through philosophical knowing. This interpretation, however, runs up against the
< previous page
page_13
next page >
< previous page
page_14
next page > Page 14
difficulty of Hegel's consistent refusal to look upon human self-development as a process of man's lifting himself by his own bootstraps (see ibid., pp. 182, 57273, 821, 878). To those who are familiar with the seventh and eighth chapters of Phenomenology of Spirit this will be clear enough; it is also clearly the teaching in Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte. Not only is the dialectic of spirit's culture one of self-activity, whereby man rises to ever-higher awareness of what it is to be human (WG, p. 35); not only is the goal to which man is oriented one which is not antecedently inscribed in a blueprint of human "nature," precisely because the human spirit is to bring into being that to which it is oriented (ibid., pp. 58, 74); but the process toward the goal is to be the activity of both the human spirit and of the divine Spirit. The ascension of the human spirit is both a "self-lifting" and a ''being-lifted-up" (Erhebung). "It is essential to this process that there be levels [of development], and worldhistory is the manifestation of the divine process, the ascension by stages, wherein spirit both knows and actualizes itself and its truth" (ibid., p. 74). Strong medicine this, it is true; but the question is not at the moment whether the medicine is too strong to take or even whether what Hegel says is true; it is simply a question of whether Hegel means what he says. We can, if we wish, say that when Hegel speaks of man as "in himself his own goal" (ibid., p. 106)a goal, nevertheless, that is not predetermined, as it would be if man were simply a being of natureand as his own goal "only through the divine that dwells in him" (ibid.), he is not speaking religious language, but rather he is using the term "divine" metaphorically. However, it would seem that the evidence for this contention has yet to be uncovered. When Hegel further says that "the goal of the spirit" is "to give itself consciousness of the Absolute," and that "this consciousness of his is alone true," or that this is at once "honor paid to God" and the "glorification of the truth" (ibid.), it is indeed difficult to see why we should not take him at his word. Nor does this take away from (rather it enhances) the dignity of man, since "in honoring God the individual spirit too finds its own dignity," in the recognition that man's "activity for the honor of God is the absolute [for man] (ibid.). Precisely here is where philosophy comes in, for it is "philosophy" which "thinks and comprehends what is contained in religion in the mode of representation, both sensible and spiritual" (ibid., p. 134; see p. 172). The point Hegel is trying to make, however, is that the activity of honoring God concerns man more than it does God, since "the dignity of man is to be found in honoring the divine . . . such that the divine receives honor through the honor given to the human, and the human receives honor through the honor paid to the divine" (ibid., p. 572; see pp. 181, 573). This last statement, it is true, is made in the context of Hegel's discussion of Greek religion, wherein the beauty of Greek art honors both the divine
< previous page
page_14
next page >
< previous page
page_15
next page > Page 15
which it portrays and the human which does the portraying, but it has to be read in continuity with a whole series of texts wherein ever higher forms of religious representation give rise to an ever more purified conceptualization of what it is to be human, to be spirit, since "God is the essence of the human" (ibid., p. 575). Nor is this to be separated from man's progressive realization of his own rationality; reason, after all, "is the substance of spirit" (ibid., p. 733). But, the rationality of spirit is not to be divorced from the rationality of spirit's object; that object is rational, whether it be present in the explicitly rational form of philosophical thinking or in the implicitly rational form of religious consciousness (ibid.). The move to explicit rationality is accomplished in the progressive overcoming of the naturality in which the human spirit, even religious spirit, is immersed (ibid.). It may seem that Hegel is taking a very large leap when he moves quite rapidly from this vague religious consciousness of the unity of the divine and the human, to the Christian dogma of the unity of the divine and the human in the Incarnation (ibid., p. 729). In a sense, of course, it is a leap, but Hegel is convinced not only that the move must be made but also that the move is philosophically defensible. That there are dogmas at all, he claims, is true only because there is philosophical explication of religious beliefnor is the philosophical explication alien to the content of religious belief (ibid., p. 742). More than that, the human and the divine are not simply to be equated (ibid., p. 734)a contradiction which "understanding" sees so readilya union with the divine is essential to the actualization of spirituality in the human; and this, "speculative" thinking can comprehend. Man becomes actual as a spiritual being only when he overcomes his naturality. This overcoming becomes possible only under the supposition that the human and the divine natures are substantially and consciously (an und für sich) one, and that man, to the extent that he is spirit, possesses the essentiality and substantiality which pertains to the concept of God. [Ibid., p. 821] This human consciousness of union with the divine is neither immediately given nor readily comprehensible; man must grow into it. "The consciousness of this union with the divine is given in Christ. What is important, then, is that man come to grips with this consciousness and that it be constantly awakened in him" (ibid.). "Denaturalization" of the Human Now, what is important in all this is Hegel's claim that the whole of post-Roman "European" cultural development has been tied in with and conditioned by Christian religious consciousness and by the latter's explication in
< previous page
page_15
next page >
< previous page
page_16
next page > Page 16
a philosophical awareness of just what it is to be human, to be spiritual, to be spirit in a way which images in a this-worldly context the spiritual reality of God. The crux of Hegel's claim is his contention that man, as the unique combination of the "natural" and the "spiritual," must by his own activity "overcome" the merely natural in himself and thus actualize the truly spiritual, which is his destiny and his dignity, by being reconciled with God as ''Spirit," the paradigm of all spirit (WG, p. 878). The process of this overcoming is the Bildung which characterizes Western man, a Bildung marked by centuries of vicissitudes whose overtones are moral, religious, legal, and political, but whose orientation is ineluctably the realization of man's true being as spirit, since only spirit is self-determining, free. We have to admit at this point that Hegel, in his Lectures on the Philosophy of World History, leaves us with what can be termed an unsolved riddle. All along he has been talking of philosophical thought and its orientation to absolute Spirit, to God. In tracing the development of European cultureand pari passu of European philosophical thinkinghe describes a movement of separation of thought and culture from their foundation in the Absolute, the Divine. He does not, however, describe any process of reintegration. The reason, perhaps, is that, because he is speaking of a philosophy of history, he will not anticipate; the process of reintegration is yet to come. Be that as it may, we can, I think, recognize in his description of the period of disintegration a hint that he is describing a transitional stage in philosophical thought, a stage ushered in by the scientific revolution emerging from the Renaissance. There can be no question that the modern spirit of philosophical inquiry, the beginning of which Hegel finds in Descartes, has effected a separation of the human thinking subject from that which had previously been conceived of as ruling that spirit from above. To find itself, the human spirit now looks to itself alone, and this is the prelude to a thinking which is conceived of as self-determining in itself (WG, p. 914). No longer, to the scientific mind, is there question of the grace of God coming from without to enlighten that mind. It was Descartes who had turned the mind's gaze inward, and his cogito, ergo sum is to be interpreted not as an inference from thought to being, but as a recognition that being and thought (human thought) are one. That this insight should be elucidated in the conviction that the external world must exhibit the same rationality that human thought does, may itself not be a thoroughly rational conviction (one is reminded of Whitehead's contention that the scientist "must begin with an act of faith in the decency of the universe"). The pattern now is one of observing nature, discovering that it is regulated by "laws" which constitute its rationality and which imperceptibly become prescriptive rather than descriptive. Enter the Enlightenment, and the disintegration is complete (ibid., p. 915). Kant, Fichte, Jacobi, and Schleiermacher accept the
< previous page
page_16
next page >
< previous page
page_17
next page > Page 17
disintegration as complete, even though they continue to insist that the validity of faith is not compromised thereby. One thing is clear: A philosophical thinking which, with Kant, Fichte, and Jacobi, has lost its mooring in the concrete Absolute has given up the very possibility of an effectual reintegration. Thus, although Hegel does not, in the Lectures, map out the path of reintegration, he does, in the very last section, entitled "The Present Situation," hint at the solution. There he suggests that the disintegration has come about because of the spirit's failure to recognize itself for what it is, a recognition which will come about only if it listens to the testimony of absolute Spirit which bears witness to the true reality of the human spirit, which, if we are willing to inquire carefully, Spirit does in "World-History"the history which on the very last page Hegel calls "the true theodicy," the "justification of God." The spirit is only what it makes of itself; and for that it is necessary that it presuppose itself. Only this insight can reconcile the spirit with world-history and with actuality, the realization that what has happened and what happens at all times not only comes from God and is not without God, but is essentially the work of God himself. [WG, p. 938; see pp. 78, 81] However, the answer is not contained here. What Hegel does is to send us back to the final chapter of Phenomenology of Spirit, where religious consciousness and rational self-consciousness are reconciled in "Absolute Knowing," the elaboration of which constitutes the whole of Science of Logic and the "System" which flows from it. The answer, then, depends on the ability of the human spirit to go beyond the "analytic" thinking of Verstand to the "speculative" thinking of Vernunft; only in the latter can the spiritual destiny of man (cultural and religious) be realized. It will be the task of the present volume to follow Hegel in his attempt to articulate this realization in his own "speculative system,'' which he takes to be what "philosophy" has made of itself. Hegel's Language That the task of following Hegel proves to be enormously difficult will come as no surprise to those who are at all familiar with his writing. There is no need here to expand on the complexityor better, perhaps, tortuousnessof his thought. However, the difficulty is compounded by the language he employs in expressing that thought. What does one do, for example, with a language which is at once so elusive and so allusive? Can one say what Hegel is saying in a language which is other than Hegel's own? Nor is the problem simply that of saying in English what Hegel has said in Germanas tantalizing as the translation of that German into English may be.
< previous page
page_17
next page >
< previous page
page_18
next page > Page 18
The problem, rather, is that of finding any language adequate to express that thought. The initial assumption must be, if we are to get on with the task at all, that what he says does make sense, whether or not we agree with that sense. But even this last point presents a problem: Can we agree or disagree with what Hegel says, if we do not know exactly what he is (or is not) saying? As we shall have occasion to note again and again in what follows, one way of not getting the task done is to insist on having precise definitions of the terms Hegel employs. By the same token we cannot insist that he use grammar in the way we want him to use it; which is but another way of saying that we cannot legitimately interpret any author by taking his words to mean simply what we would mean if we used the same words. Language is in the service of thought, not vice versa. If Hegel stretches language (or grammar) to fit thought, we have no right to insist that he confine thought so as to fit a preconceived language (or grammar). The danger, of course, in approaching the problem in this way is that we run the risks: (1) of rendering it impossible to determine just what Hegel is saying, of throwing up our hands, or of simply guessing what he might be saying; (2) of looking upon language as doing more to veil thought than to reveal it; (3) of simply allowing Hegel complete liberty to say what he pleases, since there is no way of checking on the validity of what he says. Even granting these risks, however, it does seem necessary to issue a number of cautions in the effort to come to terms with Hegel's thought, which must be expressed in language or else not expressed at all: (1) We must not demand of language more than language can deliver. Perhaps language renders to reality the fullest justice it can by admitting its incapacity to express reality adequatelywhich does not mean that thought must stop short of reality. It may well be that language itself is formed in the either/or realm of what Hegel calls "mere understanding," needing to be fleshed out in the more comprehensive realm of "reason." No philosopher has ever wrought out a language totally adequate to either reality or thought. (2) Meaning cannot be confined to what can be defined. Plato taught us that lesson many years ago, and the lesson still stands; the quest for definition is a help, but meaning as it emerges bursts the bonds of definitionbut it need not suffer from so doing. (3) Hegel is difficult, but he is not unintelligible. His language conveys a meaning which we can grasp, not completely, perhaps, but that is not necessarily the fault of the language; the language flows from an experience which is not oursnot merely in the sense that it is separated from ours by a century and a half, but more significantly because his is a special experience (as is that of all genius), and it requires great effort on our part to share that experience, even partially. (4) It may be true to say that Hegel's philosophical thought resists being put into our philosophical language; but that does not relieve us of the burden of coming to grips with his thought through his language, which itself may well be not
< previous page
page_18
next page >
< previous page
page_19
next page > Page 19
totally adequate to the thought it expresses. If nothing else, precisely because Hegel's language has interesting things to say, it will not say them with perfect precision.7 (5) Hegel's grammar does, in fact, break the rules of grammar as we know them, but that need not be a fault in Hegel's grammar. Grammar as we know it may well be unable to handle what Hegel has to say. In any event we must make the effort to come to grips with what Hegel says, in the way he says it. Having said so muchrather abstractly, it is to be fearedof how Hegel says what he has to say, we are brought around full circle to where we began, to the title of this book, Hegel's Concept of God. Why can a title such as this be said to encompass the entire thrust of Hegel's philosophical thought? It can be said without much fear of contradiction that Hegel's philosophy is from beginning to end a philosophy of manthe focus is constantly man as thinking spirit. The "system," as Hegel sees it in outline, is divided into three quite unequal parts: Logic (or the philosophy of thought), philosophy of nature, and philosophy of spirit (subjective, objective, and absolute). It is still true, however, that the focus is consistently man: man, the human spirit, thinking thought; man finding the logic of thought, the logical Idea, expressed in the thinking of nature; man coming to grips with the spiritual being which he himself essentially is. Why, then, the "Concept of God"? The answer is to be found in the culmination of the entire Hegelian system, "The Philosophy of Absolute Spirit." Only in the light of "absolute Spirit" is anything Hegel says intelligible. It will be the contention of all that follows that, in Hegel's view, ''absolute Spirit" is in fact to be identified with God and that, therefore, only if Hegel's "Concept of God" is intelligible, will anything Hegel says be intelligible. It will not be necessary to claim here that Hegel's concept of God does in fact correspond with the Christian concept of God. I am convinced, however, that Hegel indeed thought it did. More than that, I am also convinced that, if he did not think it did, there is no way to make sense out of Hegel's philosophy. Question of Sources A few final words about sources. Some might argue against the wisdom (or even the honesty) of relying so heavily on Hegel's lectureson aesthetics, on the philosophy of history, on the history of philosophy, on the philosophy of religion8which were published posthumously and taken for the most part from the notes of his students (which we all know with pain does not necessarily make for accuracy). The same could be said of the
7. "Where a language has interesting things to say, precision is never perfect" (William Barrett, The Illusion of Technique [New York: Doubleday, Anchor, 1979], p. 280). 8. The objection might be considered particularly weighty against the use of Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion, the definitive edition of which we still await.
< previous page
page_19
next page >
< previous page
page_20
next page > Page 20
many quotes from the Zusätze, which have been added to the text of the Encyclopedia, again from the notes of Hegel's students. A number of answers to such objections suggest themselves. (1) If the interpretation were supported exclusively from the lectures, with no confirmation from the Phenomenology, Logic, Encyclopedia, or Philosophy of Right, the objections would indeed have weight (it is for this reason that I have made no references to his Early Theological Writings, which Hegel presumably deliberately did not publish). The interpretation, however, can be quite clearly supported from the writings Hegel himself had published. (2) To my knowledge, it has not been possible to show, without taking quotes out of context, that Hegel repudiates what either the lectures or the Zusätze say. (3) Hegel himself says, in his prefaces to the Encyclopedia, that the whole work is but a compendium, a sort of textbook outline, which is of value only when supplemented by the oral presentation of the professorpresumably what the notes of the students contain, with considerably more accuracy than a lecturer could hope for today. A considerably more serious objection, from the scholarly point of view, could be made against my use of the Suhrkamp edition of the lectures rather than the more critical Meiner edition (the latter does not contain the Zusätze at all). My reason for so doing was simply practical: the Suhrkamp edition is more readily available for those who wish to check my references. In checking the Meiner edition myself I have found nothing that would make me want to change the interpretation. I shall be grateful, however, if anyone can furnish me with texts from the critical edition which would modify my interpretation. It should, perhaps, be noted here that I give no references to English translationssimply because I use no translations. One possible further complaint is that, in referring to Berliner Schriften, I have not given the dates of the pieces referred to. Since, however, all these Writings belong to the period of Hegel's professorship in Berlin (18181830)and thus postdate all Hegel's published writings, except Philosophy of Rightit seems reasonable to assign all of them to the period of Hegel's philosophical maturity. When all this has been said, one concluson still seems inescapable: Hegel is clearly the most "God-inebriated" of philosophers. We may or may not like Hegel's God, but we cannot refuse to take him seriouslyboth Hegel and Hegel's God. Nor can our own thinking remain unaffected if we have reflected long and seriously on "Hegel's Concept of God."
< previous page
page_20
next page >
< previous page
page_21
next page > Page 21
Chapter One Religion and Philosophy To one who read's Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit for the first timeespecially if this first reading is also one's initiation to a grasp of Hegel's thinkingit cannot but come as a surprise that chapter VI, "Spirit," which would seem to be a culminating point of the inquiry, should be immediately followed by a chapter entitled "Religion," that is, religious consciousness. Not only does this indicate that, in Hegel's thinking, human self-conscious awareness of being "spirit'' and not merely "nature" is inadequate, it also indicates that the consciousness of being spirit is not a consciousness of what it is to be spirit until it goes beyond the self-enclosed consciousness of being merely human spirit. There are those, of course, who think that when, in the chapter on religious consciousness, Hegel speaks of God he is not being serious, that he is speaking at most metaphorically of an absolute unity of spirit which continues to be no more than human, even though not individual, but it is difficult to see how those who hold this can themselves be taken seriously. There are those too who, like Loewenberg, contend that by bringing religion onto the scene, thus focusing on a more-than-human spirit, Hegel has in some way ceased to engage in a phenomenology of the human spirit at all. Loewenberg considers the entry at this point of a "superhuman spirit" to be "intrusive" into the "biography of human spirit."1 However, it should be emphasized that, although the object of religion is divine, infinite Spirit, the religious experience of which Hegel is here speaking is essentially human experience. Perhaps the trouble lies in beginning a study of Hegel with the Phenomenology at all. It is in Science of Logic that Hegel makes clear his contention that all philosophical thinking is "speculative" thinkingthat
1. J. Loewenberg, Hegel's Phenomenology: Dialogues on the Life of Mind. (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1965), p. 298; see pp. 33637.
< previous page
page_21
next page >
< previous page
page_22
next page > Page 22
phenomenology, therefore, is speculative thinkingand that speculative thinking in its search for truth can never be confined to finding that truth in what is immediately present to thought, but only in that to which the immediately present points as its "truth." No one, so far as I know, has any difficulty in seeing that this is what goes on at every stage of the Phenomenology, up to and inclusive of section C, "Spirit Certain of Itself: Morality," which ends chapter VI. That some do not see that this points beyond itself to a spirit more than human is due, not to a determination to take what Hegel says seriously, but to an antecedent conviction that there is no more-than-human spirit to which morally self-conscious spirit can point. They are faced with a rather desperate alternative: either to refuse to follow Hegel any further or to interpret him in such a way as to make him say something quite other than what he quite obviously seems to be saying.2 If we take as our guidelines for interpretation what Hegel quite clearly does say in Science of Logic, Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, Lectures on Proofs for God's Existence, and the final sections of Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, rather than some unfounded antecedent conviction, we are, I think, more likely to come to grips with the real Hegel, for whom a thought which fails to rise to the absolute fails to come to terms with itself,3 and for whom religion attains to the absolute sooner than philosophy does.4 The overriding question with which logic (and, hence, the entire Hegelian system) is concerned is, "What is the true, what is the absolute foundation of everything" (WLI, p. 51)and this makes sense only if "absolute foundation" is at once logical, epistemological, and ontological. In Phenomenology of Spirit, it is true, precisely because its subject matter is "the experience of consciousness," which reveals itself to be "spirit," Hegel is more directly concerned with "religious consciousness' than he is with the "Absolute" which is the object of that consciousness.5 Nevertheless, it is clear even here, as it is throughout the Phenomenology, that consciousness is of interest only because it is the progressive revelation of the truth of its object and because consciousness will be true to itself as consciousness only if, ultimately, it is "absolute" consciousness of an ''absolute" object. What is, perhaps, of even more significance in this context is that the culminating stage of "spirit's" itinerary in coming to adequate con-
2. It is true, of course, that any interpretation of any authorincluding my interpretation of Hegelwill be colored by the interpreter's wanting the author to make sense, which usually means "my kind of sense." By itself, however, this need not invalidate the interpretationespecially where the evidence seems to be heavily weighted in its favor. 3. The thrust of the whole introduction to the Phenomenology. 4. "The content of religion, therefore, expresses what Spirit is sooner than science does, but the latter alone is its own knowledge of itself" (PdG, p. 559). See also BDG, pp. 5, 9, 17679. 5. In BDG, pp. 4647, Hegel speaks in scornful terms of those who would speak of religion as a form of human experience and yet consistently refuse to speak (philosophically) of religion's object, i.e., God.
< previous page
page_22
next page >
< previous page
page_23
next page > Page 23
sciousness of itself and, therefore, to the "truth" of what at the beginning of chapter V was only "immediate certainty" that "Reason is all reality"the culmination which Hegel calls "Absolute Knowing"is continuous with and inclusive of ''Religion." It would be worse than arbitrary to look upon chapter VII as either a parenthesis between chapters VI and VIII or as not really saying seriously what it purports to be saying, that is, that religious consciousness, which has God as its object, is indispensable to authentic philosophical thinking and knowing. In truly dialectical fashion "religion" is "speculative" in the sense that it is the "truth" of consciousness as "moral spirit" and that it irresistibly "points to" the fulfillment of its own "truth" in "Absolute Knowing," where the philosophical form of "knowing" is suited to the religious content of "believing," and where "thought" supersedes "representation" without thereby either losing or distorting its "object." It may well be that we must go beyond the pages of the Phenomenology if we are to appreciate fully Hegel's identification of the "God" of religion and the "Absolute" of "Absolute Knowing," but there is no reason why from the vantage-point of a more mature working out of Hegel's thinking we may not look back and interpret where the Phenomenology was "pointing." One thing is clear: Hegel was dissatisfied with the views of his contemporarieswhether with the absence of a philosophical absolute in Kant's thought, with an absolute which is the object of feeling or intuition in that of Jacobi or Schleiermacher, or with an absolute which is the starting-point rather than the result of philosophical enquiry, as it is for Fichte and Schelling. This dissatisfaction begins to surface as early as the unpublished Theologische Jugendschriften; it continues, still in somewhat tentative form in Hegel's earliest published writings, Die Differenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen Systems der Philosophie and Glauben und Wissen, on into the writings of the Jena period; it is, as we have seen, far less tentative in Phänomenologie des Geistes; ultimately it becomes most explicit in Wissenschaft der Logik and has its place in all subsequent writing, even, obliquely, in Philosophie des Rechts. In a very important sense the history of Hegel's dissatisfaction is autobiographical: in his formative years the most potent influences on the development of his philosophical thought were Kant, Fichte, and Schellingby a strange sort of reversal, perhaps due to his rereading the history of philosophy in light of his own Logic, the effective influence of Plato, Aristotle, the medieval theologians, and Spinoza manifests itself for the most part only subsequently. It was Kant's and Fichte's emphasis on the rationality of the "moral order" which opened the way for Hegel to a synthesis of the theoretical and the practical which was to issue in his version of "speculative thinking," and it was Schelling's insistence on the "identity" of "spirit" and "nature" which provided Hegel with the impetus to bridge
< previous page
page_23
next page >
< previous page
page_24
next page > Page 24
the seemingly yawning chasm between the subjective world of thought and the objective world of reality. The key to Hegel's dissatisfaction with all three, however, was the failure of each of them to come to grips either with religion as a fundamental mode of consciousness integral to the human spirit's orientation to the Absolute or with the Absolute itself as the focus of religion's thrust. We can take Kant's Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft of 1793 (Fichte's Kritik aller Offenbarung had preceded it by one year) as symbolic of Hegel's dissatisfaction, which was to grow with the years. Two expressions in Kant's title alone will provoke in Hegel a reaction which will develop into a "philosophy of religion" which is at the same time a philosophy of God. "Within the limits" will signify to Hegel that, for Kant, philosophical thinking is essentially "finite" and, therefore, incapable of coming to grips with an "infinite'' object; and "mere (blossen) reason" will tell him that Kant's "reason" is not reason at all but only "understanding" trying to stretch itself beyond its limited capacities. Kant, it is true, sees, as will Hegel, an identity of content in religious consciousness and in philosophical thought, but that "identity of content" is vastly different from what Hegel will ultimately take it to be. Not that Hegel will ever deny the close connection between religious truth and moral truth, but he will consistently refuse to identify them, especially in the interests of permitting philosophical "reason" to come to terms with religious truth. Like Hegel, Kant seeks to ground religion in reason, but, because for Kant this means giving a rational foundation for a subjective religious response, he is under no compulsion to assign to reason a task which, as an essentially finite human capacity, he is convinced it is not equipped to carry out. Reason must remain silent in regard to God, the ultimate object of religious orientationexcept to the extent that "moral reason" must "postulate" God as the guarantor of a happiness to which moral activity is ordered but which reason alone "cannot demand." Better still, perhaps, Kant will recognize "postulates" as "demands of reason which need not be met." Kant will appeal to reason to give an account of religious consciousness, but he is convinced from the start that "mere" reason can give only a very limited account. In human affairsand religion is a human affairmoral reason is supreme; it needs neither a superior being in order to know duty nor a superior motive in order to accomplish it.6 It is unquestionably helpful to see in moral duty the "will of God," but there is no rational demand that
6. Kant, Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft (Hamburg: Meiner, 1956), p. 3. Earlier Herder (Schriften, ed. Walter Flemmer [Munich: Goldman, 1960], p. 143) had criticized Kant for formulating a morality which for lack of adequate motivation resulted in no action: "It is easy to formulate a law which is not followed, which without motives even cannot be followed."
< previous page
page_24
next page >
< previous page
page_25
next page > Page 25
morality do this, even though there is a close parallel between morality's reverence for the moral law and religion's reverence for God. If morality recognizes in the sacredness of its law an object of greatest reverence, by the same token, on the level of religion morality represents in the form of a supreme cause completing those laws an object of adoration and thus becomes manifest in the majesty of this cause.7 It should be noted that morality, although it can be quite certain of the universal validity of its laws, can only "represent to itself" a "supreme cause completing those laws"; it cannot say unequivocally that there is such a cause or what this cause is. If there is a content to "supreme cause," it is supplied by religion, and reason has nothing to say about that aspect of religion. For Kant, religion is in principle subservient to morality. The only religious teaching which counts is moral teaching, which religion helpfully sets forth as the "will of God."8 God is, so to speak, the personified idea of the good principle,9 and religion consists in recognizing the demands of moral reason as divine commands,10 which is not to say that religion is not right in doing this, only that religion is not "rationally" justified in doing this. Religion (considered subjectively) is the recognition of all our duties as divine commands. The religion in which I must know ahead of time that something is a divine command in order to recognize it as my duty is revealed religion. . . ; on the other hand, the religion in which I must first know that something is duty before I can recognize it as a divine command is natural religion.11 It is instructive that, although Kant does not explicitly identify God and universal moral will (as does Fichte, after him), he nevertheless makes moral will the criterion for any rational approach to God. God is recognized, as it were, as the "universal lawgiver" of a moral law which "mere reason" can infallibly know to be true without knowing God. The authority of the law does not reside in its character as "divine" but in the intrinsic moral value reason finds in it. At the same time, however, we do "sanctify'' moral duty by interpreting it as God's command, and we honor God by observing 7. Ibid., p. 8.
8. Ibid., p. 10. 9. Ibid., p. 63. 10. Ibid., p. 92. 11. Ibid., p. 170. Since, fairly obviously, religion is for Kant significant to the extent that it shows the ends of moral reason, its object, God can well be a postulate of reason, without being an object of reason.
< previous page
page_25
next page >
< previous page
page_26
next page > Page 26
the duties dictated by reason, because we have interpreted them as God's commands;12 if they are dictates of moral reason they do have a sanctity to them. It is important to note that the reason here in question is individual reason (Kant's) universalized, that is, seen to be necessary.13 In the moral order, then, the "content" of religion and of philosophical reason is identical, but that content is law, not God. The only true religion contains nothing but laws, i.e., the sort of practical principles of whose unconditional necessity we can be conscious and which we can, therefore, recognize as revealed through pure reason (not empirically).14 The "Divinity" of Thought This is the Kant Hegel read during his formative years (interpreted, perhaps, through the eyes of Fichte), and his influence is recognizable in Theologische Jugendschriften, although even there Hegel's dissatisfaction has begun to manifest itself. That dissatisfaction comes to a head in the Phenomenology, where Hegel is striking out on uncharted waters. Here, Hegel effectively dissociates himself from the "rationalism" of the Enlightenment, whose criterion of rationality was, he thought, primarily negative; namely, opposition to authority of any kind, particularly religious. He also distances himself from the "critical philosophy" of Kant and Fichte, for whom the absolute rationality of the moral order bespeaks no direct connection between human and divine reason, but only the need the mind has to "represent" to itself a God whom nonrational religion supplies. What Hegel has doneand, it would seem, quite consciouslyis to insert his own thinking into the tradition of Plato, Aristotle, Plotinus, Anselm, and Spinoza, all of whom saw human rational thinking as somehow divine and oriented to the divine. Thought reveals itself as infinite activity, and infinite activity is seen to be activity of the infinite. This is not the place to unravel the intricacies of the development through which "spirit" goes in coming to a realization of its own infinity, nor, perhaps would it be possible to do so, if we did not have Science of Logic to use as a guide in interpreting the Phenomenology (which in his preface to the former Hegel authorizes us to do). One thing, however, is clear from a reading of the Phenomenology without appeal to later works for clarification: on the subjective side moral reason is not, for Hegel, the ultimate in rationality, since "absolute knowing,'' through the mediation of religious consciousness, transcends moral reason; on the objective side, "moral law" is the ultimate content neither of religion nor of philosophy, but rather "ab-
12. Ibid., p. 114. 13. Ibid., p. 143. 14. Ibid., p. 187.
< previous page
page_26
next page >
< previous page
page_27
next page > Page 27
solute Spirit" is. Whether or not those who assert that there is no justification for the claim that Hegel equates "absolute Spirit" and "God" have validated their own claim will be the subject of the rest of this study. On the face of it, Hegel's statement, in as unlikely a place as Philosophy of Right, that the "content" of ''philosophy" is "the comprehensive knowledge of God and [thus] of physical and spiritual nature" (GPR, p. 12) would seem to demand serious consideration. On the other hand, it should be too obvious to need textual demonstration that religious consciousness is consciousness of God, not consciousness of moral lawor whatever elsewhich permits the human mind to "represent" to itself a "supreme lawgiver," who, if there be such, adds a "sacredness" we do not really need. God is self-consciousness; he knows himself in a consciousness which is distinct from him, which is implicitly the consciousness of God, but is also this explicitly, since it knows its identity with God, an identity which is, however, mediated by the negation of finitude. It is this concept which constitutes the content of religion. This is what God is: to distinguish himself from himself, to be object to himself, and yet in this distinction to be simply identical with himselfto be Spirit. [VPR II, p. 187] Whether the "God" of religion and the "God" of philosophy are one and the same may still remain to be seen, but, once again, on the face of it Hegel would seem to give abundant evidence that this is precisely what he is saying: The God whom human self-consciousness implicitly knows in religion is one and the same God that human selfconsciousness (infinitized) knows philosophically. Religion, then, is itself the standpoint of the consciousness of the True, which is in and for itself; and it is consequently the stage of spirit at which the speculative content as such is object for consciousness. Religion is not consciousness of this or that truth in individual objects, but of the absolute truth, of truth as the universal, the all-comprehending, outside of which there lies nothing at all. The content of religious consciousness is further the universally True, which exists in and for itself, which determines itself, and is not determined from without. . . . It is this speculative element which comes to consciousness in religion. [VPR I, pp. 3031]15 Nor does he confine statements such as this to his explicit treatment of the philosophy of religion: philosophy as such and religion as such have one and the same objective, that is, truth, absolute truth, God.
15. It scarcely seems open to dispute that "speculative content" is the "absolutely true" to which the entire elaboration of Science of Logic is oriented.
< previous page
page_27
next page >
< previous page
page_28
next page > Page 28
First of all, it is true, philosophy has in common with religion that their objects (Gegenstände) are the same. Both have the truth as their object, and that in the highest sensei.e., that God and God alone is the truth. In addition both treat the sphere of the finite, nature and human spirit, their relation to each other, and the relation of both to God as their truth. [EpW, no. 1] Although, then, Hegel in no way denies the close connection between religion and morality, he has come a long way from the Kantian position that religion stands in the service of morality. Nor did Hegel adopt the diametrically opposed position that morality is subservient to religionhe was careful in all matters to avoid either-or options. In a very significant sense he continued to agree with Kant that the moral roots of religious consciousness were not to be ignored. True religion, or religiousness, arises only out of morality; it is thinking morality, i.e., a morality becoming conscious of the free universality of its concrete essence. Only from the standpoint of morality are we conscious of God as free spirit. It is vain, then, to look for true religion or religiousness apart from the moral spirit. [Ibid., no. 552] The point of all this, however, is to insist that what is important for the human spirit is to be in the service of truth, which it is in philosophy, and that by serving the truth it is serving God. In a text which highlights the intimate relation not only of religion and philosophy but also of art to the highest truth, to God, Hegel makes his point very clear. By occupying itself with the true as the absolute object (Gegenstand) of consciousness, then, art too belongs to the absolute sphere of spirit and, therefore, from the point of view of its content, along with religion . . . and philosophy, art stands on the same ground. For philosophy, too, has no other object but God and is, thus, essentially rational theology, and because it is in the service of truth, it is enduring service of God. [VA 1, p. 139]16 But, Hegel is not saying, along with Kant, that moral reasoning comes first and is "absolute," finding only a kind of "sacralizing" prop in the religious "representation" of God. What he is saying is that "truth" comes first, that ''absolute truth" is God, and that to seek truth, whether morally (in the realm of "objective spirit") or artistically, religously, and philosophically (in the realm of "absolute Spirit") is to seek God. If, then, we say that philosophy ("speculative thinking") and religion
16. The German term Hegel uses is Gottesdienst, which translates the Latin liturgia, Greek leiturigia *, and could be rendered in English by "liturgy."
< previous page
page_28
next page >
< previous page
page_29
next page > Page 29
("religious consciousness") have the same content but in a different form, just what are we saying? Perhaps we can get at the meaning of what we are saying by first turning to two levels of enquiry which do not have the same contentempirical science and philosophy. We have just seen that, for Hegel, the content of philosophy is the "comprehensive knowledge of God and [thus] of physical and spiritual nature." We have also seen that both philosophy and religion have the same "objects" (Gegenstände) in common, "truth . . . in the highest sense, [which is] God,'' and both treat finite reality, that is, "nature and the human spirit." To say, however, that religion and philosophy "treat" (handeln) nature and finite spirit is not to say that as "objects" (Gegenstände) they come under the "content" of philosophy; only their "truth" does, and truth is fully true only as "absolute truth," or as related to "absolute truth." Thus, for Hegel, there is a "philosophy of nature" and a "philosophy of spirit" (subjective and objective), but the "content" of such philosophy is not the same as that of "empirical science," even though the latter shares with philosophy "the formal aspect of thinking," the "universal in experience" (EGP, p. 158). In "science," then, we can have a "content" which is "empirical" and a "form" which is "philosophical"; whereas in philosophy both "content" and "form" belong to thought and to thought alone. From this diversity of content and identity of form we can now turn once more to the identity of content and diversity of form in religion and philosophy. If it is true to say that short of a "comprehensive knowledge" of "absolute truth," philosophical thinking has not attained to "knowledge of truth" at all, then it is also true to say that only "absolute truth" can be the adequate "content" of philosophy. But "God and God alone is the truth," and, thus "philosophy, too, has no other object but God." Are we correct then, in claiming that when Hegel says "religion" is "consciousness . . . of the absolute truth" or that "it is this speculative content which comes to consciousness in religion," he is saying that the "truth," which is "God and God alone," is one and the same in philosophy and religion? The conclusion, it would seem, is difficult to avoid, unless one wishes to say that Hegel has two different meanings for the term "God," and that is difficult to prove. What, then, of "form"? The "form" of thinking of which God is the "content" in religion, Hegel says, is not the "form" of thinking of which God is the "content" in philosophy. What does this mean? Minimally it would seem to have to mean that, although the "God" of whom each thinks is the same (there is only one God), the way in which each thinks of God is different. For some, of course, this can mean nothing more than that "belief" (faith) and "knowledge" (reason) are not the same. In view, however, of Hegel's ongoing controversy with the "theologians" of his day, which begins to take definitive shape as early as 1802 in Glauben und
< previous page
page_29
next page >
< previous page
page_30
next page > Page 30
Wissen, it is imperative to see in the distinction of "form" both more and less than did those "theologians." It is necessary to see more, because it is not sufficient to be content either with the ''Enlightenment's" simplistic conception of "reason" or with "Pietism's" simplistic view of "faith"17 (see PdG, pp. 385407); and less, because at the hands of Kant, Fichte, Jacobi, and Schleiermacher, the distinction tends to be seen in terms of a dichotomy rather than a continuity. If knowledge is interpreted as a function of subjective thinking and faith as a function of subjective feeling, intuition, or what have you, the likelihood that either the distinction or the continuity will ever be grasped in their truth is slim indeed. What it comes down to, Hegel tells us, is the prejudice, inherited from the Enlightenment (aided and abetted by Pietism) that philosophy is supremely rational (the "reason" of the "philosopher") and that faith is simply nonrational (if not irrational). Hegel has many pungent things to say about this prejudice, particularly in his critique of the Enlightenment in the Phenomenology and other works, in his abundant criticisms of Kant18particularly of the latter's attitude expressed succinctly in the statement, "I had to suspend (aufheben) knowledge in order to make room for faith"19and in scattered remarks about the "modern theologians" who want to confine the approach to God to "immediate" feelings or intuition. The issue is highlighted in Hegel's Introduction in Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie, wherein he is trying to characterize philosophy in such a way as to justify saying that it has a "history." He tells us that philosophy is the highest form in which spirit reveals itself at any time or place (EGP, pp. 3839). To say that it is the "highest form," however, is not to say that it is the "only" form. There are also nonphilosophical ways in which the "absolute idea" (spirit) can be present in thought, and these are art and religion"the way in which the supreme idea is present for nonphilosophical consciousness, for sensitive, intuitive, representational consciousness" (ibid., p. 42) (hence, "art" and "religion" as integral to the "philosophy of absolute Spirit" in the Encyclopedia; hence Vorlesungen über die Aesthetik and Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion). It would be a mistake, however, to look upon this nonphilosophical presence as nonrational; it is not totally spiritualsince only "pure" thought is thatbut it is eminently rationalso long as it is oriented to and continuous with the supremely spiritual form. As we shall see later (chap. 5,
17. What comes out in these pages of the Phenomenology is the view that Enlightenment and Pietism are but two sides of the same coin. Insisting on its own "reason" the former is merely negating the naiveté of pietistic "belief," and the latter is taking Enlightenment "reason" far too seriously. 18. For a more extended study of these criticisms, see Quentin Lauer, S.J., "Hegel's Critique of Kant's Theology," in God Knowable and Unknowable, ed. Robert J. Roth, S.J. (New York: Fordham University Press, 1973), pp. 85105. 19. Kant, KrV B., P. xxx.
< previous page
page_30
next page >
< previous page
page_31
next page > Page 31
"Proofs of God"), a content can be supremely "rational" without having been discovered by subjectively rational thinking. (It has been remarked above that, like philosophy, so too religion must first of all be comprehended, i.e., it must be recognized and acknowledged as rational.) For religion is the work of self-revealing reason, its supreme, most rational work. Those are but absurd notions according to which priests out of self-serving deceit have simply manufactured a religion . . . . Rather, this region of the spirit is the sanctuary in which the remaining deception of the sense-world, of finite representations and goals, the region of opinion and arbitrariness, has been dissolved. [Ibid, p. 43] There is much in the above quotation which will have to await the next chapter for its explication. One thing, however, is clear: That the truth as presented in art and religion is not the conclusion of "subjectively rational argumentation" (Räsonnieren) is no indication that the truth of it is nonrational. Its presence in the mind is the result of rational activity, which is not synonymous with "logical argument" nor with merely subjective thinking. What makes the content of consciousness "rational'' is not the rationality of the procedure whereby the truth was arrived atwhich does not mean that rational procedure should be ignored or abandonedbut the internal rationality of the content. In fact, the procedure in question will be authentically rational only if it accords with the inherent rationality of its object; no "reasoning" at all can make the claim for itself of being rational, if the conclusion at which it arrives is not rational. For the purposes of an exercise in formal logic, perhaps, one can by a perfectly correct procedure arrive at a nonsensical conclusion, but that is merely the game of reasoningwhich has but little to do with "reason." The Rationality of the Religious Hegel, however, is saying a great deal more than that. He is saying that, if reason characterizes the human, then reason sets its mark on whatever is specifically human, be it thought, intuition, emotion, or "representation." This does not mean that whatever is the object of intuition, feeling, representation is eo ipso rational and true; it does mean that to the extent that the object of consciousness is not rational, not true, to that same extent the consciousness is not authentically human. One is not being authentically human if one's intuitions or feelings come up with what is irrational. By the same token, however, if what intuition comes up with is a truly rational content, reason has not been absent from the "thinking" in question. There is an affinity in man for what is rational: "Whatever is human, rational, finds an echo in us, in our feeling, emotion, heart, in our subjectivity in
< previous page
page_31
next page >
< previous page
page_32
next page > Page 32
general" (EGP, p. 48). "Universal reason"which, for Hegel, is not individual subjective reason abstractly universalizedreveals itself best in human reason properly so called, but it is not limited to that manifestation. We might put it this way: If the content of an affirmation is true, it is rational; the subjective process of arriving at the affirmation may not be rational, but this does not take away from the rationality of the contentnor of the human response to it. Concretely this is saying that if God, absolute truth, absolute Spirit, is objectively supremely rational, then, even if the affirmation of that truth is not itself a supremely rational activity, as it is not in art or religion, still it is the affirmation of what is rational and, as such, partakes of the rationality of its content. In no way does this mean that as human beings we should be satisfied with a procedure which is less than rational in coming to grips with inherently rational objectivityin fact it is the function of philosophical thinking to transform thought which is inadequately rational in form into adequately rational thoughtbut it does help us to understand what Hegel means when he says that the presence of truth to the mind is rational; it is rational that the mind should think what is objectively rational. As we shall see, "speculative thinking" is the adequately rational procedure which has "speculative truth" (the rational) as its "content," but this does not mean that as the subjective thinking of any individual philosopher it discovers ultimate rational truth. This truth can be discovered (made manifest) to thought at a level of less than total rationality and then be ''transformed (speculatively, "spiritually") into the rational form proper to it. (See chap. 7, "Philosophy and Theology.") It is here that the distinction between "immediate" and "mediated" becomes important. Basically "immediate" refers to that which is "given" in consciousness without the intervention of transforming"mediating"thought. It is the "immediacy" of which Hegel speaks in the first chapter of the Phenomenology in reference to "sense certainty"; it is the "immediacy" of the first content of thought, that is, "being," in Science of Logic. That no consciousness or content of consciousness is "absolutely" immediate, since both immediate consciousness and its immediate content are seen to be "mediated," if by nothing else, by each other, is of no great consequence here. What is important is that no relatively "immediate given," whether empirical "data" or the object of faith "given" in revelation, can remain simply as "given" but must be mediated by the hard labor of rational thinking in order that it may reveal its own inherent rationality. What is characteristic of "knowing" in the truly "spiritual" sense is that it is in no way "immediate," not even relatively (VGP II, p. 494). The distinction between "immediate" and "mediated" becomes particularly important for Hegel when he comes to the question of "knowing" God, the God in whom religion "believes," the only "God" of whom it will
< previous page
page_32
next page >
< previous page
page_33
next page > Page 33
make any sense to speak of as being "known," since, when the nonactual is known, it is not in truth known. The problem of human mind as "finite" capacity coming to grips with God as ''infinite Being" is not, of course, one which became crucial only with the advent of Kant. It is a problem which worried Saint Augustine and the medieval Scholastics, notably Saint Anselm and Saint Thomas Aquinas. It is to be noted, however, that in seeking a solution to the problem, each of these men, "theologians" though they were, manifested a greater confidence in human reason than did Kant, or, for that matter, the Enlightenment "rationalists," for all of whom a rational knowledge" of God was simply out of the question. What saved the medieval thinkers, perhaps, was their faith in reason, which issued in the confidence that "faith" could "seek understanding" and could bring reason to bear on the questions not only of whether God is but also of what God ishowever limited they may have thought the answer to the second question would be and however close they tied their answer to what "divine revelation" and the "teaching" of the church had already made known. Given the influence of Kant, however, Hegel had a rather different problem to face: not only that of vindicating the capacity of reason to know God but also that of counteracting the opposite convictiona reactionthat God could indeed be known, but only "immediately," either in the sense that scripture tells us all we need to know or that "feeling" or "intuition" were adequate to the task which thought could not accomplish. "Through Kantian and Jacobian philosophy the public was strengthened in its conviction that knowledge of God is immediate, that one knows right off the bat (von Haus aus), without having to study" (VGP III, p. 414). That this sort of "immediate" knowledge told the "public" no more than "that" God is, leaving the name "God" to stand for an indeterminate "I-know-not-what" seems to have caused little disturbance either among the pious or among the "Deists." Finally, immediate consciousness of God is supposed to go no further than telling us that God is, not what God is; for the latter would be an act of cognition, demanding mediated knowing. Thus God as immediate object of religion is expressly limited to God in general, to the indeterminate supra-sensible, and religion is, as far as its content is concerned, reduced to a minimum. If it were really necessary to accomplish only so much that the belief, there is a God, would still be retained, or perhaps, that such a belief should come to be, then one could only wonder at the poverty of an era which lets the merest pittance of religious knowledge count as a gain and has had in its church to seek refuge at the altar which long ago stood in Athens, the altar dedicated to the unknown god. [EpW, no. 73] What is gradually coming to the fore here is Hegel's unshakable convic
< previous page
page_33
next page >
< previous page
page_34
next page > Page 34
tionprephilosophical rather than philosophical in characterthat the "content" of religion, that is, what is believed, particularly in the Christian religion, which he calls "absolute religion," is "rational" and, therefore, suited to a human mind attuned to rationality. What is rational, however, must also be developed rationally, and this development, too, is characteristic of Christian religion; its beliefs cannot simply stand still but must unfold. Because Christian religious consciousness is in principle knowing (Erkenntnis), it develops its content; for its ideas (Vorstellungen) regarding its overall object (Gegenstand) are given to it as in themselves thoughts, and as thoughts they must expand. [VPR I, p. 26]20 As products of "thought," Vorstellungen here stand somewhere between mere acceptance of what is given and conceptual comprehension. On the other hand, because the content belongs essentially to representation, it is thus distinguished from immediate opinion (Meinung) or intuition and pierces right through the distinction. In short, over-against subjectivity the content counts as absolute, as being in and for itself. [Ibid] Merely as religious consciousness, then, Christianity is not a "knowing" in the full sense (Wissen), but it involves a movement away from immediate acceptance toward "knowing." Christian religion, therefore, of itself touches on the opposition between feeling or immediate intuition and reflection or knowing. [Ibid., pp. 2627] What it comes down to is that what Christians believe has a thought-ful content; it is something for the mind, not simply for feeling. Here we come, willy nilly, on the distinction between "representation" (Vorstellung) and "concept" (Begriff), which will be of utmost importance not only for the distinction between philosophy and religion but also for their relation to each other. Scholars have always had difficulty translating the term Vorstellung, particularly as Hegel uses it. It should be obvious from what has gone before that the term cannot be translated by "image"; it belongs too clearly to the realm of thought and not to that of sensibility or imagination (unless, of course, the meaning of the latter term is broadened considerably). It is not totally incorrect to translate Vorstellung as "image thinking," but in this the stress on ''image" would seem to be too strong,
20. The "in themselves" (an sich) here is important: as thoughts only an sich, Vorstellungen, have a true content only implicitly; the content must developexpand.
< previous page
page_34
next page >
< previous page
page_35
next page > Page 35
unless, of course, we can think of a "spiritual" image (see WG, pp. 134, 172). "Representation" is, perhaps, not the best possible translation, but it has two advantages: (1) it captures the nuance of the ''notion" which finite mind "forms" for itself in "representing" its object to itself; and (2) as Hegel himself observes,21 it conveys the additional meaning of "standing for" (stellvertretend or repräsentierend) the object which is not yet totally "spiritually" present to the mind. When the Christian, then, hears the "word of God"be it in scripture, Church teaching, or preachinghe forms for himself Vorstellungen which he must "think through" in order to arrive at Begriffe which are only implicitly present in the Vorstellungen. That Hegel's "representation" has not yet totally freed itself from sensible "image-content" is clear enough, but it leans, so to speak, more in the direction of "concept" than of "image." It has to be noted, of course, that Vorstellung covers a gamut of meanings, ranging from almost image to almost pure thought (e.g., "notion," "idea"). When Hegel says, then, that the "content" of religion and philosophy is the "same," but that the "form" is different (in the former the form is "representation," which is not adequate to the content, while in the latter the form is "concept," which is adequate to the content) we must use utmost caution in interpreting him. What adds to the difficulty is that although Hegel's more constant distinction is that between Vorstellung and Begriff, sometimes he distinguishes between Vorstellen and Denken, even though, as in the above quotation, he also says that Vorstellung belongs to the realm of Gedanke. We must interpret this: As I see it, his meaning is that Gedanke may be either in the form of Vorstellung or Begriff, but only the latter is the form of Denken in the fullest and most precise sense of that term. In any event, what Hegel is trying to do is clear enough. Having disposed of the contention that, because human "knowing" is essentially finite, its object too must be essentially finite, he sets up a distinction which will make his denial of that contention intelligible. As the activity of an essentially finite subject human thinking is essentially finite, and the form in which its "thoughts" (Gedanken) are cast is that of "representation," which is simply not adequate to an infinite object. This is human "thinking" (Denken) in its role as "understanding" (Verstand), and it is adequate only to "abstract" objects. As the activity of "spirit" which is neither merely human nor merely finite, "thinking" (Denken) in its role as "reason" (Vernunft) is adequate to its object as "concrete" (totalized). The "thoughts" (Gedanken) of the human "spirit," however, need not remain at the level of "representation": they can be raised to the level of "concept" (Begriff), and when they are they partake of the all-embracing universality of "thinking" (Denken)
21. See PdG, p. 216.
< previous page
page_35
next page >
< previous page
page_36
next page > Page 36
whose form is "concept in-and-for-itself" (Begriff an-und-für-sich). The object of this "conceptual thinking" is ''infinite." All of this will have to await chapters 2 and 4 for further elucidation. Knowing and Believing If nothing else, what has been said here should alert us to the nuances of meaning contained in Hegel's statement that "the more highly cultivated consciousness" cannot be satisfied with religious thinking of its object, because only when "thinking" is "knowing" is the mind satisfied. This Aufhebung of the "form" of religious thinking is neither the "cancellation" of religion nor its "downgrading"; it is its "completion" and "justification" as authentically human. There is no question in Hegel's mind that religious Vorstellungen, derived as they can be from a variety of sources, can and do contain truth. Only, however, when they have been adequately "thought out" can they satisfy the educated mind, which is not to say that the "educated mind" can then discard them.22 Philosophy, then, has the same purpose and content as religion, only as thinking, not as representation. The form (Gestalt) of religion, therefore, does not satisfy the more highly cultivated consciousness, which must want to know, to transcend (aufheben) the form (Form) of religion, but only in order to justify its content. This, then, not the historical, the scholarly, the extrinsic, is the true justification. The eternal does not have its grounding in the temporal, in facts, etc. What does that is the testimony of spirit. [BS, p. 15] What this is saying is that philosophy is itself a form of religion, the highest formGottesdienst (see above, p. 14 and note 16) and that to comprehend God in "systematic thinking" is religious activity"worship" in purest "interiority." For religion, in which God is for consciousness initially an external objectbecause we must first be taught what God is and how he has revealed
22. Authentic religious representation has a content which is supremely rational. In characteristically empathic fashion Emil Fackenheim interprets Hegel as authentically Christian in his approach. "In the above brief account, one decisive characteristic is not mentionedthat religious representation moves toward, but fails to reach, the universality of speculative thought. . . . We may presently only say, negatively, that the thought in question is not finite reflection and that it does not expose religious representation as mere human projection and illusion as it reflects on it. Careless readers have always mistaken it for such a reflection, and they have therefore viewed Hegel as a demythologizing enemy of religious faith. In fact, however, Hegel regards a thought of this kind as inferior to religious representation and declares himself to be in alliance with Christianity or Theology against it (e.g., Werke XI, pp. 28 ff.; XII, pp. 350 ff.)." E. Fackenheim, The Religious Dimension in Hegel's Thought (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967), p. 155.
< previous page
page_36
next page >
< previous page
page_37
next page > Page 37
himself and still doesoccupies itself, it is true, with the interior, moves and inspires the community. Still the interiority of devotion limited to emotion and representation is not the highest form of interiority. It is selfdetermining (freies) thinking which has to be recognized as this purest form of knowing. It is in this that science brings the same content to consciousness and thus becomes that spiritual worship which, by systematic thinking appropriates and comprehends what is otherwise only the content of subjective sentiment or representation. [V A I, p. 143] This "scientific" comprehension of the truth contained in religious Vorstellungen is no less profoundly religious than is religious consciousness in its representational form. When Hegel says, then, that the religious form of consciousness is not satisfactory for the "more highly cultivated consciousness"by which he clearly means highly educated modern manhe is evidently talking about "religion" in the way he has described it in the seventh chapter of the Phenomenology and in his Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion; that is, as a consciousness of the divine dependent on a "revelation," whether that be contained in created nature, art, the word of the Bible, or the incarnate Word of Christianity. This revelation has a ''content," and "religious consciousness" expresses that content in the form of "representation," which the religious mind employs to translate the revelation into products of the human mind in "seeking" to "understand" it. This may or may not be what others mean by religion; it is certainly not what medieval theologians like Anselm and Aquinas meant by "faith seeking understanding," which was not so much man looking for "representations" to interpret the content of faith as it was faith itself seeking a "rational understanding" of itselfthe "rational understanding" being part and parcel of the "faith" in question. It is significant in this connection that, when Hegel composed his Lectures on Proofs of God's Reality, he conceived them as an extension, not of his philosophy of religion but of his logic,23 and that his most extensive treatment of the "ontological argument," which he considers to be the most valid, is contained in his Science of Logic (see chap. 5). If, however, we consider all he has to say about the "religious" character of philosophy itself and about the confidence in reason manifested by the medieval theologians, we may find that he is not so far from them after all. That he distances himself, on the other hand, quite definitively from the "theologians" who are his own contemporaries is abundantly clear. These "modern theologians" (presumably under the influence of the Enlightenment) do what the "Scholastics" never dreamt of doing; they make "faith"
23. See chapter 5, " 'Proofs' of God," pp. 211212. It might be well to note here that it was not Hegel but his editors, who appended Vorlesungen über die Beweise vom Dasein Gottes to Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion.
< previous page
page_37
next page >
< previous page
page_38
next page > Page 38
and "knowledge" discontinuous, and in so doing they either surrender faith to "feeling and intuition" or they degrade knowledge to the level of abstract "understanding" by means of "representations" which simply do not do justice to the content of faithabove all to Hegel's Lutheran faith which rests on the "interior testimony of the Spirit.''24 The time has come, then, to get back to that "interior testimony of the Spirit." It is a traditional commonplace that God reveals himself in nature, either because the very existence of a nature which cannot account for itself cries out for an infinite "first cause" which does account for nature's finite existence (cosmological proof), or because the rationality manifested in the nature we observe bespeaks a supremely intelligent cause of that nature (physicotheological proof). In Hegel's view, however, God does not manifest himself to man primarily in "nature" but in the activity of the human spirit; it is the human spirit, after all, which makes nature the mirror of God (EGP, p. 201). What is more, God also reveals himself preeminently in the symbols of religion, which, again, are manmade but not arbitrary; they are the human spirit's way of permitting God to come into human consciousness (ibid., pp. 5557). The point is that in religion (or religions) men have expressed the consciousness they actually have of the supreme being, and no matter how subjective the form of expressing may be, the expressing itself is a function of reason, since what is expressed is supremely rational (ibid., p. 168). Now, although supremely rational truth is "contained" in religious consciousness, its presence is a "given" which religion as such cannot verify; only the process of "thought" can (ibid., pp. 17374). When the divine Spirit is present to the human spirit in thought, the divine is present in the medium proper to itself and not merely in a "representation" standing for it, and it is for this reason that only philosophy "knows" God, who manifests himself to the human in that activity which is most proper to spirit. The difference between individual and universal spirit, then, should be expressed thus: the subjective, individual spirit is25 the universal, divine Spirit to the extent that the former is rationally conscious of the latter, to the extent that the latter manifests itself in each subject, each man. Thus, the spirit which is rationally conscious of absolute Spirit is subjective spirit. [Ibid., p. 176] It would be a mistake, however, to conclude from this that philosophical "knowing" can dispense with "religious consciousness." In fact, the very
24. What Hegel has to say in the final section ("The Religion of Revelation") in the seventh chapter of PdG and in "Absolute Religion," the culmination of VPR, makes this abundantly clear. 25.The difficulty of integrating Hegel's use of the copula "is" is admirably illustrated here. In this citation only this "is" clearly connotes orientation, movement to; for the rest he employs "is" as the simple prepositional copula.
< previous page
page_38
next page >
< previous page
page_39
next page > Page 39
logic of the situation precludes this; de facto not every individual human being, not even every philosopher, knows God. The human spirit needs the revelation "given" in religion in order to be able by its own activity to think the revealed content through. There is even a sort of parallel to this in man's knowledge of "nature." The "thinking through" which is the "knowing'' of nature is entirely man's "spiritual" activity, but that nature be "given" in sense perception is a precondition for the spiritual activity.26 That, for Hegel, philosophy in this sense "needs" religion is eloquently expressed by Emil Fackenheim: It is a central Hegelian doctrine that the true religion already is the true "content," lacking merely the true "form" of speculative thought; that philosophy could not reach truth unless its true content pre-existed in religion; that philosophic thought therefore requires religion as its basis in life, and that the true philosophy, in giving the true religious content its true form of thought, both transfigures religion and produces itself.27 Thus, when Hegel tells us that religion and philosophy have the same content, he really intends to tell us more about philosophy than about religion. What he intends to tell us is that, in the concreteness of "life," it is only when philosophical thinking passes beyond its empirical beginnings to that which is its inescapable objectfreedom, spirit, Godis it authentically philosophical thinking. At the present time religion has more and more contracted its cultivated expansion of its content and retreated into the intensity of piety or of feeling, frequently indeed a feeling which manifests a thin and scanty content. As long as religion has a creed, a doctrine, a system of dogma, it has that with which philosophy can occupy itself, thus uniting itself in this with religion. This, however, is not to be understood in the bad, separatist sense, which restricts contemporary religiousness, making it interpret both religion and philosophy in such a way that they are mutually exclusive, so separated that unity can only be imposed from without. Rather what is also implied in what we have already seen is that religion may well exist without philosophy, but not philosophy without religion; philosophy includes religion. [EpW., pref. to 2nd ed. 1827, p, 12, Meiner] In the words of Henry Harris, Hegel's mature system of philosophy "grows out of what was called 'religion' before."28
26. Obviously one should not push the parallel too far; neither is the mode of "givenness" the same, nor is the "inner testimony" of "Spirit" operative other than, perhaps, obliquely in coming to grips conceptually with nature. 27. Fackenheim, Religious Dimension, p. 23. Note the point made that it is in "life," not in the abstract, that philosophy needs religion. 28. H. S. Harris. Hegel's Development (Oxford: Clarendon, 1971), p. 391.
< previous page
page_39
next page >
< previous page
page_40
next page > Page 40
In the concreteness of life, then, Hegel would say, "belief" comes before "knowledge," religious belief before ''speculative" philosophy. But the mind cannot stand still; it must go on to a "knowing" of what it initially "believes." This it can do, however, only if it goes beyond a Kantian philosophy of "understanding" which, in fact "has placed God beyond knowing as indeterminate, without predicates, without properties" (BS, p. 70). This philosophy has given to this kind of understanding a correct consciousness of itself, namely that it is incapable of knowing truth. But, because it has viewed mind as nothing but such an understanding, it has come up with the universal propositionas though apart from God there could be absolute objects or a truth at allthat man can know nothing of God or of anything which is in itself. [Ibid.]29 Whether or not the criticism of Kant is justified, the words tell us clearly enough what Hegel's own position was. One wonders how in the light of texts such as those we have just seen, and they could be multiplied, Richard Schacht can say, "This self-realizing 'system' is the essential nature of the whole of reality and of the only God Hegel recognizes."30 The point that Hegel is constantly making is the one he makes in the introduciton to Science of Logic that the only possible starting point for philosophizing is "God as he is in his eternal being before the creation of the world or of a single finite spirit" (WL I, p. 31). If one's own "logic" tells one that this cannot be, then one is forced, I suppose, to say that, "the only God Hegel recognizes" is not the God of transcendent faith. In criticizing Kant and Fichte, however, what Hegel is actually saying is that, if philosophy cannot "know" God, then neither can faith know what it "believes" (GW, pp. 1314), "since the religious mode of representation does not make use of the critique of thought, it does not comprehend itself" (EpW, no. 573). To speak in a very simplified way (which will be remedied in the next chapter), thinking in general begins in sense experience with what is "immediately given." The thinking subject then "reflects" on its experience and forms "representations" which reproduce experience in the form of abstract generalities. Only when thinking, however, reflects on its own reflection, thinking it through ("speculative thinking"), can it become "knowledge" in the strict sense. Religious thinking, then, can be said to follow a parallel course. It begins with what is "immediately given"be it written or spoken words, man-made images, or, perhaps, nature itselfas
29. As early as Differenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen Systems der Philosophie Hegel has equally harsh words to say of Fichte. 30. Richard Schacht, Hegel and After (Pittsburgh: University Press, 1975), p. 7; see pp. 6768, 127.
< previous page
page_40
next page >
< previous page
page_41
next page > Page 41
the result of which it forms to itself "representations" of the "supreme Being." Here, Hegel says, religion runs the risk of not passing on to the highest stage of thinking, either because it is satisfied with the "givens'' and the "representations" they call up or because it is convinced that, where the "Absolute" is in question, there is no "higher stage" to which it can go. In this, we might say, the person of simple faith who is not a "critical thinker" has the advantage over the sophisticated "theologians" who are "critical thinkers"; the former is not satisfied with "words," which do not say enough, nor with "representations" which are too abstract to say anything. Let the "critical theologians" tell the common man what his religious thinking is; he is not likely to pay much attention. When we Europeans say, "God is the supreme Being" this predicate is just as abstract and empty as is the word "God," and the metaphysics of understanding which denies knowledge of God, i.e., knowing what characterizes him, and demands that the notion (Vorstellung) of God be confined to this abstraction, is destined to know nothing more of God than it does of what Brahm is. Despite this critical wisdom the European notion will in general contain this: that in using the expression "supreme Being" and even more the word "God," it has before it something concrete, God as Spirit, and that what the notion means is richer and fuller than what it says. [BS, pp. 13839] What the "critical mind" can be satisfied with the "religious heart" cannot: God must be a reality, not an abstraction, not an indefinite object of whom content-full predicates cannot be said. If the concept of God is viewed as that of abstract "most real Being," then God becomes for us a mere "out there," and of that there can be no further talk of knowing, for where there is no qualification no knowledge is possible. Pure light is pure darkness. [Ep W, no. 36, Zusatz] Philosophy of God Once again, Hegel may or may not be fair in his criticism of "critical philosophy," but it is significant that the criticism flows from a philosophy of religion which is worlds apart from that, say, of Kant or Fichte. Hegel will have none of a philosophy of religion which confines itself to an analysis of the subjective response to notions which are not thought through and, hence, contain no knowledge. There is, in fact, a very significant sense in which Hegel's philosophy of religion is not a philosophy of religion at allexcept, perhaps, in the Phenomenology, where "Religion" is explicitly treated as a stage in the evolution of consciousness toward "absolute knowing." Hegel's is rather a philosophy of God, that is, of religion's "object." In religion, God, "absolute truth," is present to consciousness; it is
< previous page
page_41
next page >
< previous page
page_42
next page > Page 42
philosophy's task to plumb the depths of that "absolute truth" and, in so doing, to discover what its own truth is. What God is is for us who possess religion a familiar object, a content which is present in subjective consciousness; but from the scientific point of view God is initially a general abstract name, which has as yet received no true content. For only philosophy of religion is the development and knowledge of what God is, and it is through this philosophy that we first experience in a knowing way what God is. God is this very familiar (be-kannte) notion, but one which is not known (er-kannte) in the sense of being scientifically developed. [VPR I, p. 92] The content of religious consciousness, then, is rational, just as rational as is the content of speculative philosophy, because it is one and the same content. Only because the content of religion is objectively rational can philosophy "think" it, "know" it. Conversely, it can be said, if philosophy cannot think the content, then that content is not rationalwhich, of course, is what Hegel's adversaries would saybut, if it is not rational, is the consciousness of it adequately human? It is clear from his "Philosophy of Subjective Spirit" that Hegel does not completely discredit the nonrational in human behavior, but in religion he will have none of itor, perhaps, he will lift what is nonrational in it to rationality, and thus "revealed (geoffenbarten) religion becomes manifest (offenbare) religion."31 There are, however, two ways in which one can say that God, "absolute truth,'' "absolute Spirit," is the object of reason. (1) It can mean that human reason, functioning as reason, can come to a knowledge of God; or (2) it can mean that God, as "absolute truth," "absolute Spirit," having in him absolutely no admixture of the sensible, being pure spiritual activity, can be the object of reason only, because only reason is purely spiritual activity, having in it no admixture of sense activity.32 It is quite obvious that one can make the statement, "God is the object of reason" in the second sense without making it in the first sense; but it is doubtful that one can make the statement in the first sense without making it in the second sense too. In any event, when he makes the statement in the first sense, Hegel quite clearly intends both senses, precisely because he holds the statement in the second sense to be true. What it comes down to is that "on God's part there can be no obstacle to a knowledge of him by men" (BDG, p. 48). God can reveal himself to the human spirit; it would be a limitation
31. See PdG, pp. 52830. It would seem that one is thus justified in entitling the final section in the chapter of the Phenomenology on "Religion" as "Revealed Religion," even though "die offenbare Religion" literally means "manifest religion." 32. Quite obviously this means in addition that one's affirmation of God's reality is objectively rational, no matter what the subjective source of the affirmation may be.
< previous page
page_42
next page >
< previous page
page_43
next page > Page 43
to the purity of "absolute Spirit" if he could not. It bespeaks no limitation at all in God to say, "God cannot reveal himself to nature, to the stone, to the plant, to the animal [it would be to assert a contradiction to say that he could] because God is spirit." Spirit can reveal itself to spirit alone, because spirit alone can receive a communication which has nothing of the sensible about it. God, therefore, "can reveal himself to man only, who thinks and is spirit" (ibid., p. 49). If God cannot reveal himself to man, then, this inability must be due either to the inability of the human spirit in its finitude to receive the revelationand this cuts out religion entirelyor "it is owing to human caprice, to an affection of humility, or whatever you like to call it, that the finitude of knowledge, of the human reason, is put in contrast to the divine knowledge and the divine reason, and that the limits of human reason are asserted to be immovable and absolutely fixed'' (ibid.). It might, of course, be countered, as it was by Kant, Fichte, Jacobi, and Schleiermacher, that God reveals himself to man but not to man's "reason," which might well provoke the query, how can God reveal himself to man, if he does not do so through man's highest capacity? Hegel is not about to deny that man cannot know God, if God does not reveal himself; what he does claim is that in revealing himself it is to the human spirit, which is reason functioning at its highest pitch, that God communicates. One is reminded in all this of the medieval disputes about the distinction between intellectus and ratio, in which knowledge of God was assigned to intellectus but not to ratio. We must remember, however, that for the Scholastics intellectus meant "intellectual intuition" and ratio meant "discursive thinking." For Hegel, Vernunft, which is the equivalent of the Greek nonV *, combines "dialectically" both intellectus and ratio: intellectus without ratio is what he calls "mere intuition," the intuition of Jacobi and Schleiermacher; ratio without intellectus is mere Räsonnieren (ratiocination), the function of Verstand (understanding), not of Vernunft (reason). Human Spirit as Divine Revelation God's revelation, then, is not simply a communication to man of knowledge about God; it is self-revelation in the sense that God communicates himself to man. This communication of himself to man is not contained primarily in words (or signs or symbols) but in the human "spirit" which is the revelation of the divine in man, the presence of the divine in man. Because even infinite Spirit can communicate himself only finitelyother than to himselfthe human spirit is finite, but its link to the infinite makes it essentially oriented to the infinite, to "knowing" God. Thus, God not only can reveal himself to man; he does reveal himself to manelse, God would, in fact, be "jealous." To say that God as Spirit is
< previous page
page_43
next page >
< previous page
page_44
next page > Page 44
present in man is to say that man's very finite existence is God's self-revelation to man.33 For what is here suggested is that God is not jealous, but, on the contrary, has revealed and is revealing himself; and we have here the more definite thought that it is not the so-called human reason with its limits which knows God, but the Spirit of God in man; it is, to use the speculative expression previously employed, the self-consciousness of God which knows itself in the knowledge of man. [Ibid., p. 49]34 Whether this last statement raises the ugly specter of "pantheism" in Hegel's philosophy can await discussion in chapter 6. For the present, no more need be said than that it throws added light on those mysterious words with which Hegel ends Phenomenology of Spirit. The goal, absolute knowing, or spirit knowing itself as spirit, has as the road it has traveled the memory (Er-innerung) of multiple spirits, as they are in themselves and as they bring to completion the organization of their realm. Their retention from the point of view of their self-determining existence appearing in the form of contingency is history; from the point of view of their comprehended organization, on the other hand, it is the science of knowing as it appears; both together, as comprehended history, constitute the memorial and the calvary of absolute Spirit. The actuality, truth, and certainty of his throne, without which he would have been the lifeless solitary; only from the chalice of this realm of spirits foams forth to him his infinity. [PdG, p. 564]35 Looking back now, we can begin to understand what Hegel means by the "necessity" of the rational, its necessary objectivity, which makes sense only if it is rooted in the all-embracing necessity of "absolute truth" and which, thus rooted, makes sense of Hegel's talk about the objective necessity of logical truth, moral truth, and religious truth. There is no truth, not even "absolute truth," which is not "rational,'' the object of "reason." Man is in himself the purpose of his own being, only in virtue of the divine that is in him, of that which was designated from the outset as reason, which in view of its activity and power of self-determination was called freedom. And we affirmwithout at present being able to enter into the proof of the asser-
33. As we shall see in chapter 7, "Philosophy and Theology," Hegel sees in "creation" a relation internal to God, not a transient activity external to him. Hence the creation of finite human spirit is God's selfmanifestation to finite human spirit. 34. It should be emphasized that in calling this a "speculative expression" Hegel is serving notice on those who confine themselves to interpretinig the expression in terms of "understanding," which cannot but find it contradictory, that they must "think it through" rationally. 35. As Hegel sees it an infinite God who would not create would be one who condemns himself to an empty life of solitary splendor.
< previous page
page_44
next page >
< previous page
page_45
next page > Page 45
tionthat religiousness, morality, etc., have their foundation and source in that principle in man and so are essentially elevated above all extrinsic necessity and chance. [Ibid., p. 50] Hidden beneath much of what Hegel has to say about God or "absolute Spirit," both in his positive assertions regarding God's knowability and in his opposition to those of his contemporaries who deny that knowability, is his desire to make sense out of what today is called "language about God," or simply, "God-language." There can be no question that "God-language" is tricky, that philosophers should be cautious not to be misled by it, and that, to an extent at least, thinkers like Spinoza, Lessing, and Hegel took great pains to ''demythologize" that language. The question, however, is not whether Hegel was trying to "demythologize" the language but whether, in doing so, he was trying to rob it of all cognitive value. If he was trying to do the latter, one is forced to wonder if he was not guilty of "over-kill." The language he employs is certainly not the most convenient language for a philosophereven for one who had to be cautious of Prussian state censors, nor is it, if intended to be metaphorical, free of numberless ambiguities. Nevertheless, even taken at face value, it makes eminent good sense. It might make sense for a philosopher to say that philosophers should not talk about God, because it is beyond philosophy's competence to do soKant and Fichte, after all, were not nonsensical. It might even make sense to say that philosophy should not talk about God, because there is no God to talk aboutFeuerbach and Marx were not purely nonsensical either! It is difficult, however, to make sense out of the contention that a philospher of Hegel's competence would choose to employ a highly elaborate "God-language" as a smoke screen for something else he wanted to saywhich is another question entirely from that of whether the language he employed was an apt language for what he did want to say.36 There is another question, which it is beyond the scope of this study to go into: Were Hegel's contemporariesbe they "pietists," "rationalists," "dogmatic metaphysicians," or "critical theologians"able to give more than a vague and indefinite meaning to the term "God"? Our question is a different one; namely, Was Hegel able to give to the term a meaning that was not vague and indefinite? Two other questions might also be asked: (1) Did he give to the term a meaning which does not weaken its religious significance? and (2) Did he give it an acceptable meaning? These are questions for the reader to answer.
36. There was a time when philosophers of the stature of Feuerbach, Marx, Kierkegaard, Nietzscheeven Schopenhauercould say that Hegel was simply wrong. Today, we might say, Hegel has won his spurs and no oneexcept perhaps Eric Voegelin (see his "On HegelA Study in Sorcery," Studium Generale 24 (1971): 33568)has the nerve to say that Hegel is talking nonsense. Still less does anyone want to say, "if Hegel is right, I am talking nonsense." Solution: "Hegel is obviously saying what I am saying"!
< previous page
page_45
next page >
< previous page
page_46
next page > Page 46
One thing is quite clear: In September, 1830, less than a year before he died, in the preface to the third edition of his Encyclopedia, Hegel was able to reiterate his enduring opposition to the meaninglessness and emptiness of both Enlightenment "rationalism" and unenlightened "Pietism." In doing so he made an eloquent appeal both for a "faith" with an identifiable doctrinal content and a philosophical ''thinking" which would be more than just "formal and negative" in its relation to that same content. "Pietism," as he had said so often before, had emptied religion of all content "by reducing faith to the shibboleth of 'Lord, Lord,' " and "rationalism," with its "formal, abstract . . . thinking" was no less empty. They cannot even fight with each other, because they have nothing positive in common to fight about, no "matter" that they could possibly investigate and by so doing come to "knowledge and truth" " Enlightened theology" had taken refuge in a "formalism" of "freedom of conscience, freedom of thought, and freedom to teach," calling this "reason and science," without even a nod in the direction of the "first condition of truth, namely faith." It is not enough to be "free"; one must be free to "hold" something definite to be true, not simply free to have "arbitrary opinions" (Ep W, pp. 2627). Strong words for one who did not say what he meant when he talked about Godcowardly words, if all he was trying to do was keep his job! God and Metaphysics What it comes down to is that Hegel, following in the footsteps of Aristotle, sees the philosophical pursuit of truth as, ultimately, itself a religious activity. For Aristotle "first philosophy"which is, in fact, synonymous with "ultimate philosophy," since it is oriented to the pursuit of truth, which is at once "beyond" (meta *) and the "root" (arch*) of the orientation of the human mind to knowingis the "divine science." It is "divine" in two ways: (1) its orientation carries it to the ultimate "principle" of all being, knowledge, and truth, that is, to God; and (2) it is the kind of knowing which is worthy of a "divine" being.37 For Hegel this means that the orientation to truth, which is the inescapable characteristic of human thinking, is an orientation to "absolute truth" and, therefore, fundamentally a religious orientation. The doctrine of truth is entirely this, and this alone, to be a doctrine of God ordered to the revelation of God's nature and activity. Understanding, however, because it has dissolved all this content, has again thrown a veil over God and reduced him to what he was before, in the period of mere longing (Sehnsucht), the unknown. For thinking activity, therefore, the only matter
37. Aristotle Metaph. A 983a.
< previous page
page_46
next page >
< previous page
page_47
next page > Page 47
left is antecedently given finite matter. The only difference is that this is now accompanied by the consciousness that there is no matter other than temporal and finite matter. [BS, p. 65] The attitude that Hegel here impugns implies a relinquishing of man's "religious" vocation to soar above the merely finite, a vocation which, at the same time, does not view the infinite as separated by an "infinite" chasm from finite thinking. If the "atheist" finds in this attitude support of his position he is at least being straightforward in his approach. But, what of those who claim to be religious, to "believe" in God, but deny that in this they are being ''philosophical"? Are they not, in fact, claiming that God is jealous," denying the human mind all access to ultimate truth? What would it then be other than jealousy, if God were to deny to consciousness knowledge of himself? He would at the same time be denying all truth to consciousness, for God alone is the true; whatever else is true and seems somehow not to be a divine content, is true only to the extent that it is grounded in him and is known in the knowing of himwhatever else there is to it is but temporal appearance. It is knowledge of God, the truth, alone which raises man above the beast, that alone which distinguishes man, makes him happyor, rather, blessed. This is true for Plato and Aristotle, and for Christian teaching. [BS, p. 80] If one prefers, of course, to look upon Hegel's "God" as in some mysterious way an "absolute" quite different from the God of religion, or of "transcendent faith," one is, perhaps, free to do so, but one runs the risk of making Hegel even more mysterious than his actual words would seem to imply. It does not seem farfetched to say that James Yerkes has hit the nail on the head when he says that it simply makes better sense to see Hegel's philosophical position as essentially religious. As far as Hegel is concerned, it is not sufficient to say man thinks because he is religious; rather, one must also say that it is the thinking capacity itself which constitutes the fundamental mode of man's selfconscoiusness as religious: man is religious by means of his thinking capacity. To put it yet another way, in thinking, man is inescapably or "necessarily" religious. To understand the nature of man as a thinking being is to understand him ab initio as a religious being.38 One can, of course, shrug this off as "special pleading" on the part of one who is committed to a religious interpretation of Hegela "shrug" which might well turn into a boomerangbut Yerkes' approach does have the vir
38. James Yerkes, Hegel's Christology (Missoula, Montana: Scholars Press, 1978), p. 76.
< previous page
page_47
next page >
< previous page
page_48
next page > Page 48
tue of taking seriously what Hegel actually says (e.g., "true philosophy leads to God," [GPR, preface, p. 17]); unless of course, one wants to say that there is more truth in the "unsaid" than in the ''said." In this connection it might not be amiss to point out also that Hegel never says that "philosophical thinking" deals only with God. Rather, philosophy is "general theory of the universe." The question is whether philosophy can make sense out of the universe if religious truth is beyond philosophy's purview. "Still, it comes down essentially to the relation of religion to man's general theory of the universe, and it is to this that philosophical knowledge is essentially directed, and upon which it essentially works" (VPR I, p. 15). What is important to note, however, is that Hegel is constant and unambiguous in his contention that philosophy's direct concern is not "empirical knowledge" of the universe, but rather, "it is knowledge of what is not of the world . . . of what is eternal, of what God is and of what flows from his nature" (Ibid., p. 28). Philosophy, therefore, explicates itself only when it explicates religion, and it is in explicating itself that it explicates religion. As thus occupied with eternal truth which is in and for itself, and, as indeed an occupation proper to thinking spirit with regard to this object, and not a matter of individual caprice and particular interest, it is the same kind of activity as is religion. [Ibid.] Philosophical thinking, as thus understood, "immerses itself with a like living interest in this object, and renounces its particularity in that it penetrates its object in the same way as religious consciousness does" (ibid.). If the finite human spirit is to think truly it must renounce philosophically its own particularity as thoroughly as it does religiouslywhich, of course, also tells us much of Hegel's view of religion and its "renunciation" of particular interests; for example, in personal salvation rather than in "eternal truth." The barb against Kant in these lines is unmistakable: neither religion's nor philosophy's "God" is to be looked at as the "guarantor" of a reward for having followed one's "duty"no more than he is Kierkegaard's pledge of subjective "eternal happiness." The conclusion of all this, then, is that religion makes known to philosophy what philosophy's "true" content is; and philosophy makes known to religion that this content is "rational." Whether it be in religion, in philosophy, or in both, God can reveal himself to man only in man's "reason," which is the function of "spirit": "For philosophy has this in common with the form of culture referred to, that reason is regarded as the region (Ort) of spirit in which God reveals himself to man" (ibid., p. 50). Philosophy, then, is "theology" (see chap. 7). The "logos of God," which makes known to religion the latter's own "rationality": "Philosophy, which is theology, has as its sole concern showing the rationality of
< previous page
page_48
next page >
< previous page
page_49
next page > Page 49
religion" (VPR III, p. 341). But, this is a far cry, as we have already seen, from saying that religion is a "rational discipline"; it is not philosophy's function either to replace or to swallow up religion, but rather to plumb the depths of religion's object. Nowhere, perhaps, is the chasm between Hegel's thought and the thought of not only his immediate predecessors Kant and Fichte (his dispute with Schelling lies elsewhere) but also of all his predecessors from Descartes on (with the exception of Spinoza) more pronounced than it is here. When Hegel speaks of the "rationality" of both philosophy and religion, he speaks not so much (or not at all) of the logical purity of the subjective process of thinking as he does of the "objective" rationality of the content of "thought." His, then, is not the problem (even though some might claim that it should be) of explaining how an essentially subjective mental activity of thinking can possibly correspond with an essentially objective order of reality in such a way that the fusion of the two can be characterized as ''rational knowledge." The "rationality" of knowledge is not so much a function of adherence to the a-priori conditions of formal thinking as it is of the "rationality" of what is known. This is not to say that any "method" of thinking is as good as any other for the acquisition of knowledge; it is to say that the rationality of the method and, therefore, of the knowing which ensues is not dictated by the formal a-priori rules of thinking (discovered in some mysterious way prior to the philosophical thinking itself), but by the rationality of the object thought. This means, among other things, that the relation of thought to its object can be "rational," even when the "mode" of thinking in question is not that of "pure thought," when it is "belief" and not "knowledge." Here, however, there arises a difficulty for those who would follow Hegel in the intricacies of his thinking. Does the rationality of his own thinking tell him just what the rational object of that thinking is; an object which he then sees to coincide with the object of religion? If so, it is difficult to see how he has avoided the Kantian dilemma; he still has to connect the "representations" in which his formal thinking issues with the "reality" they are supposed to "represent." Or, does some antecedent intuition into the rationality of the object of religion permit him to see in it the blueprint for the rationality of the thinking which is to correspond to it? If so, his intuitionism would seem to be even less consistent than that of Jacobi and Schleiermacher (not to mention the "mysticism" of Jakob Böhme). The Logic of Being In seeking an answer we have to begin, I think, by banishing the "before and after" pattern, which no antecedent logic imposes on philosophical thinking. The key is to be found in Hegel's Logic, his account of what
< previous page
page_49
next page >
< previous page
page_50
next page > Page 50
thought inevitably finds when it examines itself (more of that in chapter 2). What this examination first reveals is what the initial "object" of thought cannot but be, that is, "being." This object reveals its essential articulation in its being thought. In doing so it reveals that being simply is not, if infintite being is not. But where to turn to find the self-revelation of "infinite being"? In Phenomenology of Spirit, as we have seen, consciousness in examining itself arrived at a similar impasse, out of which it could not get without turning to an examination of religious consciousness, wherein is revealed the full objective reality of spirit, that is, absolute Spirit. In the Phenomenology that was long in coming, and in the Logic it will be equally long in coming; but in both it will be realized that the "Absolute'' when it comes will reveal itself as having been there all alongin the Phenomenology as "absolute Spirit" and in the Logic as "absolute Idea." At the second level of the Logic we begin to realize that the self-articulation of the object of thought demands more than the "categories of being" in which it manifests itself; we who follow the articulation must also take into account that the characteristics disengaged through thoughtful "reflection" on the "thought" of being reveal what is "essential" to being if it is to be the content of thought at all. This characterization of being in thought, however, will not be complete until the thinking itself is examined as the subjective process whose ultimate claim is to be objective. Here it is that we see "concept" as the essential structure of thought, which will not be objective unless the structure of thought and the structure of reality are seen to coincide, which, Hegel tells us, they do in "absolute Idea." But once again, "absolute" will be meaningful only as "the Absolute," which is God; it simply makes no sense to speak of any other absolute as real. By equally tortuous ways the Phenomenology and the Logic have come to the realization that only God, "absolute truth" can make the whole process hold together. In both, however, it has been the nature of "speculative thinking," which alone is capable of constantly moving on to the "more" to which its own object constantly points, which comes to the realization that what it had been seeking all along was the "absolute truth," God, who, although he was there all along, "could be reached only in pure speculative knowing" (PdG, p. 530). Many years before, Hegel had recognized that knowledge would be deserving of its lofty dignity only as knowledge in the framework of the totality of the knowable: "Speculation recognizes as the reality of cognition only the being of cognition in the totality. For speculation everything determinate has being and truth only in the cognition of its connection with the Absolute" (Diff, p. 31). Only if we can come to the recognition that all knowledge is rooted in the one and only absolute (total) truth, will there be knowledge and truth at all.
< previous page
page_50
next page >
< previous page
page_51
next page > Page 51
This which formally belongs to our thinking consciousness as such [i.e., that truth is only one] is in the more profound sense the starting point and the goal of philosophy, i.e., to recognize this one truth. But this means recognizing it at the same time as the source from which everything else flows, all laws of nature, all phenomena of life and consciousness, which are simply mirrorings of this one truth. To put it another way: all these laws and phenomena are to be brought back along what could seem to be the reverse path to that one source, for the purpose, however, of comprehending them in comprehending the source, i.e., recognizing that they are derived from it. [EGP, p. 29] To see this, of course, thinking must cease to be the merely subjective activity of the individual (or of accumulated individuals), finding its self-determination not in the arbitrariness of subjectivity but in the infinity of absolute objectivity. Only because the pure infinite form, the self-manifestation which continues to be with itself, has put aside the onesidedness of the subjective, wherein it is the mere pretense of thinking, is it free thinking, which has its infinite determinateness at once as absolute content in and for itself and as object, wherein it is, precisely, free. In this sense thinking itself is simply the formal aspect of the absolute content. [Ep W, no. 571] How are we now to relate this back to God as the object of religious consciousness? Not, certainly, by insisting that religion is no more than a subjective response which stands there in all its glaring subjectivity to be examined. Nor shall we find any answer, if we cling to a narrowly epistemological view of thinking and knowledge. For Hegel, thinking knowledge is not primarily an epistemological matter at all; it is a way of life, and relating it to God is not simply a way of validating its knowledge-claims. Rather, it is the question of the whole of human life in relation to God, of the all-inclusiveness of the divine-human relationship. What Hegel experienced in his own day was a prevalent fragmentation of culture, of lifepolitical, social, religioussuch that his vision of and aspiration toward reintegration are expressed in metaphors taken from the unity of organic life and sought for in an overarching unity of a philosophical conception which would integrate the moral, political, social, and religious life of Western man. In his early years Hegel saw this as the task of healing religious disintegration; subsequently, he sought integration on the level of politics; and ultimately, he saw the necessity of a philosophical underpinning which would make total integration a reasonable possibility. the dim vision of this came to him early.
It is true that a philosophy issues from its time, and if one wants to call the fragmentation of the time its ethical corruption, then philosophy issues from
< previous page
page_51
next page >
< previous page
page_52
next page > Page 52
that corruption, but it does so in order to reestablish man from within himself, against the confusion of the time and in order to restore the totality which the time has rent. [Diff, pp. 12021] Philosophy by itself, however, especially if it be a "philosophy of understanding" and not a "philosophy of reason," runs the risk of turning man himself into an abstraction, of satisfying the needs of abstract understanding only. A philosophy which is to satisfy the concrete demands of human living must be one which embraces the manysidedness of the humanif nothing else it must take into consideration the reality of the religious and the political in human living. "Consciousness that has received an abstract culture, and whose sphere is understanding, can be indifferent to religion, but religion is the universal form in which truth is contained for non-abstract consciousness" (VPG, p. 527). To many contemporary thinkers, who are, as it were, the unconscious inheritors of both the naive religiousness of Kant and Fichte and the naive atheism of Feuerbach and Marx, Hegel can well seem to be anachronistic in his approach to his own age. He actually thinks that the thought of God plays a far more important role among his contemporaries than it does among ancient and medieval thinkers. In one sense, however, he is correct; his contemporaries agonize over the thought far more than did their predecessors, whether because to them the thought was philosophically unacceptable or because it was totally acceptable for other than philosophical reasons. For Hegel, it would seem, reasons for not accepting the thought of God could scarcely be authentically philosophical. In any event, as he sees it, the question of God perplexes the modern theologian as well as the modern philosopher, precisely because they take man's religious relationship to God and not God himself to be the object of inquiry (see VPR I, pp. 101103). "In naive ancient theology," as Fackenheim puts it, "the object is God; hence, he is . . . one object among others."39 For reflexive modern theology, on the other hand, the object is not God but "the religious divine-human relationship"whether positively or negatively. This goal as all-inclusivepositively or negatively''is identical with reflexive modern philosophy, whose object is the relation between thought and being, in their opposition as well as their union."40 What it comes down to is that, from the viewpoint of "national" culture, paramount in the thinking of Hegel's day, "religion is the sphere in which a nation gives itself a definition of what it regards as the true." One can, so to speak, judge the character of a nation by examining its concept of God: "The conception of God, therefore, constitutes the general basis of a people's character" (VPG,
39. Fackenheim, Religious Dimension, p. 178, note. 40. Ibid.
< previous page
page_52
next page >
< previous page
page_53
next page > Page 53
p. 70).41 No one today would be so naive as to think, with Hegel, that the members of a nation think alike in this respect, or that a whole "people" has this sort of cohesion in its "conception of God," but it is clearly applicable to individualsas is one's concept of God, so is one's conception of the reality of the human. No matter what distinctions one likes to make, the conception of the human is inextricably tied up with the conception of the divineor the absence thereof! Whether one can go even further with Hegel and say that "in this aspect, religion stands in the closest connection with the political principle; freedom can exist only where individuality is recognized as having its positive and real existence in the divine being" (ibid.), may be a moot question, but one wonders whether Hegel did not have more foresight than many would credit him with. In any event, Hegel saw in religion what few, if any, both before and after him saw: that the religious view of God is inextricably linked to the political view of the human, and only where the relationship of man to God is viewed as all-inclusive is the view of the human all-inclusiveat least logically so. The question, of course, is whether religion is not so ''other worldly" in its view that it cannot come down to contemplate the realities of earthly existence. That Hegel was convinced that religion could and should is fairly obvious; that philosophy follows religion in this might be more open to question. In religions people have set down what they thought of the being of the world, of the Absolute, of the being which is in and for itself; what they held to be the cause, the essence, the substantial in nature and spirit. On the basis of this we can judge what was their view of how the human spiritor human naturewas related to such objects, to the divinity, to the true. [EGP, pp. 16667] Such a view may very well seem to go beyond the evidence available to Hegel, but it is clear that he sees religion and philosophy linked in a concrete way that he has previously developed only minimally: A philosophy which lacks the contribution of "heart" which religion affords is cold; a religion which lacks the contribution of "head" which philosophy affords is empty. A philosophy without heart and a faith without understanding are themselves abstractions from the true life and being of knowing and believing. Whoever is left cold by philosophy or who is not illumined by true faith should carefully look to where the blame lies; it lies in the individual, not in knowledge and faith. The coldness lies outside philosophy; the obscurity outside faith. [BS, p. 325]
41. A theme which, as we know, Feuerbach will exploit but for the purpose of drawing a diametrically opposed conclusion.
< previous page
page_53
next page >
< previous page
page_54
next page > Page 54
It could be said in this connection that religion is directly concerned more with man's relationship to Godreligious "practice," devotion, worship, moral activity, direction of lifeand less with theoretical questions regarding the "nature" of God, creation, divine providence, and doctrinal truth. By the same token philosophy's concern is more cognitive than practical, oriented more to knowing what we mean when we speak of God than to responding through action to the reality of God. The important question for Hegel is, however, whether we can make a great deal of sense in speaking of man's relationship to God, if we do not know what we mean by the God to whom men are related. The manner in which man thinks of his relationship to God will be determined especially by the way man thinks of God. It is not the case, as is now so commonly said, that one need not know God and can at the same time know man's relationship to God. Because God comes first, it is he who determines that relationship, and thus, in order to know what is true of the relationship, one must know God. [VGP II, pp. 41718] This means, at the very least, that, if an awareness of our relationship to and dependence on God is essential to "insightful reflective judgments about being, truth, and value,"42 which in turn are essential to authentic human living, then "knowing" God is inseparable from the religious relationship to Godheart and mind must go hand in hand, for the arbitrariness of "heart" will go uncorrected if not complemented by the authenticity of "mind." The danger, as Hegel sees it, is that, although in religious consciousness there is a true awareness of God, and the God of whom man is aware is truly God, still what is present to consciousness is teaching about God, not God himself, with the result that the "emotions" raised by "representations" of God may not be adequate to their object (see EGP, pp. 18284). Here we come upon, once more, the difficult conception treated above of the finite human spirit, whose consciousness of itself can be adequate only if it is identified with the divine Spirit's consciousness of itself in the human spirit. We can only hope that this will be adequately worked out in the next three chapters. Suffice it to say here that, if, as Hegel conceives it, the function of religion (from re-ligare) is to relate man, however indirectly, to the "Absolute," and the function of philosophy is to think the "Absolute," it makes sense to say that the ''Absolute" in both is one and the same. Hegel is not saying, however, that religious consciousness does not think God, while philosophy does; he is saying that religion "thinks" God in one form and that philosophy "thinks" God in another, more adequate form. In
42. Yerkes, Hegel's Christology, p. 89.
< previous page
page_54
next page >
< previous page
page_55
next page > Page 55
both the God who is "thought" is ultimate truth, which is one and only one, the truth of all truth. As a result of all that has been said in this chapter we can note a remarkable evolution in Hegel's thought. From his earliest years he set out to find a religion and a God which would be able to heal the fragmentation of European culture and at the same time be compatible with sophisticated modern philosophical thinking. If we were to look at his Theologische Jugendschriften, which for very good reasons he did not publish, we could come to the conclusion that what he expected to find would be substitutes for the Christian God and the Christian religionperhaps the unified reason of the Enlightenment or the supreme moral principle of Kant and Fichteperhaps even grafted onto the politicosocial Volksreligion he so admired among the Greeks. As early as Differenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen Systems der Philosophie and Glauben und Wissen, however, we have been able to note his growing dissatisfaction with both of these solutions. What he came up with, then, was a transformed Christian religion and a transformed concept of God. As Fackenheim puts it, "For the early Hegel, philosophy will produce a new religion on the ruins of the old. For the mature Hegel, philosophy comprehends the old religion, and this latter is not and cannot be ruined."43 Earlier Fackenheim had gone even further: "Hegel asserts with unwavering insistence, that Christianity is the absolutely true content, and that his philosophy can and must give that content its absolutely true form."44 It can, of course, be doubtedand it has beenthat the religion Hegel speaks of is in truth the Christian religion, or that the God he speaks of is truly the Christian God. For the present, however, that is not the question. There can be no doubt that the God-question occupied him very profoundly and that he sought to understand God in such a way that the God he spoke of not only would not conflict with the autonomy of philosophical thinking but also would not be an object which simply exceeded the capacity of human reasonwhich a separated God "out-there" would. The Christian God has always been looked on as the supreme Being, infinite Spirit, and absolute Reality. Of Hegel's God the same can be said. The difference is, however, that Hegel's is a philosophical endeavor to understand what such terms can mean to modern man. With this it becomes clear that the endeavor resulted in more than a transformation of Christian religion; it produced also a transformation of philosophical thinking. For Hegel, philosophy is "science" par excellence, which has for its object absolute truth and, as the manner of comprehending this object, "absolute knowing." That knowledge is indeed knowledge
43. Fackenheim, Religious Dimension, p. 209. 44. Ibid., p. 112.
< previous page
page_55
next page >
< previous page
page_56
next page > Page 56
Hegel never really doubteddespite his insistence on "skepticism" as a necessary stage on the way to knowledge. His problem was that of working through the process of coming to know in such a way that knowledge would reveal itself as precisely knowledge. It can be said with truth of his Phenomenology of Spirit that it attempts to make this process real. Still, if we are to comprehend what even the Phenomenology is attempting to do, we must turn to Hegel's ground plan for the whole philosophical endeavor, his Science of Logic.
< previous page
page_56
next page >
< previous page
page_57
next page > Page 57
Chapter Two The Concept Hegel's contention that religion and philosophy have one and the same content, that is, have as that which makes them be what they are the same object of investigationthe absolute or Godhas seemed to some to either (1) eliminate religion, since philosophy takes its place, telling us all that religion can tell usand moreabout its object, or (2) downgrade religion to an inferior grasp of that one and the same object, or (3) at the very least permit philosophy to dictate to religion what religion's own concepts are to mean. In the preface to the third edition (1830) of Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, which, unlike the prefaces to the other two editions, has more the character of an emotional outburst, Hegel complains of those who have reviewed his book in such a way as to make him out to be not Christian at all, thus arrogating to themselves not only the exclusive right to be called Christians but also the authority to judge what is to be acknowledged as Christian in the thought of others. Although in that preface he does not specifically answer the objections raised above, it is clear from what he has written elsewhere1in the preface to the second edition of the same work (1827) and in the introductionwhat his answers are. (1) Not only does philosophy not eliminate religioneven religion's Aufhebung signifies its retentionit arrives only subsequently at what religion long before philosophy has grasped in thought, that is, the truth which grounds all truth, the absolute truth which is God. It may be that philosophy thinks God in a way that religion does not, since to know and to believe are not the same (note Hegel's unremitting insistence that belief is a form of thought), but it is religion which tells
1. See Quentin Lauer, S.J., Hegel's Idea of Philosophy (New York: Fordham University Press, 1971), p. 117.
< previous page
page_57
next page >
< previous page
page_58
next page > Page 58
philosophy, and not vice versa, what the latter's object must be, if it is to be worthy of the title "philosophical thinking" at all. Only when philosophical thinking passes beyond its empirical, finite beginnings to its inescapable foundation, its only adequate foundation, is it authentic philosophical thinking. Religion cannot, it is true, institute a critique of philosophy's thinking of Godreligion is not critical thoughtbut it contains within itself the criterion for the adequacy of philosophy as authentically rational. If philosophy fails to come to grips with the infinite reality which is religion's object, philosophy fails as philosophy. (2) It is true that, in Hegel's view, philosophical thinking is the highest achievement of the human spirit and is, therefore, more adequate to the object which is absolute Spirit than is any form of "representational" thinking, even religious representational thinking. However, this view would constitute a "downgrading" of religion only if religious thought and philosophical thought were for Hegel discontinuous, as they would seem to be for Kant, Fichte, Jacobi, and Schleiermacher. Far from being a downgrading of religion, philosophical knowing is an uplifting of religious thought to its true vocation (as Anselm saw so well), the vocation of "seeing-in'' thought (speculare) the God who is there present rather than framing thought about the God who is only represented by these thoughts (with their admixture of images). Perhaps the difficulty lies in the assumption that because Hegel distinguishes philosophical science, "absolute knowing" from religious consciousnessthe latter as the penultimate stage in the movement toward the formerhe is saying that philosophy is not religious. The assumption can be seen not to hold, if we look at Hegel's characterization of philosophy as "comprehending reason . . . whose content is speculative and therefore religious" (EpW, no. 573, italics mine). His polemic, after all, is not against theologians like Anselm who want us to come to know what initially we only believe; it is against "this new theology, which turns religion into a mere subjective feeling and denies a knowledge of God's nature" and in so doing "has made for itself an emaciated and empty God" (ibid.). The absolute, spirit, God, the Concept (Idea) can be the object only of thought, never of mere feeling, whether that thought be belief or knowledge. (3) It is difficult to see how this is even an objectionexcept, perhaps, in its employing the emotion-packed term "dictates." Philosophy is an instrument which the human spirit has at its disposal as a search for meaning. Why should not thought seek to know what the utterances of faith mean? Or, is there to be no theo-logy at all? If we want to know what is true of the object of thought, whatever the form of that thought may be, we turn to the concept of that object, "for a property (Bestimmung) which belongs to the concept of a reality (Sache) must truly be contained in it" (WL I, p. 172). When all this has been said, we can but see that, although there is no need
< previous page
page_58
next page >
< previous page
page_59
next page > Page 59
to whitewash Hegel in his view of the relation of religion and philosophy,2 we must first look carefully at just what he means by "philosophy," "concept," and ''speculative thinking" before we "cast the first stone." If to this inquiry we bring the antecedent conviction that the only way to get at meanings is to frame definitions of the terms we employ, trusting that others will see the rationality of our procedure and thus accept the meanings which our definitions express, there is little likelihood that we shall be able to follow Hegel, for whom, it is true, meanings reside in the concepts which express them, but not in concepts which we construct for the purpose of establishing our meaning. If we are to follow Hegel, we must be prepared to see meanings emerge in "speculative thinking" which seeks to "see into" the conceptual structure of the reality with which our thinking is engaged, allowing the reality to tell us what concepts mean and, thus, to put us in touch with the reality of the real, not merely with the "representations" (Vorstellungen) we frame of it, no matter how important these Vorstellungen may be as an initial stage (or stages) in our philosophical thinking. I can think of no more efficacious way of tuning in on Hegel's wave-length here than by carefully analyzing the introduction (nos. 117) to his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences. Philosophical Thinking No. 1. Philosophy, Hegel tells us, begins with what might seem to be an initial disadvantage not shared by other "sciences." It can presuppose neither that the intelligibility of its objects is already given nor that the method of coming to grips with these objects is simply at hand, to be employed at will. Like religion, philosophy has as its goal the attainment of ultimate truth, and, like religion, it recognizes that the ultimate truth, the truth of all truth, lies in the being to which all truths refer for their intelligibility and truth, that is, absolute truth, which for the moment we can simply call "God." Nature, as the sum total of all reality which is not spirit, and human spirit, as the sum total of all spiritual reality distinct from God, are, of course, objects of philosophical inquirythe Vorstellungen of God, nature, and finite spirit can be presumed to be already with us (whatever we are to make of them). The point is that they are to become the objects of thought in its purest form and, thus, to become philosophically known. There can be little dispute that the human mind, at least in modern times, seeks to know itself (even if only to find out that it is part and parcel of the physical structure of the human reality). Nor can there be dispute that the human mind inquires into the reality of the physical world which it inhabits and to whose laws the physical structure of the human is subject. The point
2. I.e., making his thought conform to what I happen to think makes good sense.
< previous page
page_59
next page >
< previous page
page_60
next page > Page 60
is that the mind, if it wants to know and not merely surmise, must seek some sort of rational necessity in the content of its thoughtwithout simply presupposing that it is there. It may be that the "scientific" mind can base its inquiries on an "act of faith in the decency of the universe"; the philosophical mind must question even that. No. 2. So much having been said, Hegel feels safe in giving a provisional definition of philosophy: "Philosophy can initially be characterized as thinking consideration of objects." The mind already represents to itself objects; now it must think them out. What do they tell the mind about themselves? The "thinking" in question, however, is not merely that which characterizes all specifically human activity, thus distinguishing the human from the nonhuman: "Philosophy is a particular manner of thinking," distinct from other modes of human response, such as emotion, intuition, and representation, which are modes of thinking, Hegel says, but not the thinking mode; because such responses are specifically human they have on them the mark of thought, but they are not themselves modes of thinking properly speaking. This distinction has two consequences: (1) It avoids the oversharp distinction between, for example, thinking and feeling, particularly in the area of religious response, where thinking is considered by some of Hegel's contemporaries ("the new theology'') as not only distinct from but also inferior to feeling, as though religious consciousness had its roots in feeling rather than in thinking. (2) It directly attacks the current prejudice that philosophical thinking is nothing but "reflective" thinking (Hegel calls it Nachdenken and then plays on the prefix nach as though it were a thinking that comes after thinking); a thinking about thinking and not about the objects of thought (today we have "meta-logic," "meta-ethics," etc.). The really important distinction is not, for example, between feeling and thinking about feeling, but rather that between mere feeling and feeling shot through with thought. The emphasis on Nachdenken becomes particularly pernicious, Hegel feels, when reflection is looked upon as the only reliable way to come to grips with eternal truth, as though God could not be an object of thought, since philosophy can handle only thought about God (or, worse still, language about God) but not God himself. It is as though one would say that the validity of belief in God depends on the formal-logical validity of the traditional "proofs" of the existence of God.3 Strangely enough, this view of philosophy would make philosophy absolutely indispensable to a degree beyond that which even Hegel made it. The approach to eternal truth would have to wait on a critique of the logic of the approachas though it
3. If the only acceptable form of "proof" is that of formal "inference" from a set of propositions, the truth of which inevitably entails the truth of a concluding propositiona truth already contained in the propositions which precede itone might legitimately question whether there are any "proofs" for the reality of God.
< previous page
page_60
next page >
< previous page
page_61
next page > Page 61
were rational to demand that the logic of philosophy be simply identical with the logic of positive science without justifying the demand! No. 3. This approach compounds the felony by making the content of thinking not the object of thought but the form in which the object is present to the mind. It is true enough to say that the content of any act of consciousness determines that act of consciousness; be it feeling, intuition, image, or thought and concept. Consciousness is what it is as the form of a content, and the content can be one and the same, no matter what the form; for example, pure feeling, a mixture of feeling and thought, or pure thought. If, however, the form of consciousness becomes the content of thought, then the object being considered is not the same but different for each mode of consciousness; to anticipate, instead of one idea in a multiplicity of manifestations, there is an uncontrollable chaos of ideas and only the unity of reflective thoughtif that be a unity at all. There is an added disadvantage in this approach, says Hegel: it reverses the authentic philosophical procedure of going from inadequate modes of consciousness of an object; from feelings, images, representations, to more adequate modes, thoughts and concepts. It is rooted in an inabilityperhaps just lack of practiceto think abstractly. Our ordinary thoughts are a mixture of the sensible and the spiritual, and when we reflect on them we fail to sort out the sensible and the intelligible elements in themwe are not used to thoughts without images or to recognizing the pure forms of thought (e.g., categories) in our thinking processes. But there is another side to this: We are impatient. We prefer to look for the image or representation which corresponds to our thought or concept, rather than vice versabecause we long for the more familiar; we do not know where we are when we are dealing with thoughts only. Better to deal in expressions we have learned by rote than to ferret out meanings which go beyond the expressions, to stick with the metaphors that stand for reality than to come to grips with reality itselflanguage is so much more comfortable a medium in which to engage ourselves than is reality! No. 4. Philosophy, then, has an important initial task to perform: it has to show that its mode of knowing is very special to itselfor, perhaps, it has to bring about this special mode of knowing, which is neither an immediate mode of consciousness nor a mere reflection on a mode of consciousness which is not its own. If we take this a step further to a consideration of the content of religious consciousness, where the ultimate truth lies, philosophy has to show that it (philosophy) has in itself the capacity to know ultimate truthand, if there seems to be a difference between the representations characteristic of religious consciousness and philosophy's own thoughts, philosophy must be prepared to justify the latter. The implication, of course, is that there can be only seeming opposition between what religion and philosophy say of ultimate truth; it is philosophy's task to
< previous page
page_61
next page >
< previous page
page_62
next page > Page 62
plumb in thought the meaning of what religion says in metaphorical language. No. 5. Even here, however, there is a dangerthe danger that philosophical thinking will be conceived of, once again, as simply reflection (Nachdenken) in the sense of thinking about thinking. There is, in fact, a significant sense in which philosophical thinking is Nachdenken; it rethinks a content which is initially presented only under the form of feelings, intuitions, opinions, and representations. Its task is to translate, to transform these into conceptual thought. This is, if you will, a Nachdenken; it follows upon other, inadequate, forms of thought, not, be it noted, to eliminate them but to raise them up to a form adequate to their content. The mistake should not be made, however, of thinking that this is all very easy, that the mind, after all, has an inborn capacity to perform this sort of transformation. It is readily conceded that other sciences and skills can be acquired only at the cost of much effort and practice, even though the human mind does have the inborn capacity to acquire them. It is no easier, to say the least, to acquire facility in philosophical thinking. There is no comfortable way to the acquisition of philosophical insight,4 as would be, for example, immediate, intuitive knowledge. Philosophy is hard work; we must not ignore the necessary steps (mediation) to its acquisition. No. 6. Perhaps the chief obstacle to coming to grips with the difficulty of philosophical thinking is the conviction that it has to do, not with the actuality (Wirklichkeit) of the real, but only with a kind of watered-down ideality which belongs to thought about the real. It might be well to note here at the beginning of any discussion of "actuality"a crucial term in the Hegelian vocabularythat the German term it translates, Wirklichkeit, is derived from the verb wirken, which means "to effect." Although the German term is rarely translated by ''effectiveness," it would be well to bear in mind that the overtones of "effectiveness" are never absent from "actuality"; it is the capacity which reality has to "effect" its affirmation through rational thinking.5 Hegel is not about to deny that our initial contact with reality is through sense experience. Nor will he deny that even in this kind of experience a distinction is drawn between that which only appears to be real and that which actually is real. The difficulty lies in knowing just what is the distinction between the apparent and the actual. In Hegel's view it is not a question of simply distinguishing between what is the case and what is not the case. Rather it is a question of distinguishing between what is rationally demanded and what is contrary to what is rationally demanded. What is
4. No "royal road": see PdG., preface, p. 56. 5. That philosophies in particular have shied away from a translation which runs the risk of making knowledge a "cause-effect" relationship is understandable. But, "effectiveness" need not have this connotation, any more than does Plato's remark (Sophist, 248a) that "being" is to be equated with "power."
< previous page
page_62
next page >
< previous page
page_63
next page > Page 63
simply the case may very well be the latter; the irrational may very well existunfortunately the world is full of it. However, this does not mean that the irrational is actual in the sense that it is the object of philosophical thinkingexcept, of course, in the sense that philosophy can judge its irrationality against the criterion of the rational, which is philosophy's proper object. There are important as well as trivial ways in which, even in our everyday thinking, we consider that which is as it ought to be real and that which is not as it ought to be unreal. The true, the good, and the beautiful are real, even if all we are saying is that "Coke is the real thing," or "Don Giovanni is real opera." By the same token, when we run up against the false, the evil, and the ugly, we can intelligibly say, "That is unreal," that is, it should not be, or it is as it ought not to be. Hegel has had to take a lot of flack for having said, in the preface to his Philosophy of Right, "What is rational is actual, and what is actual is rational." The attacks have come from all sides, from the religious as well as from the philosophical point of view (interestingly enough, the statement has been defended from the irreligious side by Engels, who, of course, interprets "the rational" from the Marxist perspective).6 In Hegel's view the opposition from the religious side is unfounded, since he takes the statement to be saying what belief in divine providence has always said. As for the philosophical point of view, Hegel says (to the discomfort, I am sure, of those who finitize his "God"), ''We have to presuppose a degree of education, such that one knows that God is actualthat he is the most actual, that he alone, is truly actual. But we must also presuppose, from the point of view of formal thinking, that existence (Dasein) is in some instances mere appearance and in others actuality." This is but another way of saying what is central to the whole of Hegel's philosophizing: that the "really real" is that which corresponds to its "concept"with the proviso, of course, that only God corresponds totally with his concept; all other (finite) reality corresponds only partially with its concept (see chap. 5). Another way to put this, as Hegel does in the paragraph now under consideration, is in the form of a value judgment, in terms of what can justifiably count as real, that is, effectively" present itself as real. No one doubts that contingent things exist, but they count as really real only to the extent that they are rooted in rational necessity; apart from that they are no more real than is the possible. Hegel is not saying that the contingent is not real; he is not even saying that the contingent is not necessaryit is necessary that there be contingent realitiesbut he is saying that the necessity, and hence reality, of the contingent does not lie in its contingency but in the necessary (e.g., the concept) of which it is a contingent manifestation. The concept of "man" is necessary and, there-
6. Friedrich Engels, Ludwig Feuerbach und der Ausgang der klassischen deutschen Philosophie (Berlin: Dietz, 1951), pp. 69.
< previous page
page_63
next page >
< previous page
page_64
next page > Page 64
fore, really real; you and I do not wholly correspond to this concept, and it is, therefore, contingent that you and I should be. By the same token, the concept of God is necessary, but, because he corresponds fully with his concept, it is not contingent but necessary that he actually be (see chap. 5) and God's "actuality" lies in his "effectiveness." It might seem to conflict with what was said before about the "really real" being what it "ought'' to be that Hegel goes on to speak here of the inefficacy of arguing from "ought" (Sollen). We must examine carefully what Sollen means in this context. He is talking about a philosophical framework wherein the idea (and the ideal) are looked upon as separate from the real, having no more than the vague "reality" which the human mind gives them. When the ideal has only this sort of vague being which mere understanding attributes to it, then its character is that of an abstract "ought" which has no power to actualize itselfit is not "effective." Rather, it is a kind of utopian dream of "how good it would be for things to be this way"and if they were the way they ought to be, the Sollen in question would lose its meaning, which persists, precisely as Sollen, only if it is not actualized (one is forcefully reminded of Hegel's sharp critique of Kant's whole moral system). It does not take a great deal of intelligence, Hegel tells us, to recognize that there is much around us which is not as it ought to be. It is questionable, however, that there is anything particularly philosophical in this recognition. Philosophy "is concerned only with the idea, which is not so ineffective as to ought to be and not actually be." That none of this can make sense, unless the idea of which Hegel speaks is the "absolute Idea," God, whose nonactuality is inconceivable, should be obvious. As Hegel sees it, it should also be obvious that the actuality of anything else whatsoever is inconceivable without reference to the absolute Idea (see chap. 5). The important point here is that the actuality of the real and the ideality of the real are not opposed to each other; they are inseparable, neither makes sense without the other. Nor does this make sense if conceiving (begreifen) is simply what the mind does when it thinks its object, or if concept (Begriff) is only a mental representation which the mind forms to itself of its object. For thinking to have concept (or idea) as its object is not to have its own mental act as its object. Rather, it is to have as its object a reality which imposes itself on rational thinking precisely because as effectively real, reality is itself rational, and it is rational because like rational thought it is the product of rational activity. It is for this reason that reality and rational thinking are effectively oriented to each other; reality demands conceptual thought for its realization, and concept demands reality for its concretization. No. 7. None of what has gone before is to be interpreted as saying that reflection (Nachdenken) does not constitute the beginning of philosophical thinking. Without reflection there would be no philosophy, only the seemingly measureless mass of that which is present to consciousnesswhat ap
< previous page
page_64
next page >
< previous page
page_65
next page > Page 65
pears. The function of reflection, however, is not simply to impose a form of unity on the manifold of that which is present in consciousness; it is to permit the rationality of reality itself to emerge in the consciousness had of it; and consciousness itself is authentically rational only to the extent that it is in tune with the rationality of realityits "concept." If reflection is to merit the title "philosophy," it must be a knowing which penetrates the boundless "sea of empirical singularities" to find therein the "necessity" of the ''universal," to find "laws" in the seeming chaos of the contingent.7 The content of philosophical thinking, then, which is properly universal and necessary, is not the form which conceptual thinking imposes on perceptual intuition, à la Kant; it is that which thinking takes from its own intuitive grasp of both an outer and an inner world, from both nature and spirit as present in the human thinking subject. What Hegel says here is couched in surprisingly metaphorical language, but it serves to emphasize that the process of universalization which characterizes thought is not discontinuous with the process of presentation which characterizes the empirical; the form of universality is not external to empirical reality, it is discovered in that reality as present to mind. In rationalizing reality, thought manifests the inherent rationality of reality. Hegel is no enemy of experience; he makes abundantly clear that experience is indispensable even to philosophical thinking; the thinker must not only be present to that which he thinks but also find himself in the content of his thinking, no matter how empirical that content be. The presence-to of experience, however, characterizes both external sensation and internal consciousness of self. A science is called "empirical," if its point of departure is experience, whether external or internal. Such sciences, however, are philosophical only if they find in what is experienced laws, universal propositions, theory, all of which belong in the realm of thought. There was a time when even the natural sciences were called "philosophical." This is no longer necessary or to the point, but it does highlight a consciousness that science has to do, not with things, but with thoughts; and to the extent that investigation is aimed at the "rational" in the content of thought, it is philosophicalhence the propriety of various branches of philosophy, each concerned with the rational content of its object. No. 8. Granted, however, that empirical objects can give rise to and be the subject matter of philosophical inquiry, there is also another realm of objects which are simply not susceptible to this kind of investigataion; for example, freedom, spirit, and God. The reason for this, however, is not that these are not objects of "experience." They cannot, it is true, be experienced
7. Precisely because the contingent is susceptible of being grasped in rational thought it manifests the kind of necessity which is characteristic of rationality; it manifests the working of "law."
< previous page
page_65
next page >
< previous page
page_66
next page > Page 66
sensibly, but if they are objects of consciousness at all, they are objects of experiencea kind of tautologythey are objects, however, which are neither limited to a particular kind of experience nor limited by the experiencing of them; they are infinite (see chap. 4), the "beyond" to which human experience of self inevitably points. Thought "infinitizes" by breaking down (or crossing over) the barriers which separate reality into finite instances. In the Zusatz appended to this brief paragraph we find a remark which is of utmost importance, if we are to see clearly where Hegel is going. There is, he tells us, a statement erroneously ascribed to Aristotleas though it characterized Aristotle's whole philosophywhich runs, "nihil est in intellectu quod non fuerit in sensu."8 "There is nothing in the intellect which was not [previously] in sense." The point which those who use the quote seek to make is that the mind is limited as to content by what is contained in sense experience (a sentiment worthy of Locke!). Speculative philosophy is supposed to be missing its vocation if it fails to recognize the truth of this statement. In true dialectical fashion, however, Hegel asserts that speculative philosophy must with equal truth state that "nihil est in sensu, quod non fuerit in intellectu." This could simply mean that the continuity of sense and intellect is such that it would be erroneous to make the first statement as though it could be separated from the second. But, to Hegel it means much more, and the whole of his philosophy hangs on that ''much more." Taken generally, he tells us, the second statement signifies that reason (nonV *, intellectus)better still, and more profoundly, spiritis prior because it is the cause (Ursache) of the world; that is, the reality of the real is to be found in the order of concept and idea, not in the order of empirical "existence." Even more to the point in this introduction, the second statement (see no. 2) means that the sort of "feelings" Hegel has been talking aboutlegal (rechtliche), moral, religiousconstitute the experience of a content which has "its root and its abode in thought alone." Thus, there are objectsfreedom, spirit, Godwhich are objects of thought and only thought, and there are empirical objects which are truly objects only because and to the extent that they too are objects of thought. No. 9. (See no. 1). Having spoken about the content of rational (speculative) thinking, that is, a content which for thought is essentially universal, Hegel now turns to what characterizes rational thinking from the point of view of form, that is, the way in which it comprehends its object, and this he finds to be the mode of "necessity." The language here may well
8. The statement is, in fact, to be found nowhere in the Aristotelian corpus (nor did Aristotle write in medieval Latin!). Nor is Hegel's citation completely accurate: the old chestnut reads, "quod non prius fuerit in sensu." I am not aware that anyone has been able to pinpoint the source of the quote. One thing is clear: authentic or not, it does not deserve all the mileage it has achieved!
< previous page
page_66
next page >
< previous page
page_67
next page > Page 67
seem strange to contemporary readers. If by "necessity" is meant the psychological necessity of thinking in a certain way, Hegel would seem to be running afoul of his own complaint against Kantian reflective thinking that it makes only the subjective mental act its object, which yields a rather fruitless form of necessity. If, on the other hand, he is speaking of the logical necessity that the object of thought be so delimited (defined) that only propositions are necessary and that propositions are necessary only if the denial of their truth would violate the law of noncontradiction, he runs the risk of being shown that much of what he saysparticularly about freedom, spirit, and Godcannot be claimed to be, in terms of formal-logical entailment, necessary at all. Hegel even concedes that not infrequently the connections we make in our seemingly logical thinking are quite arbitrary, not necessary at all, such that, for example, the connection between the generalities we set upgeneraand the particularities they are supposed to subsumespeciesare not necessary but quite clearly contingent. Classification can, after all, be quite careless; it can depend on the taken for granted, the accepted, the presupposed. More importantly, where what is in question is what Hegel calls "speculative thinking," it may be impossible to satisfy the demands of formal-logical necessity at all, since this sort of necessity is confined to the connection between concepts which have been limited for the sole purpose of making the connection between them logically unimpeachable. But this is manipulative thinking, which is more interested in not contradicting itself than in knowing what is true. If, then, thinking is to be concerned with more than what is merely plausible or merely noncontradictory (the latter being a condition of abstract possibility), it must move on to the kind of reflection (Nachdenken) which Hegel calls ''speculative thinking." We shall have more to say of this later. Here suffice it to say that Hegel sees it as a kind of thoughtful "looking-in" which sees in the object it contemplates the kind of necessity which characterizes organic structure whose parts have the actuality they have only as the living parts of a living organisman eye plucked out is not an eye, a hand cut off is not a hand, a body which is dead is not an organism. The form which characterizes this kind of thinking is what Hegel calls "concept," whose dynamic structure distinguishes it from all other forms of thought; it is the form which makes thought to be thought in the fullest sense of the term; it is not the isolated activity of an individual subject, not the mental act which represents reality, but the internal rational structure of reality itself. Concepts do not simply "represent" alien reality. They "manifest" the intrinsic rationality which characterizes reality. Once again it is important to note that in Hegel's thought there is never a question of the either/or which makes us deny one side of a seeming contradiction if we affirm the other. Having affirmed the significance of speculative science or of speculative logic, there is no need to consider either
< previous page
page_67
next page >
< previous page
page_68
next page > Page 68
the empirical sciences or formal logic as of no significance. Speculative thinking does not ignore the empirical content of the particular sciences; it both acknowledges and makes use of such content. By the same token it both recognizes and makes use of for its own content the universal laws and categories which the empirical sciences have uncovered, but it also introduces and validates other categories which are beyond the capacity of the special sciences to comprehend. Nor does speculative logic reject the thought-forms, laws, and objectivities of either formal logic or of a metaphysics tied to formal logic; it simply takes thought beyond where these earlier forms of thought have been able to take it. All of this means, of course, that concept as understood in speculative thinking is not the same as concept is commonly taken to be; from the speculative point of view concept is a dynamic totality constantly on the move, breaking through the bonds which abstract thinking has imposed on it. It is only when concept is understood in this latter arbitrarily limited sense, that abstract thinking can contend that the infinite cannot be comprehended conceptually; of course, it cannot be comprehended in concepts whose source is merely finite thinking but it is arbitrary to claim that the concept as such can be only that. The concept "man," for example, is not simply the product of any (or every) finite activity of thinking the object "man"; it is the reality of man expressing itself in a thought which exceeds all limits of particularity. No. 10. There is, then, something quite special about the kind of knowing proper to philosophical thinking; it is not modeled on but goes beyond abstract modes of thinking, beyond the merely subjective activity of merely individual subjects. The task that Hegel sees before him, then, is that both of coming to grips with speculative thinking and the kind of necessity proper to it and of validating its capacity to know the absolute objects spoken of above. The problem is that doing this is itself a philosophical task, to be accomplished by philosophical thinking itself, not in some sort of non-philosophical propaedeutic (read: "critique"?). An attempt to give an explication here in an introduction would be unphilosophical, resting as it would on a congeries of statements, assertions, and ratiocinations, "i.e., contingent affirmations the opposite of which could be asserted with equal right." Quite obviously we cannot stop here, but we do have some indication as to where we are going. By the time he wrote this Hegel had already distanced himself considerably from Kant's "critical philosophy" which had nourished him in his youth. Here he simply indicates rather succinctly some of the reasons for this distancing. Even granting that the really important questions for philosophy concern, for example, God and the essences of things, critical philosophy, he tells us, will not even attempt to answer such questions without first investigating the mind's capacity to know anything at all. The instrument to be employed in philosophical investigation, it tells us, must be
< previous page
page_68
next page >
< previous page
page_69
next page > Page 69
examined before it is put to use. Nor can there be any doubt that Kant, following in the footsteps of, but violently disagreeing with, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume, had convinced most of his contemporaries of the reasonability of just such an approach, with the result that philosophy tended to concern itself far more with thinking than it did with what thinking thinks. What is more, if one wishes to employ a term such as "instrument,"9 it is fairly obvious that in many instances one can legitimately investigate the trustworthiness of the instrument one employs without using the instrument itself in order to carry on the investigation. What seems to have escaped Kant, howeverat least as Hegel reads himis that the attempt to know that knowing is valid can be successful only if the knowing of knowing is, in fact, valid. The circle is rapidly building up! One way of solving the problem which seems too obvious to be ignored and too devastating if it is not solved, is to do what, Hegel says, Reinhold did, by assuming that knowing is valid, treating it as something problematical, which need not be rejected until it is proved to be untrue. The difficulty is that in treating the validity of knowing as a problematic hypothesis one has not very much changed Kant's procedure, nor has one escaped its pitfallsif knowing is assumed to be true until proved to be untrue, the assumption is still an unproved assumption. No. 11. What has happened is that a thinking which confines itself to the mode of abstract understanding has involved itself in a circle out of which, merely as understanding, it can find no exitunless, of course, thinking can find a virtue in the circularity of its procedure; that is, that the circle is not "vicious" but rather "dialectical," not skirting but rather making use of the very contradictions in which it has become involved. If we see spirit as the unified source of conscious activity (perhaps "source activity" would be better), there is no need to speak of ''faculties" (instruments) at all, as though the mind "employed" them in relating itself to this or that object. When the activity of the mind is that of feeling or intuition, then its objects are sensible; when it imagines, its objects are images; when it wills, its objects are purposes, and so on and on. If the mind goes all the way it will come upon an activity which is, so to speak, in contradiction with all of these lesser forms and can do what none of the others do. It can occupy itself with itself, and this is thinking.10 In the most profound sense of the word, thinking can think itself, and there is no circle here, no unresolved contradiction. Thinking in the fullest sense, that is, as speculative, can both
9. In the introduction to the Phenomenology Hegel is at pains to point out the futility of looking at knowing (thinking) as that which a subject employs (an instrument) in grappling with objects. 10. Sensing does not sense sensing; imagining does not imagine imagining; willing does not will willing; but thinking does think thinking. What is more, thinking thinks the other activities also.
< previous page
page_69
next page >
< previous page
page_70
next page > Page 70
think and resolve the many contradictions in which thinking on the level of abstraction inevitably becomes involved. Thinking, as we saw before, does not stand still in order to be examined, nor does an analysis of what would have to be the case if thinking is to be counted valid yield particularly satisfactory results. Thinking must think itself as the dynamic activity which it is in order to reveal to itself what it is. We have a foretaste here of what logic is going to be for Hegel. He speaks, however, of an "insight" (Einsicht) into the nature of thinking which reveals that it is essentially dialectic. Of utmost importance in this is the realization that on the level of abstraction proper to understanding (Verstand) thinking cannot but become involved in contradictions. What is new in Hegel's thinking is the conviction that, if the contradictions are faced honestly and not simply wished away, they will resolve themselves in dynamic interaction, showing that the complex manysidedness of thought, rather than being a cause for despair, constitutes the enormous richness which only a thinking unimpeded by images can unravel. At the same time thought can now objectify itself in all its forms, without fear that it will become bogged down in any one of them,11 nor will it have to take refuge in a kind of thinking which deliberately leaves out the dynamic mediation which makes thought to be thoughtit can avoid the pitfall of relying solely on so-called "immediate" contact with its object. No. 12. When philosophical thinking is looked upon in this way, Hegel has no difficulty in acknowledging that philosophy does, in fact, find its point of departure in experience, which provides consciousness with a content. From this point of view experience is seen as a "stimulus" (Reiz) which calls forth thoughta thought which, so to speak, lifts itself above the consciousness which is no more than naively manipulative of the content given in sensation to a level of thinking which does not need an admixture of sensible images, thus moving away from and adopting a "negative relationship" to its point of departure. Its domain is no longer that of successive appearances but rather that of the one universal essence manifested in appearances, call it the Absolute, or God, but still an essence which is at this point more or less abstract. On the other hand, the empirical sciences carry thier own stimulus for thought to raise itself above the merely empirical form of thinking, wherein its manifold content is taken to be simply given and hence contingent, to a level where that same content assumes the form of rational necessity, where the universality of laws of nature rules. It is this stimulus which cancels the satisfaction which thought initially found in its abstract absolute, by goading it on to a development which proceeds from within thought itself. But even on this level thought is no more than the reception of a content, whose determinations simply belong to it as it is,
11. The overall message of Hegel's Phenomenology.
< previous page
page_70
next page >
< previous page
page_71
next page > Page 71
thus giving thought the appearance of being free, not in the sense of being self-determined, but in the sense of zeroing in on the rationality which belongs properly to the real which is its object. Thinking in this sense is tied down, it is true, but it is tied to reality, not to its own vagaries nor to the merely sensible manifestations of reality. It is too soon, Hegel feels, to speak more in detail of the relationship of immediateness and mediation in consciousness, a theme about which he will have much to say in logic. Suffice it to say here that, even though as moments of thought the two can be distinguished, they cannot be separated, if thought is to be thought. Thus, to know Godor any suprasensible12 object whateveris to be lifted above the sensible, to be negatively related to it, and this negative relation is itself mediation, that is, a movement beyond what is immediately given. The result can seem rather paradoxical: the very immediacy of the initial grasp mediates the movement which carries thinking beyond it, a movement which is inescapable, if thinking is to be true to itself. Still, and this is important, the movement beyond the empirical is not dependent on the empirical, not derived from it. Thinking cancels out the sensible from which it took its rise; it negates that which is immediately before it. The sensible does not remain as an element in thinking. The dialectic of thinking involves not a finding in the sensible what it needs but a going beyond the sensible to find what it needs; and the going beyond must go all the way! Hegel adds here a remark which is seldom noted by commentators, especially by those who complain that for him speculative thinking simply swallows up religious belief. There is unquestionably a very special kind of satisfaction to be found in a thinking which has in itself a universality it gives itself (a priori); a satisfaction which permits it to be rather indifferent to the contingent particularizations of this universality. But the satisfaction runs the risk of being empty if it simply stops here. When we look at religion, he tells us, whether it be developed or undeveloped, brought to the level of a conscious knowing or held on the level of simple, heartfelt faith, we can see that the kind of emotional satisfaction it gives in both cases can be the same; the one does not have to be antagonistic to the other. And here, I think, we have to supply something which, although Hegel does not explicitly state it, seems to be required by what follows (and it is also stated explicitly elsewhere [see BDG, 4th lecture]), namely, that if religion becomes so intellectual that the satisfaction of the heart has been eliminated, religion itself has become empty formalism. By the same token, if philosophy stands still in the universality of ideas, as happened in the case of the "being" of Parmenides or the "becoming" of Heraclitus, there can
12. It should not be amiss to point out that the German term for "suprasensible" is übersinnlich, which means not only "above" the sensible but also ''more than" the sensible.
< previous page
page_71
next page >
< previous page
page_72
next page > Page 72
be a justified complaint that philosophy has stagnated into formalism. Even a highly developed philosophy can get bogged down in abstract propositions; for example, that "in the absolute all is one" or "the subjective the objective are identical,"13 with the result that these abstractions are simply carried over unaltered and applied to particular instances. Philosophy should remain grateful for what the empirical sciences have provided, preparing the material which philosophy can then make its own (i.e., "appropriate''). Philosophy is self-developing, it is true, but its selfdevelopment should not be separated from its appropriation of a content antecedently prepared. It develops that content "speculatively," which is what the empirical sciences are incapable of doing, but there is no reason why, in the deep satisfaction of its own independence, it must downgrade the empirical, the particular. Even the universality attaching to the term "philosophy" itself should not blind philosophers to the diversity of philosophical positions subsumed under the one heading of "philosophy"; not only are particulars no less real than the universal, but they constitute in their diversity the concrete unity of the whole which is the universal. Here is enunciated in a rather unobtrusive way the peculiarly Hegelian principle of concrete universality, arrived at not by the suppression of differences among particulars until a sort of least common denominator is reached, but by embracing in one whole the complementarity of diverse manifestations of the one. This principle of seeing unity in diversity will be of utmost importance in Hegel's philosophy of religion. No. 13. The consequences of this principle are singularly manifest in the development of one philosophy out of the diversity of philosophical positions, a development which is elaborated in the history of philosophy as, so to speak, the "organic" growth of a "concrete universal" whose unity is that of continuous process, not merely the unity of collection (a sequential movement in which "philosophies" accumulate), nor is it the unity of including diversity under one class concept called "philosophy."14 There is a danger, of course, that the continuity of the movement of thought will be missed by those who merely record a succession of philosophical positions without attention to the intrinsic growth of the very idea which is philosophy. It is here that Hegel puts so much stress on that central theme of his philosophizing which so many find unacceptable. The active source of philosophical thinking, and hence of its development, he contends, is "the one living spirit," which in the millennia which have preceded us has been progressively becoming conscious of itself as being the totality of both all thought and all reality. It is this spirit which is the articulated summation of
13. Quite clearly in these remarks Hegel has Schelling in mind. 14. See EGP, pp. 94136; Lauer, Hegel's Idea of Philosophy, pp. 6792.
< previous page
page_72
next page >
< previous page
page_73
next page > Page 73
finite thinking infinitized in the continuity of its own process. The history of philosophy, in this view, bears eloquent witness to the unity which is philosophy, one "organic" whole of which diverse philosophies are the "branches" and whose consummation in any given age retains the whole of its significant past. What becomes evident here is that the diversityeven contradictorinessof successive philosophical positions, far from arguing to the unreliability of the philosophical enterprise as a whole, rather attests to the living complementarity of diversity, which makes for richness rather than poverty, for growth rather than decline, and for the hope that truth constantly sought after can be attained, on condition that it never be required to stand still. No. 14. Development in the sense in which Hegel understands it, however, is not confined to a chronological sequence of positions. It is exhibited in philosophical thinking itself, independently of chronological sequence. Thinking itself is developmental, or it is not thinking. Truly self-developing thought is itself concrete (from concrescere, a process of internal growth). Seen in this way thought is idea, the objective unity of thought in its development or the unified interrelatedness of objective thinking. If the unity is total universality, what comes to light is the Idea, the Absolute. Philosophy can rightly be called the "science" of the Absolute as Idea, but only if philosophy is "system," wherein concrete truth unfolds itself as united in a totality which not only retains a diversity of determinations but also recognizes that diversity is necessary to the process of self-determination. Hegel will sharpen this even more by stating that a "philosophy without system cannot be scientific"; it can only be a subjective mode of thinking tied to the contingent content which the senses present to it. We must recognize that a content of thought is valid only as a "moment" of the whole, otherwise it is no more than an unfounded presupposition, a mere subjective certainty. A nonsystem is no better than a congeries of conjectures and opinions; truths cannot be isolated from each other nor from the totality. On the other hand, a philosophy which limits itself to one principle which is to explain everything (e.g., Fichte's Ich or Schelling's undifferentiated absolute) is not truly philosophy. It is the true principle of philosophy to embrace within itself all particular principlesthis is "system." No. 15. Imperceptibly, Hegel now shifts from the diversity of philosophical positions within the ongoing whole which is "philosophy" to the "parts" of philosophy, presumably the multiplicity designated by his use of the plural in the title, Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences. Looking at philosophy this way he considers each of its "parts" to have a certain philosophical wholeness in itself, even though the validity of each depends on its being a part of the one whole. If the whole of philosophy, then, can be called ''system," each of its parts is, so to speak, a system
< previous page
page_73
next page >
< previous page
page_74
next page > Page 74
within the system, or, as he says metaphorically, "a circle enclosed within itself" such that the whole can be seen as a "circle of circles." The philosophical Idea, which is one, is present in each of the parts under a form peculiar to the part. Each of the "circles," because in itself a kind of totality, breaks through the confinement of its own particularized subject-matter, thus laying the foundation for an ever-widening sphere of thought. Each of the parts, then, is a necessary moment of the dynamic whole, in such a way that the overall system which embraces what is peculiar to each of the parts is the one Idea which is manifested in each of the constitutive parts. No. 16 Once again, the point is made in the title: what Hegel is presenting here is an Encyclopedia, the whole circle (cucloV *) of instruction (paideia*) in philosophical thinking. As such its task is not to present the detailed development of particulars but rather to confine itself to the principles and fundamental concepts of the particular sciences which make up the wholea whole in the sense that it is complete, no "philosophical" sciences being left out. It is not as though, however, one could count the number of parts which must be included, if the whole is to be a whole. The parts are not separated units; each is true only to the extent that it is itself a whole. The whole of philosophy, then, can be seen as in truth one science, but it must also be seen as a whole of many particularcomplementaryparts. In this context diverse "philosophies" can be seen, even in their particular inadequacy, as converging beams of light all illumining the one "absolute." If by "encyclopedia" we ordinarily understand a composite work which treats many topics, an aggregate whose loose principle of unity is little more than to be of common interest to the enquiring human mind, then perhaps Hegel should offer an apology for employing the term. In any event what he means by a "philosophical" encyclopedia is not (1) a collection of interesting items of information, nor (2) an arbitrary inventory of what are to be called "positive" sciences, having no rationally necessary connection with each other. This does not mean that philosophy has no interest in the subject-matter of what from their own point of view are, in fact, positive sciences. To the extent that these latter have a rational foundation, they are of interest to philosophical enquiry, even though what is merely "positive" (informational) in them is not of philosophical interest. It is not, however, that facts are unimportant, even to philosophical enquiry; it is simply that philosophy's interest is not in facts as facts, only facts as illustrative of concepts which are philosophy's sole concernan uninterpreted "fact'' is, properly speaking, not a fact. The concept of beauty can be instanced in this or that work of art, the concept of law in this or that particular bit of legislation, the concept of history in this or that event, the concept of nature in this or that treeor even forestbut philosophy's concern is the concept, not the particular instance as such. What it comes down to is that a "science," to the extent that it is "positive," must recognize that it is
< previous page
page_74
next page >
< previous page
page_75
next page > Page 75
oriented to the knowledge of contingent facts and to the concepts which render these facts intelligible, not to the overall rational interrelation of concepts. Hegel is willing to admit, however, that even an empirical investigation can be so organized that its procedures are dictated by the internal consistency of the guiding concept, in which case the procedures would still be essentially philosophical. It would seem that he is referring, at least indirectly, to his own procedures, particularly in his philosophy of nature, philosophy of subjective spiritand, to a certain extent, in the philosophy of right, philosophy of art, and even in the history of philosophy, in all of which he looks to facts (or events) in order to obtain "empirical verification" for a conceptual structure which his Science of Logic had told him he could justifiably expect to find. "In such a procedure," he contends, ''an experimental physics or a history, etc., rooted in sense experience will present the rational science of nature and of human events in image form, which form, although extrinsic to the concept, still mirrors it." No. 17. It could seem that, if philosophy is to begin, it must do so, like the other sciences, on the basis of a subjective presupposition, which is to say with an initial decision as to what its proper object is.15 Just as mathematics makes space or number the object of thinking, so philosophy makes thinking itself that object. There is a difference, however; thinking is the free, self-determining act which characterizes philosophy, where its standpoint is independent, where it gives to itself an object which it itself has produced. More than that, the standpoint which appears to be immediately given must be the result of the scientific thinking in question, so that only at the end does it attain to its beginning (i.e., to its truth). Philosophy, then, is a sort of circle closing on itself, which does not have a beginning, in the sense that other sciences do, whose beginning is dictated by the scientist's decision to begin. Philosophy's (or logic's) beginning is dictated by the science itself, by the very concept of what the science is. Where does philosophy say that the philosopher must begin? Philosophy has only one purpose, only one goal of its activity, to attain to the concept of its own concept. Philosophy's proper task is to find out what philosophy is, which is to say, to bring itself into being by philosophizing. The foregoing analysis of Hegel's introduction to Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences has been, it might seem, rather prolix. At the same time it has not been erudite in the way, for example, that Theunissen's 220-page analysis of twenty-five paragraphs of the Encyclopedia has been.16 The pur-
15. We are forcibly reminded here, in the introduction to the Encyclopedia of [all] the Philosophical Sciences, of the question which introduces the first part of Science of Logic, "The Doctrine of Being": Womit muss der Anfang der Wissenschaft gemacht werden? ("with what must the science begin?"), (WL I, p. 51). 16. Michael Theunissen, Hegels Lehre vom absoluten Geist als Theologisch-politischer Traktat. (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1970), pp. 103322.
< previous page
page_75
next page >
< previous page
page_76
next page > Page 76
pose of the analysis here has been twofold: (1) to extract from the text the overall movement and direction of Hegel's philosophical thinking; and (2) to see how the movement of this thinking inevitably culminates in a thinking of God, without a knowledge of whom all thinking is condemned to fall by the wayside and never attain to the grasp of its own truth. It is not that the reality of God is the only necessary truth to which philosophy attains, but that no other necessary truth, be it that of morality, of human freedom and the rights consequent on that, of logical thinking, or of the laws of nature, would be either true or necessary, if not rooted in the necessity of the absolute Idea, which is none other than absolute Spirit, God. The "Necessity" of Truth For contemporary thinking the difficulty with all this is not so much that Hegelian thought culminates in Goddespite various attempts to claim that it does notrather it lies in an uneasiness with a thinking which speaks of "necessary truth" at all or, worse still, that the human mind can claim to know what is necessarily true. It is all right, logically, to speak of necessarily accepting a proposition as true, if it is seen to be logically entailed in another proposition (or propositions) already accepted as true, but that is a far cry from saying that a state of affairs enunciated in such a proposition is necessarily the case, that this state of affairs could not not be true. Nor need there be too much difficulty for the contemporary mind to acknowledge at least the plausibility of the Kantian contention that human reason operates in such a way that it necessarily asserts that certain states of affairs are true, even though it cannot know that this is the case. But Hegel cannot be satisfied with either of these positions. With regard to the first position, he will claim not only that the human mind is logically necessitated to affirm certain universal truths (e.g., that infinite being is real, that the human spirit makes free decisions, that murder is wrong) and is illogical if it does not, but also that what the human mind is thus logically necessitated to affirm is necessarily the case, even when the formal-logical entailment of these propositions in other propositions has not been demonstrated to be necessary. There is a logic of speculative thinking which carries the mind beyond the limitations of formal logicwihtout violating the rules of formal logic in so doing. With regard to the second position, Hegel will make a sharp distinction between the way the human mind in fact necessarily thinks (presuming that this could be known at all) and the way the human mind is logically necessitated to think, under pain of its thinking being a nonthinking. Knowing how the human mind is logically necessitated to thinkespecially if the logic in question is "speculative"may still cause us some difficulties, but Hegel is convinced that "speculative thinking" will
< previous page
page_76
next page >
< previous page
page_77
next page > Page 77
be seen to validate itself if we go through with it. What it comes down to is that Hegel is making the enormous claim that the human mind must think this way under pain of being irrational if it does not. Nor does "rational" refer only to the way the mind necessarily thinks; it also takes in the way reality necessarily is; reality reveals to and in rational thinking what reality's own rationality is. It might not be amiss here to give a few examples of what this kind of thinking entails. When I speak with you, I can (perhaps must) say "that what is before me is a human being is contingent, not necessary"no "fact" is. That a human being is immortal, if it is true at all, is necessarily true, in such a way that to deny it would be irrational. The same can be put in a slightly different way: To say that I am not human, might very well be untrue, but it is not irrational; there are nonhuman beings. To say that a human being is not immortal is not only untrue, it is irrationalthere are no nonimmortal human beings; immortality belongs to the very "concept" of human. It should be observed, of course, that in this context "irrational" carries with it no moral stigma. You may be doing the best you can, but ''doing the best you can" does not save you from irrationality. Relation of Thought and Reality In one sense all of this is very clearthere is scarcely anything in Hegel's writing clearer than the introduction to the Encyclopedia. In another sense, however, since it was not possible for Hegel, in an introduction, to spell out the doctrine of "concept" upon which the elaboration of philosophical thinking is predicated, a certain lack of clarity persists in clinging both to Hegel's text and to an analysis thereof. In a tradition of philosophical thinking according to which a sharp distinction was drawn between the subjective activity of thinking and the objective order of reality which that thinking sought to reproduce, the guiding principles in the interpretation of human knowing had been (1) the Aristotelian assertion that in knowing, the mind somehow "becomes" that which it knows, and (2) the contention, erroneously attributed to Aristotle, that the "somehow" implies that the mind is a "blank tablet" upon which reality makes its imprint. That the mind has a special capacity of its own both to receive these imprints in such a way as to produce "ideas" which, if properly produced, would be faithful reproductions of reality, was also part of the Aristotelian heritage which dominated philosophy until the eighteenth century. Explicitly or implicitly the presupposition behind all this was that the activity to be explained was causal activity: the causality of reality in imprinting itself, and the causality of the mind in working on the materials at its disposal. What the heritage was left with, however, was two worlds, a world of reality "out there," and
< previous page
page_77
next page >
< previous page
page_78
next page > Page 78
a world of ideas, which, however faithfully it might be said to reproduce the world of reality, was nevertheless another world.17 With the advent of "modern" philosophy, however, whose beginning is commonly said to be found in the thinking of Descartesalthough it might be more accurate to make the beginning more general, locating it in the overall need to secure a foundation for bourgeoning experimental sciencea new need arose, that of guaranteeing the validity of the knowledge the human mind was supposed to possess. The Aristotelian framework of causal explanation was not immediately abandoned, but a new emphasis was introduced: The world of ideas was still distinct from the world of reality, but the validation of the world of ideas was to be sought within that world itselfideas were true if they had the proper qualities to make them true, which is to say, if they were such as to make it impossible to doubt their truth. Very subtly the emphasis had shifted from the truth of reality which ideas were supposed to reflect to the certainty the mind had concerning the validity of its ideas. On the European continent this resulted in a "rationalism," which found a guarantee for ideas in the rationality of the subjective process of arriving at them. Across the channel it resulted in an "empiricism,'' which sought to guarantee ideas by tracing their derivation from indubitable experiencethe only "rational" way to guarantee them. Then came Hume, who tossed the bombshell which rocked both camps: The only indubitability attaching to ideas was their relationship to each other, which left reality in the dark; and the only indubitability attaching to experience was the experience itself, not what it was the experience of. Causality was of no help as a guarantee, since there can be no certainty of causality itself. There was no escaping Hume's challenge, and so Kant picked up the gauntlet right where Hume had thrown it. It has been said of Kant that he was the first philosopher to have inserted the human thinking subject into the very heart of the logic of thought. No longer would it be a question of validating ideas by tracing the process of arriving at themmetaphysically, rationalistically, or empiricallysince Hume had made all three approaches suspect. Rather, Kant would investigate critically the necessary conditions for the human mind's concepts to be both true and meaningful, and he would find that the human subject had all the equipment it needed for that. It the human subject would employ that equipment in the way it demandedwith necessitythat it be employed, human thinking would be trueeven though not, perhaps, true to a reality presumed to be "in-itself" independently of the experiencing of it. It was a gigantic break with a long
17. In Phenomenology of Spirit, chap. III "Force and Understanding: Appearance and Supra-Sensible World," Hegel depicts the last-ditch stand of the "objective" attitude of a consciousness which would look outside itself for the cause of its being conscious of the world. In doing this Hegel shows how the two worlds (of reality and of the mind) demand that the world of the mind be an image of the real world, where in fact it may be no more than a mirror-imagean "inverted" (verkehrte) world.
< previous page
page_78
next page >
< previous page
page_79
next page > Page 79
philosophic tradition. In one way or another Kant's predecessors, all the way back to the Greeks, had presupposed that the structure of human thought bore witness to a corresponding structure of reality. Gone now was this presupposition, whose only supportpresumablywas the causality whose cognitional significance had been impugned by Hume. Causality for Kant had not completely left the stage, but it remained on the stage only as a category operative within thought, with no justification for its application to a world of reality beyond thought. There is no question that Kant bequeathed to his successors a problem; it is a mark of his genius that, if the problem is not solved, there is no going beyond Kant. There can be a question, however, as to whether the problem is insoluble. Of the three great "system-builders" who succeeded Kant, that is, Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, each attempted in his own way to resolve the Kantian dilemma without returning to the causality principle, at least in the form of it impugned by Hume. This is not the place to describe the efforts of Fichte and Schelling to overcome the Kantian duality of objectivity and subjectivity, or of an independent reality and of a thinking whose task it was to reproduce it faithfully. Suffice it to say that both sought to solve the problem by appeal to an absolute subject which would account for both itself and objectivity, thus leaving no gap between subjectivity and objectivity to be bridged. Hegel would build on both, and he would do so by denying the basic premiss that it makes sense to speak of a world of reality "beyond thought" at all. This is what has been called Hegel's "idealism," but it is not the purely subjective idealism of a Berkeley, not the idealism of an indeterminate absolute à la Fichte or Schelling, nor, to anticipate, is it the idealism of an unidentifiable ''transcendental subject" à la Husserl. For Hegel, as for his great predecessors Plato and Aristotle, Aquinas and Spinoza, the structure of truly rational human thinking does bear witness to the structure of reality; not, however, because the structures of thought and of reality are similar but because they are, ultimately, one and the same. It will be the task of his monumental Science of Logic not only to show that they are one and the sameFichte and Schelling had sought to affirm thatbut also to show how they are one and the same, namely, as dynamic process. Logic is the unfolding in thought of the structure of thought, and the affirmation which Hegel makes in his introduction to Science of Logic, that the "content [of Logic] is the presentation of God, as he is in his eternal essence before the creation of nature and of a single finite spirit" (WL I, p. 31), however one may want to interpret it, is to be taken seriously. It means at the very least that the thought which logic investigates consists of a unified totality which is both antecedent to (logically), and the source of (ontologically), finite reality and finite thought. The structures of thought are the structures of reality, because subjective rational thinking and objective rational reality are products of a thought which at once transcends and embraces both. This, in turn, means
< previous page
page_79
next page >
< previous page
page_80
next page > Page 80
that the transcendent concept (the producing) and the transcendent idea (the produced) are identical and constitute both the reality of the real and the truth of thought. The Meaning of Concept It is time, however, to let Hegel himself speak. I have chosen, once more, to let Hegel speak in the words of the Logic contained in his Encyclopedia, not because the language of Science of Logic would not be both more instructive and more satisfying, but because an analysis of what he says in the larger work would by itself turn into a full-length book. The passages to be analyzed here are taken from the third part of the Logic, entitled "The Doctrine of Concept." In it Hegel is telling us what he means by "concept," as opposed to what a great part of the Western philosophical tradition and, in particular, his contemporary opponents have meant. He begins by saying that concept is a self-determining totality, not the mental act of an individual subject, but "independent substantial power," such that whatever is subsumed under the concept is a "moment" of the whole concept and, as a moment, expresses the whole concept and is valid only as inseparably united with the concept, deriving its determinateness from its identification with the whole (no. 160). Quite obviously a statement such as this needs some explaining, which is precisely what Hegel tells us, in the prefaces to both the first and second editions, a lecturer who uses a manual like the Encyclopedia should give. The Zusatz, presumably, contains the explanation which Hegel himself gave when lecturing. In any event, throughout this section the Zusätze are for the most part more enlightening than is the main text. The Zusatz here tells us, then, that when Hegel uses the term ''concept," he is speaking from the point of view of "absolute idealism," according to which what ordinary consciousness looks upon as a "being" independent of consciousness is seen to be but an "ideal moment" of a larger whole which only "begreifendes Erkennen" can come to grips with.18 The "logic of understanding," on the other hand, tends to look upon the concept as simply a form of subjective thinking, the way the in-
18. Apart from the difficulty of coming to grips with what Hegel means by Begriffthe thrust of this entire chapterthere is the difficulty of determining just how the term should be translated (if indeed there can be one undeviating translation). For the most part those who have translated Hegel's works into English (particularly British translators) have opted for the English term "notion." This has its merits, especially if the term recaptures the dynamic connotation of the Greek nonV *, which Hegel translates as Vernunft. It is to be feared, however, that for most of us the term "notion" does not have these dynamic overtones. "Concept," on the other hand, although it is not without its difficulties, has the merit of being related to the activity of "con-ceiving" (producing from within) and of retaining connotations of "concreteness" and "com-prehension," both of which for Hegel are essentially dynamic. It is a question of what one chooses to emphasize, and neither of the English terms emphasizes all that Hegel wishes to emphasize.
< previous page
page_80
next page >
< previous page
page_81
next page > Page 81
dividual mind "represents" to itself universally the object it thinks, an empty abstraction. As Hegel sees it, the concept is the exact opposite of abstract; it is an "utterly concrete," vital principle. The whole logical movement described up to this point should make that clear; even the distinction of form and content of the concept is seen to be a dialectical distinction, that is, one which in the movement of thought cancels itself outthe thinking is the content of the thinking, and the concept is the unity of form and content. If, of course, one means by "concrete" the sensible, then the concept is abstract, not "graspable" by the senses at all; but as uniting the totality of finite perspectives into an ideal unity, into a determinate whole, it is concrete, the locus of concrete universality, the really real, not the mentally fragmented. In this sense the concept is the definition of the absolute. It might, of course, be asked why "speculative logic'' calls what is here in question "concept," since the term can lead to so much misunderstanding. The fact is, however, that the "speculative" meaning of concept is not so far from the meaning given it in "ordinary language"; we do speak of deriving the properties of an object from its "concept," and we do try to grasp the meaning of what we are faced with by turning to the "concept" of it. What Hegel is saying of the concept, then, is that it is the dynamic reproduction in thought of the rational structure of reality. The overall pattern of logical thinking contains three main parts: (1) the logic of being, or the selfdevelopment of thought's inevitable object; (2) the logic of essence, or reflection on that object as it is reproduced in thought; and (3) the logic of concept, or the investigation of the dynamic structure of thought as expressing the structure of reality. It is not as though the concept is that which thought produces and then attributes to realitya medium between reality and thoughtit is the self-manifestation of conceptually-structured reality in conceptuallystructured subjective thinkingthe discovery of dynamic thought-structure in reality is the same movement as the self-expression of thought-structured reality in thought.19 In thinking itself thought finds that it necessarily thinks its object universally. But, if it is to come to grips with its universalized object, it must also think the particularities of that object, which it can do only if it thinks the particularities of its own structure. Although, then, the abstract universality of the concept in subjective thinking is only a moment in the concrete process of thought, it is a moment and, as such, is indispensable. If it is a function of reason to unify diversity, then unified diversity is a product of reasonbut so is diversified unity. The direction in which Hegel is moving is already clear: toward the all-unifying concept (absolute Spirit), the absolute Idea (God).
19. As Hegel tells us, he had already given an adumbration of this logical method of investigation in the Phenomenology's examination of the structure of consciousness. See WL I, p. 7.
< previous page
page_81
next page >
< previous page
page_82
next page > Page 82
No. 161. The progress of the concept, he goes on to tell us, ceases to be a passage of reality into what is other than itself, that is, thought. Rather it is a "development" of the concept itself. The progressive identification of the diverse and the unified in a whole determinateness is the self-determination of the concept as a whole. Zusatz: Hegel is not denying that there is a passage involved in the movement from reality to thought; reality and thought are distinct. But the distinction is dialectical, and so the term "development" is more accurate than the term "passage"; reality does not become thought, it already is thought-reality. As an illustration of this he takes the development in nature from seed to full-blown plant, where the progressive diversification does not presuppose the antecedent presence of infinitesimal "parts," only the ''ideal" presence of a diversity whose actualization is the growth of the plant. In a very significant sense, then, the plant is, from beginning to end of its growth, one and the same. So too with the concept; it grows according to its own laws of development. Like the plant, it takes on otherness, so to speak, only to find that the otherness is not other; it remains itself in othering itself. As a model of this Hegel takes the Christian teaching on creation, according to which God brings to being what is other than himself, only because from eternity he generates a Son, in whom God remains the same as himself. For some the example could seem farfetched, but it does point up Hegel's contention that it makes no sense to speak of "concepts" except in the framework of the one "concept" transcending all concepts (see chap. 7). No. 162. By this time it should be clear that Hegel's logic has at most a faint family resemblance to the logic with which most of us are familiar, concerned as the latter is with the forms of subjective thinking and with rules for the correct manipulation of those forms. Not only is the investigation of concept, for Hegel, only the third part of logic, but the study of the "forms" of thinking constitutes only a "part of a part." This part Hegel calls "the doctrine of the subjective or formal concept." It is to be followed by a study of the "objectivity" of the concept and by a study of the unity of subject and object, which he called "idea" and which alone contains "truth" in the full sense of the term. It is not a question, however, of repudiating formal logic but rather of clearing out the "empirical material," whether psychological, "metaphysical," or whatever, which has crept into what should be purely logical considerations. What is more, these forms, which are legitimate subjects of logical investigation, tend to be looked upon from the very narrow viewpoint of the "understanding," which is proper to positive science, rather than from the more comprehensive point of view of "reason." The real danger is, as Hegel sees it, that such notions as "being" and "essence" will be looked upon as dictated by subjective thinking alone rather than as "concepts" with their own inner laws of dialectical develop
< previous page
page_82
next page >
< previous page
page_83
next page > Page 83
ment and interrelatedness in a concrete whole of thought. If what are commonly called "concepts" are no more than the determinations imposed by understanding on the reality it thinks, that is, universalized "representations," they are essentially "finite" and, therefore, inadequate to a thought which transcends all finite instantiations. It is the danger of dealing with the "forms" of thinking in such a way that the "truth'' of thinking's "content" is either ignored (in favor of "correctness") or is considered to be supplied by a source other than thought itself. On the contrary, Hegel will look upon the forms of thought as "the living spirit of the actual," such that it is by virtue of these forms, "through them and in them" that what is said of the actual is true. Therefore, it is necessary to look into the very truth of these forms themselves. Just what are theyin truth? Just what constitutes the necessity of their connection with each other? It is more than merely formal-logical entailmenthowever difficult it may be to grasp what that "more than" can mean. That there is an initial stage in the thinking process when the reality thought is distinct from and over-against the thinking of it is not to be gainsaid; my concept is the product of my thinking, and it is distinct from the reality it represents, "as subjective thinking it is a reflection external to the thing" (WL II, p. 236). In this sense to know thought is to know oneself as positing the object of one's thinking. But, it must not be allowed to stop there; it is only the beginning of a dialectical movement "through which its isolation and consequently the separation of the concept from the thing is superseded. As its truth there emerges the truth which is the objective concept" (ibid.). Thus, "in its objectivity the concept is the thing itself which is in and for itself" (ibid.)."20 It is to be noted, of course, that what is said here is merely asserted, not proved; it is "the concept of concept," what Hegel means. Now we must follow this out. No. 163. The process of development, then, begins with the subjective concept, that which the thinking of an individual subject produces, and we must see what this subjective form, merely as such, involves. It contains the three "moments" of universality, particularity, and singularity. It should be pointed out that, by calling these "moments," Hegel is serving notice that he considers them as dynamic elements in a process, each intelligible only as related to the others in a movement from one to the otherand back. "Universality" designates the character of sameness with itself that the concept retains in each of its instantiations (Bestimmtheit). "Particularity," then, is the generalized instantiation, in which the self-sameness of the universal remains undisturbed, whereas "singularity" is the ultimate instantiation, wherein are reflected both the determinacy of the particular
20. It should be noted that the operative term here is "Objektivität" not "Gegenständlichkeit." Gegenstand is "object" as given ("standing") over-against a subject; Objekt is "object" as that toward which a movement is directed. It contains overtones of purpose, e.g., "my object in doing this."
< previous page
page_83
next page >
< previous page
page_84
next page > Page 84
and the self-sameness of the universal. The singular is the same as the "actual thing," but it is the conceptualized thing, posited in a universal way as simply this thing identical with itself. The actual thing, on the other hand, is the existing, the self-manifesting thing, which can "effect" (wirken)21 its self-manifestation as what it is. By the same token, the singularity of the concept is its "effectiveness," not like a "cause" which effects something other than itself, but as effectively moving toward its own completion. The singularity of the concept, clearly, should not be confused with the individuality of things, which is pinpointed only in judgment. Since each ''moment" of the concept is the whole concept, the singularity in question, which belongs to the subject of a judgment, is the concept posited as totality, that is, that which embraces all its determinations. Zusatz 1: To say that a concept is at once universal, particular, and singular is obviously a rather uncommon way to speak of concepts. A concept is usually looked upon as a universal, arrived at by a suppression of the particular differences which characterize its instantiations. This is the way, Hegel tells us, that understanding considers concepts, and it tends to make them empty shells. What he is talking about is a universal concept which particularizes itself, and only if we bear this in mind can we avoid the complaint that philosophical thinking deals in mere abstractions. The universal about which he is talking here, in its truly comprehensive signification, has its roots in Christianity's conception of God. The Greeks knew neither God nor man in their truly universal dimensions. Their gods were merely particular powers, and the only universal god for them was the Athenians' "unknown God";22 nor was "man" truly universal, since for the Greeks the barbarians were not men in the same sense the Greeks were. One might doubt what Hegel is saying here, but the point he is making is a familiar one: What is universally true of man, that is, based on the very "concept" of man (e.g., freedom), is not true of only some men, based on a particular reason (e.g., that they were Greek citizens), but of all men, simply because they are human. Thus, slavery is compatible with paganism but not with Christianity, according to which freedom is proper to the human in its infinite universality, because each and every human being is of equal value. There are slaves only when this is not recognized, when some human beings are considered not to be "persons." The difference, however, is not quantitative; the universal is not arrived at by counting noses but by realizing that the concept is true only if it is universally true and, thus, that what is necessarily true of the particular, or of the individual, is necessarily true only because it is universally true, and the universally true is the "concept"but
21. Not, however, by causally "affecting" what is other. 22. Acts 17:23.
< previous page
page_84
next page >
< previous page
page_85
next page > Page 85
there would be no "concepts" in this sense, if there were no one "Concept" in this sense. Zusatz 2: Nowhere is it more clear than in Hegel's "doctrine of the concept" that Karl Löwith was correct in characterizing Hegel's Logic as "a constantly repeated defining of God."23 Even one who is thoroughly familiar with Hegel's cast of thought is in for a series of surprises as Hegel asserts again and again that human thinking simply makes no sense except against the backdrop of divine thought, that conceptual thinking is valid only because "the Concept" is necessarily valid. Here he very boldly states that "the logic of understanding'' is simply wrong when it speaks of "the emergence and construction of concepts." As a matter of fact, he tells us, we do not construct concepts, "nor is the concept to be considered as something which has come to be." It is true, of course, to say the concept is not simply "being" or a "given," that "mediation" is inseparable from it; but the mediation is not applied from outside, it belongs to the very "concept of concept"; it is its own mediation, its movement. It is not true to say that first there are objects (Gegenstände) which constitute the contents of our "representations," which we then, by the subjective activities of abstraction and combination of what is common to the representations, conceptualize. It is the concept which is truly first, and "things are what they are through the activity of the concepts that dwell in them." We see this most clearly in our religious consciousness, according to which we say, "God created the world out of nothing or, to put it another way, the world and finite things have proceeded from the fullness of divine thoughts and decrees." What is being said in this religious way expresses the philosophical truth that thought or, better still, "concept is infinite form, true creative activity, which requires no already present matter outside itself in order to realize itself." This is not to say, with regard to human thinking, that there is nothing out there; it is to say that, just as divine thought is creative of the conceptual structure of reality, so human thought is recreative of a conceptual structure which is antecedent to finite thinking. No. 164. The concept, then, is what is unconditionally (schlechthin) concrete, because the self-contained unity with itself which constitutes the intrinsic determinateness of singularity is precisely its relation to itself which constitutes universality. The "moments" of the conceptuniversality, particularity, and singularityeach of which is universal (see WL II, p. 246), constitute the dynamic structure of reality itself, which is real only as concrete totality. These "moments," then, cannot be separated from each other; theoretically each has validity independently of its contradictory, but
23. Karl Löwith, Von Hegel zu Nietzche, 2nd ed., (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1950), p. 39. Gustav Müller (Hegel: Denkgeschichte eines Lebendigen [Munich: Francke, 1959], p. 386) says much the same: "The concept of God is in and for itself the proof of God."
< previous page
page_85
next page >
< previous page
page_86
next page > Page 86
the concept embraces the contradictions in a unity (shorthand for "the validity of one conditions the validity of the other"), so that only in their complementarity does any of them make sense at all. Universality, particularity, and singularity are, in fact, abstract terms, but they express what we understand by identity, difference, and the real in which identity and difference are united; universality remains identical with itself only to the extent that it includes concretely the particularities which it subsumes. By the same token, the particular is meaningful only to the extent that it is an instantiation of the universal and includes the individual within the scope of its own signification. The singular, too, makes sense only as a "subject" in which the particular (species) and the universal (genus) are actualized. In other words, the concept of any reality whatever is intelligible only if the "moments" which make it up are inseparable; the "clarity" of any concept depends on the degree to which its diverse moments are seen to be embraced in its totalizing unity. All of which sounds unnecessarily complicated, not to say abstract. In two senses this is correct: What Hegel is talking about has neither the so-called concreteness of the sensible, which is not the sphere of thought, nor does it have the complete concreteness of the all-embracing "idea." In one sense the concept of which we are speaking is still merely a "form" of subjective thinking; and yet it has no other content than itselfit does not "receive" a content from outside itself; it is not simply a form imposed on an alien content. It is, nevertheless, the form whereby whatever its content is is determined to concreteness. What this implies is that the subject which gives determinateness to its own content is the very source of concreteness and, therefore, is itself preeminently concrete, and this, in Hegel's thinking, is to say that the subject is spirit, wherein the initial total abstractness of mere "being" is progressively concretized. Thus, the concept, even though a subjective activity and, hence, distinguished from its own objectivity, is, nevertheless, the source of its own objectivity, since it does what the so-called ''concrete" outthere cannot do, that is, unify the diversified manifold of the "given." There are, it is true, determinate abstract concepts, like "man," "house," and "animal," but because they are only universalneither particularized nor singularizedthey are undeveloped and do not have the concreteness of the authentic concept. The determinateness of the concrete concept is precisely the negation of the indeterminateness of the abstract. Judgment No. 165. If, then, any concept whatsoever remains only at this formal, subjective stage of undifferentiated universality it will not be concrete; only if the universal is said of the singular, and this it is only in "judgment," the
< previous page
page_86
next page >
< previous page
page_87
next page > Page 87
articulated concept, will the movement toward concreteness continue. It is in judgment that the "moments" of the conceptuniversality, particularity, and singularityare "posited" as meaningfully related to each other. To characterize concepts as "clear," "distinct" (Descartes), or ''adequate" (Spinoza), Hegel tells us in the note to this paragraph, is to engage in a "psychological" rather than a "logical" description of concepts. These terms refer to the manner in which the subject conceives. Dependence on "characteristics" such as these is, in fact, inimical to logic, since they refer to something the subject does in "subordinating" or "coordinating" concepts, not to what is proper to the concepts themselves. By the same token, to speak of "contrary or contradictory, affirmative or negative concepts" is to list characteristics which have their place in the sphere of "being" or of "essence," not in that of "concept," because they are not necessary to the very "concept of concept." Even to speak of "universal," "particular," or "singular" is not to designate "kinds" of concepts, whose distinction would be the result of a reflection "external" to the concepts themselves. Necessary distinctions must be "immanent" to the concepts, and these belong to "judgment," that is, the concept in the process of determining itself, which will not be complete until the grounds of its determinateness are manifest. No. 166. It is in the judgment that the "moments" of universality, particularity, and singularity are at once distinguished and uniteddistinction indicating the kind of unity, and unity designating the dialectical character of distinction. This, of course, runs contrary to the common view that the subject and the predicate of judgment are independent concepts linked by a thinking subject who says "is"as though the subject were a "thing" out-there and the predicate a universal determination "residing, so to speak, in my hand," which I then bring together in judging. According to this view, then, the determination which judging gives to the subject24 is subsequently taken to be a determination of the "object" (Gegenstand). Hegel's view, on the contrary, is illustrated by the etymology of the German word for judgment, Urteil, which he takes to be "original" (ur) "division" (Teilung), indicating that the concept divides itself in order to bring its "parts" (Teile) together in a more meaningful unity. Abstractly speaking the fundamental judgment can be expressed in the proposition, "The singular is the universal." It is not likely that anyone today would enunciate it that way, but we can see the point: the subject of the
24. It is unfortunate that, in both German and English, the term "subject" is ambiguous: it can mean either the subject who thinks (experiences) or the subject of which a predicate is said. It should be noted in addition that, in Hegel's use of the term, the two meanings come closer together: what is said of the subject is not simply said by another who is "subject" in the first sense; rather the "subject" in the second sense says the predicate of itselfmediately, of course, in the thinking subject.
< previous page
page_87
next page >
< previous page
page_88
next page > Page 88
proposition is designated as an individual of which a universal predicate is said.25 In this way the abstract propositions, "the particular is the universal" and "the singular is the particular" can also make sense, but they are further steps in the self-determination of the judgment and can be expressed in the initial form, which is simply Hegel's rendition of "the subject is the predicate." The terminology may vary, but the "identification" characteristic of judgment remains the same. What he is trying to say is that the linking spoken in the "is'' indicates that it is the "nature" of the concept to express itself as identical with itself, that is, in breaking itself up it remains itself. In any event, what is in question is more than a thinking subject attributing a predicate to a subject, thus joining two different concepts. There are no two concepts which are first not joined and then joined by someone; the concept is what it is in the joining, in the judgment, that is, the articulated concept. An indication of this can be found in the very "form" of the judgment, in the "is" of predication. When I say "the rose is red," I do not mean, "I attribute red to the rose," no matter what peculiar philosophical or psychological predispositions I may bring to the question. We might, however, say "the rose expresses itself as red in my consciousness of it," which is equivalent to saying that the rose, which is much else besides being red, particularizes itself in my consciousness as red. "The concept is that which inhabits things themselves, whereby they are what they are, and to conceive an object (Gegenstand) means, thus, to be conscious of its concept." If we pass from this to judging the object, it is not our subjective activity which attaches a predicate to the object, "rather we consider the object under the determination posited through its concept," which of course, it expresses in our conceiving (begreifen). This last sentence is fraught with consequences. It means, at the very least, that all the particular determinations which can be said of an object are already contained in the concept of that object; our thinking lets them emerge and, thus, lets the concept emerge in its fullness, and its emerging is a process whose "moments" are "universality," "particularity," and "singularity." No. 167. Although it is true to say that judgment is a mental operation that takes place only in self-conscious thinking, this observation is of no particular interest to logic. Rather, logic is concerned with the objective status of judgments; not what they tell us about the activity of thinking subjects but what they tell us about the real of which they are said (or of which they speak). In this sense judgment is a structure of the relationships resident in the world of reality. Things, for example, can be looked on as singulars whose inner nature is universal, or they can be seen as singularizations of the universal. In either case, they contain universality and singularity as at once distinct and identified; that is, the singular is destined to univer
25. The caution noted in n. 24 is again to be emphasized.
< previous page
page_88
next page >
< previous page
page_89
next page > Page 89
salize itself in thought, and the universal is destined to singularize itself in existence. Although, however, judgments find expression in propositions, not every proposition expresses a judgment in the logical sense, that is, as the unfolding of a concept. The statement of a single fact or event remains just that; it may involve the psychological operation called "judging," but it is not a judgment in any logically meaningful senseunless, of course, there is a question of doubt as to what is truly the case, and there is a logical process of seeking the correct predicate for a subject. To say, Hegel tells us, "a car is passing in the street" is not to express a logical judgment, unless there is a doubt that this is true, followed by a logical process of seeking to show that there are reasons for saying that it is truewhich, of course, involves universalizing. No. 168. Because, simply by itself, a judgment does not assert the grounds of its own affirmation, its point of view is that of "finitude"; the "things" it deals with are finite, and the context within which they are dealt with is finite. In them there is a union of the singular and the universal, else "thing" would be meaningless (cf. PdG, chap. II), but if the judgment does not develop beyond the stage of mere judgment it is an inadequate unfolding of the concept, whose moments of singularity and universality are still separate. As we shall see, this cannot be remedied short of the syllogism. No. 169. When the judgment is presented in its most abstract form, "the singular is the universal," the subject is presented as only itself, related to only itself, the so-called "concrete" as given. In this case, the predicate is the diametric opposite of the subject; it is universal, in the sense of abstractly indeterminate. The very presence of the copula "is," however, shows either that such a judgment is not in truth abstract, because the predicate has to contain the particular determinateness of the subject, or that it is not in truth a judgment, because it does not really say anything. Strictly speaking the subject has a determinate content only in its predicate; that is, without the predicate it is not a "thing" but only a ''name." For example, if we say "God is the most real of beings," the subject "God" without its predicate is not a reality but a name which has been given no meaning, and the predicate, "the most real of beings" is truly a predicate only if it has a determinate meaning. This we shall find to be very important: If a predicate, that is, of God, does not involve an advance in concreteness, it says nothing. To take this a step further, which Hegel does not do here, if I say "God is omniscient" without knowing what it means to say this of God, I am not saying anything. To say of a subject, then, that it is simply the singular, or of any predicate that it is simply universal, leaving out the mediation of one with the other through particularity, is to say nothing, to express no judgment, to express only an insignificant, not a significant relationship.
< previous page
page_89
next page >
< previous page
page_90
next page > Page 90
No. 170. It must be said, then, that the logical relationship of subject and predicate in judgment is such that they are mutually determining: determining, hence distinct; mutually, hence identified in the unity of one concept. The subject is the self-identical foundation, by inhering in which the predicate has its ideal consistency and, in relation to the subject, is only one of the latter's many determinations and demands to be complemented by others. On the other hand, the predicate by itself is in its universality indifferent to this subject, which is only one of many of which it can be said (its determinate intelligibility). But a "determinate" content of the predicate effects the identification of subject and predicate. No. 171. Initially, then, subject, predicate, and determinate content are "posited" in judgment as related to each other and, therefore, as different from each other; relation presupposes difference. As contained in one and the same concept, however, the different are identified: the subject as "concrete totality" is not some undifferentiated manifold, it is this one, embracing both particular and universal in a unity which is the predicate. It is the copula, of course, which posits the identity of subject and predicate, initially again only as an abstract "is," to be concretized (filled) in the syllogism which justifies ("grounds") the linking. The syllogism, then, validates the ''is" of the judgment by moving from what is at first only the generality said of the sensible through "allness," "genus," and "species" to the fully developed "universality of concept," which contains the rationale of the whole movement. Still, simply to enumerate "kinds" of judgment on the basis of these distinctions is superficial; what needs to be shown is that the "kinds" of judgment follow necessarily from each other as the progressive determination of the concept. Thus judgment is "determinate concept." If we look back at the spheres of "being" and "essence," we can see these spheres reproduced as conceptual relations in the framework of judgment determining concepts. Zusatz: Some judgments, then, are logically on a higher plane than others, according to the manner in which they are rooted in their concept. In this sense the judgment, "the wind is blowing," which is little more than the mental record of an observation, is scarcely a significant judgment, whereas a well-thought-out moral or aesthetic judgment, demanding to be firmly rooted in the profound concepts of "good" or "beautiful," are on a much higher plane. We might add, which Hegel does not do here, that a judgment such as "the wind that is blowing is beneficial to the health of the inhabitants," would be on an intermediate logical plane, and "planes" could be multiplied. In our present context it is doubtful whether it would repay the effort to follow in detail all that Hegel has to say about the kinds of judgment in which the unity of concept is articulated. This does not mean that what he has to say in this connection is unimportant both for an understanding of
< previous page
page_90
next page >
< previous page
page_91
next page > Page 91
Hegel's thought and for the light it throws on the structure of conceptual thinking in its relation to the structure of reality. In view of the limitations of space, however, its importance can be summed up in the realization that Hegel is spelling out the close interrelationships of conceptual determinations, the rational character of reality, be it "natural" or "spiritual," as the self-manifestation of transcendent thought, and the rationality of human thinking as the locus of reality's self-revealing rationality. It is important to be aware (1) that the "qualitative judgment," which simply states that a predicate is to be said of a subject, demands to be filled out in the "judgment of reflection," which focuses on the character of the interrelatedness of universality, particularity, and singularity in one subject (such that what is said of the subject is said because of what the subject is essentially); (2) that the judgment of reflection, in turn, will be fruitful, only if there are ''judgments of necessity" which reveal a necessary relationship of the "moments" of concept (where what the predicate says of the subject, the subject necessarily says of itself); and (3) that, finally, the "judgment of concept" reveals that "necessity" itself is meaningful only if rooted in the concept, the ground for whatever is said, ultimately in the all-unifying Concept whose objective counterpart is "absolute Idea." The entire discussion of judgments, however, finds its culmination in the rational grounding of judgments which is the syllogism. It is to the syllogism that we must turn, if we are to discover the "Why" of whatever can be said of reality, a "Why" which makes sense, only if thought is the ultimate foundation of reality itself. Syllogism No. 181. In Science of Logic (II, p. 308) Hegel had defined the syllogism as "the concept posited in its completeness, the rational." It makes the complete transition, in "reason" rather than in mere abstract "understanding," from the subjectivity of the mental act of judging to the objectivity of truth in the fullest sense, whose rationality transcends that of any subjective rational activity. The framework in which the syllogism is operative is not that of the isolated judgment, which as such does not go beyond "opinion," not even that of the effort on the part of the thinking subject to relate one isolated judgment to another. Rather, its framework is that of an integrated totality of judgments, ultimately the integrated totality of all thought and all reality, whose "objectivity" resides in its fullness. As Hegel puts it in the text we are considering here, "the syllogism is the rational, and it is the whole (alles) of the rational." This is a far cry from the conviction that syllogism is a rational "form" of thinking applied to a content with a view of "proving" it, which, if its content is not true is not rational at all. As Hegel sees it, the function of syllogism is to plumb the rationality of
< previous page
page_91
next page >
< previous page
page_92
next page > Page 92
the content itself. It is still true, of course, that only if the thinking in question is rational will it perform its task. Rational thinking, then, "is none other than the (at first formally) posited real (reale) concept"the uncovering of the rationality of the real, not the imposition of rationality on the real. Syllogism, then, is "the essential ground of whatever is true." It is what we mean when we say "absolute,'' that is, that whatever really is is a syllogism. "All is concept," and "its expression (Dasein) is the distinction of its moments." Thus, the concept as universal particularizes itself in external reality, which, in turn, exists in singulars. Conversely, one can say, "what is actual is an individual (Eizelnes) which, through its multiplication in particulars, rises to universality and thus realizes its identity with itself," and the syllogism is the circular movement involved herethe universal emerging out of itself to rejoin itself, or the singular breaking itself up in order to reunite itself. This is the unfolding of the truth of boththe transition from subjectivity to objectivity. No. 182. The "syllogism of understanding," as Hegel calls it, is familiar enough to usand to all who have played logic games. A proposition, composed of subject and predicate, is to be proved true. The "understanding," standing-off, so to speak, sets to work constructing a syllogism which will prove it. It becomes a question of justifying what we say rather than of enabling a reality to tell us what is true of it. This, of course, the reality cannot do, unless it is in some sense a "subject""telling" is an activity which "subjects" perform. If, however, we are to comprehend what it can mean to say that an "object" is a "subject," we may have to take time out here and reread Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit. Hegel is not about to deny, incidentally, that "syllogizing" is something we do when we think rationally. What he does say, however, is that if that is all "syllogizing" is, it is the work of abstract "understanding" only, not the work of concrete "reason." What is more, if the reality we are dealing with is the manifold of "finite things," understanding is the best we can do; we can classify and then draw conclusions on the basis of our classifications. Zusatz: At this point in an addition, presumably reporting Hegel's oral presentation, we find a remark which will be of utmost importance for our subsequent considerations. In terms of a "faculty" psychology, reason has been called the "faculty of syllogizing" and understanding, the "faculty of forming concepts." Apart from the superficiality of looking upon the mind as a composite of "faculties," we are told there is a serious danger that the concept will be looked upon as proper only to understanding, and any and every correct syllogism will be viewed as rational. Not only is it untrue that the concept is merely a form of understanding, but it is abstract understanding itself which has thus degraded what is the truly rational form. What mere formal logic calls syllogism is no more than a syllogism of understanding and in no way deserves to be called the rational form of thinking. It is on the basis of this
< previous page
page_92
next page >
< previous page
page_93
next page > Page 93
understanding that a distinction is made between concepts of understanding and concepts of reason, as though there were two kinds of concepts or, worse still, as though the distinction simply touches what we do when we think. The result is, for example, that the concept of "freedom" is looked upon as simply the abstract contradictory of "necessity," whereas the truly "rational" concept of freedom contains in itself superseded necessity. Freedom without necessity is unintelligible, not merely in the sense that opposites throw light on each other, but in the more profound sense that truly rational freedom and truly rational necessity do not contradict each other: they are dialectically identified, one necessarily implying the other; to be genuinely free is to be rationally necessitated. By the same token, the definition which ''Deism" gives of God as a simply self-identified supreme Being is no more than a concept of understanding, whereas "the Christian religion, which knows God as triune, contains the rational concept of God." In detailing the kinds of syllogisms the mind "employs" in its thinking and in evaluating their "rational" standing Hegel characterizes them along the lines we have already seen in his treatment of the judgment. He enumerates, however, only three basic kinds, the "qualitative syllogism" (nos. 18389), the "syllogism of reflection" (no. 190), and the "syllogism of necessity" (nos. 19193). There is no syllogism of the concept, however, since the very "necessity" of the "syllogism of necessity" is its grounding in the concept which it makes explicit. Although Hegel devotes seven paragraphs to the "qualitative syllogism," it is of little interest to us here, because it is significant only for a purely formal logic, confining itself to a description of the correct ways in which subjective thinking can proceed from premises to conclusions. Because this syllogism describes only operations of understanding, because the realities to which it directs its attention are only finite realities, and because the relationships expressed in it are only "contingent," not "necessary," it is not, properly speaking a "rational" syllogism at all; so long as the process is merely what mind goes through, error is possible because mind can prove anything. The "syllogism of reflection" is, it is true, significant, because its force lies in what the mind finds to be "essential" in what it thinks. Because, however, Hegel sees its contribution primarily as an introduction to the truly rational "syllogism of necessity," he devotes little space to it (one paragraph). In the "syllogism of necessity," on the other hand, the whole force of logical thinking and of concrete rationality is concentrated. It is only here, in fact, that we can begin to see what Hegel means by "the rational is actual": what reason sees as being necessarily so is necessarily so. The emphasis here, then, will be on this last section (three paragraphs, but covering as many pages as the first section). No. 190. What characterizes the "syllogism of reflection" is that it focuses on the "essence" of the subject in question and derives the
< previous page
page_93
next page >
< previous page
page_94
next page > Page 94
predicate from it. The "determination" said in the predicate is seen to follow from the "essence" of the subject; all subjects of this kind have among other predicates the predicate in question. There is a problem, however: "allness" is true of the subject of the major premiss, only if in fact the predicate is true of the subject of the conclusion. We say, for example, ''all men are mortal; but, Caius is a man; therefore, Caius is mortal." This seems to follow, but the truth of the "all" of the major depends on the truth of the conclusion; if, in fact, Caius is not mortal, the major is not true. The truth, then, of the major depends on a complete induction based on counting all the cases that could come under the major. This, quite obviously, could not be done empirically; there simply is no such thing as counting empirically all possible cases. When we employ such a syllogism, we in fact argue from "analogy," which may provide a good rule-of-thumb, but it does not make the conclusion "necessarily" true. If it is the "essence" of man to be mortal, the conclusion follows, but how does reflective thinking decide what determinations are "essential"? Certainly not empirically. No. 191. If, however, the "concept" of "man" is available to thought, there is a way out. Where, in fact, the "concept" is available, not as the result of a merely subjective procedure of induction, the inclusive "all" is no longer required. This "way out," however, makes sense only if the "concept" is antecedent to the empirical reality; subjective thinking can derive the concept from empirical reality only by deciding what is to count as the concept. There is question, then, of determining what kind of syllogism will so thematize the concept that what are necessary determinations will reveal themselves as necessary. "Necessity" in this context does not mean the psychological necessity that the subject think this way, but the logical necessity that the subject's judgment be true (WL II, p. 345). We are looking for a "middle" in the syllogism which clearly indicates that the determination in question does in fact pertain to all the particulars subsumable under the universal, which is what it will do if the middle is either the "genus" or the "species" to which the "singular" belongs. This is what is assumed in the "categorical syllogism," which states that what is true of something because it is the sort of thing it is is true of whatever is this sort of thing (WL II, p. 346). In the "hypothetical syllogism," on the other hand, the singular is taken as given, and what is said of it is said because some other determination is the "reason" for it; if the subject is the one, it is also the other; thus the connection of one and the other is affirmed. The reason for one is in the other, and the "absolute content" of both is the same (WL II, pp. 34748). Finally, in the "disjunctive syllogism" the universality of the middle is broken up into all its possible particularities, such that the singular must be of some one of them, leading thus to a process of elimination; if all the possibilities are present, the concept is complete. The issue
< previous page
page_94
next page >
< previous page
page_95
next page > Page 95
now is that of seeing which of these forms best suits the totality of concept. To put the question in a somewhat different way: How does reality present itselfmake itself presentin thought? There is no answer to this question if all reality does is present itself empirically. Nor will there be an answer, if reality is not, prior to finite subjective thinking, already thought-realityand this is the heart of Hegel's logic, of his contribution to philosophical thinking. No. 192. Although Hegel speaks in general of "the syllogism," his treatment of it, quite obviously, is based on "different kinds" of syllogism contained in the one concept, "syllogism." What he sees as the overall result of this procedure is that the differences cancel themselves out, insofar as they are considered external to their unifying concept. It is no more essential to the syllogism that it be broken up into three propositions than it is to the concept to be broken up into "moments.'' The "because" which answers each significant "why" is but a particularization of the "syllogism," just as each "moment" of the concept presents itself as the "totality of moments," that is, as a whole syllogism, in which the "moments" are identified. Different syllogisms, then, are different ways in which one and the same concept makes itself present in thought. Thus, the negation of the differences and of the form of mediation peculiar to each constitutes the "self-identity" (Fürsichsein) of concept-syllogism. What has happened is that in the "ideality" of its moments, "syllogizing" takes on the "character" (Bestimmung) of essentially containing the "negation" of those "determinations" which make it merely a "procedure." Syllogizing, then, becomes a mediation which transcends mediation, thus joining the subject not with its "other," but with a "transcended other, that is, with itself." The predicate is not other than the subject, it is the self-othering of the subject; and the "joining-together" (Zusammenschliessennote the play on schliessen) is in fact not a "joining-together" performed by a mind external to the concept; the concept concretizes itself. "The various kinds of syllogism present the stages of fulfillment or concretion of the middle" (WL II, p. 351), and this is a progress in thought toward the totalization of reality. Zusatz: What has just been said runs counter to the common opinion that the treatment of the syllogism question closes the first part of logic, the so-called "doctrine of elements" (theoretical logic). Following this there is a second part, called "doctrine of method" (applied logic), in which by applying the forms of thinking treated in the first part to given objects we constitute an entire science. This sort of logic of understanding "tells us nothing of the origin of such objects nor of what the very thought of objectivity implies." What we are supposed to have before us is a thinking which is no more than a subjective and "formal" activity, over-against which the "objective" is fixed as simply "there." There is no evidence for this kind of dualism, nor does it make sense simply to accept the notions of subjectivity
< previous page
page_95
next page >
< previous page
page_96
next page > Page 96
and objectivity, as though there were no need to ask where the notions originate. In any case, both subjectivity and objectivity are "thoughts," determinate thoughts, whose grounding in universal, self-determining thought has to be brought out, not simply taken for granted. This is what Hegel has been trying to do with regard to subjectivity, by showing that subjectivity, or "the subjective concept," containing as it does "the concept as such," "the judgment," and "the syllogism,'' is the dialectical result of "both first main stages of the logical idea" in its self-developing process, that is, the stages of "being" and "essence." There is no problem, then, in admitting that the conceptas well as judgment and syllogismis, quite simply, "subjective." The same is true of the so-called "laws of thought" which logic studies. But that is not the point; the move from subjectivity to objectivity is. Mental activity, Hegel insists, is not an empty framework which needs to receive a content from a world of objects waiting for it "out-there"; rather, it is subjectivity itself which, because it is dialectical, breaks through its own limitations and by means of the syllogism moves to objectivity. What the mind necessarily thinks to be objectively true, with a necessity contained in the very rationality of syllogistic reasoning, is objectively true. Nor, as we shall see, is it merely the formallogical correctness of the thinking procedure which guarantees this objective truth. No. 193. What, then, is the "object" of thought? Is it a "thing"? But there are neither "objects" nor "things," except through the mediation of thought. Thus, in Hegel's view, "object" is the "realization" (in the etymological sense of "making real") of the concept. Here it is that the "universal" is "one self-contained totality," whose diverse instantiations are each also the totalityeach expresses the whole. Thought has the capacity to transcend its own "middle position" (Vermittlung) between subject and object in the only sense of Vermittlung that makes sense.26 From Subjectivity to Objectivity It can obviously seem strange, especially if one is accustomed to consider only the "syllogism of understanding" or to look upon "syllogistic reasoning" as nothing but the activity of consciousness, to speak of a "transition" from concept in generalmore precisely from the syllogismto the "object" (Kant's "leap" from concept to reality). But there is no question here of making such a transition "plausible" in the sphere of (representation"it simply cannot be "represented" at all; it must "take place." We might, of course, try to recall what our customary "representation" of what is called "object" is and see whether it approximates what in our present context constitutes the determining (Bestimmung) of "object."
26. Once again, recall the caution noted in n. 24.
< previous page
page_96
next page >
< previous page
page_97
next page > Page 97
It is not customary, however, to mean by "object" simply either what "is" or "exists" in abstraction or what is in general ''actual." Rather, we think of something "concrete," something completely independenton its ownand this completeness is the "totality proper to concept." There is no denying that an "object" (Objekt) is characterized as "what-stands-over against" (Gegenstand) and is external to "another," thus "positing" (setzt) an "opposition" (Gegensatz) between "objective" and "subjective." We do tend to think that way, and when we do, we tend to see the concept, which has left behind its "mediating" role, as a "pure-and-simple" (unbefangenes) "immediate" object (Objekt). By the same token, we tend to characterize the concept in the resulting "opposition" as "the subjective." What we fail to see is that we have characterized the concept as both objective and subjective. From another point of view we can look at "the object in general" as the "one even more indeterminate whole," call it the world, call it God, call it "the absolute object." Even in this sense, however, the object has its differentiations and falls apart into an "indeterminate manifold," precisely as objective world," in such a way that differentiation means many "distinct" objects, each existing as "concrete" " complete," "independent." Both unity and distinction would seem to be contingent. If, then, we are to comprehend the transition from subjectivity to objectivity precisely as "transition" and not "leap," we have to backtrack a bit. Earlier, in what he had called "objective logic," Hegel spoke of "being" (the most purely abstract object of thought), "existence" (abstract being manifesting its progressive determinateness in thought), and "actuality" (being as manifested in "reality"). "Objectivity" must now be seen as containing similar "moments." More than that, however, the transition from subjectivity to objectivity must be examined in the light of the transition of abstract being to existence and actuality. He had also spoken before of "essence" as the "ground " for the emergence of "existence," and this essence is a "relationship mediated by reflection which explains the transition to "actuality." What we can now see is that the "moments" of which he spoke earlier were simply "the as yet inadequately posited concept," that is, abstract aspects of the concept. Thus, "ground" is merely the concept's "essential unity," and the "relationship" is merely the "connecting" (operated in thought) of aspects which are "supposed to be" real and to have reference only to themselves. The concept in its fullness, on the other hand, is the (concrete) unity of "ground" and "relationship," in such a way that the "object" in question is not merely the "essential" unity (i.e., of reflection) but an "all-embracing" (allgemeine) unity which contains in itself distinctions which are not only "real" but also in themselves wholes" (Totalitäten); they are constituted as what they are by the overarching totality which embraces them.
< previous page
page_97
next page >
< previous page
page_98
next page > Page 98
What must be made clear here is that the "transitions" Hegel speaks of are not to be conceived of along the lines of the inseparability of thinking and being. It is obvious enough, and the point need not be belabored, that to think at all is to think beingof whatever thinking thinks is can be said, but to say this is to say very little; merely as what is contained in the subjective concept it says nothing. The "being" which thinking inevitably thinks is the utterly indeterminate, abstract being with which Hegel's logic starts, and whose ever-fuller self-determining is its process of conceptualization.27 What needs to be done is to take the concept in all its concrete determinateness, precisely as concept, and to see whether, in truth, what the concept affirms constitutes a passage to a "form'' which in reality is different from "the determination which belongs to and appears in the concept." The "belongs to" and "appears in" are important. It simply is not a question of subjective thinking attributing to reality subjective thinking's own abstract content; the real manifests itself in and through the concept. Gone is the presupposition that "conceptual determination" and "real determination" are simply different. In what sense they can be said to be the same remains to be seen. If we follow Aristotle, as we know Hegel claimed to do, we must say not only that human rational thinking can culminate in objective knowing, that is, in a true grasp of reality, but also that, in knowing, the subject knowing "somehow" becomes the object known. As Hegel sees it, then, the "somehow" must at the very least mean that when the object as product of the transition from subjectivity is put in connection with the concept which in the process has lost its peculiarly subjective form, the "result" can correctly be expressed in this way: In their innermost reality (an sich) concept, or subjectivity, and object are the same. What Aristotle, however, does not say in so many words and what Hegel explicitly says is that they just as truly remain diverse. But precisely because both statements, that is, that concept and object are the same and that they are different, are correct so are both incorrect; this manner of speaking is simply incapable of expressing their true relationship to each other. The "in its innermost reality" is an abstract expression, even more "one-sided" than the concept itself, whose onesidedness is transcendedbecause the concept is transcended in its becoming object, its onesided opposite member. Only in their "mediated"28
27. Hegel here refers in passing to those false interpretations of the "ontological proof" for the being of God, according to which the "being" said of God would have no more content than the mere abstract concept of being. 28. It is important to note here the function of "middle" (Mitte) in the real as opposed to the merely mental syllogism. It is not the "middle term" of purely formal-logical entailment. Rather it is that which mediates a process whose extremes are contradictories, whose relation to each other consists in the different relation of each to the middle, which reconciles their opposition to each other. Thus, the mutual exclusivity of the contradictories is resolved in a continuity mediated by the "middle."
< previous page
page_98
next page >
< previous page
page_99
next page > Page 99
relationship to each other is that difference transcended. The object that the subject knows in conceiving is concept, that is, concept is both the conceiving and the conceived. So too the "in its innermost reality" by negating its own indeterminacy determines itself to "independent being" (Fürsichsein). This is but another way of saying that "speculative identity" is more than the trivial identity of concept and object "in their innermost reality''an identity which says little because of its abstractness; little more than that if there is to be knowledge there must be identity, which is about the equivalent of Aristotle's rather uninformative "somehow." It is not, however, trivial to speak of the identity of knowing (thought) and reality, if that can be fleshed out. It is only at this point that we begin to realize that all along Hegel has been building up to the model for the "concrete" identity of concept and reality, "absolute Idea" "absolute Spirit," "God." It is this unity, taken in its "utmost generality" (ganz überhaupt) and leaving out the "onesided form" of its "abstract being" (Ansichsein), which is presupposed in Saint Anselm's "ontological proof of God's reality (Dasein). " God's reality is the "most perfect" reality.29 As Hegel reads Anselm, the question is initially simply whether a content of thought is only a content of "our thinking." But, just to put the question this way is for Hegel to give a hint of what his answer will be: No content is true if all it is is the content of "our thinking." It is for this reason that "finite things" are not "true," in his sense of true, precisely because their "objectivity" does not correspond with the thinking thereof, that is, with the universality proper to the "genus" to which they belong or to the "purpose" to which they are ordered. Although, in Hegel's view, Descartes, Spinoza, and others, had expressed this unity "more objectively," the "immediate certitude" of belief which is, in fact, the starting point of this kind of argumentation, sees the unity in a subjective manner more reminiscent of Anselm. This is to say that "in our consciousness" the determination "God's being" is inseparably connected with the "representation" of God. It is not incorrect, of course, to say that "belief" sees in the representations of finite things the inseparability of the "consciousness" of them and their "being," because to "intuit" them is to attach to them the character of "existence" (Existenz). But, Hegel continues, it would be nonsensical to think that even in our consciousness "existence" is connected with the representation of finite things in the same way as it is with the representation of God.30 To make the connection the same would be to
29. Although the term Dasein is in this context frequently translated as "existence," it seems preferable to say "reality," since in Hegelian terms it would make absolutely no sense to speak of "most perfect" Existenz; the latter is essentially finite manifestation. 30. It might seem to contradict the preceding note that Hegel employs the term Existenz here in relation to God. It should be noted, however, both that this occurs very rarely and that here it is not a question of God's "reality" but of the note of "existence" attaching to the "representation" of God.
< previous page
page_99
next page >
< previous page
page_100
next page > Page 100
forget that finite things are "mutable" and "transient," that is that "existence" belongs to them only transitorily, that the connection is not "eternal" but "separable.'' Anselm, then, was right when he rejected the sort of connection that suffices for finite things and declared that alone to be "perfect" which "is," not only subjectively, but at the same time objectively. To look down on the so-called "ontological proof" and on Anselm's characterization of "the perfect" will get one nowhere. The latter is present in all "uncorrupted," "common sense" representations of God, and it is present in every philosophical concept as well. Whether philosophers like it or not, it crops up again, as it does even when the principle in question is that of "immediate belief," which is adequate as belief only if it represents its object as "most perfect." Philosophers have never eliminated belief, they merely substitute one belief for another, and Hegel prefers Anselm's kind of belief; he finds it a lot closer to what reason tells him must be so. That Hegel thought Anselm's starting point the right one does not mean that Hegel found Anselm's argument (or method of argumentation) faultless. The fault that he finds in Anselm, and which he also finds in Descartes, in Spinoza, and in the "principle of immediate cognition,"31 is that what they speak of as the "most perfect," or, from the subjective point of view, as the object of "true knowing" is simply "presupposed," that is, assumed as only "in itself." What happens, then, as can be seen in the case of Anselm, is that the distinction of concept and reality is immediately opposed to their merely abstract identification. The fact that the representation and the existence of the finite are distinct is put forward as an argument against their identification in the infinite. Quite obviously the argument does not hold water, because, as Hegel had remarked earlier, the finite is the sort of objectivity which does not correspond completely with its purpose, its essence, its concept; that is, the subjective representation of the finite is such that it does not involve existence. The contradiction on which this objection is based can be resolved only by pointing out that the finite is untrue, that the determinations of "mental" and "real" existence as "independent" (für sich) are nullified as onesided, and that their identity is, thus, one in which their movement of transition culminates and in which they are reconciled in the infinite. That thought and being cannot be identified in a finite object is no argument that they are not identified in the infinite object. All of which means that the time has come to discuss just what "object" means.
31. The term Hegel employs here is Wissen, but it does not have the strong sense it has elsewhere, only a rather generic sense.
< previous page
page_100
next page >
< previous page
page_101
next page > Page 101
The Meaning of "Objectivity" In the German language there are two terms, Gegenstand and Objekt, which are normally translated by the English term, "object."32 In German, however, although the term Gegenstand is intended to translate the Latin objectum, the etymological thrust of each of the two terms is quite different. Gegen-stand is a purely German term designating that which "stands-over-against" a conscious subject antecedently to the consciousness had of it. Objekt, on the other hand, is a transliteration of the Latin ob-jectum designating that which is "thrown-out-from" the subject. In Hegel's language Objekt has, in addition, the connotation of purpose, much as it has in a familiar usage of the term in English, as in the Mikado's "My object all sublime, I will achieve in time." We can recall what Hegel has to say about "speculative terms'' which have more than one meaning in such a way that when the "speculative thinker" employs the term he does not choose which meaning he intends but rather intends all meanings at once.33 No. 194. "Object" (Objekt), then, designates the "being" of what the mind thinks without regard to the "differences" of the many which the mind embraces in thinking them as one "object." "Difference" has been aufgehoben in the object, and the object is a self-contained "totality." At the same time, however, because the "identification" achieved in the object is only abstract (ansichseiende) identity of "moments," the object is equally indifferent to its "immediate" unity; it is broken up into a differentiated multiplicity, wherein each of the different (objects) is itself the totality. The "object" then is the "absolute contradiction" involving the complete independence of the manifold and the equally complete dependence of the differentiated. Sinuous language indeed, but it simply signifies that the object of thought at once "cancels out" and "retains" the differences of the manifold it embraces. That it also "lifts up" manyness to a higher form of unity we shall also see. In this context Hegel finds that he can say, "The absolute is the object," a definition which most aptly characterizes the "Leibnizian monad" which is at once an object and as such also "represents"; that is, it is supposed to be a "totality" representing the totality of the world. In the simple unity of this monad, whatever differences there may be are "ideal" and "depend-
32. To translate Gegenstand as "general object" and Objekt simply by "object" serves no useful purpose. 33. The parade example of the speculative term for Hegel is aufheben, which means "cancel out," "retain," and "lift up," and which are all meanings Hegel intends when he employs the term. Another example is vorstellen which means "represent" in the sense of "render mentally present," "stand in place of," and "introduce." Quite obviously such terms offer peculiar difficulties to the translator.
< previous page
page_101
next page >
< previous page
page_102
next page > Page 102
ent. " Since the monad has no windows, nothing comes into it from outside, and it is, thus, within itself (in sich) the whole concept, differentiated only according to greater or lesser self-development; not every monad reflects the totality with the same adequacy. By the same token the simple totality of the monad breaks up into an absolute multiplicity of differences, such that each is an independent monad. Each is a "substance," and all are united in the "monad of monads" and in the "preestablished harmony'' of the internal development of each, such that each "substance" is likewise again reduced to the dependence of ideality. Leibniz's philosophy, then, is the completely developed "contradiction," of identity and differenceor of the identity of identity and difference; identity which constitutes difference, and vice versa. Zusatz 1: If the "Absolute (God)" is seen as object and only object, that is, 'out there," over-against, then Fichte was right in characterizing this as the root of superstition and slavish fear. Of course God is "object," but only in the fullest possible sense of that term. God is object in the sense that, apart from God as object, our own subjective opinion has no truth, and our subjective willing has no validity. If we claim to think but do not think God, we do not think truly; if we will and do not will God, we do not will what is right. But, precisely as absolute Object, God does not "stand" as an obscure and alien power "over-against" our subjectivity. Rather, God as "subject" (Spirit) contains finite subjectivity within himself as an essential moment; human subjectivity is an expression of the divine Subject (the perfect subject-object). We find this stated clearly in Christian doctrine, according to which God wills that all men be helped (to be what they are destined to be) and that all men achieve blessedness. This is accomplished in that human beings come to the consciousness of their union with God and, thus, God ceases to be for them mere "object" (Objekt)34 and, by that very fact, ceases to be an "object" (Gegenstand) of "fear and trembling" as he was for the religious consciousness of the Romans. If we go further into Christian religion to the consciousness that God is love, to such a degree that his Son, who is at once an individual man and one with God, has revealed himself to men and thus redeemed them, we can also see in this that the opposition between objectivity and subjectivity has been overcome "in itself" (it has yet to be overcome in us). It is now our task to share in this redemption by putting off our own immediate subjectivity ("to put off the old Adam") and thus become conscious of God as "our true and essential self." What emerges from this is the realization that just as religion itself (including cult) consists in overcoming the opposition between subjectivity
34. It is not too clear why Hegel uses the term Objekt in this context. If, however, the term is employed in only one of its meanings, i.e., projected by a subject, as the adjective "mere" (blosses) would seem to indicate, then it is no better than a Gegenstand.
< previous page
page_102
next page >
< previous page
page_103
next page > Page 103
and objectivity, so too science, particularly philosophical science, has as its task overcoming the same opposition in the realm of thought. The whole question of knowledge is that of getting rid of the alien character of the world which "stands" objectively "over-against" us and, thus, to find ourselves in this world, which is another way of saying that our task is to find what is objective in conceptualization itself, which is our innermost self. This means that we must overcome the tendency to look upon subjectivity and objectivity as in fixed opposition to each other. They are both in the most fundamental sense "dialectical." Granted that ''concept" is initially a subjective designation, that is, our thinking, it moves, nevertheless, in the direction of objectifying itself, without the need of some "external material," with the result that its object is not something static but is its own process, both objective and subjective, culminating in the objective "idea." We can put it this way: By "objective" we mean that which is the way it is independently of the intervention of some individual subject. In this sense the subjective is not automatically objective; what is required is the Aufhebung of subjective intervention such that objective interrelatedness is seen to be intrinsic to reality itself (WL II, pp. 35859). If one is, of course, not conversant with the determinations "subjectivity" and "objectivity," which will mean clinging to them as "abstractions," one will find that such abstract determinations will be lost before being fully grasped, with the result that one "says" precisely the opposite of what was intended. There is nothing more confusing to thought than the confusion of what is subjective and what is objective about it; and the worst confusion of all is to look upon it as nothing more than the activity of a finite thinker. It is true, of course, that "objective" has meaning only in relation to "subjectivity," but the merely subjective of finite individual subjectivity must be canceled" in its "onesidedness," "retained" in its essential relation to the objective, and "lifted up" in its fusion with "absolute subjectivity." Zusatz 2: What Hegel will seek after this is a "model" in the reality which "science" investigates of a process which at one and the same time identifies diversity and diversifies identity. What he seeks is a principle intrinsic to reality which unifies it in such a way that the unification of being in thought will not be a process different from its unification in reality. The two sciences of his day which were taking giant strides in this direction were mechanics (Newtonian) and chemistry; one seeing all physical activity as the working out of physical "laws," the other seeing the chemical affinity of "substances" as somehow explicating the complex relationships of real multiplicity and ideal unity, whether as the unification of diversity or the diversification of unity. Philosophically speaking, however, Hegel sees the "teleological" relationship, the working out in reality of purposes contained in the world of "idea" and embodied in the world of "reality" as the keystone for a genuinely intelligible relationship of thought and reality. One
< previous page
page_103
next page >
< previous page
page_104
next page > Page 104
is forcibly reminded of Socrates' contention in Plato's Phaedo that one does not "know" even something so simple as a "wagon," if all one knows is what it is composed of and the mechanical relations of this composition, if one does not know "what it is for." By the same token, for Hegel, knowing the mechanical relations of "causality" or the chemical relations of "affinity'' is to know very little of the world of reality; mechanical laws tell us only of external relations of "acting on" or "being acted upon," while chemical laws speak only of the instrinsic affinity of "elements" for each other; and both are deterministic in their operation. The real key to the identification of thought and reality is the concept of "purpose," without which thought is mere emptiness and reality is mere chaos. Nos. 195203. It is not really important for us to go into what Hegel has to say about "mechanics" and "chemistry." It is no more, or less, naive than what the scientists of his day were saying. The point is, however, not so much the "scientific" significance of what he says as the conviction that neither provides the model for a philosophy which would be "scientific" in its grasp of the unity and diversity of the real world in which finite thinking subjects liveand to this only the concretely totalized concept is adequate. The question, then, of a "model" of this process of totalization (Zusammenschliessen) becomes important, nor is it farfetched to say that some, in their quest for a "unified science," would by preference look for a "mechanical" or "chemical" model to explain the world of "spirit"! The Dynamism of Purpose We have to remember, then, that what Hegel is looking for in his discussion of "objectivity" is not a thoughtprocess which "from outside," so to speak, puts the diverse moments of reality together, but rather a thought which recaptures reality's own process of putting-itself-togetherin thought, to be sure. It is a self-putting-together which makes sense only if the "totalizing" (Zusammen-schliessende) concept is not merely the product of subjective (finite) thinking. It is for this reason that Hegel now turns to the concept of intrinsic "purpose," which, of course, is significant only if reality is in some sense a "living" whole. There is nothing uncommon, we might say, in the question as to whether life has a "meaning," but we have to be clear that, in asking this question, we are equivalently asking, "does life have a purpose?"35 To ask that same question with regard to the totality of reality, obviously, will have far-reaching consequences, but there is no a priori reason to say that the question is nonsensical. In any event, only if we do ask the question shall we ever get to the heart of Hegel's philosophizing,
35. It is not without significance that the German word Sinn, which can be translated as "sense" (hence "meaning") also (like the French sens) has the connotation of "direction" or "orientation." As usual, Hegel intends all the "senses" of the term.
< previous page
page_104
next page >
< previous page
page_105
next page > Page 105
which sees the world of both nature and spirit as the finite expression of infinite (divine) life, or purpose. In tracing the movement from the subjectivity of conceptual thinking to the objectivity of "the concept," then, the notion of "purpose" is of utmost importance. Purpose is, Hegel goes on to tell us, the "self-contained" (für-sichseiende) concept, which "has moved into self-determining (freie) existence," by negating its "immediate''that is, in subjective thinking alone"objectivity." This initial determination is, it is true, subjective because the "negation" in question is "abstract," which means that subjective thinking in operating the negation initially merely "stands-overagainst" (gegenübersteht) objectivity. In relation to the totality of the concept, however, this character of subjectivity is "one-sided," that is, contained only in the subject's own limited conceiving, since in this conceiving all determination has simply been "posited" as superseded. Thus, in this framework the presupposed object is only "an ideal (ideelle) reality, in itself unreal (nichtige)." The contradiction between the concept's self-identity and its opposing negation is resolved only by the "activity" of negating the opposition which it "posits" as identical with itself. If, however, the notion of "purpose" is included in that of "object"and purpose is integral to the "speculative" meaning of the termthen the "activity" of negatizing identification is the "realizing of the purpose," such that the concept "makes itself" the other of its subjectivity and thus objectifies itself, transcending the subject-object dichotomy, uniting "itself with itself" and maintaining this union. To see in objective reality, then, a "teleological" principle is, with Aristotle, to see objectivity as a rational striving toward the realization of a purpose. For Hegel, however, unlike Aristotle, this makes sense only in a framework of "total" reality. To today's readers language such as this can well seem hopelessly complex; its aim, however, was to bridge the gap between human subjectivity and objective reality bequeathed to philosophy by Kant. If knowledge is to be knowledge of what "really is" not merely of its "appearing" to consciousness, the correspondence of linguistic fact (proposition) and mental act (judgment) has to be validated in a manner which goes beyond the mere "correctness" of subjective thinking based on rules, without taking refuge in a questionable "causality" in the thinking processmost emphatically questionable, if that causality is taken to be physical. What Hegel seeks is a return to the Aristotelian contention that in knowledge the thinking mind is "somehow" identified with the reality it thinks. What Hegel has done may or may not resolve the ambiguity of the "somehow," but it has the merit both of recognizing the problem and of seeking a dynamic solution. It is Hegel's claim that Aristotle himself saw "purpose" included in the very "concept of concept"witness Aristotle's philosophy of the internal finality of natureand that this can make sense only if the structure of "concept"
< previous page
page_105
next page >
< previous page
page_106
next page > Page 106
(including judgment and syllogism) is common to both reality and thought, which it will not be if the "identification" (Zusammen-schliessen) of thought and reality is no more than the imposition by thought of a form of identity on a recalcitrant reality. In one sense, then, Hegel tells us, the "concept of purpose" is superfluous, saying, as it does, the same as "rational concept," as opposed to "understanding's" ''abstract universal," which is related to its particulars as merely "subsuming" particulars, not as "containing" them "within itself." Here the important distinction is that between "final cause" and simple "efficient cause"the latter being what is usually meant by "cause." "Efficient cause" belongs to the ambiguous sphere of mere "blind" necessity (expressed in the "mechanical" and "chemical" metaphors), which touches reality only from the outside. It can be "posited" as the necessary relationship of cause and effect (a Kantian "category"), but this misses the point that "cause" and "effect" are related to each other as at once mutually extrinsic to each other and mutually defining each other. "Purpose," on the other hand, is "posited" as "containing in itself" the effective determination of that of which it is the purpose (e.g., the plant in the seed). In this sense purpose "realizes itself" in the becoming of that which is intrinsically ordered to an end. Purpose, however, is a closed book to "formal" thinking; it has to be grasped "speculatively" as the concept "which in its own unity and ideality of determinations at once contains the judgment" and the opposition of "subjective and objective," while at the same time "superseding" the opposition. No amount of mental prestidigitation is going to "make" the concept objective if it is not already "subjective-objective." It is a mistake, then, to think of "purpose" merely in terms of the "form," according to which purpose is a determination "at hand" (vorhandene) in conscious "representation." It is the merit of Kant, Hegel says, to have resuscitated the "idea," particularly that of "life," in his concept of "internal finality." We all know what it means to speak of "someone" having a purpose in making or using "something," but that is not the finality proper to life, of which both Aristotle and Kant speak; it is no more than "finite," "extrinsic" finality. In short, to speak of the "purpose" of something is to speak of its "internal impulse" to go beyond itself and become what it is not yetand yet, what it is to be it already is in this impulse to go beyond itself. The objective, then, is the purpose of the subjective, that toward which it is oriented, not as to something outside itself but as to something contained within itself. Either subjective consciousness is oriented to objectivity or it is not true to itself.36
36. Hence, the progressive "negation" of illusory satisfaction with less than authentic objectivity, which characterizes Phenomenology of Spirit.
< previous page
page_106
next page >
< previous page
page_107
next page > Page 107
This can be illustrated in the "syllogism" which is the working out of purpose, the purpose of "reason." The "realization" of purpose, that is, the identification (Zusammenschliessen) of the extremes effected by means of the middle, is in truth the negation of the extremesas opposedthe negation at once of ''mere" subjectivity and "mere" objectivity. To make sense out of this is to see in the "negation" spoken of the same sort of negation as that contained in the "lifting-up" (Erhebung) of the (human) spirit to God"against" the contingent things of the world as well as "against" one's own subjectivity. This "lifting-up" is the "moment" which, in the form of "syllogism of understanding" given to it in the so-called "proofs for the reality of God," has not been recognized (see chap. 5). We get an important hint as to what it means to say that the objectivity of thought is in truth "subjectivityobjectivity," if we can compare it with the knowledge of God as "subject-object," borrowing, as Hegel does, Aristotle's characterization of God as nohsiVnohsewV. No. 205. It would be difficult to assert that Hegel's view of teleology is shared by a great many philosophers, particularly by those "modern" philosophers, whose name is legion, who do not share Hegel's reverence for the Aristotelian tradition. Nor can it be denied that the far more obvious instance of the "teleological relationship" occurs in what Hegel calls "extrinsic finality," wherein purpose is assigned by a subject who is other than the "purposeful" object, which as "object" is assumed to be antecedent to and distinct from the "concept" of it. In this context purpose is simply "finite," both because "what is purposed (der Inhalt)" is a finite end and because a condition for the "realization" of the purpose is an "already given" object which serves as "material" for that realization; with the result that "purpose" applies to the object only as conceived ("formally"). What is more, purposes are particular and as such subjective, so that "what is purposed" is "distinguished" from the "totality" of the "form" of subjectivity, that is, the concept. This diversity makes the purposes intrinsically finite. Like the object which is particular and antecedent to its concept, "what is purposed" is "limited," "contingent," and "given." Thus, things are not looked at as having an end in themselves; they merely serve as means for the realization of what a subject "purposes"; they are "useful." Although Hegel does not use the terms here, a distinction is being drawn between Zweckmässigkeit, "having a purpose," and Zwecktätigkeit, "serving a purpose," which is in effect the same as Kant's distinction between "internal" and "external" finality. Hegel's adversaries simply deny that things "have a purpose" at all. Hegel, however, is not saying that every naive view of purpose is true (e.g., the bark of trees serving as corks for bottles!); what he is saying is that the assignment of an external finality is not synonymous with the reality of an internal finalitywhere it is a question of "living" things, or more importantly when it is a question of the totality of reality.
< previous page
page_107
next page >
< previous page
page_108
next page > Page 108
No. 206. We can now begin to see what Hegel meant when he said that "all is syllogism": If the structure of thought when it is adequately rational is syllogistic, and the structure of reality is rational, then the structure of reality is syllogistic; the rational is syllogism, hence the totality of reality is, as totality, rational. The form in which this argument is here expressed is itself scarcely syllogistic, in the formal-logical sense, but it is not intended to be; the reasoning is "speculative," and what it is saying is that "the teleological" is what we find in the "syllogism.'' "Subjective purpose," which is purpose as we first recognize it, "identifies itself" (sich zusammenschiliesst) by means of a middle, which, as "teleological activity," that is, as "objectivity immediately posited under the heading of purpose," the middle" (term), then becomes the "means."37 The ob-jectivity of the "object," then, is subjective "activity," but not that of a separated thinking subject; it is subjective activity as the totality of conceptual relationship. Farfetched? No more than the subject "becoming" the object is; the subject recognizes its own rationality in the rationality of reality, which is the overall theme of Phenomenology of Spirit; how else can Spirit take reality unto itself, which it must, if there is to be knowledge all? Zusatz: If there is knowledge of reality as it is, it is contained in "idea," and "purpose" develops into idea in three "stages": first, the stage of subjective purpose; second, in that of purpose "accomplishing"; and, third, in that of purpose "accomplished." If we can identify subjective purpose with self-contained (für sich seiender) concept," then purpose is the totality of "moments of the concept," concept, of course, being self-developing process. The first "moment" is universality embracing all its particulars indiscriminately. The second, then, is not the "particulars," but the activity of "particularizing" the unviersal, whereby the universal achieves a determinate content, because it is the "activity" of the universal which "posits" this determinate content and, thus, by means of this content "returns to itself," thus "identifying itself with itself" (schliesst sich mit sich selbst zusammen).38 Once again, the complexity of the language needs to be unpacked: When we conceive an "ob-ject, " we set ourselves a "purpose," we "decide on something" (etwas beschliessen), and in this we look upon ourselves as "open" to a "determination," that is, we have "made a decision" (sich zu etwas ent-schliessen). This means that we have stepped out of our "self-contained interiority" and "surrendered ourselves" to the objectivity over-against us. We have moved from the merely subjectively conceived purpose to outwardly oriented "purposeful activity." "Objective" thinking is not "receiving" into the subject an already prepared object; it is the subject objectifying itself in its purposeful activity. All of which makes very lit-
37. The logical "middle" (Mitte) becomes the "means" (Mittel) of attaining purpose. 38. The play on Schluss (syllogism) and zusammenschliessen (identify) should be obvious.
< previous page
page_108
next page >
< previous page
page_109
next page > Page 109
tle sense, if all that is at stake is the limited subjective activity of an individual subject; to let oneself go in the stream of meaningful subjective activity is to realize the goal of objectivity; objectivity is beyond the capacity of self-enclosed individuality. No. 207. What all this means, Hegel tells us, is that the "moments" of the concept, universality, particularity, and singularity, are not merely the moments of subjective mental activity. "Subjective purpose" is itself the unifying "syllogism," in which the "universal concept" by means of particularity so ''identifies itself" (sich zusammenschliesst) with the singular, that the singular becomes the "self-determination" which "judges," that is, both particularizes the as yet indeterminate universal, making of it a determinate "content," and "posits" the "opposition" of subjectivity and objectivity. For the individual subject this is at the same time a "return into itself," because by comparing the presupposition that the subjectivity of the concept is "opposed" to objectivity with the self-contained and self-identified totality, it can see that the presupposition is deficient, and thus it turns "outward." It should be noted that here Hegel has operated a subtle and very important switch. He begins by speaking of the "moments" of the objective "concept," whose identification occurs in a movement from universality, through particularity, to singularity and its identification with universalitythe conceptual dynamics he had spelled out beforethen in turning to the dynamics of subjective "conceiving," he makes the "singularity" (Einzelheit) of the subject of the "judgment" (proposition) into the individuality (without changing the term Einzelheit) of the subject "judging." This may be a trick, but the move is significant: the single individual judging (syllogistically) must come to the realization that precisely because he judges only from the subjective point of view, the distinctions he makes are deficient; only a turn to the total concept away from a onesided aspect of it will remedy the deficiency. Subject-Object No. 208. Hegel is now zeroing-in on what is perhaps the most important element in his whole "doctrine of the concept": The concept is neither a relation of receptivity to a content presented to it from outside nor the product of a subjective activity which merely re-acts to what is presented to the minda "representation" (Vorstellung) of reality. It is the "activity" itself of thinking, a purely "spiritual" activity. There is no question that it first manifests itself as the subjective activity of an individual subject, but it is significant only because within itself it is oriented to burst the bonds (limitations) of individual subjectivityits inescapable orientation is "outward." This activity is that of a "singularity," which, in the framework of "subjective purposes" is identical with a particularization of the universal; a par
< previous page
page_109
next page >
< previous page
page_110
next page > Page 110
ticularization which includes within itself not only a content but also "external objectivity." As singular, then, this purposeful activity is initially related "immediately" to the object (Objekt) which it employs as a "means." The concept is the very capacity to employ the means, because as negating the reality of the object it transforms the very ''being" of the object into "ideal being." The "middle" (of the syllogism), then, is this intrinsic power of the concept as "activity" to transform, and the "ideal" object as "means" is subservient to it. Since we are speaking here of "finite teleology," it is to be noted that this involves the "breaking-up" of the middle into two "moments" extrinsic to each other, the "activity" and the "object," which latter serves as a "means." In this context the relationship of the purpose as "power" over the object is "immediate"the first premiss of the syllogismwhich is to say that in the self-contained ideality of the concept the reality of the object is "nullified." The relationship expressed in the first premiss, then, "becomes itself the middle," which is at the same time the syllogism, because the purpose through this relationship, that is, its activity, is "identified" with objectivity. In this sense, the "end" (purpose) is a "cause," in the sense of "effective" orientation, which therefore makes the conceptual activity "objective." What Hegel seems to be trying to say here, in what is admittedly a round-about way, is that the objectivity of conceptual thinking does not consist in the activity of an already constituted object on a subject who thinks in response to such activity. Rather, the thinking, which is initially the activity of the subject and, in this sense, a subjective activity, is at the same time the self-objectifying activity of the subject. It is the subject's thinking which constitutes the object in its objectivity, which it does precisely by "derealizing" (to employ an expression of J.-P. Sartre) reality in order to make reality the subject's own and in so doing to "realize" the thinking's own inward thrust toward objectivity, which once again the individual subject can do only if it ceases to be merely a subjective subject, that is, by realizing in its activity the objectivity of "universal" subjectivity. Zusatz: The relationship explicated here can be exemplified in the living human being. The living being has a body, which the soul controls and in which the soul immediately objectifies itselfthis implies no body-soul dualism, merely that the body in question is the body it is only as animated. The human soul makes its own corporeality a means of action; it does not employ the body in a dualistic way. Thus, the human being must, so to speak (gleichsam), "take possession" of its body, making that body its "instrument." The dualistic tone of the language indicates nothing more than the ontological priority of soul over body, paralleling the logical priority of thought over objectivity. The body is only "so to speak" an "instrument." No. 209. We are still concerned with a teleological activity which, along
< previous page
page_110
next page >
< previous page
page_111
next page > Page 111
with its "means" is directed "outward," precisely because the "purpose" is not identical with the object (despite the note of purpose in the term "object"), but is related to it ''mediately." This it is in the second premiss, in which "the means as object" is immediately connected with the other extreme of the syllogism, that is, objectivity as "pregiven," the "material object." Once again the "mechanical" and "chemical" metaphors come into play; they are modes of relationship serving the "purpose" in question, and they have some "truth," because the purpose is "their self-determining concept." "Mechanical" and "chemical" relations become the means which "reason" employs in achieving its purposes. Physical activities do, in fact, serve the purpose of the concept's development, provided, of course, the concept is seen as being realized in the attainment of its purpose. None of this, however, will make sense except in the context of an overriding "reason," which transcends all particular purposes. In a sentence reminiscent of the introduction to his Philosophy of History, Hegel here speaks of the "cunning of reason," which makes use of "the subjective purpose as the power controlling the physical processes" ("mechanical" and "chemical") wherein "objective" reality is broken up into parts which act on each other, while the purpose of reason at once holds itself apart from the processes and maintains itself in them. The "cunning of reason" uses particular "purposes" to attain the overarching purpose of "reason" itself. Zusatz: Here, as in other places, Hegel explicitly connects this notion of the "cunning of reason" with "divine providence," which achieves its purposes in and through particular purposes which may very well "in themselves" be opposed to God's own. Divine providence, in relation to the world and its process of development can even be called "absolute cunning." God permits men to follow their own "passions and interests" in such a way that what results from human activity is the accomplishment of what God intends. This is but another way of expressing what we have seen before. "The actual is rational, and the rational is actual"; reason can come to grips with reality only because reality itself is rational. No. 210. "Realized purpose, then, is the posited unity of the subjective and the objective." The unity in question, however, is achieved in such a way that only what is "onesided" in both the subjective and the objective is "superseded," while at the same time the objective is made subservient to the "self-determining concept," which is objectivity's criterion. "Purpose," then, "sustains" (erhält) itself both against and in what is objective, because in addition to being subjective and, therefore, "onesided," that is, particular, it is also "concretely universal," that is, the intrinsic identity of subject and object. It is because the many particulars subsumed under the universal are oriented to a universal purpose that their significance as particulars is not eliminated by being universalized. Seen this way the universal, as simply "reflected" back on itself, is the "content"
< previous page
page_111
next page >
< previous page
page_112
next page > Page 112
which remains the same in the movement of the syllogism's three terms; that is, they explicate one and the same concept, of which they are the dynamic articulation. No. 211. If, however, we remain on the level of "finite" teleology, where particular purposes hold sway, we are faced with a situation in which even the "realized (ausgeführter) purpose" is just as much "broken-up'' within itself as was the relationship of the "middle" and the "initial purpose." This means that where the purpose is finite only a form "extrinsically imposed" on a preexistent material comes into play, and because of its limited "purposecontent" such a form is, by the same token, a contingent determination, whose presence or absence does not alter the "material," since another purpose can take its place; finite purposes are not "intrinsic" to reality. The accomplished purpose, then, is only an object which is also the "means" to or "material" for other purposes, on into an "infinite" series. No. 212. When we look at the realization of purposes simply by itself we find that what happens is that "onesided subjectivity" and what seems to be a given independent objectivity over-against it are both superseded. Purpose is the key to identification of subject and object. In "taking hold" of the means "the concept" posits itself as the "intrinsic" (an sich) essence of the object. This means going beyond the "mechanical" and the "chemical"processes in which the independence of the object had taken refuge. In the course of a process subservient to purpose, however (i.e., process without purpose is not process, it is going nowhere), the "illusion" of independence, which "in relation to the concept" is negative, "dissolves." If, however, the realized purpose is characterized as merely a means to or material for another purpose, then this object too is being posited as of itself null, "merely ideal"; and this spells the disappearance of the opposition between form and content, that is, what is content is also form, and what is form is also content. The "concept" which was initially "formal activity" has only itself as its content; its activity produces only itself. What has happened, then, is that "what the concept of purpose" was, that is, the intrinsic unity of the subjective and the objective, has now been posited as "self-contained" (für sich seiende)and that is "the idea," the concept as its own product. Zusatz: An extrinsic purpose, which is always contingent upon the intent of a finite subject is inevitably a finite purpose. When it is attained, the means which were employed to bring about its attainment have to that purpose a relation imposed from without. When on the other hand, Hegel tells us, we speak of the relation between purpose and object (Objekt) we are speaking in terms of the concept, for which the purpose realized in the object is precisely a manifestation of what is intrinsic to the concept. An object extrinsic to the concept, then, turns out to be a kind of shell concealing the concepta shell that is broken through only in the realization of "infinite"
< previous page
page_112
next page >
< previous page
page_113
next page > Page 113
(total) purpose. Strictly speaking, finite purpose never is attained; there is always a purpose beyond it. Infinite purpose, on the other hand is always being attained, and its realization is the removal of the deception of thinking that it is not being attained. The rationality of the world is its constant orientation to "absolute good," to "absolute purpose," which, according to Hegel, is constantly in the process of bringing itself about, no matter what individual, finite purposes may be: that is the "cunning of reason." We do live in the deception of thinking that by attaining the purpose we as finite human beings have before us, we bring about whatever good there is. Our world is of interest to us because it is a world in which we achieve these purposes. More than thatand here the language is indeed strangeeven "the idea" in its process of being realized in our thinking deceives itself by setting up what is "other than itself" to be achieved. Nevertheless, it is the proper function of the idea by its activity to eliminate the deception. In the idea truth and error are intermixed, and out of the error comes truth, and in this emergence the idea is reconciled with both error and finitude. All of which says that what is other than idea, that is, error, is a necessary moment of truth, in that truth is only as emerging from nontruth, and the emergence is its own doing, its activity as self-manifesting concept and idea.39 Truth as Idea No. 213. Very gradually, almost imperceptibly, Hegel has been bringing us around to what is, perhaps, the most controverted contention in his whole philosophical position; his doctrine of "idea" as both the locus and source of all truth. At this point he tells us, "The Idea is the true in and for itself, the absolute unity of concept and objectivity." In terms of the language Hegel has just been employing, Nicolai Hartmann expresses the same by saying, "The end which provides its own means, the concept which realizes itself, the subjectivity which objectifies itself, is the 'Idea.'"40 The "ideal" content of the Idea is the same as that of the fully determined conceptthe latter is total subjectivity, the former is total objectivity, and they are identified. The ''real" content of the Idea, then, is the totality of reality, the identity of the real and the ideal. This is very much in the tradition of the
39. The language is unquestionably rather bizarrethe language of the text is even more bizarre. We have to remember, however, that here we are dealing with a ZusatzHegel's lecture mediated by the pen of a notetaking student. I am convinced, however, that it would be a mistake simply to ignore the Zusatz completely. If it is true to say that the Idea as absolute (infinite in its significance) expresses itself in and through the human mind thinking, it should not be amiss to say that the expression is deceptive and thus that, so to speak, the Idea "deceives itself." Nor, if the self-manifestation is a dialectical process, should the notion of truth emerging from the confrontation with the idea be shocking. 40. Nicolai Hartman, Die Philosophie der deutschen Idealismus: II Hegel (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1929), p. 225.
< previous page
page_113
next page >
< previous page
page_114
next page > Page 114
Platonic "idea," as that in the "light" of which reality, in all its particularity, is intelligible. The Idea, then, is absolute, not only in the sense that it depends on none of its "realizations" for its truth, but also in the sense that it embraces in its unity the totality of its "particularizations." To define "the Absolute''short of which the true is not trueas "Idea" is to give it its "absolute definition." The Idea is truth, because, as we saw before, that is "objectively" true which corresponds fully with its "concept," and "idea" is this full correspondence. When we speak of "external things" we do not say that they correspond with my "representation" of them, but rather that I correctly represent things in my thinking. In speaking of "idea," however, we are speaking neither of "representations" nor of "external things." Rather, whatever is realto the extent that it is trueis "idea" and is "true" only by virtue of the idea resident in it. An isolated "being" is but an "aspect" of the idea, needing for its completion other realities which also "seem" to be "self-contained" (für sich bestehende), but it is only in the interrelationship of all these that the concept is realized; that is, idea is the objectively interrelated totality corresponding to the concept. As we have seen, nothing isolated from the whole corresponds with its conceptand it is precisely this which constitutes the "finitude" and contingency of the "isolated." Clearly, then, to speak of "the idea" is not to speak of "an idea" of something or other, no more than "the concept" is this or that concept. To get back to the "absolute," it is "one" all-embracing idea, which in its self-articulation becomes the "system" of particular ideas, which have validity only as verified in the one idea. The idea so articulated is seen initially as simply a "substantial" unity, but if the articulation is seen as "development," its true "actualization," then it is a "subjective unity," or better still, it is "spirit," pure activity whose only adequate object is itself, the absolute "subject-object." If we make the mistake of looking upon idea as no more than a mental "form," then we shall also make the mistake of looking upon "existing things" which have not been caught up in the unity of idea as the true "realities" or "actualities." It is the same mistake as that of looking upon "idea" as merely "abstract." In the sense that in true ideas "untruth" is overcome, they can be called "abstract," that is, withdrawn from the untruth of existential instantiation, but intrinsically idea is essentially "concrete," the concept "determining itself" as "real." An idea is abstract only when the concept of which the idea is the culmination is itself abstract, that is, subjective thinking cut off from the concrete totality of thought, not when the idea is rooted in "subjectivity" in all its comprehensiveness. Zusatz: It is important to distinguish the "truth" which characterizes "idea" from the "correctness" which can characterize my subjective think
< previous page
page_114
next page >
< previous page
page_115
next page > Page 115
ing process. We do, in fact, speak of a "true man" or a "true work of art," for example, when we mean that what we are speaking of corresponds with its concept, that is, is as it ought to be. Strictly speaking, we are referring in this manner to what is "good" or "bad,'' but that is precisely the point: "good" and "bad" are meaningful only in reference to the concept of what "ought" to be, and the "ought" is the content of the "idea" as well. This is where "philosophy" comes in; it is "knowing" the idea, or knowing "ideas" in the "Idea." In one way or another the Western tradition of philosophical thinking has considered the locus of truth to be the term of rational thinking, that to which reason turns in looking for the truth of reality. Not until the advent of Descartes, however, was this term of cognition "in" the mind looked upon as that which the mind knows in knowing, the idea, the thinking of which enabled the mind to know the reality "represented" by the idea. Both rationalists and empiricists, in different ways to be sure, followed Descartes' view, until Hume cast doubts on man's ability to be sure that ideas corresponded to reality at all. As we have seen, Kant sought a way out of this dilemma by turning his gaze on the process of thought in order to establish its claim to objectivity. The German "idealists," notably Fichte and Schelling, sought in their turn to overcome the Kantian dilemma by turning attention not so much to ideas "in" the subject's mind as to the subject's knowledge of itself as ultimately the absolute source of true knowledge. What Hegel does when he comes on the scene is to go back to the roots of philosophy in Plato and Aristotle, which "modern" philosophy had consistently ignored, where he found "ideas" and "concepts" more intimately linked to reality than any merely subjective thinking process could make them. Borrowing also from Spinoza, for whom the whole of reality was but the unfolding of the one idea of "substance," and from Leibniz, for whom the whole of reality was mirrored in each subjective "monad," awaiting only its unfolding in thought, Hegel came to the conclusion that the truth of reality is not "represented by" ideas but rather "contained in" ideas to the extent that they were all embraced in the "absolute unity" of "absolute Idea," which is at the same time "absolute Reason," "absolute Thought," "absolute Subject," "absolute Spirit,""God." No. 214. When Hegel says, then, that "Idea can be comprehended as reason (this is the proper philosophical meaning of reason), and in addition as subject-object, the unity of the ideal and the real, of finite and infinite, of body and soul, as the possibility which has its actuality in itself, as that whose nature can be conceived only as existing, etc., because in reason are contained all the relationships that understanding comes upon, but contained in reason is infinite return to and identity with itself," he is but spelling out what he means by "absolute Idea is absolute Spirit, the being whose reality
< previous page
page_115
next page >
< previous page
page_116
next page > Page 116
fully corresponds with its concept." This is the ultimate ("absolute") object of all knowing, and whatever else is known is known in the knowing of this, because whatever else is known is the product of this. Having said this, Hegel goes on to say that understanding has an easy task to show that whatever is said of the "Idea" is contradictory. It is, in fact, contradictory, because the truth of the absolute can be expressed only in contradictory terms, without which only "aspects" and, hence, not the "truth'' of the absolute could be revealed. It is the task of "speculative logic" to recognize that "the subjective that is taken to be only subjective, the finite that is taken to be only finite, or the infinite that is taken to be only infinite, etc." is really not true, really contradicts itself and, thus, goes over into its opposite. What is revealed as the truth of such opposites is the unity of the idea in which the contradictories are reconciled "moments," whose contradictoriness is integral to the emergence of their truth. The misunderstanding here is simple enough; it is that of taking the meaning of the opposed moments as they are in the "concrete" unity of the idea to be the same as their "abstract" meaning in isolation from each other, that is, to assume that because they are not synonymous they cannot be united in one idea. What it comes down to is missing the significance of the copula "is" in the "speculative judgment." We have no difficulty, for example, in admitting that, although "rose" is not synonymous with "red" or "Socrates" with "man," it still makes sense to say that "the rose (singular) is red" or that "Socrates is a man," but we do balk at saying "the subject is object" or "the finite is infinite." What is more, "understanding" tends to look upon the contradictions in question as occurring in its own "reflection" on the idea, not in the idea itself. If, however, we see "reason" as inevitably "dialectical," we can also see its task as that of reconciling what "understanding" can see as only abstractly contradictory"Socrates," as an isolated and therefore abstract individual, is no more "humanity" in the abstract than "finitude" is "infinity"; strictly speaking, abstractions cannot be predicated of abstractions at all. There is no need to pretend, of course, that the viewpoint of "totality" is easy to adopt. There is a point of view from which the "ideal" is not "real," the "finite" is not "infinite," "identity" is not "difference," but it is a misunderstanding to see this as the only possible viewpoint, even though it is not a viewpoint to be passed over. "The idea," says Hegel, "is the infinite judgment," not made up of abstract parts united by an abstract "is," but each of whose moments is the whole concept (idea). No abstract concept is the totality, but "the concept" is and thus is both subjective and objective.
< previous page
page_116
next page >
< previous page
page_117
next page > Page 117
Idea as Process No. 215. What has been gradually emerging in this discussion is an awareness that "idea is essentially process," and that the kind of unity it manifests is the unity proper to process. The kind of identity idea manifests is the "absolute," the "self-determining" identity proper to "concept," because idea, too, is dialectical. The idea, it can be said, recapitulates that movement of concept whereby the latter is the "universality'' which is also singularity, oriented both to objectivity and to the opposite of objectivity, thus reorienting, by means of its own immanent dialectic, the "externality" which finds its "substantial reality" in the concept back to the "subjectivity" without which substantiality does not make sense. Precisely because idea is "process" it is not accurate to say that the absolute is the "unity of finite and infinite, of thinking and being, etc.," because "unity" expresses static abstraction. By the same token it is inaccurate to say that the absolute is "subjectivity"; the abstract "unity" of subjectivity says only what is implicit, "substantial," in "true unity." In such expressions the "infinite" (absolute) has the appearance of being "neutralized" by the "finite"; so too, the subjective by the objective, thinking by being. In the "negative" unity of the idea, on the other hand, a dynamic unity of process, the infinite embraces the finite, as thinking does being, as subjectivity does objectivity. The kind of unity proper to idea, then, is at once subjectivity, thinking, infinity; this unity is to be distinguished, however, not only from "substantiality" but also from merely formal, onesided, exclusive subjectivity, thinking, infinity: a subjectivity which is not subjective-objective is not even truly subjective. The same is true of a thinking which is exclusively subjective or of an infinity which is exclusively infinite. Having asserted rather summarily what are the implications of seeing idea as process, Hegel now tries to spell out the dynamics of idea-process just as he had previously (nos. 194212) sought to spell out the dynamics of objectivity-totality. In the former procedure he sought to discover in the "objective" world an intrinsic principle of unification by turning first to a "mechanical" model, then to a "chemical" model, only to find that nothing short of a "teleological" model could account for the rationality of the first two. Now, in an attempt to discover in subjectivity an intrinsic principle of unificationnot only of the subjective but also of the subjective-objectiveHegel turns to other models, this time not quite so metaphorical. Looking at the human subject he can find a model of unified process in "living," in "knowing," and finally, in the "absolute idea" as that which alone makes sense of the other two. No. 216. Idea as process, then, finds its first exemplification in "life," as
< previous page
page_117
next page >
< previous page
page_118
next page > Page 118
that whereby organic bodies are united in one process of "living" (nos. 216222). The initial "immediate" focus is on the "living body'' (animal), which is living not simply because it is a body but because in it resides a principle of lifeAristotle's "soul" or "entelecheia." Hegel likens this to a sort of incarnation of "idea." Just as the "members" of the living body (hand, eye, heart) are what they are only as living, as animated by all pervasive "life," so "ideas" are what they are only as inhabited by the all-animating "Idea."41 That life as process of the "living body," then, is likened to a "syllogism" (no. 217) whose "moments" are "syllogisms," should come as no surprise. Life in general is a rational, systematic whole, and so is each living body, in which "living" is both "process" and "result," the process which is its own end. The "moments," as could be expected, are three: (1) "Immediately" there is life as the internal process of one living body, in which each and every part is animated by one principle (no. 218), articulating itself as "sensibility," "irritability," and "reproduction." (2) The process is one of "mediation," wherein living is oriented to its "ob-ject," and the living body employs its inorganic components as "means" to its "end," which is the nonterminating culmination of the process (no. 219). (3) The synthesis of "immediacy" and "mediation" is completed in the relation of one body to another, precisely in the life-process, where organic bodies are only as sexually differentiated (no. 220). No. 221. What the process thus described results in is quite clearthe "species," which, as a "reality" and not merely a mental classification, affords Hegel an instantiation of the identity of the ideal and the real (cf. WL II, pp. 41011). The living individual is a member of a real class, but the living individual "dies" because it is the embodiment of a "contradiction"; the universal (class) "exists" only in the individual, but it is not identified with the individual; the "ob-ject" of animal life qua animal is not the individual but the species, which means that no individual in the species corresponds with its "idea"it "needs others" (cf. WL II, p. 409); individuals come and go, but the life of the species goes onand it is "one" life. Nor is the individual, however, simply the univocal instantiation of the abstract universal in the concrete process of life (cf. WL II, p. 408). This contradiction, which is inescapable in animal life, will be resolved only in "spirit," which is both individual and "for itself," singular and universal; individual spirit is not for the species (no. 222).42 Nos. 22335. Although the unity of process exhibited in organic life,
41. "The actual is only so far as it contains the idea in itself and expresses it." (WL II, p. 409) 42. It is here that both Feuerbach and Marx find fault with Hegel; for them man is essentially a "species-being" (Gattungswesen). To Feuerbach this means that man belongs to the abstract class "mankind" and is thus related to all other members of the class; to Marx this means a more concrete universality embracing the concrete relationships of all its members to each other. But neither of these positions is what Hegel is denying.
< previous page
page_118
next page >
< previous page
page_119
next page > Page 119
whether of the individual organism or of the animal species, is manifestly real and shows a manifest correspondence between the process as conceived and the process as real, neither the overall unity of the real nor the correspondence of ideal and real unity of the totality can be concluded from a consideration of vital organic unityalthough the latter might be looked upon as a "model" whose structure could give a hint as to what an overall unity might be. As a "mean" between the "given" unity of the organic and the "sought-for" unity of the totality Hegel now introduces a life-process which clearly exceeds the capacities of the organic qua organic, but which is exhibited as embodied in one of the kinds of organism in the world, the human, the nonorganic process of ''knowing." No. 223. As so often happens, Hegel begins with a presupposition (better, perhaps, an "ideal"): If the idea he is searching for is to resolve the problem of totalizing unity, it must be the "objective universality" which constitutes the orientation of concept, and it must be the adequate resolution of the apparent conflict between the "subjectivity" of concept and the "objectivity" of reality. This, then, is what he is looking for, not having found it on the level simply of "life." No. 224. Implicit in the idea of life, it is true, is the unity of the subject objectifying itself, but the unity is implicit only, because to it clings "finitude." In the subject endowed with "reason," however, there resides the conviction that it can legitimately "posit" the identity of subjectivity and objectivity, of singularity and universality.43 No. 225. The question, then, is that of legitimizing the claim of "knowing" to embrace all reality, by actively removing the "onesidedness" of both objectivity and subjectivity. So long as the knowing in question, however, remains "finite" the resolution of the conflict will be a task not an accomplishment. Nor will it be an accomplishment short of a synthesis of the spiritual activities of "knowing" (theoretical) and "willing" (practical). No. 226. The "idea" of knowing exceeds by far the finite fact of knowing. In the latter there is simply the assumption that what is known is a "given" which is "received" in thought, in "reason" functioning as only understanding"the finite grasp of a finite object. But, even this has its roots in the overall comprehension which is the concept. No. 227. Where the knowing is finite it presupposes a diversity of objects which are united only because the knowing subject imposes an abstract form of universality on them. This sort of "classification" Hegel calls the "analytic method"breaking up and putting together again, both merely subjectively, beginning with the singular and, by comparing it with other singulars, forming a universal. It is a method of moving away from the
43. This notion is admirably spelled out in the opening paragraphs of Phenomenology of Spirit, Ch. V, where Hegel speaks of "reason certain of itself as being all reality."
< previous page
page_119
next page >
< previous page
page_120
next page > Page 120
"concreteness" of the immediately given toward the "abstractness" of universality (the method of the empirical sciences). No. 228. The "synthetic method," on the other hand, begins with the universal, equally applicable to all particulars. The "synthesis" is the application of the one determinate concept to the many particulars it subsumes. No. 229. When an object is brought under the universal heading (class) to which it belongs and to that is added that which characterizes the object as particular under this heading, the result is "definition." It is the "analytic method" which accomplishes this, but it does so by assigning to it what the subject decides is the defining characteristic. No. 230. When, on the other hand, the subject in considering the universal "particularizes" it, the technique is that of "division"again on the basis of characteristics decided on by the subjectand this belongs to the "synthetic method." No. 231. What Hegel is trying to bring out in all this is the artificiality of both methods, particularly if they are thought to be adequate to philosophical thinking; the methods simply cannot be arbitrarily applied to any and every object. The artificiality comes from their being "applied" to objects, not dictated by the inner dynamics of the concept itself. The two methods work very successfully within a limited field, but they are simply too "formal" to be of use in philosophy, which simply does not permit of "constructing" either "theorems" or "proofs.'' Philosophy, speculative thinking, looks for an inner necessity in its concepts, not the necessity of subjectively thinking in a certain way. "Knowing," in this sense, means more than simply "putting" into concepts determinations received from an object as "given"; there is a "logic" of reality to be uncovered (cf. WL II, p. 444). No. 232. The necessity proper to "proofs," then, applies to finite knowing, and it is "extrinsic" to the concept, belonging only to subjective activity.44 It is only when the concept relates itself to itself, that it finds in itself what "necessarily" belongs to itself. That the merely "subjective idea" should move from what is "given" in it to what is "immanent" but not "given" requires a passage from mere "knowing" to the ideal of "willing," which is essentially oriented, but not arbitrarily directed, to the "not-yet-given." Its orientation is rather to what "ought" to be, which, again, is inseparable from the concept. No. 233. If the "subjective idea" contains in itself the determination good," that is, ought to be realized, the subjective is being described as oriented to reality. Once more the teleological aspect of objectivity has been
44. As we shall see in chapter 5, there is a far more significant form of "proof" which is not ratiocinative, as is the "proof" here spoken ofperhaps the term "argument" would be better here.
< previous page
page_120
next page >
< previous page
page_121
next page > Page 121
introduced: the given world is more than just "given"; its givenness has a "purpose," even though this is initially only "posited" in the "subjective idea." No. 234. What needs to be overcome here is the "contradiction" contained in the "finitude" of a world in which the "good as purpose" is just as often not realized as realized. From the side of the subject the "realization" of the good stands merely as an ''ought." What the "ought" does, however, is more than characterize subjective activity; it pertains to what is "substantial" and "true" in the object. To say that willing ought to be oriented to the realization of the object is to say more of "knowing" than that it is abstractly true; the "oughtness" of the object is far more significant than its "givenness." This is even more significant when we see an "oughtness" in the world itself, an "oughtness" which brings the world together into a onethe unity of "is" and "ought." "Willing," then, is part and parcel of rational process, which cannot simply "take" reality as it is but must "make" it into what it ought to be. Nor does this mean that any particular "good" attains to truth by being realized; it is true as the demand "to be realized" which is intelligible only in the framework of totality (cf. WL, p. 479). No. 235. "Thus is posited the truth of the good as the unity of the theoretical and practical idea." It is as though Hegel had resurrected Plato's "Idea of the Good," which alone gives ultimate intelligibility to reality. If nothing else, it enables us to "see into" (speculare) what Hegel calls the "absolute idea," the idea which realizes itself, because in it there is the rational demand that it be realized. What this is to mean we shall see in the final paragraphs of this Logic (nos. 236243). No. 236. What needed to be broken down, then, was the mere "givenness" of the objective over-against the subjective and the mere "subjectivity" of idea over-against the "objectivity" of the real. The "concept of the idea" bespeaks precisely the "oneness" of subjective and objective idea. The point is that idea as "absolute" bespeaks the reality of that to which "concept," as the activity of spirit is oriented. What "idea" in this sense "logically" demands to be true is absolutely true, and "concept" as subjective activity is true only if it corresponds to "idea." Zusatz: Dialectically speaking the absolute idea reconciles the defects present in both the "idea of life" and the "idea of knowing" as explanatory of total unification. In "life" the totality is "implicitly" contained, but what a "living" totality can possibly be is not explicated. On the other hand, mere "knowing" is equally "onesided"; "totality" is "explicit," but the working-out of totality is unexplicated. In the "absolute idea," Hegel says, these defects are remedied, because the "absolute idea" is at once "living process" and the concrete thinking out of all that is implicit in the "idea." Previously it was "we" who "had" the idea in its process as "our" object;
< previous page
page_121
next page >
< previous page
page_122
next page > Page 122
now it is the idea which is "objective" to itself; it is its own working-out, the nohsiVnohsewV, the highest form of the idea, the synthesis of the rationality of the theoretical and practical idea, the fusion of "is" and "ought" in the truly real. Idea as Absolute No. 237. Because as "self-contained" the "absolute idea" contains no "transition," no "presupposition,'' and above all no "determination" which is not at once "fluid" and "clear," it is the "pure form" of the concept which sees itself as "its own content." To say that it is its own concept, however, is not to say that its content is not "objective"; it is to say that its content does not "come to it" from outside but is its own activity. Quite obviously this would make no sense if "its own activity" were nothing more than the subjective activity of a finite subject who "has" the idea. If, however, it can be said that "reason" transcends individual reason, "thought" transcends individual thought, and "spirit" transcends individual spirit, may it not be said that "idea" transcends the "ideas" of individuals? If this last makes sense, then it also makes sense to speak of the "content" of the "idea" as the "totality of form" the "logical system" of all content. "Absolute idea" is the thoroughly rational concept (cf. WL II, p. 484). It is this totality of content which dictates the method of thinking the idea. Zusatz: Appended to this paragraph is an addition, presumably, as we have seen, taken from Hegel's own oral presentation, which goes a long way toward clearing up misgivings about the elusiveness of the "absolute idea." There is a danger, the author admits, that enthusiasm for the all-embracing idea will be without foundation. The danger is that talk about the idea will be empty, precisely because the content of the idea is too vague to be genuinely convincing. Its true content is the entire "system," the tracing of whose development has been the task of the whole Logic up to this point. The "absolute idea," then, is not a mere abstract "form" thrown as a cloak, so to speak, over an unspecified content from without. Rather it is the "absolute (concrete) form" which so unifies the totality of objectivity as to illuminate all the real determinations of being (which have emerged in systematic discussion) by relating them intimately to each othernothing is intelligible except within the framework of the whole. To illustrate this, the author compares it to the old man who pronounces the same religious creed as does the child, with the difference that for the old man what he pronounces synthesizes the experiences of a lifetime. Even if the child "understands" the religious content, still for him his whole life and his whole world are not caught up in what he says. The same thing is true of human life and of all the events which make it up. Everything one does is
< previous page
page_122
next page >
< previous page
page_123
next page > Page 123
oriented to the goal of making life what it is, but when one attains the goal one is surprised to find that it is that toward which one was striving all along. It is only the "whole movement" that counts. If one contemplates the whole of one's life, its "end" can seem severely limited, but the whole of life is summed up in that "end." By the same token, the content of the "absolute idea'' is the entire vast panorama which has gradually been unfolding for us. The ultimate insight is that it is the unfolding whole that counts. Philosophically speaking this means the view that whatever simply "by itself" (für sich) seems limited in significance takes on value as belonging to the whole, not as a "given" but as a "vital development" of the idea, which is the form embracing the whole restrospectively. Each of the stages we have already seen is an "image" of the absolute, but each in a limited way; each is driven forward toward the wholeness, the unfolding of which is the method which has been described. No. 238. Out of this last protracted remark comes a recapitulation of the whole logical endeavor, the "speculative method," whose "beginning" is described in the present paragraph. The beginning is simply "being," which is "immediate" precisely because it is only the "beginning." From the "speculative" point of view, however, "being" is a process of "self-determination," which it can be only as the "movement" of the concept that in "judging" posits its own negation: the "being" which is initially taken to be "given" is recognized as "posited," that is, the "negative" of "given," which is to say, it is "mediated." However, the concept as no more than "negation," in which it recognizes itself as "positing" its other and therefore "identical with" its other, in which it finds the mere "certainty" of itself, is not yet explicitly but only implicitly the "concept as concept." The universality which belongs to the concept at this stage is only "immediate," "indeterminate." This sort of "beginning" is the result of the abstract characteristic of the "analytic method" proper to "finite" knowing. But, precisely as "universal," this resulting "beginning" is at the same time the beginning of the "synthetic method," wherein progressively the "particular" determinations of being emerge. Zusatz: Previously Hegel had said that neither the "analytic" nor the "synthetic" methods of finite knowing were proper to philosophy. Here he is saying that the "synthesis" of the two methods, in which neither remains simply what it was, is "philosophical." As merely "analytic," thinking is no more than "passive" reception. Add to this, however, synthesizing activity, along with the effort to avoid "private conjectures" and "particular opinions," and the philosophical method comes into its own as the "activity of the concept itself." No. 239. What the "activity of the concept itself" can mean has, of course, been a problem to many an interpreter of Hegel, especially to those
< previous page
page_123
next page >
< previous page
page_124
next page > Page 124
who do not share his views on the primacy of "spirit." If we go back, however, to the basic meaning of "concept," which first manifests itself as the subjective activity of the individual as "conceiving," we can rely on the fundamental distinction between an "immediate" object, "given'' in such a way as to be "received" by a subject, and an object "posited" in the activity of a subject and, thus, "mediated" by that activity. The "activity of the concept," then, is that of "positing," of "mediation." If it is further possible to see "concept" as the activity, not of an individual subject, but of "spirit" transcending the sum total of individual subjects, we may also be able to grasp what Hegel is trying to say in speaking of the "concept itself" as an "activity" transcending the sum total of all merely individual subjective activities. In this way we may also be able to grasp what Hegel means by speaking of "idea" which is not anyone's idea but is the transcendent "absolute idea." It is only thus that we shall be able to fathom Hegel's meaning when he speaks next of the "progress" (Fortgang) beyond the "immediate" beginning in the "speculative method." "The progress is the idea's posited judgment." We have already seen the kind of dynamic relationship which Hegel describes under the heading "judgment." If we remember that judgment is "articulated concept" we can at least see judgment as enjoying the same "transcendence" as does concept. If, in addition, we can grasp what he means by saying that the universal as "posited" in concept is "dialectical," that is, self-developing, we can also see both that all universality is "mediated" and that the universal is thus, posited as the "negative of the beginning" (immediate), the "positing" of a "determinateness" not present in the "immediate." Initially, however, even this "positing" is considered only as the work "of one" (für eines), i.e., "moment of reflection." As could be expected, after the explanation in the Zusatz to no. 238, the "progress" here described is both "analytic" and "synthetic": "analytic," because in light of the "immanent dialectic" of the concept only that is posited which is contained in the concept as "given"; "synthetic," because in this initial stage of the concept dialectic distinction "had not yet been posited." Zusatz: To confront directly those who ignore the primacy of spirit Hegel goes on to say that the "progress of the idea" makes it clear that even the "beginning" was not simply "immediate" but "mediated." Only when consciousness itself is "immediate" does it look upon "nature" as "primary" and spirit as "mediated." The true state of affairs is that spirit posits nature and only thus "makes" nature its "presupposition"; the process of conceptual thought transforming reality into idea is not to be distinguished from the process of idea "realizing" itself. No. 240. Looked at abstractly, the progress is seen at the stage of "being" as "transition to another" rather than just being. At the stage of
< previous page
page_124
next page >
< previous page
page_125
next page > Page 125
"essence" (the "moment of reflection") progress is seen as the ''showing" of what is over-against. Finally, at the stage of "concept" progress is seen as the "distinguishing" of singulars from universality; a universality, however, that is "continuous with" what is distinct from it and, therefore, in this sense, "identical with it." This last sentence is extremely important: "Identical with" does not mean "equal to" but rather "continuous with"; that is, the dialectical dynamic of the concept demands the "positing" of both singular and universal. No. 241. If we take a step backward to the stage of "essence" (reflection) we can see that the concept, which was initially only "implicit," has come to "manifestation" (Scheinen) and is, hence, "implicitly" already the "idea." This is but another way of saying that, at this stage, development involves not only a transition from the first to the second stage, but also a return from the second to the first; and it is only by virtue of this double movement that the distinction of stages makes sense. The reason for this is that each of the distinct spheres considered in itself is completed in the totality and thus functions only as combined in a unity with the other. Only because each of the two transcends its own onesidedness in the unity of the two is the unity itself saved from being onesided. In a dialectical union of the distinct neither of the two sides dominates the other; the unity both embraces the two and has a significance other than the sum of the two. No. 242. In the third moment of the "speculative method," then, unity and distinction are preserved in a delicate balance. The stage of reflection develops the connection of distinct moments into the kind of "contradictory" relationship it first of all is. This works itself out in a "progress to infinity," where the contradiction is ultimately "dissolved" in that the "different" is posited as what it is "in the concept," that is, both identical and different. What is different, then, is the negative of the first, but as identical with the first it is also the negative of itselfa somewhat complex way of saying that the concept distinguishes with a view to identifying and identifies with a view to distinguishing. The "concept" is the unity in which "being" and "essence" are ideal moments, at once transcended and retained. Thus, the concept whose "implications" are "explicitated" by means of its differences and of their supersession, which enables it to "come together into itself," is the "realized concept," that is, the concept which contains in its "independence" the "positing" of its own determinations. This is what Hegel calls "the idea," which as the "absolute principle" (of the method) is simply the disappearance of the illusion that the beginning is "immediate" and that the idea itself is a "result"and this means the "knowledge" that the idea is a totality embracing all the "different" moments of the process, which is the "method." No. 243. All along it has been becoming more and more clear that when Hegel speaks of the "method" proper to the "science" of logic, he is not
< previous page
page_125
next page >
< previous page
page_126
next page > Page 126
speaking of a method one chooses with a view to solving problems, as one does, for example, when one employs geometrical constructions extrinsic to the figure under consideration in order to "prove" the relationships of the angles, lines, area, and so on, of the figure in question. Thus, when he identifies method with the "soul and concept of the content," he is telling us that the "method" as inseparable from the content is dictated by the content of philosophical thinking, and that the animating principle of the content is the concept. If the concept, then, has ''moments," whose relationships to each other constitute the concept as a whole, the method of conceptual thinking simply must follow where the relationship of these "moments" lead it. Now, since the "determinate content" of the concept along with its "form" harks back to the "idea," then this latter presents itself as a "systematic totality," which ultimately is only one "idea," whose particular moments are "in themselves" (an sich) the same as are those which in the dialectical movement of the concept "produce" the simple "self-contained-ness" (Fürsichsein) of the idea. There is no place to look but in "idea" for objectivity, and the structure of idea can be only "conceptual." The "science" of logic, therefore, closes by comprehending its own conceptwhich tells us what the "science" must be45the concept of the "pure idea," to which any and every "idea" points. No content of any concept will be true, except insofar as it finds its place in the overall "system" of the one "idea." The total content of the "idea" may be beyond the capacity of finite mind; the "method" dictated by the "idea" is not (cf. WL II, p. 485). No. 244. Logic as such is now complete, but it must make itself real by turning to the real contents offered for its inspection. Thus, the idea taken "by itself" (für sich) is "contemplation" (Anschauen), that is, "looking at" what is before it, and the "contemplative idea" is the idea of "nature," which is "totality in the form of immediacy" (WL II, p. 505) to which "speculative thinking" must now turn. As contemplation alone, however, the idea is posited as no more than the "onesided characterization" of immediacy or of negation by means of a reflection external to nature. It is the "self-determining" idea in nature which must be uncovered, which means that it is not enough for "the idea of nature" to make the transition to "life" or, as finite knowing to let life "manifest itself" in knowledge; the idea must "enclose itself" in its own "absolute truth," thus enabling it to "let emerge from itself" the "moment" of its "particularization," its "determinate self-othering," the "immediate idea" as its "self-mirroring," which is nature. The philosophy of nature, then, is what "speculative logic"
45. The initial "Womit muss der Anfang der Wissenschaft gemacht werden?" becomes: "What does the end result tell us scientific philosophy essentially is?"
< previous page
page_126
next page >
< previous page
page_127
next page > Page 127
inevitably leads to, the "idea" expressing itself in nature. When "speculative thinking," however, does turn to "nature," it must carry with it the remembrance that "dialectic" is not merely a subjective act of discovery or of argumentation; it is what the contradictions which ''understanding" finds in contemplating nature impose on thinking (cf. WL II, p. 496).
< previous page
page_127
next page >
< previous page
page_128
next page > Page 128
Chapter Three God As Spirit From all that we have seen so far, one conclusion emerges with utmost clarity: Hegel has made a profound act of faith in the human, in the capacity of the human spirit both to respond religiously to the self-revelation of absolute Spirit and to plumb philosophically the profound rationality of that revelation. More than that, we have become more and more aware that, in Hegel's view, the rationality of the revelation has its source in the Spirit who reveals, just as the capacity to comprehend the revelation resides in the spiritual character of the recipient who "appropriates" by "reproducing." Spirit speaks to spirit, so to speak, and the result is both religion and philosophy. The time has come, it would seem, for us to try to fathom what Hegel means when he speaks of both God and man as ''spirit." One rather obvious way of doing that, of course, is to do what I have attempted to do in another place,1 by tracing laboriously the intricacies of his Phenomenology of Spirit, but this is hardly the place to do thatalthough we shall have occasion more than once in this study to consult that master work. Without entering here into the complexities of both distinction and identification, we can say with Hegel that in the world in which we live we are confronted with two realitiesnature and spirit, the world of "things" and the world of "spiritual activity." In one sense there seems to be an unbridgeable chasm between matter and spirit; one is simply not the other, and all our experience of knowing, loving, willing, acting upon, using, and so on, in which they would seem to influence each other, does not solve the mystery of the relationship of spirit and matter. (1) One of the solutions attempted has been that of materializing spirit, whether in the naive form of
1. Quentin Lauer, S.J., A Reading of Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit. New York: Fordham University Press. 1976 (second printing with revisions, 1978).
< previous page
page_128
next page >
< previous page
page_129
next page > Page 129
mechanical "reductionism" or in the more sophisticated form of some sort of "dialectical" emergence of "spiritual" activity from its "material'' base. It is called "naturalism" and has as its motive and aim a "scientific" grasp of all that is or possibly could be. This "solution" Hegel categorically rejects. (2) Another solution has been that of spiritualizing matter, and this, too, can take two principal forms: (a) By some kind of indescribable power spirit can, from out of its own resources only, transform "material" reality into "spiritual" reality, thus taking possession of the former and making it object for thought; or (b) spirit can recognize that matter is not merely matter; its very being has the stamp of spirit on it, thus making it antecendently susceptible of appropriation by spirit. Both forms of "spiritualization" have been called now "realism," now "idealism," until it is not clear what either term means, even in the context in which it is being used. Of these "spiritual" solutions the first, on the face of it, would seem to contain much that is both mysterious and gratuitous, requiring the hypothesis of a number of intermediate entities to make it work. There are, unquestionably, those to whom the second of these solutions will seem as mysterious and gratuitous as the first. Still, the difference which separates them is vast. Fundamental to the second solution is the conviction not only that, weighed in the balance, spirit takes precedence over matter, both logically and ontologically, but also that the capacity of matter to be appropriated by spirit is a capacity inherent in matter, its intelligibility. Intelligibility, however, is not simply there, because matter is matter; it is a communicated intelligibility, just as its reality is communicated reality. If we follow Hegel this farand many, perhaps most, do notwe are, it would seem, forced to go further with him and agree that to communicate is the privilege of spirit alone. More than that, if "communication" is to be meaningful, it must be self-communication. Matter, then, has the mark of spirit on it. But, if the "appropriation" of matter by spirit is a "communication"spirit speaking to spiritwho, or what, is the communicator?2 If the question is put this way, it might be argued, the questioner is employing an unjustified argument from analogy. But what logic is it that tells us that such an argument from analogy is unjustifiedor unjustifiable? If I find that "things"make themselves known to me, and if I argue that the activity of self-manifestation is the activity of spiritwhich things are notwhy is it an unjustified use of analogy to argue that the "communication" in question makes sense only as the activity of a spirit which transcends both the things which finite spirit appropriates and the finite spirit which appropriates? What is illogicalexcept in an un-
2. As will become manifest in chapter 5, "Proofs of God," simply to put the question this way is to embark on what Hegel considers the most rational proof, i.e., the "Ontological Proof."
< previous page
page_129
next page >
< previous page
page_130
next page > Page 130
justifiably narrow sense of "illogical"in seeing the being of both "things" and "spirits'' as a communicated being which gives both things and spirits that in common which not only relates them to each other but also relates both to the Spirit without which neither is in any meaningful way a possibility?3 Most of us would agree that our experience testifies that nature "speaks" to usin a not totally metaphorical wayin somewhat the way a work of art "speaks" to us of its author. Perhaps "nature," too, is but the voice with which the Artist who is greater than all speaks, and perhaps, if we really listen, we shall be conscious that the voice we hearor the word spokenis that of the one Spirit who is above allso long as we do not understand "above" either spatially or separatistically. In any event, it is difficult to see how such a consciousness would be "illogical." We might even from this go on to say, with Hegel, that the "one" who speaks is "God." If, however, we prefer to conceive of the speaker as "force" or "power," or even as "supreme being," we run the risk of making the "speaking" both unintelligible and lifeless. I remember speaking many years ago to a friend of mine in Paris. He was an artista painterand a good artist, too. He had spent the greater part of his lifeall of his adult lifepainting, trying to express on canvas who he was, what he was, what was his experience of the world in which he was immersed. Only gradually did he come to the realization that the self-expression to which his art compelled him was more than just that; he was putting forth that which was to be appropriated by others. He found in himself the need, the effort, not merely to express himself but, more significantly, to communicate himself. Each work he turned out, he saw, was autobiographical, and he began to see that he had a need to let others in on the story and that the mode of communication was the beauty he created. All of this passed through my friend's mind without his thoughts straying much beyond the art in which he was engaged: his own art as the effort of self-communication, his appreciation of the work of others as his appropriation of their efforts at self-communication. He could not be an artist, however, without being overpowered by the beauty of nature.4 Still, it was not until he was in his forties that he began to realize that he was not simply finding beauty in naturenor was he putting it therethe beauty of nature was nature speaking to him. Here, without being able to give it a
3. It might, of course, be arguedwith Feuerbach and Marxthat since things actually are, it is illegitimate to shut our eyes to their actuality and to speak of a condition of their possibility, but it is difficult to see the logic of that position. The notion of conditioned actuality is scarcely illegitimate. 4. We might note that Hegel sees things a bit differently herehe is overpowered by man's capacity to be both overpowered and controlling.
< previous page
page_130
next page >
< previous page
page_131
next page > Page 131
name, he was beginning to argue from "analogy." If his artistic production was his effort to communicate himself to others in the language of beauty, was he not forced by his "logic" to conclude that it was not nature by itself that was "speaking" to himit had no intelligencebut that another ''speaker" was employing nature as (its?) voice and beauty as the language in which to speak to him? His logic, indeed, pushed him one step further to the conclusion that, just as he in his work spoke to others of himself, so the one who spoke through the voice of nature was speaking to him of the speaker himself. With that realization my artist friend became both religious and a philosopherand it was his "logic" which impelled him to both. "A strange sort of logic, indeed," one might say; and yet, it was not too different from what, as we have seen, Hegel calls "speculative logic" (even though, for Hegel, the human spirit spoke far more loudly of "absolute Spirit" than did nature). The artist's logic, to be sure, was not of the kind that permitted him to draw out of his premisses a conclusion already contained in them. Rather, it was a logic which would not permit him to rest in only what the premisses already contained and which forced him to move in the direction of that to which the premisses were pointing; and that to which they were pointing he found himself incapable of refusing. The analogy with Hegel's "speculative logic" may seem forced; it may not adequately explain to us what went on in the "spirit" of the artist. But perhaps we can approach this experience from the opposite direction: Does it help us to understand something of what Hegel is trying to tell us in his "speculative philosophy," which does not permit him to stop short of an affirmation of the reality of "absolute Spirit"provided, of course, we remember that, for Hegel, the most potent indicators of both the reality and "nature" of God is the reality and "nature" of the human spirit? With regard to what has just been said, one further question might be asked: Could the artist himself, prior to his intuition of God's self-communication in nature, fully appreciate his own continued efforts at self-communication? Was the real revelation the self-manifestation of God in the activity of the artist's own spirit rather than in natureand is this the overall message of Hegel's Phenomenology, indeed of his whole system? Human spirit reveals divine Spirit in a way that neither nature nor art can.5 In whatever way one might wish to interpret my artist friend's experience or however critical one might be in evaluating the conclusion he drew from it, one thing is clear: It is far more difficult to get off the hook in interpreting Hegel's contention that the only way to come to grips with the
5. Texts could be multiplied which converge on this point, but it seems scarcely necessary to do more than refer to chapters VI and VII of PdG; EpW, nos. 55377; and VPR II, part III, B.
< previous page
page_131
next page >
< previous page
page_132
next page > Page 132
human spirit's experience of itself is to cast it in the light of that same spirit's experience of "absolute Spirit." There is more to this, however, than simply saying that the human spirit is led step by describable step to an affirmation of the reality of an all-embracing Spirit; it means rather that consciousness is not consciousness if it is not consciousness of self, that it is not consciousness of self if it is not consciousness of itself as spirit, and that it is not consciousness of itself as spirit if it is not consciousness of absolute Spirit, short of which the very concept of "spirit" is unintelligible. Thus, when Hegel says, "Spirit is not merely the sort of knowing in which the being of the object is separated from the process of knowing it'' (VPR I, p. 197), one might respond naively by saying, "of course there are no mental objects apart from the mental process of their becoming objects; that is almost a tautology." Or, one might respond even more naivelynot to say crudely"This is just nonsense; it is too obvious that there are any number of objects which exist independently of anyone's knowing them." There is no question in Hegel's mind that "things" exist independently of any individual consciousness or sum total of individual consciousnesses. It is equally clear, however, that no "thing" is an "object" except as object-for consciousness. But, neither of these statements touches what is at issue. What Hegel is saying is that we have not come to grips with "spirit" at all if we treat it merely as a "form"albeit the highest formof consciousness: "Spirit does not exist merely in the manner of a relation, not merely as a form of consciousness" (ibid.). Rather, when we speak of spirit, we recognize that consciousness is "included as a moment in the being of spirit; and this at once implies an affirmative relation of the spirit to absolute Spirit" (ibid). This means, in Hegel's language, that finite spirit is at once different from and identified with absolute Spirit, and this first becomes manifest in religion. Only this identity where, in its object, knowing posits itself for itself, is the spirit, reason which is objectively for itself. Religion is, therefore, a relation of spirit to absolute Spirit; only thus is spirit as that which knows also that which is known. [Ibid.] Identity of Finite and Infinite Spirit It is not, therefore, as though finite spirit stands off from absolute Spirit in knowing it; rather, finite spirit is a manifestation of absolute Spirit knowing itself as the totality of both knowing and the known.
This is not merely a way in which spirit relates itself to absolute Spirit; rather absolute Spirit is itself that which is the self-relating to that which we posited
< previous page
page_132
next page >
< previous page
page_133
next page > Page 133
on the other side as the element of difference. Thus, on a higher plane, religion is the idea of the spirit which relates itself to its own selfthe self-consciousness of absolute Spirit. [Ibid., pp. 19798] The consciousness which finite spirit has of objects as, so to speak, over-against itself is but an aspect of its selfconsciousness, and this self-consciousness is but a facet of the overall self-consciousness of absolute Spirit. Strictly speaking, finite spirit does not have either consciousness of objects or of itself; it is finite manifestation of infinite self-consciousness. Only as identified with absolute Spirit is finite spirit what it itself really is. Consciousness, as such, is finite consciousness, it is the knowledge of what is other than the ego. Religion, too, is consciousness and consequently includes finite consciousness, but superseded as finite; for the other which absolute Spirit knows it itself is, and thus only is it absolute Spirit, i.e., in knowing itself. [Ibid., p. 98] To put all this in another way, the initiative, so to speak, belongs to infinite Spirit, whose self-differentiating in the totality of spiritual activity is the very being of the finite. If it is essential to spirit that it manifest itself, "communicate" itself, it is equally essential that there be an "other" to whom spirit manifests itself. But, if ''absolute Spirit" is a meaningful term at all, its "other" can only be the term of its own "self-othering." As we shall see in the final chapter, "Philosophy and Theology," Hegel understands this in three sensestrinitarian, creational, and incarnationalbut here it is enough to see the principle expressed in its religiousand hence, also philosophicalbearing, without being explicitly theological. The religious consciousness proper to finite spirit is that spirit itself as the self-manifestation of infinite Spirit. The self-consciousness of infinite Spirit is the very being of finite spirit.
The finiteness of consciousness comes in here, since [absolute] Spirit by its own movement differentiates itself. This finite consciousness, however, is a moment of the Spirit itself which is its own selfdifferentiation, self-determination; that is to say, its own self-positing as finite consciousness. By means of this, however, it is mediated only through finite spirit's consciousness in such wise that it has to render itself finite in order to become knowledge of itself by thus rendering itself finite. Thus religion is the divine Spirit's knowledge of itself through the mediation of finite spirit. Accordingly, in the Idea in its highest form, religion is not a transaction of man, but is essentially the supreme determination of the absolute Idea itself. [Ibid., p. 198]
< previous page
page_133
next page >
< previous page
page_134
next page > Page 134
Whatever else this prolonged analysis of an extremely dense and difficult text may tell us, it makes one thing abundantly clear: There is no coming to terms with Hegel's thought which is not a coming-to-grips with his concept of God, who makes sense only as "Spirit." There is no understanding what Hegel has to say of spirit (be it finite or infinite) without understanding what he says of God; but, by the same token, there is no understanding what he says of God without understanding what he says of spirit as such. "The relationship which grounds (das Grundverhältnis) all religion and all philosophy is first of all the relationship of spirit as such to nature and then, that of absolute Spirit to finite spirit" (BS, p. 123). That finite spirit is related to nature needs no elaboration; its very immersion in nature is its finitude. But, it is also related to nature in that it can know nature, work it, and transform it; and all this it can do only becausae as finite spirit it is the expression of absolute Spirit. To be spirit is to be conscious of being spirit; and this is but a truncated consciousness if it is not consciousness of all that spirit is, which it will not be short of knowing absolute Spirit. To many, perhaps most, it may seem supremely arbitrary on Hegel's part to insist that only with the advent of Christianity did it become possible for the human spirit to get this grasp of itself. He is not saying, however, that the grasp is not rational, that the Christian religion in revealing Spirit to spirit superseded human rationality; he is saying that the Christian religion in laying before man a supremely rational content is at the same time laying on human "reason" the onus of working out the rationality of that content. "It is now the task of the world to recognize God as Spirit and to recognize this in [the human] spirit" (EGP, p. 245; my italics). The implications of this last statement are important: The essence of spiritincluding human spiritis activity, which means that the human grasp of divine spirit is activity of the human spirit, and this in turn means that, if what relates the human spirit to the divine is not to be an inadequate substitute, a ''representation" of the latter, the divine must somehow inform the very activity of the human. When man in thinking, then, knows God, there has to be some significant sense in which not only what is known but also the knowing is divine. We have already seen that this is precisely what Hegel says when he speaks of the human spirit thinking God religiously, "the divine Spirit's knowledge of itself through the mediation of finite spirit." It does not seem adequate to interpret this as meaning no more than that God has "created" the human spirit with a capacity to know the divine; it would seem more accurate to say that Hegel looks upon the human spirit as, in some sort of Plotinian way, an offshoot of the divine. This, however, "is a hard saying, and who can bear it?" For a more profound investigation of it we shall have to wait for chapter 6. Here we must be content to note that to say that what the human spirit does in knowing is "analogous" to what the divine Spirit does in knowing is not enough, and that to say the divine and the human
< previous page
page_134
next page >
< previous page
page_135
next page > Page 135
spirit are one and the same is too much. There is an identification, to be sure, but it is a "dialectical" identification, which makes sense only if it is at the same time a differentiation. It might also be noted that terms themselves do not have exactly the same meaning when predicated of the infinite as they do when predicated of the finite. Nowhere, to my knowledge, does Hegel make use of the Scholastic concept of analogia entisnor does he give evidence of being aware of itbut he does say very clearly, as we shall see in the next chapter, that predicates, which in the context of the finite are contradictory, are in the context of the infinite compatible. We might try to approach this whole question from a different angle. Whatever one may think of Hegel's philosophy of religioneven granting that it is far more "philosophy of God" than "philosophy of religion"there can be little question, if we look at the broad lines of his development, that he makes a good case for a progressive development in the religious conception of God. As man moves from a conception of the divine drawn from and rooted in the things of nature, through the progressive attempts to portray the divine in a variety of art forms, all tending to anthropomorphize the divine, until the self-conscious self-revelation of God in the Judaeo-Christian tradition supplants all othersin the West at leastand as this culminates in the self-revelation of God in the form of an individual man, whose "spirit'' subsequently vitalizes the religious community, it can be said that the God man believes in becomes more and more "spiritual." Nor does it demand too much of a concession to agree that parallel with this development of God-consciousness there occurs a growth in man's consciousness of himself as a spiritual being, a progressive recognition that to be human is to be spiritual. Thus, it follows that man's "concept" of God and man's "concept" of man develop hand in hand. That this development bespeaks a closer and closer approach to "the concept" which is itself infinite but includes finite "moments" may well be unpalatable, but it is not illogical. In this connection it has to be admitted that to speak of "a progressive recognition that to be human is to be spiritual" involves a certain degree of fuzziness. The expression "progressive recognition" would seem to describe a process of coming to awareness of what has been true all along rather than spirit's own process of coming to be that which is altogether different from nature. What characterizes spirit, as opposed to things of nature, is that spirit is not simply "given" as what it is; it is the activity of making itself, of, we might say, "progressively realizing itself" as spirit. It is precisely for this reason that in the Encyclopedia Hegel divides the "Philosophy of Spirit" into three parts: (1) "subjective spirit," or man as natural science sees him; (2) "objective spirit," or man as he develops rationally; and (3) "absolute spirit," or man as he comes to the realization of all that it is to be spirit.
< previous page
page_135
next page >
< previous page
page_136
next page > Page 136
Spirit is simply not immediate; natural things are immediate and remain in this condition of immediate being.6 The being of spirit is not thus immediate, but is, exists only as producing itself, as making itself for itself as subject by means of negation; without that it is merely substance. And this coming to itself on the part of spirit is movement, activity, and mediation of itself with itself. [VPR I, pp. 7879] What is important to note here is that in the discovery of spirit, religion and philosophy go hand in hand. What is true of spirit as spirit is true of both divine and human spirit. If Hegel, then, can say, "The absolute is spirit," that "this is the supreme definition of the absolute" (EpW, no. 384), he is saying that what we know of human spirit as spirit enables us to know what we mean when we say "God is Spirit"; ''It may be said that the discovery of this definition and the comprehension of its meaning and content was the ultimate orientation of all culture and philosophy" (ibid.).7 By the same token, however, "Christian religion," by making clear that God is spirit, has thrown light on the otherwise vague notion of human spirit. "Both the term spirit and the notion (Vorstellung) corresponding to the term were discovered early, and it is the purport of the Christian religion to make God known as Spirit. It is the task of philosophy to grasp what is here given presentatively, the essence in itself in its own proper element, the concept" (ibid.). That this is a constant in Hegel's position is borne out abundantly by even a cursory reading of chapter VII of the Phenomenology and of part III of Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion. It is, then, the concept of spirit which makes philosophy intelligible: "The final result of the philosophy of nature and mediately of logic is, therefore, to attain to the proof of the necessity of the concept of spirit" (EpW, no. 381, Zusatz). At the same time it is the philosophical comprehension of spirit which makes religion intelligible. God is more than living; he is Spirit. Spiritual nature alone is the worthiest and truest point of departure for thinking the absoluteif, that is, thinking does seek a starting point and wants what is at hand. [EpW, no. 50]
6. This remark could be interpreted as flowing from Hegel's denial of biological evolution. Although there is little evidence that Hegel affirmed biological evolution, there is no greater evidence that he denied it. But, that is not the point here at all. Whatever may be true of organic growth, it is still toto coelo different from spiritual development. Natural organisms (individuals) are what they are, and their growth process does not change that; whereas spirit (individual) is itself process, a self-producing process. 7. "Culture" (Bildung), as Hegel sees it, is the mode of self-development characteristic of the human spirit in its history. This might be called the overriding theme of his Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte.
< previous page
page_136
next page >
< previous page
page_137
next page > Page 137
Self-Manifestation Essential to Spirit What we have seen so far of Hegel's thought regarding the concept of spirit and of the being of God as Spirit may well be controversial in the minds of those who reject either the reality of God or the reality of spiritor both. It may even be unpalatable to those who are religious and who feel that philosophy should be more humble and make no claim to know what must be said of God. It is doubtful, however, whether anything we have seen can be construed as unequivocally opposed to religion, or to the Christian religion in particular. But when it comes to the next point, which, Hegel is convinced, his "speculative" meditation on the "concept" of spirit makes clear to him, he unquestionably becomes controversial, precisely in religious circles. It is essential to spirit, he tells us, that it be self-manifestation, and, since this belongs to the very ''concept" of spirit, it must be said of divine Spirit, too, since what is essentially true of spirit must be said of the divine as well as of the human. This has given rise to the accusation that, for Hegel, the existence of finite spirits to whom God makes himself manifest is necessary to the very being of God as Spirit. We shall have occasion to go into this contention in more detail in chapters 6 and 7, but it does seem necessary here to at least air the difficulty. This is what spirit is: self-manifestation, to be for spirit. Spirit is for spirit, and not, be it observed, only in an external, contingent manner. On the contrary, spirit is spirit only insofar as it is for spirit; this constitutes the very concept of spirit. Or, to express it more theologically, God is essentially Spirit, so far as he is in his church. It has been said that the world, the material universe, must have spectators, must be for spirithow much more, then, must God be for spirit. [VPR I, pp. 5253] He puts the same more succinctly when he says, "God must appear . . .; since essence as such must appear; it is not if it does not appear" (WG, p. 580). On the face of it this could seem to be saying that the very being of God as Spirit demands other spirits to whom God appears. We have need of caution, however, before we jump to this conclusion. Hegel does, indeed, say that "God is Spirit," that it is essential to spirit to be "for spirit," and that what is essential to spirit as such is essential to "divine Spirit" as well. But, what he does not say is that what is essential to spirit is to be said in exactly the same way of infinite Spirit and of finite spirit.8 It is certainly safe to say that, for Hegel, a solitary finite spirit does not make sense; the necessity of its communicating itself demands that there be other finite
8. Once again, one wonders if Hegel is not very much aware of the analogia entisor at least of the analogy of predicationwhether he uses the term or not.
< previous page
page_137
next page >
< previous page
page_138
next page > Page 138
spirits "for whom" it is; a solitary finite spirit would not be spirit. Still, whatever other reasons we may have for contending that Hegel means this to apply also to God, it is not part of his thesis here that God needs "other" spirits to whom he can appear. As spirit, God must be "for spirit"; but Hegel does not say that the spirit ''for whom" God is is necessarily "other." Theunissen puts this well in his commentary on no. 564 of the Encyclopediawhich takes up in its essentials the text we are examining. According to Theunissen, one might wish to argue that Hegel does hold for the necessity of finite spirits, but one is not justified in stating this as a consequence of what he is saying in the present context. That is forbidden precisely by the fact that this thesis belongs to the thoughts he has just been unfolding regarding revelation. For, if the manifestation in question begins with God's internal self-objectification, then the Spirit to whose being it belongs to-be-for in no way needs to be different from the Spirit for whom he is. Absolute Spirit, then, does not necessarily require finite spirit for its own being. To put it positively the statement can be and must also mean: Absolute Spirit is spirit only insofar as it is for itself.9 The point is one that Hegel had made much earlier in the Encyclopedia: that it is only in thought and as thought, that spiritual being, including that of God, can make sense. God, then, can be object of thought and thought alone, which does not mean that there must be finite thought, if God is to be; rather it means that if God is to be for finite spirit, he must be for finite spirit as thinking. This content, God himself, is in its truth only in thinking (Denken) and as thinking (Denken). In this sense, then, the thought (Gedanke) is not simply mere thought (Gedanke); rather it is the highest and, accurately speaking, the sole way in which the Eternal which is in and for itself can be grasped. [EpW, no. 19, Zusatz 2] It is precisely this which enables Hegel to say that logic is oriented to God: only if God is can there be logic, which is quite obviously not to say that only if logic is can there be God. What this says further is that only a thinking which has completely freed itself from every trace of the sensibility proper to nature can come to grips with God who is Spirit and only Spirit. "Only through this contemplation of God's being as thoroughly spiritual and imageless, over against the mundane and natural, is the spiritual [said of God] completely wrenched away from natural sensibility and freed from finite existence" (VA I, p. 478). Hegel does, nevertheless, say that the human spirit,
9. Michael Theunissen, Hegels Lehre vom absoluten Geist als theologisch-politischer Traktat (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1970), p. 221.
< previous page
page_138
next page >
< previous page
page_139
next page > Page 139
finite as it is, is capax Deiby virtue of the "reason" which characterizes this spirit, reason which is the "divine" dimension in the human. If, then, Hegel speaks of the relationship of man to God as a "oneness" of spirit, or of "reason," we must be careful not to think that he is simply erasing all distinction between the human and the divine. From a purely formallogical point of view we might be tempted to look upon ''spirit" (or "reason") as a purely abstract universal, subsuming both the divine and the human in its scope. This, however, is exactly what Hegel is careful not to say. That is one reason why he is nervous about characterizing God as "supreme being"or whatever other expression one wants to employ, which would modify a noun with an adjective that would simply make the being in question a one of manyeven "supreme" among the many. To say, on the other hand, that God is "absolute Spirit" is to indicate that God is absolutely all that spirit isthe "concrete universal"and that whatever other "spirit" there is is so only in relationship to the all-embracing Absolute. It is for this reason that Christianity, because it truly represents in spirit God as Spirit, and not as an individual, particular spirit, but as absolute, returns from the sensibility proper to representation to spiritual interiority, making this and not the corporeal the matter and reality (Dasein) of its content. By the same token the oneness of the human and divine nature is a oneness which is known and which is to be realized only through spiritual knowing in spirit. [VA I, p. 112] To say, then, that God is "Spirit" and that man is "spirit" is not to achieve oneness by a suppression of difference in abstraction; it is to see the concrete oneness of God embracing in its wholeness the manyness of the human. There cannot be two kinds of reason and two kinds of spirit, not a divine reason and a human, not a divine Spirit and a human, which would be absolutely different. Human reason, the consciousness of one's essence is indeed reason; it is the divine in man, and spirit, insofar as it is the Spirit of God, is not a spirit beyond the stars, beyond the world. On the contrary, God is present, omnipresent, and as Spirit is present in all spirits. (VPR I, p. 40] What can, of course, be difficult to see in this sort of "oneness" of the human and the divine, the finite and the infinite, is how the human can succeed in not being swallowed up in the divine, the finite in the infiniteif, indeed, the problem does not turn out to be the reverse! If the human spirit is to be truly spirit it must be self-determining, free; it must be the product of its own activity; its concepts must be its own, even its concept of God. How can the relationship of the human spirit to the divine be "absolutely free,"
< previous page
page_139
next page >
< previous page
page_140
next page > Page 140
as Hegel claims it must be? An initial answer to this question would be that being finite, in the sense of cut off from and independent of infinite Spirit, is by no means a condition of being free, self-determining. On the contrary, being cut off from infinite Spirit, infinite Reason, is tantamount to being determined from without by an "infinity" of finite factors in human existence and, thus, not to be free, except perhaps in the sense that a freelyfalling body is called "free." To be bound to the rational is to be freed from the multitude of nonrational constraints on the self-determination of finite spirit. We see this clearly enough in the moral order: that spirit is not free which is subject to all the whims of arbitrariness; only that spirit is free which can stick to the narrow path of rationality. Rationality, however, is not a private affair; there is not one rationality for one man, another for another; a condition for the freedom of both is that they accord with the objectivity of rationality. If, then, divine infinite Spirit, divine infinite Reason, is integral Spirit, integral Reason, to be in accord with it is to be rational, or free; to be out of step with it is to be unfree. The human spirit is not automatically free; it is free only to the extent that its "principle" is the "absolutely'' free Spirit which pervades it. One can romantically glorify the "free spirit" of the pagan Greeks, but, says Hegel, theirs was but a truncated freedom; "still, neither in philosophy nor in religion did they attain to cognition of the absolute infinity of spirit; thus among them the relationship of the human spirit to the divine is still not absolutely free" (EpW, no. 377, Zusatz). The adequate principle of free subjectivity becomes manifest only in Christianity with its doctrine of the entry of divine Spirit into the finitude of history. "It was Christianity, through the doctrine of the incarnation of God and of the presence of the Holy Spirit in the communion of believers, which first gave human consciousness a completely free relation to the infinite, and thus made possible the conceptual cognition of spirit in its absolute infinity" (ibid.). One way to put this would be to say that to know man adequately, as spirit, is to know God; another would be to say that short of a knowledge of God it is impossible to know man adequately, as spirit. In Science of Logic, as we shall see in chapter 4, Hegel quite clearly states that to conceive "being" without knowing it as "infinite" is not to comprehend being. Here he is telling us that to conceive "spirit" without knowing it as infinite is not to comprehend spirit, not to know just what spirit is. It is precisely for this reason that he considers the greatest dignity of man to be not that man can know the world of nature, and control it and transform italthough this, too, is important and is the work of spiritbut to pass beyond nature, both man's own sensuous nature and the mere naturalness of initial objects of consciousness, to the Spirit which transcends not only nature but all that is finite.
< previous page
page_140
next page >
< previous page
page_141
next page > Page 141
Spirit takes indeed its beginning from nature. [But] one should not think merely of external nature; to nature belongs also the sensuous nature of man himself, his sensuous, bodily being . . . . The extreme to which spirit tends is its freedom, its infinity, its being in and for itself. These are the two aspects, but if we ask what spirit is, the immediate answer is that it is this motion, this process, this activity of emerging, of freeing itself from nature; this is the being, the substance of spirit itself. [Ibid.]10 There is a risk, of course, in employing this kind of languagethe risk of seeing only the unity of the human and the divine, the finite and the infinite, without seeing the distinction, the difference. The point, as Hegel sees it, is that the difference is not that God is spirit and man other than spirit, or that man is spirit and God some vague, indeterminate, "supreme being," in one sense "infinitely" removed from the human, but in another sense a being, distinguished from the finite by being other, that is, infinite, and thus, effectively limited by not being what the finite is. A condition for knowing what God is is to know what spirit is, but a condition for knowing what spirit is is to know man as spirit, just as a condition for knowing all that spirit is is to know spirit as infinite, that is, to know God. The unity of spirit, then, must not be seen as the absorption of two different ''spirits," divine and human, under one categorial heading, "spirit." Ratherand here Christian "religion" comes in againman, finite spirit, is to be seen as a finite "moment" of the infinite divine Spirit, who is God. This will have to be spelled out more fully in chapters 4 and 6. Thus finite spirit is itself posited as a moment of God. Man himself, therefore, is comprehended in the concept of God, and this comprehension may be thus expressedthat the unity of man with God is posited in the Christian religion. But this union must not be superficially conceived, as if God were merely man, and man were likewise God. Rather, man is God only to the extent that he transcends the naturality and finitude of his spirit and elevates himself to God. [VPG, p. 392] Activity Without Passivity We can, perhaps, come closer to a comprehension of what Hegel is saying here, if we can conceive of spirit as a reality whose whole being is to be "activity," an activity which, because it contains in itself no passivity, no beingacted-upon, no mere "re-activity," produces only itself. Aristotle, in an effort to explain the activity of thinking as "pure activity," draws an
10. This addition, which comes from the carefully prepared notes of Major von Griesheim (1825), is contained in M. J. Petry, Hegel's Philosophy of Subjective Spirit, vol. I (Boston: Reidel, 1978). It is not contained in the Suhrkamp edition.
< previous page
page_141
next page >
< previous page
page_142
next page > Page 142
analogy from the physical activity of "seeing," which is productive only of itselfthe activity and the term of the activity are one and same, that is, "seeing." As an illustration of "spiritual" activity the analogy may limp, but it does get a point across: there is an activity which does not consist in ''acting-on" something, and "spiritual" activity is precisely that. Human self-activity is not synonymous with divine self-activity, but each is revelatory of the other, and to know one is to know the other; they are united in being "self-activity"; the self-activity of the human is a "godly" self-activity. To put it another way: The self-activity which constitutes finite spirit is finite activity, but it is oriented to transcending limitation, because nothing outside itself is a limitation to it. This is best exemplified in thought, which, as Hegel sees it, is an acting involving no being-acted-upon; the "thinking" subject "produces" its own thinking, no being other than the subject produces the thinking. On the other hand, there are subjective "activities" which are not so completely self-determining. Things do act on subjects and produce an immediate response; for example, sensation, feeling, and even willing, which looks to producing what is other than the activity itself. "Only thinking is the sphere in which all alien influence has disappeared, with the result that the spirit is absolutely free [self-determined], with itself" (EGP, p. 111). When thinking produces thought it produces no "other" over-against itself; whatever "otherness" there is is its own "self-othering." "Furthermore, when objects of a subjective kind are present, that is, in spirit alone and not as external sensuous objects, then we know that in spirit there is only what its own activity has produced" (VA I, p. 41). Among other things this means that the highest form of knowing is self-knowing, because in it spirit is fully aware of itself as productive of itself in its activity. Nothing external to it produces knowledge in it, least of all its self-knowledge, which is what knowledge, ultimately, is. "It was noted above in reference to the essence of spirit that its being is its doing. . . . More precisely, its doing is its selfknowing" (EGP, p. 36). The human individual, it is true, is a "vital organism," but that is not its being as spirit: "I am as spirit only insofar as I know myself" (ibid.). This is what it is to be self-productive; spirit is what it is in knowing itself for what it is. This is what Hegel means when, with regard to spirit, he speaks of "freedom." Sometimes the expression he uses is "self-determination," sometimes it is "freedom"; the terms may or may not be synonymous, but what he is speaking of is the same: Spirit finds the resources for its own dynamic being in itself, but only in its knowing itself as source of itself are these resources activated. "Quite simply, we can call the highest content which the subjective can find in itself freedom. Freedom is the supreme characteristic of spirit" (VA I, p. 134). Initially all this means is that the "subject" does not find in its "object" something alien to itself; it finds
< previous page
page_142
next page >
< previous page
page_143
next page > Page 143
itself constituting the objectivity of its object, which is not an object imposed on it from something outside itself. "On the basis of even this formal characterization . . . the subject is reconciled with the world, satisfied with it, and every opposition or contradiction is resolved" (ibid.). This is not denying that there are impulses from without which affect the body; it does deny that these corporeal impulses work on spirit; the latter, in transforming these impulses, gives itself its own content. In the characterization of spirit as self-active which we have just seen, it is not difficult to detect the direction in which Hegel is moving. He is gradually building up to the characterization of "absolute Spirit" as "infinite" selfactivity (self-determination, freedom), upon whose intelligibility the intelligibility of self-active finite spirit is dependent. How the relationship between infinite self-activity and finite self-activity is to be characterized remains to be seen, but it is legitimate to anticipate that if each is the "self-manifestation" of spirit, the finite will be dependent on the infinite, or, to put it in more Hegelian language, the infinite will be inclusive of the finite. Nor is it difficult to see that this bespeaks some sort of infinitizing of the finite. Because, however, spirit contains no determination which it would not know to have been posited by itself, and which therefore spirit could itself supersede, it endures the contradiction of objectivity and subjectivity. This power over the whole content present in it constitutes the basis of spirit's freedom. . . . The whole development of the concept of spirit simply exhibits the manner in which spirit frees itself from all forms of its determinate being which do not correspond to its concept. The liberation is accomplished in that these forms are transformed into an actuality entirely adequate to the concept of spirit. [EpW, no. 382, Zusatz] To speak of the "concept" of spirit, however, is not to speak of this or that finite instantiation of it. It is to understand even finite spirit as significant only to the extent that it expresses the "infinity" proper to the concept, "spirit." This universality is also its determinate being. As being for itself the universal particularizes itself in that it has being-for-self and is, thus, constituted self-identical. The determinateness of spirit is therefore manifestation. Spirit is not a certain determinateness or content, the expression or exteriority of which is merely a distinct form of it. Rather than revealing something therefore, its determinate content is itself this revelation. Its possibility is therefore immediately infinite, absolute actuality. [Ibid., no. 383] Finite spirit, then, without ceasing to be finite is the self-manifestation of infinite Spirit. That this has to be called, in some sense at least, an "in
< previous page
page_143
next page >
< previous page
page_144
next page > Page 144
finitizing of the finite" seems clear enough. We must now try to see whether this makes sense without some sort of concomitant "finitizing of the infinite." If, however, we are to understand what this can possibly mean, we must recall very emphatically that, for Hegel, spirit as such is process, and more precisely, the process of coming to consciousness of self. Now, all process is made up of "moments," which is to say, dynamic elements constituting in their totality a dynamic whole. On the level of the development of human consciousness, whether it be that of the individual or human consciousness as a whole, it is not too difficult to see what this means: Hegel has delineated it masterfully in Phenomenology of Spirit. The "moments" in the process constitute a series of ''forms" (Gestalten) of consciousnessultimately recognized as "forms" of spiriteach of which both makes a contribution to the ongoing process and reveals its own inadequacy if taken as a stopping point in the process. Thus, each of the "forms"in their character as "moments"must be aufgehoben, in the triple sense of "canceled" (the inadequacy), "retained" (the positive contribution), and "lifted up" (the succeeding level), until they all come to rest (to coin a phrase, "dynamic rest") in the completeness of the "absolute"here "absolute knowing." If it belongs to the "concept" of spirit, however, to be "process," then even "absolute, infinite, divine Spirit" must be process and, thus, must be made up of "moments." But, there are no "infinite moments"; that would be a contradiction. The "moments" of infinite Spirit, then, are finite. Two things are to be noted here: (1) the "moments" are moments only as moments-of the process; and (2) the "moments" of "infinite" process cannot come to it from without; they must be its own doing. If there are "moments"which means "differentiation"in the process which is "absolute Spirit," then, they must be the "moments" of its own "self-differentiation." The model, obviously, is taken from Hegel's own "Trinitarian" theology, which, as we shall see in chapter 7, is continuous with his theology of creation and Incarnation, but here we can confine ourselves to his philosophical view of what constitutes "absolute Spirit." The process of "consciousness" is that of coming to be "spirit," and the process of spirit is that of coming to be aware of what it is to be spirita coming-to-be which "points to" completeness only in absolute Spirit, where "consciousnes . . . experiences the joy of finding itself therein and becomes aware of the reconciliation of its individuality with the universal" (PdG, p. 160)finite spirit is spirit at all only because as "process" it is continuous with infinite Spirit, whose manifestation it is. But the "finding itself" takes place only because the "reconciliation" is the doing of the "universal." In the words of R. Williamson:
However, the dialectical process is not just the coming to this recognition by individual consciousness, for the life and movementthe total processof all
< previous page
page_144
next page >
< previous page
page_145
next page > Page 145
reality is also the self-manifestation or unfolding of, and the coming to fulfillment of, Absolute Spirit. It is only because this is so, in Hegel's view, that the individual has any reality: the finite individual has reality only as a "moment" of the infinite universal; but conversely, the Universal or Absolute Spirit has reality only in and through finite particulars which are the concretization and self-manifestation of the Universal, and which are therefore stages or moments in the coming to self-knowledge and self-actualization of the Absolute.11 It might seem, of course, unjustifiable to confine what Hegel says of the self-manifestation of the Absolute in the totality of finite realitynature and spiritto self-manifestation in the human spirit. We must remember, however, that because Hegel finds the very "essence," the "truth," of nature only in spirit"as what it essentially is nature exists in spirit" (JR I, p. 191)he can still hold that the ''external" manifestation of absolute Spirit is contained "essentially" in finite spirit. With that nature has made the transition to its truth, into the subjectivity of concept, the objectivity of which is itself the transcended immediacy of singularity, i.e., concrete universality. The result is that there is posited that concept, which has as its determinate being the reality corresponding to it, i.e., the Conceptand this is spirit. [EpW, no. 376] More than that, we must also remember that Hegel takes as his point of departure Christian religious consciousness, according to which the most significant locus of divine self-manifestation is the human spirit, since only in human spirit is God known as spirit (VA I, p. 106). Granted that Hegel is talking about the Incarnation here and not about any and every human being as "image" of God, still he is talking about man as the exclusively fitting locus of incarnation, for the reason given. It is not merely that no other finite reality can know Goda too-obvious truth to need emphasizingbut that the very being of finite spirit is to be existential term of God's self-knowing. Only Spirit Knows Spirit Sometimes, admittedly, it is difficult to know when Hegel is speaking theologically, in the sense of explicating rationally what to faith is "given," and when he is speaking purely philosophically, in the sense of working out what reason demands, without employing religious teaching as a starting point. This is particularly true when he speaks on the one hand of "pure"
11. Raymond K. Williamsom, "Hegel's Philosophy of Religion" (Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Newcastle. New South Wales, Australia, 1979), p. 136.
< previous page
page_145
next page >
< previous page
page_146
next page > Page 146
spirit, which, because there is in it no admixture of what is not spirit, is "absolute" and on the other hand of spirit incarnate in nature, which, precisely because it is incarnate and therefore multiple, is finite. We shall see, however, in chapter 7, that he does make a very clear distinction between the theological doctrine of the Incarnation, where the divine Spirit takes on human form in an individual and yet remains "with itself" and therefore infinite, and the philosophical contention that the spirit which is spirit only is absolute, infinite, while the spirit which is immersed in nature is finite, even though it somehow shares the infinity of absolute Spirit. What is important from this second point of view is that it takes spirit to recognize spirit and that, therefore, only because man is spirit, even though finite, can he both recognize divine Spirit and affirm that only absolute, infinite Spirit can be divine. Nor could man do this if he could not see rationally that the very concept of spirit can make no sense if there is not absolute Spirit. Our experience is such that we can "think" spirit at all only because we are confronted with a human "nature" which is also "spiritual," the paradigm of which is the divine Spirit incarnate. ''Only with the advent of the self-certain, interior spirit [the God-man] can human spirit bear to dispense with the phenomenal side and have the assurance to assign the divine nature to an individual" (VPG, pp. 305306). But precisely because we can thus "think" Spirit can thought rise to spirit not immersed in nature. This spirit, then, no longer needs to insert the natural into the realm of the spiritual, in order to hold fast its conception of the divine, and to have the unity of the divine externally visible. Rather since free thought thinks the external, it can leave the latter as it is; for it also thinks this unification of the finite and the infinite, and recognizes that it is not a mere accidental union but, as the Absolute, is the eternal Idea itself. [Ibid., p. 306] So far, of course, even those who disagree with Hegel can recognize a certain cogency in his reasoning. But when the capacity which the finite human spirit has to "rise" to the infinite is described as a "being-lifted-up" (Erhebung), which in turn is possible only because finite spirit is an expression of the infinite's "selfdifferentiation," thus making the "union of finite and infinite," so to speak, a doing of infinite Spirit, then a long line of thinkers, beginning with Feuerbach and Marx, sees in this an attack on the autonomy of the human, to say nothing of an unwarranted introduction of "theology" into philosophy. At this point we can withhold any judgment as to the justification of the objection; before all else we must try to understand just what Hegel is saying. As he sees it, there are two points of view from which the question can be approachedfrom the point of view of "finitude" or from that of "infinity." Both approaches require us to do
< previous page
page_146
next page >
< previous page
page_147
next page > Page 147
minor violence to linguistic propriety by interpreting "finite" as "noninfinite" rather than interpreting ''infinite" as "nonfinite." Here, it would seem, Hegel stands on fairly solid ground: There is little likelihood at all that the term "nonfinite" by itself will yield any intelligible sense at all; there is a better chance that "noninfinite" will say something worth saying. "Spirit looks upon finitude as the negative of itself and thus attains to its own infinity. This truth of finite spirit is absolute Spirit" (VA I, p. 130). Here we are on familiar enough ground; finite spirit in trying to come to grips with its own finitude finds itself positing infinity as a prerequisite to its own intelligibility. "In this form, however, spirit is actual only as absolute negativity; it posits within itself its own finitude and transcends it" (ibid.). In so doing it starts from itself precisely as finite: "at its highest level it makes itself the object (Gegenstand) of its own knowing and willing" (ibid.). This points it in the direction of the Absolute: "The Absolute itself becomes the object (Objekt) of the spirit, because the latter takes its stand on the level of consciousness and distinguishes itself as knowing from itself as the opposite of that, i.e., as absolute object (Gegenstand)" (ibid.). Finite spirit, then, simply characterizes itself as finite over-against the infinite, finding its own intelligibility simply in its own distinction from the infinite. "From this previous point of view of the finitude of spirit, the spirit which knows about the Absolute as an infinite object (Objekt) over-against itself is by this very fact characterized as the finite distinguished from the infinite" (ibid.). It should be noted that Hegel is not saying that this approach is untrue, merely that it is too negative, too onesided, too separatistic, in short, too much on the level of understanding. The "speculative" approach is higher and more fruitful. It is the self-differentiation of infinite Spirit in knowing itself which makes the finite intelligible. From the higher speculative point of view, however, it is absolute Spirit itself which, in order to be for itself the knowing of itself, differentiates itself within itself and, thus, posits the finitude of spirit, and in this finitude becomes absolute object (Gegenstand) of its own knowing. [Ibid.] We are back, once again, with the notion of finite spirit as a "moment" of absolute Spirit. "The finitude of spirit, however, should not in fact be regarded as a fixed determination; it has to be recognized as a mere moment" (Ep W, no. 386, Zusatz). In this sense it is true enough to say that the Absolute is "the negatedness of that which is finite," which is to say that what constitutes spirit essentially is infinity, not finitude; "the quality proper to spirit then is rather true infinity" (ibid.). The finite is, so to speak, derivative of and included in the infinite. "Spirit as spirit is not finite, but has finitude within itself, although only as that which is to be superseded and has been superseded" (ibid.). This means that "finite spirit" is simply
< previous page
page_147
next page >
< previous page
page_148
next page > Page 148
inadequate to the concept of spirit (ibid.). But precisely because finite spirit is not an independent other, "outside God himself," it is also true to say "that in its character as otherness it does not hinder unity with God; otherness, the negation, is consciously known to be a momemt of the divine nature" (VPR II, p. 297). It would be a mistake, however, to think that "self-othering," positing its object out of its own resources and thus remaining with itself in its other, is a prerogative of divine Spirit alone. "The only real antithesis that spirit can have is itself spiritual: its inherent heterogeneity, through which alone it acquires the power of being as spirit" (VPR II, p. 278). Whatever is for spirit must be spiritual; an alien content is content only as spiritualized. That this is characteristic of spirit as spirit is something which the human spirit discovers by looking into itself. What it also discovers by taking a long, hard look at itself is that its own self-othering will be meaningless if spirit is not "essentially'' infinite and, therefore, that what is true of the human is true only because it is first true of the divine. Once more, it would seem, we are confronted with a Hegel who takes his cue in speaking of spirit from Christian theological thinking regarding God. That he considers the identification of identity and distinction in the infiniteand only in the infiniteto be a "rational" principle is clear enough; but that he finds the model for this principle antecedently in the Christian "dogma" of identity and distinction in the triune God seems equally clear. That, in Christian theological language, "identity" comes under the rubric of "nature" or "substance," and "distinction," under the rubric of "persons" would seem to be due to the limitations of a language tied to Vorstellungen, which Hegel seeks to translate into "speculative" language, but that does not obscure the theological parentage of what he says. By the same token, the notion of "identity"without synonymityof divine "attributes" is of theological provenance. Here, however, as we shall see in chapter 7, Hegel replaces "attributes" by "predicates," since it is not a question of what is "attributed" to God by struggling finite thought, but rather what God "says" of himself in his activity as infinite Spiritthus doing what spirit as such must do, that is, speak of itself. "But spirit must have opposition; the principle of dualism belongs therefore to the very concept of spirit, which, in its concrete form, finds distinction essential to it" (VPG, p. 222). What the "concept" of spirit "essentially" demands is derived concomitantly from a philosophical consideration of human spirit and a theological consideration of divine Spirit, "and this point is important, since the divine as such has to be conceived of as Spirit; which involves its being concrete and having in it the moment of negativity (ibid., p. 240).
< previous page
page_148
next page >
< previous page
page_149
next page > Page 149
Relation of Divine Spirit to the World Christian theologians, who take the Christian doctrine of the Trinity seriously, should have no difficulty in going along with Hegel this far. When, however, he carries this principle of identity in distinction over to the relationship (Verhältnis) of God to the world, even to the extent of saying that God can be "thought of" only as related to the world, many a theologian will balk. "It is imperative that God be thought in relation to the world, to man, insofar as God is a living God. This relationship to the world, then, is relation to another, and thus distinction, determination is posited" (VGP II, p. 416). We already know that Hegel sees that only as related to God is the world intelligibleto us. What needs nuancing, however, is the character of "otherness" in the world to which God is conceived of as related. "The relationship to the world, then, appears initially to be relationship to another which is outside God; but, because it is God's relationship, his activity, then this having a relationship in himself is a moment of God himself" (ibid.). Relationship to the world, yes, but it is God determining himself as so related, and the relationship is internal to God. "The connection between God and the world is determination in God himself. In other words the otherness of the one, the duality, the negative, in short (äberhaupt) determination, is essentially moment, which is to be thought of in God'' (ibid.). Only at the risk of conceiving an abstract God can this selfdetermination be thought away. "In himself God is concrete, opening himself outward and, thus, as positing distinct determinations in himself" (ibid.). The very notion of "creation" becomes a self-determining of God, a relationship which is proper to God in himself, the only explanation Hegel can see of the reality of the finite. This differentiation within himself is the point of connection between him who is in-and-for-himself and man, the mundane. We say, God created man, created the world. This is a determination in God himself, and this determination is first of all self-determinationand this determination is the starting point of the finite. The point of God's self-differentiation is the point of mediation between the finite, the mundane and God; and so the former begins within the latter. The source of the difference is that God differentiates himself within himself; and this is his concrete nature. [Ibid.] Finite reality, then, is, but its being is not to be independent, so to speak, "alongside" God; to speak of God "and" the world is simply misleading. It makes no more sense to speak of an independently existing world than it does to speak of God as vague, indeterminate "substance." "Subjectivity is the infinite form, and as such it no more leaves to form which is not free, that is to say external naturalness, any independent existence alongside of it,
< previous page
page_149
next page >
< previous page
page_150
next page > Page 150
than it does to empty, pure, undetermined substantiality" (VPR II, p. 10). If we were to speak of God "and" the world as some sort of irreducible duality, it is difficult to see how we should not be positing a world which sets limits to God. In an effort to explain, then, how "absolute Spirit" can be at once absolutely self-contained, which is a condition for being "spirit" and not some natural agent producing an effect outside itself totally distinct from itself, and the source of all finite reality, which is a condition for being "absolute," Hegel has recourse to the concept of spirit as activity whose term is both other and not other than itself. Absolute Spirit comprehends itself as itself positing being, as itself its other, bringing forth nature and finite spirit, such that this other loses every appearance of being independent of it, ceases completely to limit it, and appears merely as the means by which spirit achieves absolute being-for-self, the Absolute unity of its being-in-itself and being-for-self, of its concept and its actuality. [Ep W, no. 384, Zusatz] But to say "absolute Spirit" is more than to say simply "spirit"; "absolute" must be an intelligible, positive determination of Spirit, raising it essentially above the level of finiteness. "If we wish to indicate what the absolute Idea is in its true actuality, then we must say that it is spirit. More than that, we must say that it is not spirit, so to speak, in its limitation and confinement, but rather universal infinite and absolute Spirit, which from within itself determines what in truth is the true" (VA I, p. 128). Quite obviously, however, we cannot even speak of "absolute Spirit,'' if we confine ourselves to the way we "represent" spirit to ourselves on the basis of our experience either of ourselves or of those with whom we are in communion. "If we consult only our ordinary consciousness, then of course the notion (Vorstellung) of spirit which forces itself upon us is as though it were spirit over-against nature, a nature to which we then ascribe equal dignity" (ibid.).12 Hegel is, clearly, the archenemy of all mere "naturalism," even a mitigated kind which accords to nature an independence of spirit and at the same time accords to spirit a superiority. "Still, to consider nature and spirit as equally essential spheres connected with each other is to consider spirit merely in its finiteness and confinement, not in its infinity and truth" (ibid.). Nature simply is not a limit to absolute Spirit set outside spirit. "In relation to absolute Spirit, it should be noted, nature neither possesses equal dignity nor is it posited in such a way as to be a product, which would give it the power to be a limit or a barrier" (ibid.). We must try to come to grips
12. Precisely what Feuerbach and Marx, in their opposition to Hegel, insisted on doingand, quite consistently, since in denying infinite Spirit, they are equivalently denying finite spirit any ontological superiority over nature.
< previous page
page_150
next page >
< previous page
page_151
next page > Page 151
with absolute Spirit as the absolute activity of self-differentiation. "At the same time absolute Spirit is to be apprehended simply as absolute activity and, thus, as the absolute differentiation of itself within itself" (ibid.). Although, then, we go nowhere if we do not begin with spirit as it first presents itself, we are mistaken if we simply stop there. "The supreme definition of the absolute is not that it is spirit in general, but that it is the Spirit absolutely manifest to itself, absolutely self-conscious, the infinitely creative Spirit we have just indicated" (Ep W, no. 384, Zusatz). Our purpose in all that has been said up to this point is to show that, in Hegel's view, there is only one way to conceive the "Absolute," whether it be "Idea" or "God," and that is as ''Spirit." Gradually it has been becoming evident that, for Hegel, our conceiving the absolute as Spirit and God's revelation of himself as Spirit is one and the same "process" whose "moments" are being delineated. One way of understanding this, and perhaps the most common, is to see God, the creator, revealing himself to man, the spiritual creature, through the workings of "nature," behind which the human mind can see the necessity of an infinite source, without whom the very existence of an intrinsically oriented nature would be inconceivable. It is the attitude summed up in the words of Joyce Kilmer: Poems are made by fools like me, But only God can make a tree. The world in which we live presents to our experience two kinds of external reality which we readily distinguish, the things of nature and the works of human ingenuity. When these two types of reality are distinguished from each other, the palm is given to nature as revelatory of its divine source; what is made by man is revelatory of the human. That man has the ingenuity to transform nature into the useful, the pleasant, the beautiful, is, of course, a cause of great wonderment and deep satisfaction, but it is precisely that which man cannot maketrees, mountains, stars, human nature itselfwhich lifts the human mind to a contemplation of the Being who is beyond nature. Hegel's attitude, however, is the diametric opposite of this. This is not to say that Hegel downgrades nature in the hierarchy of divine self-revelation, but that he upgrades the activity of the human spirit. It is as though he were borrowing the medieval distinction between the things of nature as "traces" of God (vestigia Dei) and the human spirit as the "image" of God (imago Dei). His emphasis, however, is not on "things," whether natural or spiritual, but on "activities." "Things" are not revelatory of God at all; only "activities" are, precisely because they are revelatory of the Being who is "pure activity"without shadow of passivityand on the scale of activity
< previous page
page_151
next page >
< previous page
page_152
next page > Page 152
the "spiritual" stands higher than the "natural" because it is closer to the "pure." Spirit, and spirit alone, can do what nature cannot; spirit not only can make its source known by mirroring him forth to another, but it can also "comprehend" its source by looking into the activities of finite spirit where absolute Spirit is more fully revealed than in the activities of finite nature. Hegel is clearly coming out on the side of ''theism," for whom God is a personal, self-conscious "subject," over-against "deism," for whom God is no more than an impersonal, unconscious "substance"a "force." It is not that God is not active in nature, but that he is more manifestly active in spirit, because only spiritual activity is itself somehow divine. It is easy enough, Hegel tells us, to look upon nature as the product of divine activity and thus as a manifestation of the infinite, while looking upon the products of human ingenuity as issuing from an essentially finite activity and, hence, less significant in manifesting God. But this is a mistake. Of course God is active in nature, but he is even more manifestly active in the activity of finite spirit. In contrasting the production of nature as divine creation with human activity as merely finite one has begun with a misunderstanding, as though God did not act in and through man, as though the sphere of divine activity were confined to nature. [VA I, p. 49] "Only God can make a tree," and the vital activity of the tree tells us that. But, only God can "make" a human being, and the spiritual activity of the human tells us that even more clearly. Trees produce apples, and men produce poemsand producing the latter tells us more about God than does the former, because the producing is spiritual activity. God is more honored in what spirit effects than in the products and structures of nature. For not only is there the divine in man, but in man the divine is active in a form which in a completely other, higher way than nature, is in accord with the essence of God. [Ibid.] God as spirit finds a more significant echo in self-conscious finite spirit than in unconscious finite nature. "God is Spirit, and in man alone has the vehicle through which the divine emerges the form of conscious, actively selfproductive spirit" (ibid.)and this simply cannot be said of nature; man is "image" in a way that nature cannot be. "Spirit conceived (vorgestellt) truly is simply that which comprehends itself" (EGP, p. 176). What is most significant in this is that, by revealing himself to man, God not merely lifts man above nature but also lifts man above his own finitude; to "know" God is to be in a very special way the "image" of Godknow
< previous page
page_152
next page >
< previous page
page_153
next page > Page 153
ing God is the best way of imaging God. Man is different from God, but the difference does not exclude the identification which knowing effects. The difference between the individual and the universal, then, is so to be expressed: the subjective, individual spirit is the universal divine Spirit to the extent that the latter is comprehended, that the divine Spirit manifests itself in each subject, each man. Thus, the spirit which comprehends absolute Spirit is the subjective spirit. [Ibid.] Once again, Hegel finds this succinctly expressed in Christian teaching on the nature of faith, the validation of which is not something external but the indwelling testimony of divine Spirit, since only spirit, not things or events, can speak to spirit; only spirit can comprehend spirit. What is the ground of man's faith? The testimony of the Spirit regarding the content of religion. In the Christian religion this is also expressly stated: Christ himself warns the Pharisees not to base faith on miracles; what justifies faith is the testimony of the Spirit. If we want to be more precise regarding the testimony of the Spirit, then we must say, only spirit comprehends Spirit. [Ibid.] It is precisely because man is spirit, and only when aware of being spirit, that he can be aware of the unique Spirit who manifests himself not by means of externals but in the innermost depths of the human spirit itself; for man to know himself as spirit is to know God. This is not to say, as we have already seen, that Hegel would abolish from the sceneof either religion or philosophyall that is external, whether the externality of nature or of the work of human art. Spirit alone speaks; spirit alone hears. But the Spirit who speaks may employ external signsnature, artin speaking, so long as the spirit who hears internalizes the message which is spoken. Not only, then, is speaking spiritual activity; so too is hearing. But this rather obvious point is not the important one that Hegel is trying to make. Rather it is that the very being of spirit is activity, and that activity, therefore, is revelatory of spirit. More than that, however, spiritual activity of whatever kind it may be, is revelatory of absolute Spirit. This brings us back to that rather strange contention that God manifests himself (to man) in the finite work of nature, which man cannot possibly simulate, but not in the finite work of finite spirit. Apart from the fact that this contention runs the risk of seeing man in his progress as no more than a being of nature and thus of eliminating the need of a Spirit higher than man, the contention also simply misses the point. If it is possible at all to say that the work of nature manifests God, it is impossible to say that the activity of the human spirit does noteven the activity of transforming nature or of knowing it.
< previous page
page_153
next page >
< previous page
page_154
next page > Page 154
Human Self-Consciousness Reveals the Divine Now, if we can say that the human activity which most clearly manifests man as spirit is self-conscious activity, it appears necessary also to say that human spiritual activity is revelatory not only of infinite Being but also of Being which is infinitely self-conscious (see chap. 6). That such a conclusion is not immediately self-evident is no argument against it; no important truth is immediately self-evident but requires the mediation of profound reflection, of a highly trained mind. Under the heading of this higher training, then, belongs preeminently the more profound principle that absolute Being must be conceived of as self-consciousness, that precisely this is its essence, to be selfconsciousness, and that therefore this self-consciousnes is present in individual consciousness. [VGP II, p. 432] What Hegel is struggling to say and what we, undoubtedly, are struggling to understand, is that the outstanding revelation of God as he truly is is human self-conscious spirit. Nor is this to be understood in the sense that, as is so often said, God is a Spirit external to the world and to self-consciousness, but rather that his manifestation as Spirit conscious of himself is precisely actual selfconsciousness. [Ibid.] In what we have just seen, Hegel is making two statements, which may or may not be separable: (1) God manifests himself preeminently in finite self-consciousness; and (2) in so doing, he manifests himself as preeminently selfconscious being. The first of these statements will be the focal point of chapter 6. The second concerns the nature of God which we are investigating here. Once again, we must note here that Hegel is countering two opponents: (1) Enlightenment rationalism, which, if it acknowledges a God at all, contents itself with a deistic "supreme being"; and (2) illuminationist pietism, which will make God so transcendent that human reason in effect has nothing intelligible to say about him. Hegel, as we have seen, is convinced not only that human reason can say a great deal about God but also that it has said a great deal. The most significant way in which reason can designate Godand in this it agrees with religion at its highestis as "Spirit," which, of course, means "self-conscious, personal subject" and, thus, "pure activity." Negatively this is to say that to speak of God as ''being" is to say the least that can be said; only if "being" is qualified does it say anything: The being of God is to be Spirit. There is even the risk that in speaking of God as "being" one will understand by that "a being," one among many; and the qualification "supreme" merely emphasizes the risk.
< previous page
page_154
next page >
< previous page
page_155
next page > Page 155
On the other hand, no matter how one otherwise characterizes God, if personality, which is inseparable from spirit, is left out, the characterization is inadequate. There is no escape: to conceive of God in any way other than as "Spirit" is to conceive of a non-God. It is precisely on this point that Hegel takes issue with Spinoza, whose "God" is substance but not subject. Many a "theologian" in Hegel's day referred to Spinoza as an "atheist"; in one sense, Hegel will say they were right, but for the wrong reason. Thus, Spinozism is far from being atheism in the customary sense, but in the sense that it does not conceive of God as Spirit, it is atheism. By the same token, however, so are many theologians atheists, those who designate God simply as all-powerful, supreme, etc., being, who do not wish to know God and who allow the finite to count as trueand these are worse [than Spinoza]. [VGP III, p. 195] The difficulty is that Spinoza's God is incompatible with the God of Christianity, precisely because a God who is just "substance" is not personal and, therefore, not God. "That he is the absolute Person, however, is a point which Spinoza never reached; and in that regard we have to admit that the philosophy of Spinoza falls short of the concept of God which constitutes the content of religious consciousness in Christianity" (EpW, no. 151, Zusatz). Hegel, incidentally, is not saying that God is not substance, merely that "substance" is an inadequate designation; "spiritual substance" would be better. To say that God is not substance at all would be to say that he does not ''subsist in and for himself as absolutely independent" (BS, p. 347). It is, indeed, difficult to conceive of a God who is "infinite activity" but not "substantial" as a genuinely "actual" God and not a figment of the mind. "On the other hand, the Christian God is God not merely known but also self-knowing; he is personality not merely represented in our minds, but rather absolutely actual Personality" (EpW, no. 147, Zusatz). Absolute Spirit, in short, is not only activity but also one who acts. The absolute religion, on the other hand, contains the characteristic of subjectivity or of infinite form which is equivalent to substance. We can call this knowledge, pure intelligence, this subjectivity, this infinite form, this infinite elasticity of substance whereby it fragments itself within itself, and makes itself object (Gegenstand). The content of absolute religion, therefore, is identical with itself, because it is infinitely substantial subjectivity which makes itself both object and content. [VPR II, p. 193] For those unaccustomed to the Hegelian "speculative" thinking it may seem strangeeven contradictoryto speak of God as at once "substance" and "activity," or "substantial activity." But this is precisely the point we
< previous page
page_155
next page >
< previous page
page_156
next page > Page 156
have seen so many times already: What on the level of understanding, which deals only with the finite, is contradictory is on the level of reason, whose adequate object is the infinite, noncontradictory (or not unresolved contradiction). Finite spirit is immersed in nature and, therefore, shares the finitude of all things natural. Finite spirit, however, is also activity and, therefore, although it partakes of the infinity proper to spirit as such, it is also finite, with the result that its finitude and its infinity are distinguishable. That they can be united at all is due to the fact that the human spirit is the expression, the vehicle, the "moment" of the divine, infinite Spirit. The human "substance," therefore, is not pure activity; it is also passive, it acts (spiritually) and is acted upon (naturally). The divine "substance," on the contrary, is "absolute substance," at once pure substance and pure activity, and there is no contradiction in this. As Hegel sees it, this is what Aristotle was saying when he spoke of God as at once ''unmoved" and "moving," eternal, changeless, and yet "pure activity" (VGP II, p. 158). If in modern times it has seemed novel to characterize absolute Being as pure activity, we can see this as ignorance of the Aristotelian concept. The Scholastics correctly viewed this as the definition of God: God is pure activity [actus purus], that which is both in and for itself; God needs no materialthere is no higher idealism. To put it another way: God is the substance whose potentiality is also actuality, whose essence (potentia) is activity itself, where both are inseparable. In the divine substance potentiality is not distinguished from the form; this substance it is that produces its content, its very determinations, its very self. [Ibid., pp. 15859] Finite beings, then, are, but only insofar as they are finite determinations, expressions of infinite Being. Continuity between the finite and the infinite, as we shall see in chapter 4, is unbreakable. There is, quite clearly, a whole theology of creationwhich includes a trinitarian and incarnational theologyin what has just been said. Here, however, it is imperative to confine the import of what is being said to the relationship between finite spirit and infinite Spirit. God reveals himself to finite spirit; in a very real sense that is what we mean by "revelation." But, God also reveals himself in finite spirit; the preeminent revelation of God is the human spirit itself, whose essence is to be manifestation of the divine; other than as manifestation of the divine the human spirit essentially is not. To speak of God as "revealed," however, is to speak of God first of all as religious truth, as object of religious consciousness, and it is of this that Hegel speaks. That God is the content of religious consciousness implies, as we have seen, that he is also the ultimate content of rational consciousness and that, if the God of religion is not to become the object of thought, he is
< previous page
page_156
next page >
< previous page
page_157
next page > Page 157
not an object for man as man. But we must begin with religious consciousness, where absolute Spirit is for finite spirit, because God has made himself known, has revealed himself to man. It belongs essentially to the concept of true religion, i.e., to that religion whose content is absolute Spirit, that the religion be revealed by God. For, because knowing, the principle whereby the substance is spirit, is an infinite form which is for itself the self-determining, the knowing is out-and-out (schlechthin) manifestation. Spirit is spirit only insofar as it is for spirit, and in the absolute religion it is absolute Spirit who no longer manifests abstract moments of himself but manifests himself. [EpW, no. 564] Absolute Spirit is present to finite spirit not because he tells the latter something about himself, but because he is present in finite spirit. It is this which permits Hegel to say that there is some truth in the contemporary (Kantian) view that a philosophy of religion is concerned with the subjective response of the human spirit to the divine, even though this view fails to grasp the continuity of the divine-human relationship. We have to recognize the truth which is involved in the modern view, namely, that God is not to be considered as separate from the subjective spirit; this, however, not on the ground that God is an unknown, but because God is essentially Spirit, exists as one who knows. There is then a relation of spirit to spirit. This relation of spirit to spirit lies at the foundation of religion. [VPR I, p. 102] For Hegel, then, God is known, not as an object out-there but as a presence-within making the very knowing a possibility. This brings up one of the most controverted points in Hegel's philosophy of religion, to which we shall have to return in more detail in chapter 6. His contention is that to say that finite consciousness "knows" God is to say that God knows himself in and through finite consciousness. "Finite consciousness knows God only to the extent to which God knows himself in it" (VPR II, p. 187). So far so good: knowing God is in some sense a divine activity which takes place in human consciousnessor, which is human religious consciousness. That the Christian community worships God is somehow God's doing: "Thus God is Spirit, the Spirit of his community in fact, i.e., of those who worship him. This is the perfect religion, the concept becomes objective to itself'' (ibid.). We can look upon this as God sharing his self-knowledge with menif knowing God is to be truly knowing at allin such a way that in knowing God men know themselves and in truly knowing themselves know God. "Here it is manifest what God is; he is no longer a Being above and beyond the world, an unknown, for he has told men what he is, and this not merely in an external account, but in con
< previous page
page_157
next page >
< previous page
page_158
next page > Page 158
sciousness" (ibid.). Knowing God is an activity of human consciousness, not merely a passive acceptance of teaching about God, even though the initial form in which human consciousness "represents" God may be simply a response to teaching about God. Many "theologians," however, began to find a difficulty here. If human spiritual activity is essentially finite, and God knows himself in this activity wherein man knows God, then God would seem to be finitizing himself in being known by manunless, of course, man is being infinitized in knowing God. In either alternative there seems for these theologians to lurk the danger that the God of whom Hegel speaks is really not God. On the other hand, I am not aware that any theologian has explained how the self-revelation, even of infinite Spirit, could be other than finite if it is a revelation to and in finite spirit. It is for this reason, perhaps, that they prefer not to call the human response to divine self-revelation a "knowing" at all. But, it is difficult to see how this solves anything. "We have here, accordingly, the religion of the manifestation of God, since God knows himself in the finite spirit. God is simply manifest, and this is the relation in question" (ibid.). We have to remember that the ''theologians" Hegel is debating do, in fact, believe that God reveals himself; but it is difficult to comprehend what "reveal himself" can mean, if man does not "know" what is revealed. If, however, even finite human spirit in its relationship to infinite divine Spirit can cancel out the finiteness which is not essential to knowing as such, there may be here an intelligible subsumption of the finite in the infinite. "The transition consisted in this, that we saw how this knowledge of God as free [self-determining] Spirit was, so far as its mode (Gehalt) is concerned, still tinged with finitude and immediacy; this finitude had further to be discarded by the activity of spirit; it is negativity, and we have seen how this negativity was made manifest to consciousness" (ibid., pp. 18788). If, as we saw before, it makes no sense to conceive of finiteness as other than the negation of infinity, and if negation is meaningful only in terms of that which it negates, then perhaps, after all, it makes a great deal of sense to say that a knowing of the infinite is essential to a recognition of the finite as finite. Beyond this we cannot go until we have examined more in detail the very meaning of "infinite" as Hegel employs the term (see chap. 4). The Function of Negation Whether or not the riddle of finite spirit's "knowing" infinite Spirit has yet beenor ever will besolved, one message does come through loud and clear: The God of the Christians is at once concrete personality and pure spiritual activity; if it is possible to know what one is saying in saying that, then there is a sense in which one can know not only that God is but also
< previous page
page_158
next page >
< previous page
page_159
next page > Page 159
what God isand this by virtue of negating what is negative in human spiritual activity. The Greek god is not an abstraction but is individualized and has a form closest to the natural. The Christian God, it is true, is also concrete personality, but as pure spiritness (Geistigkeit), and he is to be known as Spirit and in spirit. The element of his manifest being, therefore, is essentially inner knowing and not an external natural form, by means of which he can be presented only imperfectly and not according to the full profundity of his concept. [VA I, pp. 102103] God reveals himself, then, not because he chooses to do so but because, as pure Spirit he is eternally pure selfrevelatory activity: "God is self-revelation just because he is Spirit" (VPR II, p. 219). This, however, need at first simply mean that God is totally manifest to himself. But if self-revelation is to be manifestation outward, there must be finite spirit for whom God is, and this is what Hegel calls God's "appearing" (ibid.). As Hegel sees it, then, spirit is thinkable only because it is unthinkable that absolute Spirit should not be: If spirit is, God is. There is still a danger, however, that the "universal" Spirit embracing all spirits be conceived as an abstraction, a category unifying the "infinite" diversity of finite spirits. Just as Plato saw the "Idea of the Good" as the absolutely universal form, both uniting and giving meaning to all formssurely an abstractionmay not Hegel be seeking to unite all "spirits'' under the abstract form of "Spirit"? There are those who would say this is so, because this is the only way they can make sense out of Hegel. It would seem preferable, however, not to make sense out of Hegel rather than to fly in the face of all we have seen him saying about "reason," "spirit," "speculative thinking," the "concept," and the "concrete universal." That subjective thinking universalizes its object is undeniable, but that is not the universality Hegel speaks of when he speaks of "absolute Spirit." The divine is not to be conceived of as merely a universal thought, or as something inward and only potentially real. The objectifying of the divine is not to be conceived of simply as the objective form it takes in all men, for in that case it would be conceived of simply as representing the manifold forms of the spiritual in general, and the development which the absolute Spirit has in itself and which has to advance until it reaches the form of the Is, which is immediacy, that development would not be contained in such objectivity. [VPR II, pp. 27576] Divine Spirit in this sense is concrete, not abstractly "universal." The "Spirit" of which Hegel speaks, then, is "infinite subjectivity" in its
< previous page
page_159
next page >
< previous page
page_160
next page > Page 160
"actuality," a Spirit which can become incarnate precisely because it is not an abstraction. "Secondly, according to its concept the idea does not stop short in the abstractness and indeterminateness of universal thoughts, but is in itself free [self-determining] infinite subjectivity and as Spirit comprises this subjectivity in its actuality" (VA I, p. 391). God is pure subject, not merely pure object of thought. This Spirit is the Christian God who, unlike the gods of the pagans, makes himself manifest in the only external form adequate to spirit, the human. "Now, the Spirit as free subject is determinate in itself and through itself, and in this self-determining finds in its own concept the external form adequate to it, a form in which it can unite itself with itself, as with the reality which belongs to it in and for itself" (ibid.). In words reminiscent of the closing lines of the Phenomenology, which we have already seen, Hegel speaks of infinite Spirit "othering" itself in the multiplicity of finite spirits only to return to its eternal oneness with itself in the consciousness these spirits have of it as one. The enduring reality of the [spiritual] community is its continuous, eternal becoming, whose foundation is the very nature of spirit knowing itself enternally, shooting forth in the form of finite flashes of light which constitute individual consciousness, and then gathering itself again out of this finitude and comprehending itself. In this way the knowledge of its essence and consequently the divine self-consciousness appears in finite consciousness. Out of the ferment of finitude, since it changes itself into foam, Spirit rises like a vapor. [VPR II, p. 320] The poetic language may well seem to hide more than it reveals, but the thought it expresses is without doubt intoxicating. It is unquestionably true, of course, that God has beenand to a great extent continues to beconceived abstractly. The progress of religious consciousness itself is a process of concretization in the sense that the universal content of that consciousness moves from abstractness to concreteness, from the multiplicity of particular "spirits" to the unity of "absolute Spirit." The process of concretizing, however, is not merely an inner mental process of forming more and more adequate "representations" of an abstract "deity"; it is a process of coming closer and closer to the truth of the concrete concept which is eternal, and this coming-closer is the historical process of divine self-revelation.
The principles of the national spirits (Volksgeister) are by virtue of their particularity, wherein they have their objective actuality and self-consciousness as existing individuals, simply limited. Their destinies and their deeds in their relationship to each other constitute the manifest dialectic of their finitude, out of which dialectic the universal Spirit, the Spirit of the World, brings itself forth as unlimitedwhich it is. [GPR, no. 340]
< previous page
page_160
next page >
< previous page
page_161
next page > Page 161
This "universal Spirit" is both universal "reason" and universal "will," unfolding its own concreteness in history. "This good, this reason, in its most concrete form (Vorstellung), is God. God governs the world: the actual working out of his governmentthe carrying out of his planis the history of the world" (VPG, p. 53). One might conceive of the "plan'' abstractly; one might even think of the subject-who-plans as an abstraction; but it is difficult to see how one would be following Hegel in so doing. "This plan philosophy strives to comprehend; for only that which has been developed as the result of it possesses bona fide reality" (ibid.). What this is saying is that "rational will," as a self-determining reality, that is, spirit, governs the process we call "history." "Only the rational will is that universal principle which of itself (in sich) determines and unfolds itself, and articulates its moments as organic members" (ibid., p. 67). When Hegel, then, identifies "universal reason," "universal spirit," and "absolute Spirit," he is speaking of a "subject" who is "actual", "personal," and "concrete." At the same time he calls this Spirit "God." It would seem, consequently, that the burden of proof lies with those who wish to claim that Hegel's God is no more than an abstractly universal, or perhaps collective, spirit, to which he attaches the name "God." Over and over again he has told us that the name, by itself, is empty of meaning until its determinate content has become manifest, and that this manifestation is the activity of Spirit revealing itself. The concept "spirit" is, for Hegel, never abstract.
< previous page
page_161
next page >
< previous page
page_162
next page > Page 162
Chapter Four The Infinite There is scarcely a term in Hegel's philosophical ("speculative") vocabulary that he repeats more frequently than the term "infinite" (unendlich), usually, of course, accompanied by the opposite and correlative term, "finite" (endlich)indicating, at the very least, that, if we are to understand either of these terms as Hegel employs them, we must grasp them as mutually defining, implying, explicating each other. One might wish, of course, that Hegel had not been so generousor so imprecisein the use, particularly, of the term "infinite,'' since it is both enormously difficult to pinpoint the meaning of the term (especially if the only instrument we have for so doing is a language couched in prepositional expressions) and problematical whether Hegel's use of the term corresponds in any intelligible way to the traditional use of the term as applied to God or to God's "attributes." We like to tell ourselves that we are perfectly clear in our mind as to what we mean when we say "finite," but that we say "infinite" precisely when we do not quite know exactly what we do mean, unless it be to designate in as vague a way as possible the absence of those limitations which inevitably accompany any object whatsoever of our experiencea condition for the very possibility of experiencing and of knowing what we experience is that the object of experience be limited, that is, have assignable boundaries of intelligibility and meaning. What should be perfectly clear, however, to anyone who reads Hegel even cursorily, is that Hegel not only intends that the concept of "infinity" be thoroughly intelligible (whether or not the language employed to express the concept be adequate) but also sees its intelligibility as the necessary condition for the intelligibility of whatever else the human mind is to understand. As Hegel employs the terms "finite" and "infinite," the form in which they appear is for the most part adjectival, whether as attributive, for example, "finite spirit" (der endliche Geist), "infinite Spirit" (der unendliche
< previous page
page_162
next page >
< previous page
page_163
next page > Page 163
Geist), or as predicative, for example, "beings [multiple] are finite" (die Seienden sind endlich) or "Being is infinite" (das Sein ist unendlich). Frequently, however, the adjectival form is given nominal significance, as when he speaks of "the finite" (das Endliche) or ''the infinite" (das Unendliche). Sometimes, too, he employs thegramaticallyabstract terms "finitude" (die Endlichkeit) or "infinity" (die Unendlichkeit) in the sense of categories. Finally, Hegel also uses the adverbial form (but only to express infinity), and his intention is either to be deliberately vague or to designate what he considers to be the least significant form of the infinite, the mathematical. In these cases it might well be preferable not to translate unendlich as "infinitely" at all. Thus, when Hegel speaks of a problem as being unendlich kompliziert, he means something like "enormously complicated"; unendlich viel means "innumerable" (with the added connotation of "undifferentiated"); unendlich klein is "infinitesimal," unendlich gross is "immeasurable," and so on. The adjectival (unendlich) and the abstract (Unendlichkeit), too, can sometimes express this sort of indeterminateness. I know of no instances, however, where the expression das Unendliche expresses other than "the authentically infinite," and it always takes its meaning from "the finite" to which it is opposed in the context. As frustrating as it may be to find unendlich and its cognates "infinitely" repeatedsometimes as often as ten times on one page1it is frequently relatively easy to determine what Hegel has in mind as he employs the term. What is not nearly so easy, however, is to come to terms with the subtle shades of meaning which Hegel attaches to the term unendlich in contexts where it quite clearly cannot have one and the same unambiguous meaning, even though in each case it can be translated as "positively" or "authentically" infinite. It is in these cases that the term must be understood as inseparably linked to its opposite number "finite" (endlich). What causes partbut only partof the difficulty is that, although grammatically unendlich is simply the negative of endlich, for Hegel this can make sense only if endlich is read equally well as the negative of unendlich and if both terms are seen to have both positive and negative significance. Because only with difficulty do we conceptualize reality other than in a spatiotemporal framework, we tend to think of the determinate as that which has closely defined limits and thus to think of the infinite as the negative of this, that is, the indeterminate.2 If, however, we can, with Hegel, conceive of infinity as primary, in the realms of both reality and intelligibility, we should be able to understandeven if at this point we are unable to accepthis contention that the negative expressed in the concept "in-finite" is negative only as negating the negation already contained in the concept "finite."
1. See the writings of the Jena period in particular. 2. It is for this reason, it would seem, that William James opts for a "finite" God, since only the finite can James conceive of as determinate.
< previous page
page_163
next page >
< previous page
page_164
next page > Page 164
If addition we say that the infinite is the not-finite we have in fact spoken quite truly, for, since the finite is itself the first negative, the not-finite is the negative of the negation; it is the self-identical negative and thus at the same time truly affirmation. [Ep W, no. 94, Zusatz] Such an infinite, of course, is a far cry from endless progression in space or time, but that is precisely the point: Philosophical thinking is not concerned with mathematical infinity, except, perhaps, to the extent that its abstract intelligibility affords a hint of the intelligibility of concrete infinity. "What philosophy has to do with is always what is concrete and in the best sense present" (ibid.). We have to grasp not only the intelligibility of infinity but also the infinity of intelligibility. It would be a mistake for us not to recognize that the only sensible approach to Hegel's use of the terms endlich and unendlich is from the point of view of the at least initially religious use of these terms. In religious languageand here, for Hegel, the paradigm is Christian religious language (Christianity is "absolute religion")there is only one infinite, and that is God, whether he be designated as "the Absolute," uncreated Being," ''absolute Spirit," or "infinite truth, love, goodness." All else is finite; that is, whatever can be multiplied, whether it be things, souls, spirits, thoughts, or the universe, as the sum total of finite realityno conceivable accumulation of finite reality can add up to infinite reality. That Christian religious language speaks this way there can be no doubt; the problem for Hegeland it occupied him from the beginning to the end of his careerwas whether he could make rational sense out of what the religious language of Vorstellungen proclaimed so glibly. Is it possible to speak of "the infinite" and to know what one is saying, or must one say with both the philosophers and the religionists of his day that to speak of the infinite God is to make affirmations which only faith but not rational thought could justify? If it can be said, and it would seem that it must be said, so their contention goes, that human reason is essentially finite, then must it not also be said that an adequate relation of a finite capacity to an infinite object does not make any sense? That this would also involve saying that human reason could scarcely find adequate the faith relation to an I-know-not-what-it-could-mean infinite object scarcely seems to have disturbed those whom Hegel singled out as his adversaries. Nor could Hegel be satisfied with what he considered a subterfuge, namely, that the human mind could indeed be related, through intuition or some sort of religious feeling to an infinite God whose infinity consisted in indefiniteness, indeterminacy, or the indiscriminate heaping together of perfections whose content man's thinking could in no adequate way come to grips with. In Hegel's view this attitude, which could look like cognitive humility, is
< previous page
page_164
next page >
< previous page
page_165
next page > Page 165
in reality a far cry from humility; it is the existential refusal to submit to the infinite, to relinquish one's own finite particularity. It is as though one were to say, "My heart, my emotions, my religious intuition can affirm an unintelligible infinite, but my mind knows that it can affirm only what is on its own level of finitude." This kind of "humility" Hegel can do without. "True humility, on the contrary, renounces itself, renounces its claim as this particular to be the affirmative and recognizes only the true, the absolute (Anundfürsichseiende) as the affirmative'' (VPR I, p. 182). The decision to insist on the absoluteness of one's own finitude is a strange humility indeed! Immediately, however, there enters the but, i.e. whether we are capable of knowing the truth. There seems to be a disproportion between us limited humans and the absolute truth, and there arises the question of a bridge between the finite and the infinite. God is truth; how are we to know him? The virtues of modesty and humility seem to be in contradiction with such a proposal. Some, then, also ask whether the truth can be known, in order to justify their persistence in the pettiness of their finite aims. Humility of this sort accomplishes little. [Ep W, no. 19, Zusatz 1] There would seem to be in this sort of "humility" a kind of fear that by allowing infinite Spirit to be known by finite mind the Infinite thus becomes finitizednot unlike the contention (see chap. 6) that to speak of God as related to finite spirit is to degrade God. Difficult as it may be to comprehend on the level of reflective understanding, what Hegel consistently says is that, although the relation of finite to finite is itself part and parcel of the limitation of what is finite, the relation of finite to infinite is not of itself a limiting relationship. By the same token, a relationship of infinite to finite is not a limiting relationship, precisely because the very reality of the finite is relation of the infinite to itself. The distinction of finite from infinite is a distinction which is no distinction, because as source of all distinctions the infinite is identical with itself in all distinctions.
Infinity is identical with itself, because its distinctions are tautological; they are distinctions which are no distinctions. This self-identical being, therefore, is related only to itself; to itself, which is thus an other to which the relation is directed, and the relationship to itself is rather duplication; in other words, precisely that self-identity is internal distinction. What have been doubled are thus in and for themselves, each an opposite of another. In this way, to say the one is at the same time to say the other. To put it another way, it is not a question of the opposite of another, rather only the pure opposite, and thus the one is in itself its own opposite. [PdG, p. 125]
< previous page
page_165
next page >
< previous page
page_166
next page > Page 166
Such language, quite obviously, is completely unintelligible on the level of mere "understanding," all of whose forms are simply finite; what is only the object of finite reflective thought is in fact finite. Now because, on the other hand the True and the Eternal are known, i.e. enter consciousness, are supposed to be for the spirit, then this spirit for which they are is the finite spirit, whose mode of consciousness consists in the representations and forms of finite things and relationships. These forms are what is familiar, customary for consciousness. This is the general mode of finitude, which consciousness has made its own and has made into the general medium of its conceiving (Vorstellens). [EGP, p. 49] The Infinite Object of Thought As mentioned in the first section of this chapter, to speak in this way of finitude and infinity is to speak the language of religious consciousness, for which God is the unique "infinite," but it is also to try to make this language intelligible to "speculative thought." What Hegel is doing is taking seriously talk about God as unique, uncreated, eternal Creator, absolute Being, infinite Spirit, a subject of whom predicates such as "omnipotent," ''omniscient," "omnipresent," "all good," "all loving," can be said. At the same time, he is convinced that none of this can be said in a way that is other than nonsensical unless placed squarely in a context of human knowing, which alone can make sense out of any language. This is not to say that the language of religion, of faith, of devotion, is nonsensical; it is to say that it is not faith by itself which can make sense of this language, only faith informed by rational thinking. For Hegel, the very "concept" of the human is that it must be characterized by thought. Human beings, to be sure, do many things which are not characterized by thought, but it is precisely these things which do not constitute the uniquely human in man. If it can be said, and it would seem that it must be, that science, morality, law, politics, art, religion, and philosophy, are uniquely human accomplishments, then they are so only because all are characterized by thinking; take away the thinking and they are empty, "sounding brass and tinkling cymbals." But a thinking which is not a knowingor, at least, oriented to knowingis itself not a thinking in any intelligible sense of the term. If, then, we are to understand what Hegel means by saying that a human thinking which stops short of the infinite and turns that over to "faith" or "intuition" is not really thinking at all, or that a human knowing which stops short of knowing God who is infinite is not really knowing at all, how are we to proceed? A necessary presupposition of any procedure, I think, is the recognition that, for Hegel, the essential focus of all philosophical investigation is human thinking, both as that which essentially characterizes
< previous page
page_166
next page >
< previous page
page_167
next page > Page 167
the human and as that which delivers all that is susceptible of philosophical investigation. Here a caution is in order. There is a persistent temptation to see in the quality of infinity, as applied to the human, either (1) the human infinitely multiplied (through time and space), which would, so to speak, exhaust and therefore "infinitize" the possibilities of the human, or (2) the human ideally expanded to infinity, à la Feuerbach, such that the "universal" human spirit would constitute the only "infinite" which can make sense. The first of these is too obviously nonsensical to need comment: Numerical infinity simply cannot be concretized, least of all in its application to concrete humanity; the number of humans who have existed in this world is clearly finite, and multiplication through future time will not make that number infinite. The second kind of infinity simply flies in the face of all that Hegel has said, both in terms of God as the paradigm of infinity, and of the individual human person as in some intelligible way "infinite"because continuous with the essential infinity of spirit. We have but to consult Phänomenologie des Geistes, Vorlesungen über die Philosophie des Weltgeschichte, Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie, "Philosophy of Objective Spirit'' in the Enzyklopädie, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechtsall are replete with statements regarding the infinity of the individual human person. We must concretely come to grips with a concept of infinity which is paradigmatically said of God but also said authentically of the individual human subject, spirit, person, thought, will, right, value, and so on. We could, then, institute a "genetic" investigation, seeing how Hegel's thought on the inseparability of the finite and the infinite as foci of human thinking and knowing develops from his earliest published writings (we can conveniently leave out his Early Theological Writings on the assumption that, if he did not publish these, it was because he did not want to), beginning with the Differenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen Systems der Philosophie and Glauben und Wissen, both of which are concerned with the division, unacceptable to Hegel, between the finite and the infinite in human thinking. From there we could move on to the writings of the Jena period, where begins to emerge the conviction that only a "system" which seeks to come to terms with reality as a totality of interrelationships is viable. These early investigations would prepare us for another hard look at Phenomenology of Spirit, where Hegel makes it clear that only in the light of infinite Spirit does it make sense to seek to know the human spirit at all. The transition then would be to Science of Logic, where human thinking is seen in the light of the very essence of thought, ultimately the proper object of philosophical investigation. Finally, we could see how the relation of finitude and infinity shapes the structure of the mature system, through philosophy of nature, philosophy of subjective and objective spirit, to the
< previous page
page_167
next page >
< previous page
page_168
next page > Page 168
philosophy of absolute spirit, which then draws all the threads together, culminating in an overall view of philosophy as infinite thinking of infinite reality; a view embracing in its grasp the total framework which permits Hegel to make sense of finite reality. That, however, is the blueprint of the entire Hegelian endeavor, and would require a treatment as extensive as Hegel's own. A more modest approach would be to see first in Science of Logic how the thinking of finitude and infinity is crucial to the philosophical endeavor as Hegel sees it. This could then be illumined by a study of the movement of the human spirit from the minimal data of consciousness to the realization both that the only satisfactory culmination of spirit's progress is in the recognition of spirit's infinity and that the only way in which "the infinite" can make sense at all is as spirit. For the rest, the mature system of Hegel will supply abundant confirmation of the continuity of his conviction that only a knowing which is infinite and has as its object infinite reality is in the final analysis knowing at all. Taken in isolation from all else that Hegel says, this could, of course, simply mean that a thinking whose determinations are wholly its own is in no way limited by these determinations and is, hence, "limitless" (see Ep W, no. 440). That, however, would be to beg the question of whether a thinking which is not continuous with the concrete infinite reality of spirit could in fact be wholly selfdetermining. Precisely because human thinking is finite, it cannot by itself lift itself to the infinity of selfdetermination. According to Hegel, then, one can say that, logically speaking, knowledge of infinite being is prior to knowledge of finite beingsthe former a logical precondition, so to speak, for the latter. Epistemologically speaking, on the other hand, we must say that human knowing, finite as it is, must first come to grips with the finite reality in which it is immersed, finding in the process that its knowing is inadequate even to its finite object if it does not pass beyond (rise above) the finite to the infinite precondition of both the being and the knowing of the finite. This is but another way of saying that, logically speaking, the very concept of being, with which thinking must begin, makes sense only if being is infinite. What the system, taking its cue from logic, makes clear is that the only conceivable concretely infinite being must be spirit. It is Phenomenology of Spirit which attempts to make clear both that this is true and what it means for spirit to be infinite. The system in its totality, then, emerges out of the Logic and the Phenomenology operating, so to speak, in tandem. One might say, of course, as more than one contemporary author has tried to say (Kojève, Findlay, Kaufmann, Schacht), that Hegel's "infinite being," "infinite spirit" need not be Godof course leaving it very unclear just what else it could bebut it is to be feared that one can do this only by making Hegel speak nonsense, a rather risky tactic. Why not take what Hegel says at face
< previous page
page_168
next page >
< previous page
page_169
next page > Page 169
value? It is difficult to see how one can read Hegel's Science of Logic and not recognize that its overriding theme is that to know being at all is to know being as infinite (WL I, pp. 31, 144; II, pp. 15960, 441). It is equally difficult to see how one can say, without talking nonsense, that in affirming the infinity of being Hegel is not affirming the being of the infinite, that is, of God. Just what would an "infinite being" (Spirit) be which is not God? By the same token what would a "God" who is not infinite being (Spirit) be? One might also want to say, very piously I am sure, that Hegel thinks he knows too muchnot that the infinite Spirit of which he speaks is not God, but that to claim to know the infinite Spirit who is God is to claim too much. This is tantamount to saying that the God whom faith acknowledges cannot be knowna position that Hegel was clearly fighting. The difficulty here, it would seem, is that the disavowal of knowing God demands a context in which we speak of the God we do not know. Might it not be better not to speak at all, if we know not that whereof we speak? Perhaps, with Kierkegaard, we should not speak of God at all, only speak to him. A tenable position, perhaps, but one which requires that we also do not speak of not knowing God. Faith may tell us that God, infinite Spirit, is, but has faith told us anything, if we do not know what it has told us? Are we to say that, philosophically speaking at least, the terms "God," "infinite being" (Spirit), are empty of meaning, or, if given a meaning by faith, a meaning that is impervious to reason? Would that be "meaning" at all? What Hegel seems to be saying is that the term "infinite" has a meaning we cannot do without, that its meaning is discoverable by human reason (indeed that reason will fail to be reasonable if it is not), and that the intelligibility of the term ''infinite" is not confined to its application to the infinite being who is Godalthough a failure to see God as the paradigm of all talk of the "infinite" is to empty all such talk of meaning. If nothing else, Hegel should shake those who think they know what they are saying when they say "infinite"and shake even more those who think that the only paradigm for talk of the infinite is the mathematical infinite. Our question, then, will be whether Hegel successfully articulates a meaning of "infinite being," such that it is both precise and determinate enough to be justifiably called knowledge, and not simply feeling, aspiration, or religious conviction. In attempting to answer this question we must first examine the manner in which he employs the term "infinite" as part of his philosophical (speculative) vocabulary. We must remember, too, that what Hegel does say can be understood only against the backdrop of those contemporary opinions according to which the infinite could be the object only of faith, not of knowledge (Kant, Jacobi, Fichte)without ever explaining how even faith as human activity, could be capax infinitior of those according to which
< previous page
page_169
next page >
< previous page
page_170
next page > Page 170
the infinite could indeed be known, but only immediately in intuition, not through a process of mediated rational thought (Schelling and the Romantics). The Meaning of "Infinite" What, then, does the term "infinite" mean for Hegel? If the purport of this question were taken to be "how does Hegel define the term infinite," the question would, quite obviously, be self-defeating; the answer to it would necessarily be a contradictionto de-fine a term is to set identifiable limits to its meaning, so that language can legitimately perform its function of clarifying discourse. To define a term in a language is to express its meaning more clearly and precisely in that same language and thus to set up boundaries beyond which that meaning does not go and within which that meaning is always the same. This is not to say, however, that the intelligibility of meaning need be confined to definition. Plato, we remember, taught us that lesson long ago: his Socrates was ever in search of definitions which he never found, and yet he was ever shedding new and expanding light on meanings. Plato it is who shows us that the intelligibility of forms cannot be confined to definitions and that the inexhaustibility (read: "infinity") of the forms of truth, beauty, goodness in no way militates against their intelligibility.3 Nor is the inexhaustibility of intelligibility to be equated with the "and-so-on'' of endless repetition of the sameeven though, as Hegel recognized so well, the intelligibility of this sort of mathematical infinity gives a hint of the intelligibility of a much more significant infinity (see Ep W, no. 104, Zusatz 2). The key text which will permit us at least to begin to understand Hegel's concern with infinity comes rather early in the first book ("The Doctrine of Being") in Science of Logic. Hegel has already told us that the science which seeks to think thoughtand all its implications"must" begin with the most general and most unified object of thought, that is, being. This is but a way of saying that to think at all is to say mentally of thought's object that it is, which is, quite obviously to say little or nothing. Only when thought says determintate being does it say anything, but to say determinate being is to say determination as distinguishing. Thought is faced, however abstractly, with one being distinguished from another. With this introduction of otherness the seamless robe of unified being seems to have been rent; multiplicity has been inserted into the very heart of unity; universality has surrendered to particularitythat which is other is "something" other, and that which is something other both limits and is limited by its other (see
3. Perhaps what needs to be said here is that "defining" can be of two kinds: (1) putting limitations on a meaning in order to handle it; and (2) permitting an object to define itself, i.e., its concept.
< previous page
page_170
next page >
< previous page
page_171
next page > Page 171
Ep W, no. 92). Hegel's concern, then, becomes threefold: (1) Can thought restore the imperiled unity of being? (2) Can thought do this short of thinking a concretely infinite being which would embrace the totality of being? and (3) Can thought think infinite being, if thought itself is not in some sense infinite? In attempting to come to grips with Hegel's answers to these questions, we must bear in mind that throughout Science of Logic Hegel is engaging in a not-too-thinly-veiled polemic against all those who contended that human reason is essentially finite and only finite; for him, to say that being makes sense only if there is infinite being involves saying that rational thought makes sense only if rational thought is infinite. What can it mean, then, to say that rational thought is infinite? What it cannot mean, in a purely negative way, is that human rational thinking is not the activity of a finite being nor that it is simply not finite activity. There can be no question that Hegel regards the human mind (spirit) as finite. This does not mean, however, that rational thought is essentially finite, nor that human rational thinking is discontinuous with infinite rational thought. It means, rather, that human thinking, precisely as rational, is conceivable only as continuous with infinite thought (see Ep W, no. 24). Thus, in saying that "reason observing" is seeking in what it observes "its own infinity" (PdG, p. 183), Hegel is quite consistently saying that only in infinity, where its "truth'' is to be found, is rational thinking adequately rational (ibid., p. 184). By the same token, if Kant is right, and the content of rational thinking is to be found only in sensory experience, then rational thinking is not capable of coming to grips with the infinite. "It is unquestionably correct to say that the infinite is not given in the world, in sense-perception . . . . Spirit is for spirit alone" (VGP III, pp. 35253). As Hegel approaches the task he has set himself he reminds one of the pole-vaulter distancing himself from the bar he is to clear in order to muster up force and momentum and to plan carefully the sequence of steps which will take him to the barand over it. One could suppose, of course, that it is relatively simple to say what one means by infinite; it is the opposite, the negative, of finite. What is limited is finite; what is unlimited is infinite. Such simplicity, however, labors under a number of difficulties. (1) It assumes that it is sufficient to look for a meaning without any concern as to whether what is meant is, to say what the infinite would be if it were. Hegel's concern is to show that the infinite is, that apart from infinity there is no way to make sense of finitude. (2) The simple solution presupposes too, that the intelligibility of the finite is primary and that, therefore, whatever intelligibility is to be found in the infinite is derived from that of which it is the negation. For Hegel it is the essential negativity of the finite which makes it necessary to assert that the supremely affirmative is the infinite. That, precisely, is finite which does not contain within itself all that it is to be what it is. (3) It presupposes, further, that the infinite differs from
< previous page
page_171
next page >
< previous page
page_172
next page > Page 172
the finite in exactly the same way as one finite entity differs from another or, worse still, as one thing differs form another thing; one is simply not the other. (4) Finally, the simple solution is based on the assumption that finitude and determinacy are synonymous, with the result that infinity becomes synonymous with indeterminacy, indefiniteness, emptiness. For Hegel, on the contrary, it is the infinite which is supremely determinate, because it contains within itself all its own determinations; it is not determinate merely by its relation to others which thus limit it. If this is what Hegel means by infinity, then there should be no doubt in anyone's mind that the paradigm of infinity for him should be God, the Absolute, absolute Spirit, the absolute totality of reality, the Inbegriff aller Realitäten. That God is the paradigm of infinity, however, does not mean that every time Hegel employs the terms infinity, the infinite, or simply infinite (as an adjective), he is referringdirectly at leastto God. He also, for example, speaks of the world, the soul, the concept, thought, freedom, and the value of the human individual as "infinite." It is nevertheless necessary to say that the true concept of unqualifiedly infinite is realized in God alone and, thus, that other uses of the term are derivative. Wherever, then, reality can be said to be infinite (or infinity said to be real), it will be (1) determinate, not an undifferentiated abstraction; (2) self-determining, not needing what is other than itself for its determination, which would be limitation; (3) having predicates which, although in a finite mode they might be contradictory, do not contradict or limit each other and yet are not simply indifferent to each other; and (4) self-contained, complete in itself. Whether or not one likes the language Hegel speaks, there can be no question that the overriding theme of his Science of Logic is that to know being at all is to know being as infinite (see WL I, pp. 31, 144; II, pp. 15960, 441). This, however, can make sense for Hegel only if to know being as infinite is to know what it is for being to be infinite, and short of knowing God as he is (the paradigm of concrete, determinate infinity) knowing being as infinite does not make sense. This, in turn, is but another way of saying that to know being as finite without knowing being as infinite is not even to know being as finite"finite being" without reference to "infinite being" is a meaningless formula (''finite" and "infinite" are, as we have seen, mutually implicativebut only infinite is explicative of finite (see WL I, pp. 41, 80, 109, 117, 126, 128, 143, 145; Ep W, nos. 36, 112). The difficulty that we all experience in coming to grips with (begreifen) infinity in our thinking, according to Hegel, is that we have the seemingly inescapable tendency (Kant would call it essential to human thinking) to couple conceptual thought with sensible or imaginative representations, while it is the very nature of the infinite that it cannot be represented, either sensibly or imaginatively; it is the object of thought alone, or it is no object at all.
< previous page
page_172
next page >
< previous page
page_173
next page > Page 173
We might put it this way. It could scarcely occur to anyone that what is infiniteif there be suchcould possibly be the object of the senses or of imagination. There is simply no way that the senses or imagination could represent infinity. Nor could the understanding (Verstand), if its task is to represent abstractly what the senses or imagination have presented sensibly or imaginatively, represent infinitythe mathematical infinite is its last ditch attempt to do this. Infinity, then, can be the object of thought and thought aloneas Hegel puts it, of pure rational thought (Vernunft). The question then arises whether the converse of this will not also be true: that, whatever is the object of thought only and in no way of the senses and imaginationfor example, unity, universality (the unity of multiplicity), value, truth, beauty, goodness, and so on; in short, the ideal as suchis infinite in some intelligible sense of that term. At the very least it should be said that such objects of thought are not finite in the way objects of sense and imagination are. If this is true, however, then infinity is inseparable from ideality"ideality is the quality of infinity"the infinite is ideal; not, however, in the sense that it is not real but rather in the sense that the ideal is the truly real (toontwVon). But here we are brought up short by what, to the inquiring mind, could well seem to be utter nonsense. How can the ideal, whose existence is by definition mental, be more truly real than the "things" we can stick our knives and forks into? Is the essence "man," for example, which has meaning only as the ideally united totality of all human beings, more truly real, than the living, breathing, acting, feeling, thinking, loving and hating, human individuals who inhabit our world? It depends on what we mean by "real.'' If the concept of man can be arrived at only by a mental activity which abstracts from all the differences which distinguish one human being from another, from all others, then the concept of man is obviously less really human than are the individuals from whom the concept is derivedif indeed this is the way the concept is derived. If, on the other hand, the concept is in some very significant sense (logically, ontologically?) antecedent to its finite exemplifications in isolated individuals, such that the concept of the human serves as the criterion for the reality of the humanity of each individual, then as the foundation of the reality of the humanity in each isolated individual, the inexhaustible, infinite concept has to bespeak more reality than the particular exemplifications it unites in a totality which only mind can grasp. The universal "man" is the concrete, determinate totality of the human. When the manufacturers of Coca-Cola, for quite unphilosophical reasons, to be sure, insist that "Coke is the real thing," they are not saying that each individual bottle of Coca-Cola is more real than "coke." They are saying that there is a very real concept of "real thing," against which the reality of the individual drink can be evaluated. The illustration is trivial, but it points up an important fact of life; we simply do not look to the finite individual human being
< previous page
page_173
next page >
< previous page
page_174
next page > Page 174
for the total reality of what it is to be truly humanor else, what is striving all about. "Be an authentic human being" means "strive to embody in yourself what it is to be really, truly human." The model of the "really, truly human'' is to be found in the inexhaustible concept of the humanor, perhaps, in the "true idea of humanity," a goal, not a fact (Objekt vs. Gegenstand). Infinity of Concept It is thus that we can begin to understand how the finite particular, the object of particular experience, is real only as the realization of the infinite reality which is its concept. We can also begin to understand how the infinite universal concept is but an empty abstraction apart from its realization in finite particulars. Of course, the universal is the object of thought alone, not of sensation or imagination, but it is also the product of thought alone; it is not produced in thought by something other than thought. This is not to say that thought can simply dispense with sense or imagination; it is to say that in the activity of thinking, of bringing forth (conceiving) its object it is selfcontained, gives itself a content, does not receive it from what is other than thought. None of this, of course, would make sense, if thought were no more than the finite activity of particular finite mindsor even of the accumulated totality of all finite mindsif one could make sense of the latter at all! "All" and "every" are not synonymous; "all" bespeaks essence and, therefore, infinity; "every" bespeaks accumulation and, therefore, finitude. Nevertheless, it is still true to say that finitude is intelligible only in relation to infinity, and infinity is intelligible only in relation to finitude; each contains the other in its concept, that is, each is a movement toward, a passing over into the other. Thus, infinity must be somehow said of the finite (only if the finite is idealized, i.e. infinitized, is anything being said), and finitude must be said of the infinite (only if the infinite expresses itself finitely is it actual), if either is to be intelligible. To ordinary thinking it can well seem patently contradictory and, therefore, absurd to speak of an infinite which is also finite or a finite which is also infinite; the terms (concepts) are mutually exclusivewhat is infinite is not-finite, and what is finite is not infinite, and that is all there is to it. And so it is, Hegel assures us, for a thinking which fragments the universe of reality and is, thus, constrained by mathematical or formal-logical rules. Such a thinking is abstract, compelled to "represent" a reality presumably over-against itself by Vorstellungen which it constructs, keeping its distance from a reality which is not present in but only represented by it. This, Hegel goes on to say, is not a thinking which comes to grips with (begreift) reality, precisely because it leaves reality "out-there" never bridging the gap between thinking and the reality thoughtthe "thing-in-itself" men
< previous page
page_174
next page >
< previous page
page_175
next page > Page 175
tality. This thinking contracts thought by abstractly fragmenting reality, thus enabling it to manipulate reality, perhaps even satisfactorily, but comprehending reality only partially because statically. Beyond this, Hegel tells us, there is a thinking which expands in Begriffe, seeking to reproduce in itself the conceptual movement of dynamic reality, recognizing in this very reality a thought which is its source, not its outcome. If, then, we look in another way at the thought which Hegel describes, wherein finitude and infinity are inseparably linked conceptually (see Ep W, no. 60), we may find that the contradiction which "ordinary thinking" shies away from resolves itself (i.e., its resolution is not due to the efforts of abstract thinking). Just what meaning could we assign to (find in) an infinite reality which would be so cut off from finite reality, so opposed to it, that the very reality of the finite would be inimical to it? By the same token, what could it mean to speak of a finite reality whose only claim to reality would be its not being infinite (on the assumption, of course, that finite is eo ipso more determinate than is infinite)? Either each would exclude the very possibility of the other, or each would be limited in its reality by the reality of the other which it itself is not; the reality of the infinite would conflict with the reality of the finite, and the reality of the finite would conflict with the reality of the infinite. "All well and good," one might say, "let us drop the terminology altogether"other than in mathematical abstraction, "finite'' and "infinite" are empty terms which lead only to confusion of thought. Still, dropping terminology will not make the problem disappear: unity and diversity are going to remain with us, whether we talk about them or not, or, no matter what terminology we employ in talking about them. The unity which the mind cannot but find in reality (totality) bespeaks infinity (the self-containedness of totality); the diversity of reality (plurality) which the mind cannot think away bespeaks finitude. Neither militates against the other, but only the decision to throw up our hands in the presence of reality can prompt us to ignore the problem of concretely reconciling diversity and unity, finitude and infinity. What Hegel is trying to show, then, is not merely that they do not militate against each other, but that neither is conceivable without the other. What further needs to be shown, perhaps, is that it is not nonsensical to speak of unity in terms of infinity and of diversity in terms of finitude. Here it is, then, that we can, in one sense, see all of this as an attempt to clarify language about infinity by reference to an infinite which is not Godfor example, thought (concept, idea), truth, value, spirit, freedom, the universethe elaboration of which will enable us better to understand the concept of infinity in a thinking which has God (Der Inbegriff aller Realitäten) as its object. By speaking of a qualified infinite which is nevertheless intelligible precisely as infinite, we can move on to the intelligibility of an unqualified infinite which exhausts the very concept of infinity, seeing
< previous page
page_175
next page >
< previous page
page_176
next page > Page 176
in God the very foundation for the possibility of unifying the totality of reality in conceptual thinkingprovided, of course, one does not prefer to remain on the fringe of reality, seeing only a chaotic manifold, upon which a finite thinking is satisfied to impose order, since that worksup to a point. In another sense, however, we might approach Hegel's endeavor from another point of view, seeing it as an attempt to move in the other direction alsosomehow Hegel's thought always does. His endeavor begins with God as the paradigm of infinite reality and, thus, makes it possible to understand Hegel when he speaks of an intelligible infinity, which, although not unqualified, characterizes reality in the order of idea, where it is most authentically present to mind. If it can be said that it is impossible to make sense of the concept of being (foundational for all logical thinking), unless being ultimately reveals itself as both infinite and determinate (the task of logic, as Hegel sees it), then it is only in recognizing that any idea, precisely qua idea, is infinitereality must reveal its characteristic infinitythat we can come to terms with it in its truth, which, Hegel tells us, is the goal and purpose of logic (see Ep W, nos. 21314). If we are to understand what Hegel is saying when he speaks of "infinity," of the close link he sees between the infinity of God, the unique concretely infinite Being, and the infinity characteristic of the ideal order which unifies the diversity of the finite, the time has come to examine what he has to say of finitude, of the negativity which is inseparable from the finite and which the infinite negates in affirming its own reality, affirming its own determinacy in negating the unsatisfactory determinacy of the finite (see WL I, p. 143). Actually, however, Hegel has little to say about the finite by itself, precisely because, as he sees it, there is little to say of the finite by itself, since by itself it is nothing; its reality is its relation to thought, to the infinity of idea: "The proposition which states that the finite is ideal (ideell) constitutes idealism. The idealism of philosophy consists in nothing else but the recognition that the finite is not a true being" (ibid., p. 145). More than that, reality without ideality is not truly real, because it is merely finite (ibid., p. 146). He goes so far as to say that both "finite being" and ''finite thinking" are of themselves contradictory and that their contradictoriness can be both recognized and resolved only in "infinite thought" (BS, pp. 408409; see also pp. 7980). This is not to say that finitude is not significant, but that what can be said of it is significant only as pointing to infinity; merely finite being can neither be nor be thought (see Ep W no. 92, Zusatz). To further understand what has just been said we must grasp the close parallel which Hegel draws between finitudewhich characterizes "things" (Etwas)and "immediacy"which characterizes the given (to sense or imagination) independently of the mediation of thought. If Hegel says, then, that the "immediate" is not true, because the mediation of thought is ab
< previous page
page_176
next page >
< previous page
page_177
next page > Page 177
sent from it, he is but saying the same in asserting that the "finite" is not true, because its reality (Dasein) is that which characterizes "things" (Etwas) without reference to thought in the fullest sense. The mind can give no account (logic) of "things," only of thought conceptualizing things in the unity of idea. It is not too difficult to see that thinking cannot deal with "things" by themselves, but only with the thought of things. What may be difficult is to see that thinking is dealing with reality at all when it is dealing only with thought. What can it mean to say that things are true only when mediated by thought? What it does not mean, according to Hegel, is that the very being of what is other than thought is the subjective thinking of it, esse is not percipi. What, at the very least, it does mean is that thought enters into the constitution of the object of thought; the latter is not simply there, to be reproduced or mirrored in thought. More than that, it means that thoughtin its fullest senseis indispensable to the constitution of reality. Here it is that Hegel distinguishes between subjective thinking, which is finite, and objective thought, which is infinite, and whose paradigm is divine thought, which is productive of not only the objectivity but also the reality of its object. In regard to the relationship already mentioned of the three stages of the logical idea, this relationship presents itself thus in concrete and real form: God, who is the truth, is known by us in his truth, i.e. as absolute Spirit, only to the extent that we at the same time recognize as untrue the world created by Godnature and finite spiritif separated from God. [Ep W, no. 83, Zusatz] Infinite Being, which (as we shall see later) can only be absolute Spirit, thinks, and its thinking is creative of finite reality, and this, since thought can think only itself, is, so to speak, the finitizing of the infinite. This is not to say that infinite thought exists in sovereign independence and then "decides" to think and, thus, create finite reality. Rather it is to say that infinite thought in thinking itself both engenders its infinite trinitarian Other, the Son, and creates its finite other, the world of finite reality, a self-finitizing othering. "The answer to the question, how the infinite becomes finite, therefore, is this: that there is no infinite which is first of all infinite and then, in order simply (erst) to become finite needs to go out of itself into finitude. Rather, in its very being for itself it is already just as much finite as infinite" (WL I, p. 143); "The absolute, then, is that which in one unity is both finite and infinite" (VGP II, p. 79). Hard to swallow, indeed, if we take Hegel to be saying by "is" that ''infinite" and "finite" are being predicated of God in exactly the same way. If, however, we take the Hegelian "is" as descriptive of a movement which is inseparable from the very being of the infinite"this inseparability is the concept of the infinite" (ibid., p. 144), we can see him saying that all thoughteven in
< previous page
page_177
next page >
< previous page
page_178
next page > Page 178
finite thoughtis movement, and that infinite thought is a creative movement toward finitude4 (see Ep W, no. 441, Zusatz). Be the difficulties of understanding Hegel's language about the infinite creativity of a thought which issues in a finite reality and which he calls the "self-finitizing of the infinite" what they may, it is not difficult to see how this can help us to understand him when he speaks of human rational thought as an "infinitizing of the finite." If it is true to say that it is impossible (presumably for us finite mortals) to conceive the infinite without conceiving the finite (since the conceiving is finite activity), it is equally true to say that infinite reality can be only as containing in its bosom, so to speak, the finite. By the same token, if it is true to say that infinite thought issues in an object which is finite, and this is creation, it does not seem absurd to say that finite thought issues in an object which is infinite (else the thought would be no more than partial thought), and this is re-creation. What is more, this finite thought is in an intelligible sense infinite, since it is self-determining, self-contained, not dependent on something outside itself in its re-creative activity.5 That finite thought is dependent on infinite thought offers, for Hegel, no contradiction: only if we spatialize thought is infinite thought "outside" finite thought; and thus in such a dependence the self-determination and self-containedness of even finite thought is not lost. There is, however, a difference between the infinity of infinite reason and the infinity of finite reason: the thought of infinite reason is prior both logically and ontologically to the finite reality which is its term; finite reason is logically but not ontologically prior to its term. The reality of the finite has as its criterion the rationality of the human thought which thinks it; it does not have it as its existential source. The Infinity of the Finite Back to the finite, which is not only in the unfortunate position of not being able to maintain itself in existence but is also by its very essence as finite destined to go out of existenceunless, of course, its link with the infinite is such as to sustain it in existence.6 Every being of "nature," for example, is
4. This leaves us with the difficulty, to be discussed later (chap. 6), that Hegel seems to be making creation necessary, what God cannot but do. Without here going into the intricacies of this problem, we can simply say that, for Hegel, just as unity and multiplicity, ideality and reality, infinity and finitude, are contradictory only for the finite thinking of Verstand, not for the infinite thinking of Vernunft, so too, the necessity which infinite thought imposes on itself in no way contradicts the freedom of infinite self-determination. It is difficult to think that anything we can truly say of God is not necessarily true of God. 5. To say, "not dependent on something outside itself" is simply to say that its thinking is its own activity, not a being-acted-upon. 6. For a reason which is not thoroughly clear to me Hegel never does discuss explicitly the question of the immortality of finite spiritnot, that is to say, philosophically, except, as we saw earlier (chap. 2), when he speaks of "immortality" as essential to the "concept" of man.
< previous page
page_178
next page >
< previous page
page_179
next page > Page 179
essentially finite, not only because it is limited in being related to and dependent on other beings of nature for its very being, but also because the ideality which unites it in the whole of nature is to be found not in itself but in another, that is, in spirit. Nature does not think, cannot be aware of itself, cannot contain itself, and can be idealizedinfinitizedonly in being thought by spirit (see WL I, p. 106); what nature is "in-itself" can be realized only in its "being-for-another." Only in spirit, which is infinite capacity for awareness, is there an awareness of both the finitude of the natural and the infinity of nature as ideal totality (ibid., p. 109). Nature without spirit, then, simply is not (ibid., p. 105). The "things" of nature, however, are not condemned to nothingness, precisely because "in the concept of the limit inherent in a something'' (ibid., p. 116) is contained "the contradiction which propels it beyond its limit" (ibid., p. 115) toward a totality which is unlimited and which is realizable only in thought (see VGP III, p. 435). Because, however, human thinking has a tendency to get bogged down in "categories of understanding," and because finitude is "simply (überhaupt) negation . . . the most stubborn category of understanding" (ibid., p. 117), thinking itself, often enough, refuses to go beyond the finite, seeing the finite as only finite (ibid., p. 118). The question, however, is whether the insistence on finitude is not self-defeating; could finitude be known as finitude, that is, as bursting at the seams to be beyond itself, if the knowing of this were not infinite, an infinitizing activitythe finite, simply as finite, cannot know its own finitude, whereas in being known it is carried beyond its limit (ibid., p. 121). This can make eminently good sense, if we consider how the concept of a particular "something" breaks down the barriers which confine that something to its particularity; for example, the concept of "man" as opposed to "some-one-particular" man. Nor is there here a question of mere abstract universality; it is rather a question of the interrelatedness of concrete totality. "If a particular existence contains the concept, not merely as an abstract self-identical being (Ansichsein), but rather as a totality which is independent (für sich seiende), as drive, life, feeling, representation, and so on, then this existence itself accomplishes both the transcending of and the having transcended its confinement (Schranke)" (ibid., pp. 12223). Thought does not lift the finite over the barrier which confines it; the finite itself surmounts the barrier in thought. Surmounting the barrier is the rationality inherent in reality (ibid., p. 123). Even where the passage is achieved only in abstract universality, it shows that the barrier of finitude is not insurmountable (ibid.). The being of natural "things" is simply indifferent to being thus confined; the being of the human strains at the bit to get beyond it, even if the getting beyond is achieved only in abstract understanding, which is not satisfactory (ibid., pp. 12425). It is finitude itself, then, which cries out for infinity, which makes the human mind, if it truly follows out its logical bent, incapable of resting con
< previous page
page_179
next page >
< previous page
page_180
next page > Page 180
tent with either its own finitude or the finitude of its object. If the mind thinks logically it is going to see that the infinite is the condition for the very possibility of the finite (ibid., p. 126), just as the mind can think the relatedness of one "thing" to another only if the foundation for the relatedness of the diverse is the unity of total interrelatedness which is the absolute. In fact, "the infinite in its simple concept can initially be looked at as a new definition of the absolute" (ibid., p. 125); that is, relativity-finitude is intelligible only if absoluteness-infinity is. ''It is not that infinity as such comes to be in the transcending of finitude as such; rather the finite is such that of its own nature it comes to be infinite. Infinity is its affirmative orientation (Bestimmung), what the finite in itself truly is" (ibid., p. 126); the finite is destined to be infinitized in thought (ibid., p. 127). It is not enough, however, that the mind cannot think the finite without thinking the infinite; the foundation of the impossibility of thinking the finite must be the impossibility that the finite be without the infinite (ibid., p. 129). Finite and infinite are inseparable not only in thought but also in reality (ibid.), which means that the finite in passing beyond itself has to be more than endless repetition of essential finitude (ibid., p. 130). Nevertheless, the finite can pass beyond itself only in thought (ibid., p. 131): the finite is the "external realization of the concept" (ibid., p. 132); the infinite is the rational concept in which the finite finds its full reality (ibid., p. 135). True infinity, then, is reality. "Not the finite but rather the infinite is the real" (ibid., p. 139), the truth of which is to be found in the ideality of "essence, concept, idea" (ibid.). The finite shares this reality, "not as independent but as a moment" (ibid.). Thus, the ideal is not the negation of the real but the negation of that which negatives the real, that is, finitude (ibid., p. 140). After all this it may well seem rather arbitrary to employ such a grandiose term as "infinity" to designate the ideality which characterizes the rational conceptualization which in turn unifies the multiplicity and diversity of the finiteeven if the proviso is included that the unity in question is not a cloak thrown over the multiple by subjective thinking. Worse still, it may seem not only arbitrary but futile to try to come to grips with the unique infinity of God by finding in the infinity which characterizes ideality a sort of model which makes the infinity of God intelligible. If, then, we are to avoid falling into a trap of our own (or Hegel's) making, we must first move on with him to a consideration of the infinity of the concrete singular, which he treats under the heading of Fürsichsein, and then move backward, so to speak, to Phenomenology of Spirit, wherein Hegel makes it clear that only of a being which is spirit does it make sense to speak of infinity at all. In doing this we must bear in mind that, for Hegel, to think out the thought which has reality for its object is to discover the implications of reality, one of which is that without infinite reality there simply is no reality at all. "The whole of the Science of Logic, then, becomes an extended proof that being
< previous page
page_180
next page >
< previous page
page_181
next page > Page 181
is infiniteor that infinite being isand, correlative to this, that the reason which knows infinite being is itself infinite."7 In thinking out the implications of thought, then, it is inevitable that the thinking of being should come up against a being which is special, which is not only a thought being but also a thinking beingthinking thinks itself, is selfconscious; there is self-conscious being (Selbstbewusst-sein). It is in this category that the perfection of being will be foundor else it will not be found at all (or there will not be any finding at all). Such a being, even though "posited" (gesetzt) by thought as its own object, is "complete" (vollbracht) in itself, depending on nothing outside itself for being what it is (WL I, p. 148) and is, thus, "the parade example (das nächste Beispiel) of the presence of infinity" (ibid.), of which it is characteristic to become other while remaining the same (see EpW, no. 95). The being in question is the being an object has for the one who thinks it, but the object and the one who thinks it are one and the same. "The ideal is necessarily for one, but it is not for another [one]; the one for which it is is only itself'' (WL I, p. 149). This is true of the "I" (who thinks); it is true of "spirit" (which is active source of thinking); it is, above all, true of "God" (the active source of all reality): "God, therefore, is for-self, in the sense that (insofern) he is himself that which is for him" (ibid., p. 150). The being, then, which the I, spirit, God have is "ideal," but not ideal merely in the sense of "not-real" (ibid.). The infinity which must be said of this ideal being is not the vague, undifferentiated infinity of Parmenides' "being," nor yet that of Spinoza's "substance"; rather it is the selfdifferentiating being, whose determinations are its own activities, differences which do not limit each other (ibid., pp. 15152). Once again we are up against the seeming contradiction of unity and multiplicitynot merely the trite, "there is a one and there are also many ones," but the much more difficult and significant, "there is one which is also many, and there are many which are also one." In true Plotinian fashion Hegel sees this as explicable only in terms of Aristotle's nohsiVnohsewV, which he calls "infinite self-determining," wherein the relation to what is other is not different from the relation to self. This is not to say that the self and the other are identical (let alone synonymous), but that the relation to other is the relation to self.8 There is (dialectical) distinction between the self and others, without loss of unity in the self, because thought's thinking itself (nohsiVnohsewV) is its thinking what is other than itselfthe distinctions are its own (ibid., p. 155)it is "the absolute unification of the relation to what is other and the relation to itself" (ibid.). That Hegel should apply the nohsiVnohsewV *which Aristotle applies only to Godto the I and
7. Quentin Lauer, Essays in Hegelian Dialectic (New York: Fordham University Press, 1977), pp. 14243. 8. This will be spelled out in much greater detail in chapter 6.
< previous page
page_181
next page >
< previous page
page_182
next page > Page 182
the spirit should cause no panic; the application is not identical in all three; Hegel simply hopes that, if we can see its applicability to the I and the spirit, we shall see how it applies a fortiori to God, who is absolute I and absolute Spirit. By the same token we should not be thrown off by Hegel's metaphors, borrowed from the science of his day, which he employs in an effort to illustrate the dynamic character of the relationship between unity and multiplicity. What hs is trying to show is that, when the mind seeks to think the unity of the one and the multiplicity of the many (ones), neither unity nor multiplicity are simply given, to be analyzed by a subject who thinks. If, then, we are to think dynamically, we can conceive of multiplicity as a multiplication of ones and unity as a unification of many (ones); not that the one becomes many or that the many become one (ibid., p. 158) but that the one conceived as one breaks itself up into many, and the many conceived as many unify themselves into one (concept) (ibid.). More than that, if both unity and multiplicity are inseparable from the concept of any reality, then they belong essentially to the reality in question; that is, it is inconceivable that they should not, "for a determination which belongs to the concept of a thing (Sache) must truly be contained in it" (ibid., p. 172). What Hegel is saying, further, is that multiplicity must be conceived as a movement from one to many, and that unity must be conceived as a movement from many to one. Contradictory? Yes, but that is precisely the point: There is no solution short of the infinity which resides in concrete (Vernunft), not abstract (Verstand), thought. "The multiplicity of the ones is infinity, as unabashedly (unbefangen) self-producing contradiction" (ibid., p. 160). Now, clumsy and inadequate as the metaphors may be, Hegel seeks to illustrate the reciprocal movements (unity-to-multiplicity and multiplicityto-unity) in terms of two quasi-forces familiar to the physics of his day, "attraction'' and "repulsion." Repulsion designates the movement of the one breaking itself up into many; attraction, the movement of the many into the unity of the ideal one. Like positive and negative electricity, attraction and repulsion imply each other; neither is intelligible except as related to the other. It is not merely, however, that the mind must think of them as inseparable; in the real order the condition for the possibility of the many is the breaking up of the one, and the condition for the possibility of the one is the unification of the many. But here, in Hegel's exposition, a subtle shift of thought takes place. Reality, at least in the accepted sense, is multiple; ideality, on the other hand, is unified (multiplicity). In terms of "attraction" and "repulsion," repulsion is "the reality of the one," that is, ideality realizing itself; attraction is "the posited ideality of that reality" (ibid., p. 164), that is, the multiplicity of reality demands unification in ideality. Ideality, then, is the condition for the possibility of reality: (1) as the source from which reality flowsdivine infinite Spiritand (2) as the
< previous page
page_182
next page >
< previous page
page_183
next page > Page 183
unifier which makes reality intelligiblethe "infinity" of human thinking spirit. Neither makes sense without the other: "Attraction is attraction only through the mediation of repulsion, just as repulsion is repulsion only through the mediation of attraction" (ibid., p. 167). Mutatis mutandis, we can apply this to divine (one) and human (multiple) spirit: to know what it is to say that the unique divine Being is Spirit, we must look to spirit as realized in man for a clue; to know what we are saying when we say that man is spirit, we must look to the divine Being who is in himself all that spirit can be. If we do this, we may find out what "infinite" means when it is said of both. This, however, is the task of Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit, to which we now turn. Phenomenology of Spirit When we look at the Phenomenology we may be surprised to find that the term "infinite" (unendlich), along with its cognates, "the infinite" (das Unendliche) and "infinity" (Unendlichkeit), occurs rather infrequently; much more often Hegel employs the term "absolute" or "the absolute.'' In the earlier writings, as we have seen, particularly Differenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen Systems der Philosophie, Glauben und Wissen, and the writings of the Jena period, on the other hand, the term "infinite" occurs with baffling frequency. If we combine the frequent occurrence of the term in the earlier writings with the seeming hesitation to employ it in the Phenomenology and add to that the remark we have already seen from the first volume of Science of Logic, "the infinite in its simple concept can initially be looked upon as a new definition of the absolute," we can be led into some interesting surmises, which we cannot develop here, regarding the technical importance of the term as it is employed in the earlier writings. At any rate, in this regard the Phenomenologyterminologically at leastseems to be transitional. The term "infinity" occurs initially in chapter III, "Force and Understanding,"9 where Hegel is trying to point up (1) the tendency of the mind to move from the merely finite to the infinite, and (2) the fundamental incapacity of understanding to make this move, because its thinking is essentially finite and thus incapable of coming to grips with true infinity. As might be expected it occurs alsoalthough sparinglyin chapter IV, "Self-Consciousness," since it is there that the characteristic whereby consciousness finds the other of itself in itself, thus remaining in itselfa feature of infinity which we have already seen elaborated in Science of Logicbegins to assume prominence. In chapter V, "Reason," where Hegel begins to plumb the significance of reason's
9. We can here ignore the occurrence of the term in the preface, which is as much an epilogue as a prologue.
< previous page
page_183
next page >
< previous page
page_184
next page > Page 184
awareness "that it is all reality," the concept of infinityif not the termassumes greater importance. It is not until chapter VII, "Religion," however, that the infinity of the absolute Spirit who is Godthe term is still scarceboth points the way to the importance of the concept in Science of Logic and in Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion and thematizes the infinity of divine Spirit as a foreshadowing of the relative infinity of the finite spirits which are its manifestations (Gestalten). Finally, in chapter VIII, "Absolute Knowing," the whole movement comes to a head in the awareness that out of the prolonged investigation of the "spirits'' which are the manifestations of the absolute emerges the true infinity of the absolute itself: "from the chalice of this realm of spirits there foams forth to him [the Absolute Spirit] his infinity" (p. 564).10 It is the infinity of absolute Spirit to embrace within itselfand, thus, to infinitizethe finitude of multiple spirits. If there is one thing that the foregoing painfully brief summary of the movement of Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit should make clear, it is that phenomenology, as Hegel conceives it, consists in an investigation of consciousness (whether by consciousness itself going through its process of development or by the philosopher observing the process) which finds in consciousness itself all the evidence necessary for the objectivity of that of which consciousness is conscious. What the investigation, then, discovers is that the process is throughout that of rational thought, which is not a process of "inference" at all but a "thinking consideration," wherein thought raises itself above the sensibleor else it is not truly thoughtand thus passes from the kind of limited perspective which characterizes the sensible to the limitless perspective which characterizes the intelligible, the essential suprasensible (EpW, nos. 7576). In this is contained a recognition that, if the finite is to be thought at all it must be in the thinking of the infinite. This is but another way of saying that the true being of the sensible is its intelligible being, or that the being of the sensible is to be found in its intelligibility, which is the object of thought, not sense. Whatever one's propensities for explanation may beand these prephilosophical (perhaps unphilosophical) propensities usually dictate what one's interpretation of Hegel is going to beit scarcely seems possible for anyone to ignore that man is a peculiarly double being, composed of an organic body, subject in all its operations to the laws which govern the physical universephysical, chemical, and biological lawsand a conscious activity which, no matter what the efforts to explain it reductively on purely natural grounds, is uniquely characteristic of the human organism. Hegel, for one, is thoroughly convinced from the very beginning of his
10. We have already seen, at the end of chapter 3, a striking parallel to this passage in VPR II, p. 320, where Hegel is speaking of the "Realization of the [spiritual] community": "Out of the ferment of finitude, because it is transformed into foam, the Spirit arises like vapor."
< previous page
page_184
next page >
< previous page
page_185
next page > Page 185
philosophizing that man's conscious activity belongs to an order of reality, the spiritual, which is simply other than the activity of physical nature. It is for this reason that, at the beginning of his mature philosophizing, he institutes a study of human consciousness, a Phenomenology of Spirit, as a sort of prologue to the whole philosophical endeavor. Added to his own conviction that consciousness is spiritual activity, all the resources for which are to be found within the activity itself, is the conviction that man, any man, if he honestly examines consciousness (Bewusstsein), will become more and more aware that the activity examined is spiritual, that is, not proper to the order of physical (chemical, biological) nature. That the orientation of consciousness is ineluctably toward a knowing which is knowing and only that, that is, in no sense dependent on what is not-knowing ("absolute" in that sense at least), is a conviction which he will allow to grow as the result of the consistently honest examination. The examination will proceed by stages, each stage both demanding that the examination move on to the next stage and indicating what that next stage must be. The process might be likened to a progressive sloughing off of the limitations of what consciousness only "seems" to be, until its true reality is seen to be without limitations, infinite. Man is limited, dependent, finiteexcept on the spiritual side. The finite has to do with the other aspect of man's existence. As spirit, to the extent that spirit functions non-spiritually, it has to do with external things. When, however, man is spirit, precisely as spirit, then he is without limit. The limits of reason are only the limits of this subject's reason; but when man functions rationally, he is without limitations, infinite. [EGP, p. 182] We might put it this way: A knowing which has not reached its ultimate goal of being knowing and nothing else is only partial knowing and, therefore, partial nonknowing; on the other hand, a knowing which has reached its ultimate goal is "absolute"; but a knowing which does not have "the absolute" (whatever that is to mean) as its object is not itself absolute; and a knowing which has the absolute as its object11 has to be more than the merely finite activity of a merely finite agent. A basic premiss of the whole movement, to be confirmed in the process, is that in progressively examining that of which it is conscious, consciousness will consistently find, not something over-against and independent of itself, but rather its own product. This is to say that consciousness does not operate the way "things" operate (it is nothing); it does not act upon what is given to it from outside itself, the way natural "things" do; it
11. Here again the distinction between Gegenstand (object as over-against subject) and Objekt (object as a goal of striving) is important. For authentically rational thinking the absolute is not Gegenstand at all, it is Objekt.
< previous page
page_185
next page >
< previous page
page_186
next page > Page 186
gives itself its own content. This is not to say that there are not "things" out there of which consciousness is conscious; it is to say that it is conscious of them only by transforming them into its own product; the activity of thinking has thought and only thought as its termnor is it acted upon by what is other than itself. Initially what has just been said could seem to be nonsensical: How could consciousness give itself its own content and still be in touch with a reality which, in fact, is not its own product? Unless, of course, the opposite is even more nonsensical: How could a spiritual activity have as its content a reality which is other than spiritual? In coming to grips with "things" we examine the ideas of things, which is all we have to examine (even a computer does not scan things, only translations of them). In any event, it is not farfetched to say that in examining the ideas we have of reality, we not only come to a more concrete grasp of the reality which reveals itself progressively in ideasin coming to grips with the ideas we are coming to grips with the reality they reveal (e.g., the process of scientific advance)but we come to know more and more fully the spirit whose product the ideas are. The question then is whether the process will take us all the way to the infinite Spirit whose product is the very reality of the real. If it does not, it would seem, we shall never resolve the paradox of the unity of being and the multiplicity of beings. Scientific "understanding," as Hegel sees it, resolves the paradox by placing the abstract unity of the idea over-against the concrete multiplicity of realities; but this is not enough. So long as concepts are no more than the thoughts of individual subjects, they are as finite as are the subjects who think them; their unity (universality) is abstract, not concrete, and their concreteness is not universal, merely cumulative. Only a thought which integrates the multiplicity of the finite into the unity (totality) of the infinite can resolve the contradictions of finitude. The essential relativity of multiple finite beings can be unified only in the absoluteness of infinite being. The work to be done, then, cannot be performed by essentially finite understanding, which can see that only an infinite mind could solve the problem but of itself cannot come to terms with infinite mind as reality. Reason, on the other hand, whose function is not to break up unified reality into manageable fragments but to integrate the diverse fragments into an intelligible unity, can perform the task, because it does not receive its content from an alien source but rather is itself the source which gives itself a unified content. Here it is (at the end of chapter IV, "Self-Consciousness") that Hegel comes up with the startling statement that self-consciousness becomes aware that as reason "it is itself all reality." Initially this means little more than the triumphant assurance of the scientific mind, flushed with all its successes since the Renaissance, that there is indeed no reality with which it cannot cope. By stages, however, the claim will take on more and more profound significanceafter a large number of attempts on the part
< previous page
page_186
next page >
< previous page
page_187
next page > Page 187
of individual human reason to issue a principle which will serve to unify all reason in a finite way. The progression in meaning which the assurance takes on would seem to be the following: (1) In seeking to come to grips with reality reason has nowhere to look but into itself, since for reason to go outside itself does not make sense (Fichte), but this is no guarantee that it will find what it is looking for. (2) The rationality it finds in reality is, strictly speaking, not different from the rationality it finds in itself, since there is only one reason (Schelling), but this is only an assertion, not spelled out, of two manifestations of one and the same reason. (3) Ultimately, both the rationality of reality (which science must assume if it is to be viable) and the rationality of finite reason (which philosophy must assume if thought is to get anywhere) make sense only against the backdrop of one infinite reason which is the source of both (Hegel); "there is but one reason; there is no second, superhuman reason; reason is the divine in man" (EGP, p. 123). (4) Finite reason is valid as reason only because it is not merely finite but infinitizes itself in its conceptual grasp of the infinite object which gives meaning to all objectivity, as in itself the unified totality of all reality and rationality (see VA I, pp. 204205). (5) The unification of diverse finite reasons in one overarching (in space and time) human spirit will, again, be no more than abstract, if the diversity of spirits is not seen as the self-diversification of one infinite Spirit which is more than human, more than finitethe lesson of both chapter VIII and the preface to the Phenomenology. A hint of where all this is going can be seen in the spiritual unity of the human communityas opposed to the natural unity of the human species. Reason, then, will be able to see itself as truly "all reality" only as effectuating reality, and this it can do initially as a communal spirit effectuating a moral order which applies to each and every member of the community. If, however, the community in question is only a particular communitya particular peoplethe moral order effectuated will be only a particular moral order, which must be rationally extended to the total human community if it is to be effectively real. But even this universality is scarcely "all reality"; it is no more than a hint of the kind of "allness" which has spirit as its source. It is also, however, a kind of relative "infinity" resident in the human spirit, the infinity of self-containedness which gives itself a universal moral law. And that, Hegel tells us, is about as far as human spirit can go without, so to speak, starting all over again. Spirit does not really know what it is to be spirit if all it knows is itself as moral spirit. Even its own moral quasi-infinity will come up empty unless it rises above the moral consciousness to a consciousness which has the truly infinite being as its object, that is, religious consciousness. It can, of course, be saidand it has been saidthat any spirit which finds all the objectivity it looks for in itself is in
< previous page
page_187
next page >
< previous page
page_188
next page > Page 188
finite, but its "infinity" will be a rather sad copy of the real if it simply stops there. There is a kind of infinity in self-conscious spirit, but that infinity will be authentic only if the self-consciousness in question is at the same time consciousness of the truly infinite Being who is divine. Religion, even in its most primitive stages, pierces through the veil of finitude which hems it in to find an infinite which both is beyond the finite and inhabits it. But what can it mean to say, as Hegel does, that religion is a Gestalt of self-conscious spirit wherein the human spirit, in being conscious of itself is also conscious of the divine, the infinite Spirit? It means at least that the human spirit does not know itself as spirit short of knowing all that being spirit implies, and this it cannot know short of knowing what divine infinite (absolute) Spirit is, and only if divine Spirit communicates itself to human spirit can the latter know this. The communication can be the self-revelation of the Absolute which takes place in what we call "creation." But, says Hegel, even creation is an adequate revelation of God only against the backdrop of a more intimate revelation of God in "revealed religion," where creation is seen as continuous with the inner life of God, as a "moment" in the totality of that inner life. Although revelation itself is a communication limited by the form which mediates it, a multiplicity of finite "representations" of unique infinite reality, the content of that revelation, that is, absolute Spirit, God, makes it clear that a human knowing which falls short of knowing absolute Spirit is not knowing in the fullest possible sense. For Hegel, then, "revealed religion" (PdG), "absolute religion" (VPR), is the Christian religion, in which is recapitulated the coming-to-be of the human spirit, as transcending any and every finite spirit. Until this transcendent spirit, however, is concretized in thought it remains the cumulative total of finite spirits and, thus, still a finite grasp of infinite reality; man is conscious of God as infinite reality but not yet conscious that this consciousness is his own complete self-consciousness, which it will not be until God's consciousness of himself in the finite spirit which is his creation coalesces with that finite spirit's consciousness of itself. Here Hegel's theology enters in once more: God as infinite self-consciousness in thinking what is other than himself, that is, created reality, "others" himself while remaining totally within himself. This, then, is the paradigm of spiritual awareness, knowing that to know what is other than itself is not different from knowing itself. If this is essential to the knowing which is proper to spirit, it must be true not only of God, the uniquely infinite Spirit, but also of the human spirit, which as truly knowing must in some sense share this infinity. For spirit to know at all is to ''posit" that of which spirit is conscious and to remain "with itself" in so doing. For the finite self to know the absolute self is to know truly, and it is to know itself truly. This is to say that the "being" which the finite spirit
< previous page
page_188
next page >
< previous page
page_189
next page > Page 189
knows in knowing itself is a "being-in" the infinite, where alone finite spirit can find itself. As we saw before, in his Science of Logic Hegel sees "the infinite" as a "new definition of the absolute." Whenever, then, in the Phenomenology, Hegel says "absolute" we can legitimately substitute ''infinite." This helps to tie together the Phenomenology and the Logic. What the full import of this tieing together is we shall see if we look at Hegel's Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, which he did not publish himself, and his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, which he did publish himself (in several editions). With regard to Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion one could, by examining its three parts, find nearly everything that we have been saying about Hegel's theory of infinite being. Most pertinent, it is true, is what he has to say in part III, "Absolute Religion," section B, "The Metaphysical Concept of the Idea of God," where he spells out in far more detail what he had already written in chapter VII of Phenomenology of Spirit. If, however, we are to see this section in proper perspective we must pick up from the beginning of Philosophy of Religion, not forgetting that even this will be intelligible only if we have first seen the foundation laid in the Logic and Phenomenology. Philosophy of Religion What becomes obvious from the very beginning is that, for Hegel, it is not possible to speak of infinity, unless that of which it is being said is "spirit"and, conversely, that to speak of spirit without speaking of infinite spirit is simply to miss the point of spiritual being, self-contained being. To say "infinite" is to say "spirit," that is, a being which is free, effectuating its own determination, a being which is "object to itself" and is, thus, "with itself" in its object: "for freedom means to be self-contained, or at home with itself" (VPR I, p. 65). Such a being need not look elsewhere for what is requisite to being itself. Later he will define "consciousness of freedom" as "infinite beingfor-self" (VPR II, p. 260). What is most important to note here is that the infinity which is inseparable from spirit, including human spirit, finds no obstacle in the finitude of the very same spirit. To say that for human spirit to lift itself to a grasp of the infinite is to infinitize itself is not to say that in so doing it relinquishes its finite empirical mode of operation (VPR I, pp. 6869); empirical thinking is truly thinking only on condition that the empirical be aufgehoben, that is, canceled, retained, and lifted up. The finite does not cease to be finite, but its very finitude reveals that its foundation is infiniteor else the finite simply is not (ibid., p. 107). Nor is it the thinking subject who recognizes this and thus cancels out finitude; it is the finite content of thought, which, because it is
< previous page
page_189
next page >
< previous page
page_190
next page > Page 190
not sufficient unto itself, bespeaks an infinite without which it would not be (ibid., p. 109). Finite reality is indeed necessary; the infinite idea which is necessary to the very conceivability of the finite can manifest itself only finitely (ibid., pp. 11314).12 We must, of course, remind ourselves again that, for Hegel, to know what thought must necessarily think is to know what must necessarily be: If thought, then, necessarily passes beyond the finite to the infiniteas a necessary condition for thinking the finitethis is itself proof of the necessity of the infinite (ibid., p. 165). We shall see this later as Hegel's interpretation of the "ontological argument" for the reality of God (chap. 5). Here, however, he is speaking not only of the necessary infinity of thought's ultimate object but also of the necessary infinity of a thought which is truly spiritual. For the human mind to be conscious of being finite is itself a passage beyond the limitations of finitude, because it is to know itself as spiritual in the spirituality of its knowing (ibid., pp. 16768). Thus, Hegel tells us, to affirm only finitude of self is not, as some would have it, humility; it is the pride of holding a finite self to be adequate, to be the only infinite there is (ibid., p. 182). It might well seem that, as this thought unfolds, the distinction between finite and infinite is gradually becoming blurred; the finite is infinite and the infinite is finite. What has happened to the distinction? It is not being denied; to do that would be to affirm "the dark night in which all the cows are black." The distinction is being affirmed, but as a dialectical distinction of dynamic relationship, where finite and infinite are only in the passage from one to the other (WL I, p. 125). To say that the "I" is infinite or that God is finite is not to employ the prepositional "is," which could result only in contradiction; it is to affirm ''activity, vitality, and spirituality" of both the "I" and God (VPR I, p. 192). Hegel will later say that the created world is the finitizing of the infinite (VPR II, p. 236); God himself cannot create an infinite world. Here he says that the infinite divine activity of creation both posits (puts into being) the world and lifts it to infinity in the human spirit (ibid.). In the present context religion is the liftingup in questionnot the finite activity of a finite subject, but the infinite activity of the infinite in the finite (VPR I, p. 198), the presence of the divine in the human, which, as we shall see later, is what "revelation," "lifting-up" (Erhebung) means (VPR II, p. 220). The divine spirit present in human self-consciousness (ibid., p. 305) is the very "eternity of spirit" (ibid., p. 330). Thus, to say that "infinite" is the "ideal quality of thought" is to say that spirit which is characterized by thought is the only being of which it makes sense to say "infinite." Although it is Hegel's contention that only with the ad-
12. This, of course, brings up the thorny question, which we shall have to deal with more fully in chapter 6. Can the infinite (spirit) be without othering itself? Can the other of the othering be other than finite? Hegel will answer with a distinction: Infinite Spirit must indeed other itself, but this othering is both infinite (Trinity) and finite (creation).
< previous page
page_190
next page >
< previous page
page_191
next page > Page 191
vent of Christianitythe "absolute" religionis God recognized as spirit and only spirit, he nevertheless sees even in the most primitive "religion of nature" a passage beyond the finite natural object of worship to the infinite divine object (VPR I, p. 308). This is, however vaguely, to see the being of the finite in the infinite, to rise to God as more than an abstract infinity (the sort of infinity which the mind as mere "understanding" cannot but think of despite its inability to resolve the contradiction it finds here) (ibid., pp. 31112). As we have already seen in our discussion of Science of Logic, it is not enough to recognize infinity in human spirit as overarching totality. If it is true to say that the characteristic of self-determination has the quality of infinity (VPR II, p. 10), infinity must also be said of the individual human subject. This is what Hegel means when he speaks here (ibid., p. 128) and, more than once, in Philosophy of Right (e.g., nos. 35, 39, 125, 218) of the "infinite rights" of the human subject, that is, the subject which, by virtue of its own being, is the source of its own rights; they are not assigned to it by another.13 It is for this reason, too, that he can speak of the Incarnation (of God in a human individual) as the paradigm of "infinitizing" the individual (VPR II, p. 141). The infinity of God as Trinity is the uniquely concrete infinite (ibid., pp. 22829), an identity in difference which is not merely abstract and which only reason (not understanding) can comprehend (ibid., pp. 23031). This permits Hegel, in a manner reminiscent of Plato's Phaedo, to speak of human "immortality" as a qualitative not quantitative (durational) concept, the infinite quality of the soul (ibid., p. 303). All that we have seen up to this point in Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion is clearly, in Hegel's mind, for the most part only preparatory to what is philosophically the most important section in these lectures, namely section B of part III ("Absolute Religion"), which bears the implausible and clumsy title, "The Metaphysical Concept of the Idea of God" (Der metaphysische Begriff der Idee Gottes). If, however, we bear in mind that the term Begriff as Hegel employs it need not always be translated "concept" and that the verb begreifen from which the noun is derived contains the overtones of "comprehend,'' we might be more accurate in speaking of "comprehending metaphysically the idea of God." What is involved in comprehending" is: (1) that only if reality is itself conceptual can it be thought and, therefore known; (2) that "idea," abstractly defined, is the "unity of concept and reality"; (3) that "knowing" reality is a passage from the abstract idea of reality to the concrete reality; and (4) that this passage is the self-concretizing of the concept (ibid., p. 205). Applying this to God, then, the first step is the abstract idea of God, what we mean when
13. The sort of thing described by Hegel in chapter VI of PdG under the heading "The Situation of Right" (Rechtszustand), referring to the Roman Empire.
< previous page
page_191
next page >
< previous page
page_192
next page > Page 192
we say "God." This, Hegel tells us, is the pure concept which "durch sich selbst" is real, which can only be the "absolute Idea," that is, Spirit in the fullest possible sense (ibid.), the "being than which no greater can be conceived" of Anselm. In this context the transition from the abstract idea to the concrete reality, without which the idea itself is not even a possibility, is what Hegel calls the "proof'' that God is real. "Proof," however, will be meaningless unless the finite human spirit is real, as both the manifestation of the divine spirit and the spirit to which the divine spirit is manifested. The proof, then, of the reality of "absolute Spirit" is the reality of the human spirit, and the concrete idea of spirit is the "unity of divine and human nature," paradigmatically in the divinehuman nature of God incarnate and consequently in the divinizing of the human spirit which knows (begreift) infinite Spirit. If the attempt is made to express the truth of this divine-human unity in a proposition, what comes out is only difference: "The divine is not the human"; "the human is not the divine." The "is" of the logical proposition simply cannot express the movement, the process which is the essence of spirit. "Spirit, then, is the living process wherein (dass) the abstract (an sich seiende) unity of the divine and human nature is concretized (für sich und hervorgebracht werde)" (ibid.). The implications of the abstract idea are progressively explicated, that is, seen to be concretely real, and this is what has been traditionally called the "ontological argument" for the reality of God, wherein the necessary reality of infinite Spirit is seen in its very idea. In other "proofs," on the contrary, the movement is from the factual reality of the finite to the necessity of infinite reality. True "comprehension" demands both movements: without infinite reality there would be no finite; an infinite reality which did not issue in finite reality would not itself be real (in any intelligible sense). Hegel's concern, of course, is to say "infinite" in an intelligible sense of an absolute Being for whom issuing in finite reality is a "necessity." In any event, Hegel sees both movements of thought as philosophically necessary: Finite spiritthe only spirit that philosophizescannot comprehend its own finitude without moving on to infinity, nor can it comprehend infinity except as issuing in finitude. The path between concept and reality is a two-way street: Finite spirit cannot conceive itself without positing the reality of infinite Spirit, and infinite Spirit cannot conceive itself without positing the reality of finite spirit (in a finite world). "Neither [concept nor being] must have merely the determination of remaining simply a starting-point, a source (ein Ursprüngliches);14 each must rather manifest
14. The play on words is significant but untranslatable. The term Sprung is ordinarily translated as "leap" or "jump." The prefix ur, which signifies "Original" gives Ursprung, which is translated as "origin" or "source," but it can carry the connotation of a "springboard," which remains behind, when the leap is madeprecisely the connotation Hegel wants to eliminate.
< previous page
page_192
next page >
< previous page
page_193
next page > Page 193
itself as going over into the other, i.e., each must be as posited [by the other]" (ibid., p. 206). Nor has much been gained by saying that concept passes to being, since to say being is to say nothing (cf. WL I, pp. 6667) except "abstract self-identity" (VPR II, p. 206); abstract concept demands no more than abstract being (ibid., p. 207). What is significant is the concrete relation of concept to being, and this is "the profoundest interest of reason" (ibid.). To grasp this concrete relation is to resolve the opposition between self-identity and self-differentiation, the infinite in the finite and the finite in the infinite. "The appearing (Erscheinung) of this opposition is a sign that subjectivity has reached the acme of its being-for-self (concretion), has achieved the totality of knowing itself in itself as infinite and absolute" (ibid.). To put it somewhat crudely, it takes an infinite to know the infinite. "Within itself finite spirit has achieved this grasp of its own infinity" (ibid.). The gulf between finite spirit and the infinite Spirit over against it, however, would seem to be impassable (if, of course, infinite Spirit is ''over-against" finite spirit). Only if the finite subject can recognize its own infinity can it resolve the opposition, seeing the relation as not that of finite to infinite but of infinite to infinite. Thus, the condition for the finite spirit's comprehending infinite Spirit as infinite is to grasp itself as infinite, having the infinite capacity to posit the infinite, or knowing that there are no limits to its capacity to posit. "Spirit is simply this, even (selbst) in the opposition to comprehend (erfassen) itself infinitely" (ibid., p. 208). We are back again with the ontological argument, which proves to be not an illegitimate inference from a finite concept to an infinite reality, precisely because it is not an inference at all. The "argument," it is true, does begin from the "concept" of God, but we shall appreciate its force only if we ask the question, "What, then, is the concept of God?" (ibid.). To answer the question is obviously difficultsome would say impossiblebecause it requires putting into language, whose function is to express abstract concepts, the most concrete of all realities. If one were to reply, "God is infinite Being," "God is the supreme Being," or even, "God is all reality," one would fall into the trap of abstraction, thus indicating that God is a being unique in his distinction from all other beings, but actually limited by this very distinction from others. The point, then, is not to find a linguistic expression which will adequately define God, but rather to use language in such a way that the concept emerges without being defined at all.15 The concept is "the most real of concepts"; "its content has no limitations"; "it is all reality and only as reality is it without limitation." "Being is reality which belongs to the concept of God" (ibid.). Has Hegel's language performed the task he set for it? To answer this second question requires two steps. (1)
15. Which, interestingly enough, would seem to be the Platonic dialectic also.
< previous page
page_193
next page >
< previous page
page_194
next page > Page 194
We must recall a statement we already saw from the Phenomenology, "Reason is all reality," where the "is" of the proposition indicates neither attribution nor identification, but the process of becoming. The concept of God, then, is ''all reality" both as the source of the becoming of all reality and in the sense that to conceive God is to conceive the totality of reality. (2) We must conceive of God as the only reality in which there is absolute identity of concept and being; the concept of God is absolute reality. This can make sense, however, only if it can somehow be said that the reality of any real being is its concept, that is, that which constitutes the reality of the real. That Hegel should have said this in the wake of Kant's shattering separation of all concept and all being is a testimony not only of Hegel's boldness but also to his unshakable conviction that only as thought is being really real, that reality shares with thought the latter's conceptual structure. What all this comes down to is that when Hegel says (thinks) "concept" he does not mean what Kant means when Kant says (thinks) "concept." For Kant, conceptany conceptis simply other than the being of which it is concept; because it is what mind forms for itself in thinking (Vorstellung), it merely stands for (vorstellt) a reality it does not, cannot, contain. Even when thought says "being," the being it says "is no reality . . . being is not a determination proper to the content of thought; it is rather pure form" (ibid., pp. 208209). If we go this far with Kant, we are compelled to go further; that which is not part of the content of a concept cannot be derived from the content of the concept16from the concept of one hundred dollars there is simply no way of deriving the reality of the hundred dollars, nor can the reality ever be grasped conceptually. Then comes Kant's lyric leap: The reality of God, therefore, can simply not be grasped conceptually, no concept can contain that realityor, perhaps, only God can grasp conceptually his own reality, all we can do is believe it, or postulate it for practial reasons. It is easy to see why Kant had to reject Anselm's "ontological argument." According to Anselm there is only one way of conceiving God, namely, as most perfect being. But, if the God as conceived is only a representation and not reality, then the God conceived is not most perfect, that is, is not God. Therefore, the God who is conceived is (or else the conceiving does not conceive God). Hegel, too, is not quite happy with the form Anselm's argument takes, that is, the formal-logical employment of concepts by a subject in order to come up with a conclusion. Hegel would agree that the human subject does not prove the existence of God, but that rather, the concept of God proves its own reality. But that is not Kant's objection. Hegel agrees with Anselm that to conceive of the most perfect being is to conceive of the most perfect being as existing (ibid., p. 209). He also
16. This is the sort of thinking which characterizes formal logic (scientific "understanding"), where the conclusion of argumentation is contained in the premises and permits no movement beyond the premisses.
< previous page
page_194
next page >
< previous page
page_195
next page > Page 195
contends that nowhere does Kant prove "the difference between concept and being" (ibid., p. 210). What Kant fails to see, Hegel thinks, is that, where the being in question is infinite being, the difference of being and concept does not preclude the identity of being and concept. Where the propositional "is" signifies only identity, the concept of God is not the reality of God. Where "is," however, says "bespeaks," the concept of God is the reality of God; the concept itself is a possibility only if God is. The task Hegel sets himself, then, is that of transcending the difference between concept and being, recognizing at the same time the risk of ending up with empty words, which is what transcending by believing without knowing does (ibid.). ''Thus, what is to be demonstrated is that the determination of being is contained in the concept; this, then, is the unity of concept and being" (ibid.). In this unity, however, the difference of concept and being (they are not synonymous) is to be both preserved and reconciled, which they are when the concept is seen as the movement of reconciliation, its self-objectification (ibid., p. 211). The Necessary Connection of Thinking and the Reality of God The problem, of course, is that the reconciliation, if it takes place only in the mind of the finite thinking subject (a Vorstellung), gets nowhere. It is true that the concrete concept of "the most perfect" says "being," but if it is a mere concept, without further determination, it says nothing, nor does the mere presupposition that concept and reality are united in idea say anything more (ibid.). What is all comes down to is getting rid of the Kantian error of seeing the concept as having no reality but that which our finite minds give it (ibid., p. 212); the error, which Kant inherited from Locke and Hume, of considering as concrete only that which can be empirically grasped (ibid.). That which pure (not empirical) thought alone can grasp is more truly concrete, but pure thought is not the activity of the isolated human subject (ibid.). What "metaphysical" meant in the title of the section, then, was a grasp of reality which has as its foundation, not an empirical reality from which the idea of God is derived, but rather the idea of God which is the source of empirical reality (ibid., p. 213). The process, then, is one in which human thinking, recognizing that its validation can be guaranteed only by infinite thought, to which it cannot but rise if it is true to itself as thinking, progressively makes its own ("appropriates") what on inferior levels of conciousness it merely "represents."17 In this sense all authentic thinking "proves" the reality of God. The "infinite object," God, is the reality short of which human thinking cannot stop, if it is to be truly thinking and not simply opining. "It is the work of 'proofs' for God's
17. For a more extended development of this, see Lauer, Essays in Hegelian Dialectic, p. 98.
< previous page
page_195
next page >
< previous page
page_196
next page > Page 196
existence to carry on the march from finitude to infinity, which is a way of describing the movement of thought from the abstract to the concrete: 'The abstract is finite; the concrete is truth, the infinite object'" (ibid., p. 226).18 What human thinking must be able to recognizewhich it cannot, so long as the objects it thinks are only objects of senseis that the finite realities it thinks make sense only as objects of divine activity.19 The process of authentic thinking, then, is summed up in the "ontological proof," which is the "passage from the essential non-being of that which is merely finite to the essential infinity of being."20 "Infinite being," however, is "absolute truth," and absolute truth is God,21 whose reality is to manifest himself to a thinking which is actively, infinitely receptive of the manifestation.22 The finite spirit to which infinite Spirit reveals itself is only qualifiedly infinite, it is true, but it is nevertheless an inexhaustible capacity which cannot be satisfied by other than infinite actuality. All that we have seen so far regarding Hegel's thought on the concretely (actually) infinite Spirit which alone is capable of satisfying the infinite craving of spirit, we can find masterfully summarized in the concluding section of the Encyclopedia, entitled "Third Part of the Philosophy of Spirit: Absolute Spirit." It is perhaps the most systematic treatment of the topic in all of Hegel's writings. "Absolute Spirit," for Hegel, is spirit which is only spirit, endowed with all the predicates which are said of spiritinfinite, inexhaustible, self-conscious, selfdetermining, self-contained, self-sufficientin no way susceptible of the limitations which accompany its finite manifestations. It is the Spirit with which man has to do when he is operating at the highest peak of his spiritual potential, in artistic creativity, religious exaltation, and philosophical speculation. It is in Spirit thus understood that the concept of what it is to be spirit and the reality which is spirit are identicalidentified in knowledge of the "absolute Idea," which is absolute Spirit wholly objectifiedto itself [EpW, no. 553). In one very important sense religion has to be looked upon as the supreme human endeavor to have God, infinite Spirit, as its object, and in this sense the believing which stretches out to God is not opposed to the knowing which seeks to conceive the very same God, who dwells in the human spiritual community and thus makes possible both believing and knowing. "Religion . . . is to be looked upon both as that which proceeds from the subject while remaining in the subject and as that which proceeds objectively from the absolute Spirit, who is as Spirit in his community" (ibid., no. 554). In this context artistic activity, both as creative and appreciative of the
18. See ibid., p. 129. 19. Ibid., p. 26. 20. Ibid., p. 127. 21. Ibid., p. 128. 22. Ibid., p. 132.
< previous page
page_196
next page >
< previous page
page_197
next page > Page 197
supremely beautiful work of art, is at once a knowing and a believing whose ultimate object is self-revealing absolute Spirit. Art is, it is true, first of all, an immediate grasp of a finite object, "the moment of finitude in art," but it is at the same time "the concrete contemplation (Anschauung) and presentation (Vorstellung) of the spirit which as the ideal is in itself absolute Spirit." The work of art is, of course, finite, but "in it natural immediacy is but a sign of the idea" (ibid., no. 556). Nor is this form of presentation adequate to the spirit it reveals: "it is not absolute Spirit which enters into this consciousness" (ibid., no. 557). "Absolute Spirit cannot be made explicit in so singular a manifestation; hence the spirit proper to fine art is a spirit limited to a particular people (ein beschränkter Volksgeist)'' (ibid., no. 559). Because the work of art is the arbitrary product of this or that artist, the artist is "the master of the god" (ibid., no. 560)and the art-work no more than a reminder of the true God. Art, then, is not enough; its product is not adequate to the self-manifestation of Spirit; and an art such as this is a need only of an inadequate religion. "With regard to the close connection between art and religion a more profound observation should be made, namely, that fine art can belong only to those religions in which the principle is concrete, interiorly liberated spirituality, which is not yet, however, absolute spirituality" (ibid., no. 562).23 The true God cannot be manifested sensibly at all, neither in the beautiful nor in the nonbeautiful object of sense, but only in thought, "the element in which alone pure spirit is . . . for spirit" (ibid.). The religion of art, then, must give way to the religion of revelation, wherein absolute Spirit makes itself known to finite spirit without the interposition of a sensible manifestation. The contact is strictly on the spiritual level, the level of self-acting intelligence, "in such a way that the content of the idea has as its principle the determination of free intelligence and is as absolute Spirit for spirit" (ibid., no. 563); spirit speaks to spirit. The point is that God makes himself known to the human spirit; there can be no question of mere "feeling" or of a believing in a weknow-not-what; a revelation which is not revelation to thinking spirit simply makes no sense. "Spirit is spirit only to the extent that it is for spirit, and in absolute religion it is absolute Spirit which manifests no longer abstract moments of itself but its very self" (ibid, no. 564); revelation cannot mean less than that. If God does not make himself known to man, then in truth he is, as Plato and Aristotle had said, a jealous God, keeping himself to himself, which, to say the least, is not very spiritual! "If, however, the word spirit is supposed to have a thoroughgoing meaning, then spirit involves the revelation of itself" (ibid.). This means that God's self-revelation demands the activity of
23. This should put an end to the complaints of those who object that Hegel's system spells the end of fine art. Only religion's need of art to express its own truth is ended, precisely because art, however sublime, is not adequate to what is to be expressed.
< previous page
page_197
next page >
< previous page
page_198
next page > Page 198
speculative thinking, if it is to be received as revelation, not as empty words. "To grasp correctly and determinately in thought what God as spirit is demands profound speculation. To say that God is spirit involves at the very least the following propositions: God is God only insofar as he knows himself; further, his knowledge of himself is his self-consciousness in man; and that is man's knowledge of God, which proceeds to man's self-knowledge in God" (ibid.). It is all there: to know self and not to know that knowing self involves knowing God is not to know self; self-knowing is itself infinite knowing. It might seem strange to some that at this point, in speaking of man's religious relationship to God, Hegel should choose to explicate what he has to say in terms of the threefold syllogism, of the universal, of the particular, of the individual. If, however, we remember that, for Hegel, to say that God is spirit is to say that God is trinity of persons and that the movement of trinitarian life involves (1) God in himself (universal), (2) the emergence of the reality which is this world in creation (particular), and (3) the divinizing of one man in the Incarnation (individual), all issuing in the dialectical identification of infinite Spirit and infinitized finite spirit, it may seem somewhat less strange. It may be that Hegel is dealing here with purely religious-theological truth, but he cannot be too far wrong in saying that only speculative thinking can come to grips with such truth at allif indeed, man is, as Hegel is convinced he is, to come to grips with the truth that is God. We must remember, too, that in an Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences, Hegel is less concerned with religious consciousness itself than he is with a philosophical comprehension of religion, the model of which comprehension is the logic of speculative thought. When, therefore, Hegel speaks of God conceived first of all as "creator of heaven and earth," we can catch unmistakable echoes of "the presentation of God as he is in his eternal essence before the creation of the world" (WL I, p. 31). Here, however, he adds the theological notion of God (Father) who in his infinite identity with himself generates a Son who is at once different from and identical with himself, the model of spiritual ''conceiving," in that spirit in knowing conceives itself. "In this eternal sphere, however, [God] generates only himself as his Son and at the same time remains in primordial identity with this differentiated one, who is characterized as being he who is distinguished from the universal essence, eternally transcending himself and by virtue of this mediation is essentially the first substance as concrete singularity and subjectivitywhich is what Spirit is" (EpW, no. 567). To comprehend God, however, as at once generating the distinct Son and remaining identical with that Son is to grasp also the movement of creation of a reality distinct and not yet identified with himself. "His movement is the creation of the appearing (Erscheinung), the sundering of the eternal moment of mediation, his only Son, into the independent
< previous page
page_198
next page >
< previous page
page_199
next page > Page 199
oppositon of, on one hand, heaven and earth, i.e., of elemental, concrete nature, and, on the other, of spirit as standing in relation to nature, i.e., finite spirit which as the extreme of negativity contained within itself signalizes (verselbständigt) itself as evil" (ibid., no. 568). "Evil" is to be understood here in the sense of what Hegel takes to be metaphorical "original sin," spirit's declaration of independence from nature, which is spirit's loss of innocence.24 Hegel understands this movement under the heading of ''particularity." Taking up the theme of "evil" in finite spirit's declaration of independence, he then sees the canceling of this evil through the Son's (as both distinct from and identical with the Father) taking upon himself sensible temporal existence, without ceasing to be infinite subjectivity identical with the divine self. Herein Hegel finds the reconciliation of universality and particularity in the individuality of the God-man, model of the union of divine and human spirit, "the idea of the eternal yet living Spirit present in the world" (ibid., no. 569). Whether or not one likes this "logicizing" of Christian revelation, it is not difficult to understand Hegel's contention that philosophy as philosophy could not be complete prior to Christian revelation.25 Nor is it difficult to see how the movement of thought Hegel describes is not that of any individual thinker, not even of the sum total of individual thinkers; it is the movement of thought transcending all finite thinking. Revelation itself, then, is syllogistic, explicating the self-othering and the return to self of divine infinite Spirit. These three syllogisms, which constitute the one syllogism of the absolute mediation of Spirit with itself, are Spirit's self-revelation, which explicate its life in the movement (Kreislauf) of concrete representational forms. Out of their dispersal, their temporal and external succession, the unfolding of the mediation resolves itself in its result, in the reconciliation (Zusammenschliessen) of Spirit with itself, not only into the simplicity of faith and emotional devotion but also into thinking, in whose immanent simplicity likewise the unfolding expands, but consciously as an inseparable collecting of the universal, simple, and eternal Spirit into itself. In this form of truth the truth is the subject-matter of philosophy. [Ibid., no. 571] It is for philosophy now to think out the implications of revealed truth, to think the infinite thought of God. Although, as we have seen, the content of fine art in the service of religion is absolute Spirit, both veiled and revealed, so to speak, in the sensible imagery of the art work, neither the artist who creates nor the devotee who contemplates is adequately conscious of just what this content is, because only in concept is adequate consciousness possible. Only in concept is the necessity of the content known, and only as
24. See chapter 7, "Philosophy and Theology." 25. The theme of chapter VII, section C, "The Religion of Revelation," in PdG.
< previous page
page_199
next page >
< previous page
page_200
next page > Page 200
necessary is the content known for what it is, absolute Spirit. By the same token, religion itselfwhich goes beyond art-in-the-service-of-religionalthough it grasps more profoundly its own self-revealing content, is not up to comprehending it, because the emotional element in religion still needs a form of objectivity which has not been liberated from the imagination, which throws over the content a cloak of sensibility, what Hegel calls "representation" (Vorstellung). This is the work of spirit, it is true, but of spirit functioning as understanding, which abstracts from sensible conditions without both cutting its ties with those sensible conditions and penetrating thoroughly to the reality they both embody and veil. As Hegel sees it, then, the task of comprehending the content of both art and religion devolves on philosophical knowing in the fullest sense of that term, that is, Wissenschaft. "Hence, this knowing is the concept of art and religion as recognized (erkannt) in thinking, the concept in which what is diverse in the content is recognized as necessary, and the necessary is recognized as free [selfdetermining]" (ibid., no. 572). The necessity of the concept is free in the sense that it is rationally self-determined. Thus rational thought is the only form adequate to a content which is necessary with the necessity of absoluteness, and this is where philosophy must step in. "This movement which is philosophy, is already complete, because at the end it grasps its own concept, i.e., simply looks back on its knowing (ibid., no. 573). It is true, of course, that religious faith, too, grasps the truth of the concept and that it does so because the divine Spirit in man bears witness to the truth, but only philosophy is ''comprehending reason." What is more, the content of philosophical reason is "speculative and, hence, religious." Still, it is rational in a way that religion is not, and only the human spirit at peak performance, that is, as rational, can come to terms with the spirit within it "witnessing to" the truth (ibid.). At this point, however, there arises a difficulty, which I need not go into at length since I shall do so in chapter 6, "Hegel's Pantheism." The difficulty comes from the contention that any philosophical knowledge of God is bound to be pantheistic, precisely because it cannot preserve the distinction between the knower and the known, thus blurring both the line which separates the divine from the human spirit and the line which separates the infinite Spirit, which the human claims to know, from the finite world, the knowing of which is not adequately distinguished from the knowing of God. If philosophy seeks to assign a precise meaning to "infinite reality," which religion need not do, the expression would seem at the very least to signify the "totality of reality," which would, it is claimed, identify God with the sum total of finite reality. The objection, Hegel tells us, comes from "this new theology which has turned religion into a subjective feeling and has denied any knowledge of God's nature. In so doing it has diluted, emptied out, its God" (ibid.). Philosophically the difficulty stems from a
< previous page
page_200
next page >
< previous page
page_201
next page > Page 201
failure to distinguish, when speaking of the world, between a unity of total interrelatedness and the unity of a numerical onethe mathematicizing tendency of contemporary thought. What, after all, has been said, if the world is said to be numerically one?which, Hegel tells us, is precisely what philosophy does not say. This can be said, he further states, only at the price of ignoring the innumerable multiplicity of determinations which characterize this one world. Philosophy, on the other hand, finds the model of totality in the spiritual unity of conceptual thought, according to which only in thinking the infinite unity of divine Spirit is it possible to conceive the unity of the world. "Because philosophy, it is true, has to do with unity as such and not with abstract unity, the unity of mere identity, the empty absolute, but with concrete unity (the concept)and in its entire course has to do only with thisbecause of this every stage of [philosophy's] progress is a special determination of this concrete unity, and the most profound and ultimate of the determinations of unity is that of absolute Spirit" (ibid). In this context faith as human spiritual activity cannot be simply divorced from conceptual knowing. As thus divorced "faith . . . means no more than not proceeding to a definite notion (Vorstellung), refusing to enter more fully into its own content" (ibid.). Does such a "faith," for example, know what it is talking about when it speaks of God's ''omnipresence" in a sensible reality to which it accords independent substantial being? Philosophy, on the contrary, does not make that mistake: "The esoteric consideration of God and of identity, like the consideration of knowledge and of concepts, is philosophy itself" (ibid.). As if he wants, so to speak, to heap coals of fire on the heads of his adversaries, Hegel goes on to say, "philosophy is . . . the logical, in the sense that it is universality maintained (bewahrte) in the concrete content as in its actuality" (ibid., no. 574).26 Reality as we know it is the actualization of concrete universality, which only concept, in the full sense, can comprehend (Begriff is the "comprehension"). Once more Hegel's language is that of the syllogism, two extremes united in a middle term. "The syllogism, whose foundation and point of departure is the logical and whose middle is nature uniting spirit with the logical, constitutes the first appearing. The logical becomes nature, and nature becomes spirit" (ibid., no. 575). Nature as we know it is an embodiment of reason (das Logische), and in being known nature is spiritualized (universalized, infinitized). There is, then, a second syllogism, in which nature is presupposedas to-be-knownand spirit is the middle which rationalizes nature (unites it with the logical) (ibid., no. 576). Finally, there is a third syllogism, in which reason (das Logische) serves as the middle uniting nature and spirit, in such a way that spirit can justifiably find its own true reality in considering nature and find what the
26. Note the play on wahr in bewahrte.
< previous page
page_201
next page >
< previous page
page_202
next page > Page 202
reality of nature truly is in considering itself, its own spiritual activity. This third syllogism has as its middle selfknowing reason, the absolutely universal. This middle splits itself into spirit and nature: "making spirit its presupposition, as the progress of the subjective activity of the idea; making nature into the universal extreme, as the progress of the idea which is objectively in itself" (ibid., no. 577). Philosophy has come around full circle: It unites concept (subject) and idea (object), spirit (reason) and nature (rational), infinite Spirit (God) and finite spirit (man), in the all-encompassing activity of absolute knowing (activity without passivity), which has as its object the totality of realitya reality which is and is not distinct from the knowing of it. The divine self-knowing which is the knowledge of all reality becomes the human knowledge of reality. Man knows himself in knowing God; man knows in knowing himself; man knows at all only in knowing God.
< previous page
page_202
next page >
< previous page
page_203
next page > Page 203
Chapter Five "Proofs" of God When human beings reflect on what it is to be humanand we have no evidence that any other beings among those we experience possess this power of reflection on the meaning of their own beingthe profoundest mystery that confronts them is that, as human, they have the capacity to think, to ask questions and to come up with answers to those questions. Whether or not that same reflection can reveal that the answers to those questions are correctwhich, rather crudely, is what we mean by "knowing"may well be another question, which belongs to a later, more sophisticated stage of human reflection. All the evidence of human history, no matter how far back that may go, points to the fact that the survival of the human race has been due to man's capacity to think, and to think successfullyif not correctly. Man has been able to survive, despite the fact that his predators have been physically far more powerful than he; he has been able to subdue nature despite its recalcitrance; he has been able through thought to produce what was necessary to survival, and to a more and more enjoyable survival; he has been able to leave in his world marks of his presence which long outlive him; he has been able to seek and find explanations of why things are the way they are, no matter how fanciful subsequent reflection may have proved those explanations to be. It may also be true to say that man's capacity to give a "rational" explanation of the reality he could not but experience was very late in coming and still belongs to only a miniscule fraction of developing humanity. It is still significant that human "rationality" has enabled man not only to survive but also to progress, and that man has progressively turned the light of reason on more and more facets of his experience in order to find there more and more satisfactory explanations. If we confine our attention to "Western" man, we can say that his capacity to act rationally far antedated his capacity to explain rationally either why he so acted or why his world
< previous page
page_203
next page >
< previous page
page_204
next page > Page 204
submitted to his power of acting rationally. For we know not how long, all the explanation man needed would seem to have been mythical, even though the devices he employed for doing what needed to be done were superbly rational. The time came, however, when man felt the need to reflect rationally even on his myths, which ineluctably led him, by slow stages indeed, to reflect on his own rationality. There can be no question that, no matter how far back we are able to go in tracing the history of man, we witness extraordinary marvels of human ingenuityeven during that long period of time when the capacity to perform those marvels was explained mythically. Western philosophizing, it is said, began with an attempt to explain rationally rather than mythically the world in which man lives, and so the first myths to go were the cosmogonic. As primitive as they may seem, the attempts of the early Greek philosophers to explain the cosmos on the basis of material principles or, more sophisticatedly, by adding to these material components quasi-psychological principles, such as the nonV * of Anaxagoras or the logoV* of Heraclitus, nevertheless marked a triumph of human rationality. By the same token, when the "atomists" sought to explain human subjective activity on the basis of similar material principles, the search for rational explanation went beyond the world to man himself. With the Sophists man became a much more complex phenomenon, whose responsibility for his thinking, willing, and acting could not be reduced to material principles. This movement toward a rational explanation of man was carried to its ancient highpoint by Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, who inevitably turned the light of reason not only on man but also on the gods. The relation to the gods was still one of belief, but philosophy turned itself in the direction of giving reasons for beliefeven to "proving" the very reality of the divine. It is not without significance that philosophy, which, with the advent of Christianity, was able to attribute supreme value to the human individual, whom, the Christians' faith told them, God loved and willed to be saved, had to wait until the philosophico-theological flowering of the Christian Middle Ages, before it could set out on a quest for rational "proofs" for the "existence" of God himself. It is not really strange that an age in which, perhaps, Christian faith was at its strongest could turn the light of reason to the question of God, thus seeking to penetrate rationally what man already believed. That it could do so was based on a double confidence: (1) in the rationality of man, whose religious experience was no obstacle to the adventure of thought; and (2) in the reality of God, who the Christian philosopher had no fear would be explained away, if the light of reason was turned on the content of the Christian faith experience. The Medieval philosopher by no means doubted the reality of God, nor did he feel that the "existence" of God had to be "proved" in any ''scientific" sense of the term. He was convinced, however, that man would be shirking his rational calling if he did
< previous page
page_204
next page >
< previous page
page_205
next page > Page 205
not demand that reason be applied to an antecedent religious conviction. That application of reason, nevertheless, was also colored by the antecedent religious conviction. If human reason was to claim the right to reflect on the whole of experience, then it had to be a reason adequate to the whole of experienceincluding the faith experience. If mystery persisted, that was no obstacle to the rational quest; it was rational to expect that mystery would persist. It was not until philosophers began the attempt to rationalize reason itself that the real trouble started. When Descartes turned the attention of philosophers not only to the thinking subject as the one who thinks and is thus related to the reality thought but also to the thinking wherein resides the ideal being of that which is thought, he did something which needed to be done; the focus on ideality was necessary. At the same time, however, he raised a problem which neither he nor those who followed him could solve: how to bridge the gap between the subjectivity of thinking and the objectivity of that which was thought. He himself sought to guarantee the ultimate objectivity of ideas by an appeal to the veracitas Dei, which in turn demanded that he prove the existence of the Guarantor (at best a ticklish proposal). In their own individual ways, Malebranche, Spinoza, and Leibniz attempted to do the same, but they failed because the God who was to do the guaranteeing turned out to be just too remote from the thinking which was to be guaranteed. Across the channel Locke, Berkeley, and Hume, who, for reasons different from those of Descartes, stressed the subjectivity of thinking, were also unable to solve the problem, with the result that their empiricism quite logically ended up in the skepticism of Hume; not even God, whose activity was taken to be causative, could enable human thinking to bridge the gap, since the very knowledge of causation had turned out to be problematic. Back on the continent again, Enlightenment rationalism solved the problem by fiat: All that was needed was to rely on reason, and all that was required to guarantee reason was to guarantee that thinking was not influenced by tradition, custom, or authoritynot even the authority of God. The breakthrough came with Kant, whose roots were in the Enlightenment but whose attitude was not nearly so negative. Reason could guarantee itself, because by examining itself it could not only set down the conditions for its functioning as reason but could also see to it that it observed those conditions. The only trouble was that, because Kant saw thinking as a purely subjective function whose only guarantee of objectivity was the necessity and universality of its functioning, it had to be given a content from outside itself, which left the reality of that content still in doubt (or, perhaps, it left in doubt just what "reality" could mean). Sense experience could give a phenomenal content; practical reason could give a moral content; and faith could give a noumenal content which reason could only postulate. In addition, Kant compounded the difficulty by making God, who might have been
< previous page
page_205
next page >
< previous page
page_206
next page > Page 206
appealed to as a Guarantor, not a content of human rational thought at all. There was simply no way for rational thinking, which is essentially finite, to come to grips with the Infinite, who is God. The human mind couldand had tothink of God as an "ideal," but could find in itself no resources to affirm that the ideal is real. Fichte and Schelling, although they recognized the enormity of the dualistic dilemma bequeathed to them by Kant, were no more successful than he in solving it. It is all the more remarkable, then, that Hegel, following in the wake of Kant's demolition of all "proofs" for the reality of God, should have insisted not only that human reason can "prove" the reality of God but that human reason is the "proof" of that reality. To say that, however, is to anticipate what is to come. For the present suffice it to say that Hegel is not concerned with proving the "existence" of God, that is, that God exists; he is concerned rather to show that the "infinite being,'' which logic sees to be a rational necessity, coincides with the "God" in whom faith believes, and that faith is in fact "blind," if reason cannot come to its aid and tell it what this God is in whom it believes. Faith, if it is to be an authentically human endeavor, must seek illumination through reason, fides quaerens intellectum, but its existential conviction that God is real need not wait for "proofs" in order to be effective, no more, Hegel tells us, than eating must wait for a knowledge of chemistry, or digestion for a knowledge of anatomy and physiology (EpW, no. 35). When Hegel speaks of "proof" (Beweis) he does not speak of "existence" (Existenz) at all; the term he uses is Dasein, which is strictly speaking untranslatable but which signifies the being proper to concrete reality. Existenz, on the other hand, properly signifies "external manifestation," which, rather than needing to be proved, is itself the "proving" (EpW, no. 123, Zusatz). God manifests himself to faithspecifically "Christian" faith (PdG, pp. 52331, 54445; VPR II, pp. 203204)and God manifests himself to reason, precisely because that faith is not "blind." It is one and the same God who manifests himself to both, and the process of self-manifestation is one and the same continuous process. Thus, to "prove" the reality of God is to ascend in thought the existential pathway of acceptance which has preceded philosophical thought. It is also to show that rational thought has the capacity to ascend that pathway. All of this is but another way of describing the movement of Hegel's Science of Logic, the march of the concept toward objectivity (WL II, p. 354). The question, then, is not whether God "exists," but what does God "do" in making his reality available to human reason. Nor is there question of man's employing thought in order to prove God's reality; rather God manifests himself to man in and through thought.
< previous page
page_206
next page >
< previous page
page_207
next page > Page 207
Critique of Kant There is, perhaps, no better way of appreciating what Hegel is saying than by consulting his critique of Kant's insistence that of itself human reason cannot attain to the infinite being of God. Since in another place I have already analyzed this critique in detail,1 I shall here confine myself to a summary of the principal points Hegel makes. As is well known, Kant had in his Critique of Pure Reason assailed all proofs of God's reality on the grounds that any attempt whatever so to prove God's reality involved an illegitimate leap from the content of a purely subjective mental act of thinking (no matter how adequately universalized) to the affirmation that the object of that thinking is a "reality" outside the mind (the so-called "ontological argument"). In one sense Kant is quite correct in thus assailing "proofs": If human thinking is a purely subjective activity, then the only objectivity of which it can boast is the objectivity of a mental content, which no amount of subjective manipulation of arguments can turn into a reality. What Hegel challenges, then, is not the legitimacy of Kant's conclusion but rather the legitimacy of the initial assumption that thought is nothing but the finite activity of a finite thinking subject and that therefore knowing God exceeds the human mind's capacity to know. This does not mean, however, that he is criticizing Kant for arguing from principles which are not Hegel's own; his claim, rather, is that Kant failed to see the implications of his own ''Copernican Revolution," with its insistence on the autonomy of reason, which, Hegel claims, could not be autonomous, if all it is is the subjective activity of a finite subject. The principle of "idealism" Hegel had said in the Phenomenology is that "reason is consciousness' certainty of being all reality" (PdG, pp. 176, 178). "Certainty," however, is not enough, it is no more than the subjective conviction, nourished by one scientific triumph after the other since the Renaissance, that reason needs no help from outside in appropriating whatever is real. That "certainty" will become "truth" only when reason sees how it is all reality, and this will require the tortuous meanderings of reason coming to an awareness of what it is to be reason, of reason realizing itself as "spirit," of reason coming to grips with "absolute Spirit" in religion, of reason realizing itself as absolute in "absolute knowing." But none of this will make sense without ultimately a dialectical identification of finite and infinite reason; and it is precisely this identification that Hegel sees reason making: "There is but one reason. There is no second supra-human reason. Reason is the divine in man" (EGP, p. 123). Only because this last is true, is it true to say that reason is "autonomous." If Kant does not say this he is equivalently contradicting
1. Quentin Lauer, S.J., "Hegel's Critique of Kant's Theology," in Essays in Hegelian Dialectic (New York: Fordham University Press, 1977), pp. 13157.
< previous page
page_207
next page >
< previous page
page_208
next page > Page 208
himself and saying that reason is not autonomous. The "mere reason," within whose "limits" Kant had confined the philosophical discussion of religion, was not in fact "autonomous," because (among other reasons) the "reality" of religion's object, God, escaped it. If human thinking is to affirm the truth of this reality, it must do so as "faith,'' not as "reason." The Hegelian philosophy radicalizes not only the Kantian autonomous reason. It radicalizes as well the Kantian and post-Kantian search for an existential matrix of philosophical thought. And in this process it is driven into a unique philosophical confrontation with historical Christianity.2 As Hegel sees it, then, Kant has failed to distinguish adequately between understanding" (Verstand), with its abstract and therefore necessarily finite categories, and "reason" (Vernunft), with its concrete and therefore infinite scope.3 As no more than the "certainty of being all reality," Kant's "reason" is little more than a glorified "understanding," for which "reality" itself is but an abstract category and "all reality" but an abstract cumulative ideal. There can be only one concrete "all reality," and that is the "Absolute"; the "absolute Spirit" of Phenomenology, chapters VII and VIII and the preface; the "absolute Idea" of the last chapter of Science of Logic; "God as he is in his eternal essence, before the creation of nature or of a single finite spirit" of the introduction to the same Logic; the "Concept" as the unique "concrete universal" unifying the whole of the Hegelian "system." Kant had had, it is true, the merit of recognizing that, if knowledge is to be truly knowledge and not merely the presence to a subject of a chaotic manifold of formless content, it must be conceptual. He had also seen that the essential unifying force of the concept is "the originally-synthetic unity of apperception, as the unity of the I-think, or of self-consciousness" (WL II, p. 221), which means that in conceiving an object the subject makes the object its own in such a way that in knowing the object the subject knows the concept as its own and thus knows its own self (ibid., p. 222). Because, however, the only concept Kant knew was the purely formal concept, a sort of intellectual form which at once raised the manifold to unity and universalized it (ibid., p. 224), he was faced with a concept which was of itself empty, containing no reality (ibid., p. 225). Out of such a concept, quite obviously, "no amount of effort can hammer reality" (ibid., p. 223). Thus, the content of the only concept there is is not real, and the only kind of reality there is is not conceptual. Strictly speaking, then, there is no
2. E. Fackenheim, The Religious Dimension in Hegel's Thought, (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967), p. 228 (emphasis deleted). 3. Understanding, so to speak, immobilizes what is essentially finite objectivity and then analyses it with the aid of static categories; while reason permits the infinite process of the concrete to unfold.
< previous page
page_208
next page >
< previous page
page_209
next page > Page 209
knowledge of reality, only a knowledge of the "experience" of reality or of reality's "appearing," and reality "appears" only to the senses, the only direct contact the human subject has with what is not itself. What experience does, then, is to trigger, so to speak, a process of concept-formation which has its own sort of objective validity but which does not reproduce reality, nor does it afford the mind a way of guaranteeing that what it thinks is the way it thinks it. Quite obviously a thinking such as this cannot think God, but one is entitled to ask whether a thinking such as this is thinking. Hegel thinks it is not. What Kant has done, he asserts, is to substitute the "formal" character of concepts of understanding for the ''concrete" character of concepts of reason (ibid., pp. 22728). If concepts are separated from reality there seems little justification for asserting that sense-intuitions are not separated from reality, since it is only thought that tells us they are not.4 As Hegel sees it, then, the rational knowledge of which Kant speaks is simply not rational, precisely because to exclude reality from it is to exclude rationality (ibid., pp. 23132). It is not enough that reason be autonomous in its formal function of unifying the concepts of understanding, which in turn depend for their content on the manifold of sense; reason must be autonomous in regard to the content which it justifiably gives to itself, which it will not be if all it is is a subjective funciton of the human mind, dependent on the receptivity of sense for a content. On the other hand, Hegel says, Kant did have, in his notion of "the a-priori synthesis of the concept," a principle which could have enabled him to bridge the gap between thought and reality, "but sensible matter, the manifold of intuition, was for him too powerful to permit him to go beyond it to a consideration of the concept and the categories in and for themselves and [thus] to a speculative philosophizing" (ibid., p. 233). Had Kant, faithful to his own principles, gone this far, philosophical knowledge of God would not have remained closed to him. What begins, then, as a critique of Kant's epistemology and of his antimetaphysical bias, turns into an attack on his antitheological argumentation. We can recall that Kant refers to a concept of God as the ens realissimum, the reality of all realities, a concept the objective being of whose referent human reason simply cannot affirm (WL I, p. 99; II, p. 61). The concept of God, then, is for Kant no more than a limit-concept. It is for this reason that Hegel, not only in Science of Logic but also and even more caustically in the third volume of his Lectures on the History of Philosophy, concentrates on Kant's inability to see any rational validity in "proofs for God's existence." Hegel is convinced that Kant's drastic separation of faith
4. Fichte, of course, had seen this already, but the conclusion he draws with regard to ultimate reality is scarcely less (rationally) skeptical than Kant's.
< previous page
page_209
next page >
< previous page
page_210
next page > Page 210
and knowledge ("I had to suspend knowledge in order to make room for faith"5) was not only illegitimate but also prejudicial to the very possibility of genuine philosophy. Thus, although Hegel applauded Kant's desire to make rational sense of religion, he could not pay Kant's price of impoverishing that rational sense by confining the philosophical account of religion to an investigation of the response to a God whom reason could not know. What this criticism comes down to is Hegel's insistence that reason in the concrete is identical with spirit and that "spirit" makes sense only if there is "absolute Spirit," the knowing of which is, precisely, the infinitizing of finite spirit (EGP, p. 178). To say, then, that human reason cannot "know" God is to set unwarranted limits to spirit (ibid., p. 179). It is not surprising, then, that when in his Lectures on the History of Philosophy Hegel turns to a criticism of Kant he focuses on the limited character of the reason of which the latter speaks; on its inadequacy precisely as reason, if it cannot ascend to a knowledge of God by breaking out of the confinement of individual subjectivity (VGP III, p. 333). Having put an end to the "dogmatism" of a causal metaphysics, Kantian philosophy turns out to be equally dogmatic in its insistence on the supremacy of the finite determinations of understanding (ibid.). A reason whose content does not exceed that of understandingin Kant's own words, "the faculty of thinking the object of sensory intuition"6 (ibid., p. 343)says Hegel, is not reason at all; it is no more than "individual self-consciousness" (ibid., p. 349). The trouble is that, even though Kant speaks of reason as the "faculty of the unconditioned," the infinite, he insists that the infinite is an "ideal,'' as opposed to a "real," content of reason (ibid., pp. 35152). To speak of reason thus, says Hegel, is to make individual reason represent the totality of reason, but such a reason is only the abstract expression of concrete spirit: "Spirit and reason are the same. We do, it is true, represent reason to ourselves abstractly; but active, knowing reason is spirit" (EGP, p. 175). In relation to this Hegel launches into a critique of Kant's treatment of the very notion of "proofs" for the reality of God (VGP III, pp. 35253, 35565), something he will go into more in detail later in his Lectures on the Proofs of God's Reality. Kant admits that God is an "ideal," that is, that which, if it were real, would satisfy the Wolffian definition of "the most real being." Kant, however, denies that reason can be justified in ascribing reality to this ideal. The basis of this denial is the contention that any attempt to ascribe reality to the ideal (to "prove" it) involves an illegitimate passage from concept to reality, since reality is not a conceptual content at all and cannot, therefore, be derived from the concept (ibid., pp. 35961). This, as Hegel sees it, is tantamount to saying that the only concept there is
5. Kant, KrV B, p. xxx. 6. Kant, KpV A, p. 51.
< previous page
page_210
next page >
< previous page
page_211
next page > Page 211
is the finite concept of finite understanding, out of which reality cannot be "hammered" (ibid., p. 360). What Kant has done is to opt for an identification of "representation" (Vorstellung), which understanding forms to itself in thinking, and "concept" (Begriff), which is reason's ''comprehension" (begreifen) of the real. Here Hegel becomes sarcastic about Kant's example of the "hundred possible Talers," the concept of which cannot contain their reality. Of course not, says Hegel, no amout of thinking is going to make them real; if one wants them to be real one had better stop thinking and get to work! But authentic "thinking" (denken) is not to be confused with merely "representing" (vorstellen). Precisely as "represented" the object of thinking is not realthat is why representation is inadequate. Thinking in the fullest sense, on the other hand, grasps (begreifen) its object in its reality, and concept (Begriff) is the grasping (ibid., pp. 36162). In "proofs" of God, then, there is no question of ascribing a nonconceptual content to the concept; the real is the content of the conceptotherwise "objectivity" is mere emptiness (ibid., p. 362). Kant's reason has no content at all; it is "no more than the formal unity for the methodical systematization of understanding's cognition" (ibid., p. 363). Granted that, when subject and object, thought and reality are separated in this way they cannot be put together again (ibid.), there is no justification for saying that thinking God is this kind of thinking. Despite Hegel's manifest debt to Kant in his own thinking, and despite his clear acknowledgment of that debt, he is more critical of Kant than he is of any other major thinker. The main reason for this would seem to be that Kant, having constructed a philosophy, a main position of which is precisely the unknowability of God, has had a far more destructive than constructive influence on the ideal of philosophizing as Hegel sees it. It is interesting in this connection that Hegel has little or nothing to say directly regarding explicitly atheistic philosophiesunless, of course, one wants to consider Enlightenment "rationalism" as explicitly atheistic. In any event, Hegel does return again and again to his criticism of Kantand Kantian philosophynowhere more in detail than in his Lectures on Proofs for the Reality of God, which at this point need be treated only summarily. It is no coincidence, apparently, that Hegel's critique of Kant comes to a head in his treatment of "objectivity" in "subjective logic," in his remarks on the built-in unknowability of God in Kant's philosophy where Hegel treats that philosophy historically (VGP III), and in the Lectures on Proofs. In introducing this course of lectures Hegel makes a remark which sheds considerable light on the sequence of criticisms. Since he had intended to give only one course of lectures, that is, on logic, during the Spring semester of 1829, the necessity of preparing another course for the same semester, he says, made him choose a topic "closely related to logic and constituting a sort of supplement to it, not from the point of view of content but from that
< previous page
page_211
next page >
< previous page
page_212
next page > Page 212
of form, since the topic is simply a specialized form of the fundamental themes (Bestimmungen) of logic" (BDG, p. 1). The question, then, of knowing God as real is integral to the logical problematic, because an investigation of thinking cannot sidestep the issue of what thinking necessarily thinks. Believing and knowing, faith and reason, are not identical forms of thinking, but they are not completely separate operations, in the sense that faith could deliver an object which is not an object for reason; if the object of faith is not an object for reason, it is not an object for man. Believing and knowing are united in such a way that neither can be without the othereven though selfdetermining thought supplements (not supplants) other-determined belief (ibid., pp. 89).7 It is by separating the two that contemporaries (under the influence of Kant) think that they can investigate rationally the subjective state of religious consciousness, while leaving God who is religion's object outside reason's purview. A philosophy of religion is permitted, but not a philosophical theology! (ibid., p. 46). The result is that "we hear much, endlessly much saidor rather, little endlessly repeatedof religion, and so much the less said of God. This continual explanation of religion . . . coupled with an insignificant or even suppressed explanation of God is a characteristic phenomenon of the intellectual culture of the time" (ibid.). What this comes down to is that, even though God and divine revelation may still be loked upon as real, the terms are emptied of meaning, because the human mindall we have to work withis considered incapable of coping with that meaning (ibid., p. 48). When Hegel, then, speaks of "the ascent of thinking spirit to God'' (whether or not the expression carries overtones of Saint Anselm's definition of prayer, ascensio mentis in Deum), it is clear that he is not speaking primarily of a purely rational discovery of divine reality but of a philosophical thinking out of what religious consciousness represents to itself. As revealed by God the content is thoroughly rational; as represented by the human mind in response to this revelation, it is in need of a rational articulation, which its antecedent rationality makes not only possible but demanded. One way or the other, clearly, we are back with a problem with which we are already familiar, the essential finitude of the human mind over-against the infinity of Godassuming, of course, that the concept of "infinity" says anything at all to that mind. If we are not to say that the human mind simply cannot come to grips with the reality of Godand this Hegel will not countenance, since it equivalently means giving up the entire philosophical enterpriseare we to make this coming-to-grips possible by finitizing the
7. "This religion which is manifest to itself, is in the second place not only manifest but is also the religion which is designated as revealed. By this is understood that, on the one hand, it has been revealed by God, that God has made himself known to man and, on the other, that it has come to man from outside, that it has been given" (VPR I, p. 194).
< previous page
page_212
next page >
< previous page
page_213
next page > Page 213
infinite or by infinitizing the finite? (see ibid., p. 110). Religion, it would seem, presents God to the human subject as truly infinite Being. Either the human spirit is content to simply leave it at that or, true to its vocation as spirit, it will seek to rise to the infinite, refusing to leave its infinite object "unthought," "unknown." What stands in the way of admitting this rise to the infinite as a human possibility is (1) the assumption that the passage of finite thinking to an infinite object is a "leap" (ibid., pp. 11112); (2) the presupposition that as "finite'' the human spirit is sufficient to itself or, as Hegel puts it, is "absolute" (ibid., pp. 11213); and (3) the refusal to recognize that to speak of the activity of the infinite in the finite is not to make that activity cease to be activity of the finite (ibid., p. 113). What those who refuse to accept this last fail to see, says Hegel, is that the relation of God to man, unlike the relation of things in the world to subjects in the world, is a relation of spirit to spirits. To know God is simply not to know a "thing"; it is to be in communion with "Spirit." That man has knowledge of God is, on the basis of the essential community [of God and man in spirit], a communal knowingi.e., man has knowledge of God only to the extent that in man [in man's knowing] God has knowledge of himself. This knowing is God's consciousness of himself, and at the same time it is God's knowledge of man, and this knowing of man by God is man's knowledge of God. [Ibid., p. 117] There are those, of course, who think that Hegel has spoiled everything with these words: In knowing God either man is no longer manhe is "divine"or he no longer really knows, since it is God who is doing the knowing.8 If, however, we understand the last sentence above in the light of Hegel's theology of creation (see chap. 7), according to which creation, particularly that of "finite spirits," is God's "determining of himself" in the mode of knowing rather than a "making" in the mode of efficient causality, the difficulty would seem to vanish. Finite Mind and Infinite Being The finite categories of understanding can no more come to terms with the infinite Spirit who is God than with the ascensio mentis in Deum which is philosophical ("speculative") knowledge of God. Is it really too much to say, as Kant would have it to be, that philosophical thinking can see more than its own finite self in its thinking of God? Kant, of course, will see contradiction in such a unity of the finite and the infinite, and, as he consistently does when reason becomes involved in contradiction, he solves the problem not by resolving the contradiction but by blaming the contradiction on
8. See Lauer, Essays in Hegelian Dialectic, p. 150, n. 18.
< previous page
page_213
next page >
< previous page
page_214
next page > Page 214
reason, not on reality. Hegel, too, sees contradiction here, as he does wherever he sees life, the perennial contradiction, but he is convinced that both reality and reason can resolve the contradictionthat is what "infinity" is all about. In fact, it is only by both recognizing and resolving contradiction that life of the spirit avoids stagnation. In his lecture, "On Kant's Critique of the Cosmological Proof" appended to the course "on Proofs," he tells us: In fact, however, reason can decidedly put up with contradictionand, of course, also resolve itand things too are quite capable of putting up with it; or, rather, they are simply existing contradiction, whether as that Kantian schema of the thing-in-itself or as empirical thingsbut only to the extent that they are rational do they at the same time resolve contradiction in themselves. [Ibid., p. 148] So little, then, does the unity of finite and infinite present an unresolvable contradiction, that it is the principle for the very resolution of contradiction, the condition for the intelligibility of being itself. If we look back at the overall movement of Hegel's Science of Logic we find that the movement is precisely the unfolding of the implications of this unity. Logic begins with a being which is infinitely emptyand, therefore, in no way different from nothingand ends with being which is infinitely full (determinate), and the path from one to the other is marked by a progressive negation of the limitations of abstraction. What is important to note is that it is the same being which is infinitely empty and infinitely full, and it is the self-determination of the infinite in finitude which constitutes the filling-up process. The finite simply cannot make sense by itself but only as integral to the movement toward the infinite. The question, then, is not whether reason can know that the infinite really is, but whether reason must know that being is infinite (ibid., p. 152). Hegel is convinced, as we have seen, that the mistake which his contemporaries have made is to have looked upon the finite as the originally affirmative which is negated in the infinite. Rather the infinite is affirmative; it is negated in the finite and reaffirmed in the progressive negation of limitation. "The essential point in this mediation, however, is that the being of the finite is not the affirmative, rather it is by the self-transcending of the finite that the infinite is posited and mediated" (ibid., p. 153). Thus, there has been no "leap" from the finite to the infinite; to posit the finite as real entails ("speculatively") positing the infinite as real. Moreover, the spirit which posits both finite and infinite is itself both finite and infinite; the movement of spirit and the movement of being are not to be divorced (ibid., pp. 15354). Kant was certainly not wrong in criticizing the "form'' in which proofs for the reality of God had been presentedas though they were syllogisms of understandingwhat he failed
< previous page
page_214
next page >
< previous page
page_215
next page > Page 215
to do, however, was to see the profounder foundation on which they rested (ibid., p. 154). The exposition of this profounder foundation, Hegel is convinced, is "logic," properly understood. Logic tells us that there is no being which does not imply the infinity of being, no thought which does not imply the infinity of thought; and the real infinite, God, is the perfect identity of thought and being (see JL, p. 159). God is that which thought must think, if it is to be adequate as thoughtand this is "proof"! We must be able to make the move from the conviction that what is inconceivable cannot be to the conviction that what must be conceived cannot not be ("What breaks up the unity of the logically rational likewise breaks up the actual." EpW, no. 541, Zusatz) Philosophy Is Not to Eliminate Religion Just as in the Kantian way of thinking there is the danger already noted that the content of thought will be looked at as given in one way and the form of thinking in another, there is the danger of misinterpreting Hegel in such a way as to have him say that, when speculative philosophy "thinks out" the content of religious consciousness, philosophy supplants religion. It is as though one were to read him as saying that the infinitizing of the finite, the divinizing of the human spirit takes place only in philosophical thinking. On the contrary it is quite clear that Hegel's position is far more nuanced than that. As he sees it, "absolute Spirit" bears witness in man to "absolute truth," whether that be the truth of religion, of morality, of law, or of philosophy. It is true, of course, that he does say, "The witness of the Spirit in its highest form takes the form of philosophy" (VPR II, p. 198), and it is also true that he says this because, as we have seen in his treatment of religion in the Phenomenology, he sees thought or concept in contrast to ''representation" as the form most adequate to the presence of absolute truth in the human spirit. It is the concept, after all, which, "purely as such and without the presence of any presupposition, develops the truth out of itself, and we both recognize it as developing and perceive (einsehen) the necessity of the development in and through the development itself" (ibid.). The witness of absolute Spirit in and through the concept, nevertheless, is not discontinuous with the witness of Spirit in other forms: "the witness of the Spirit may, however, be present in man in manifold and various ways; we have no right to demand that the truth in the case of all men be got at in a philosophical way" (ibid.).9 The "various ways" (including the religious) are not eliminated by philosophical thinking. From the point of view of Phenomenology of Spirit, we can say that Hegel sees
9. It is not too often emphasized that Hegel quite clearly recognizes that the simple "believer," who simply has no time to "philosophize," is not thereby cut off from the supremely rational content of thought.
< previous page
page_215
next page >
< previous page
page_216
next page > Page 216
the culmination of spiritual development in that "absolute knowing" where spirit becomes conscious of itself as infinite in and through many finite "spirits," but this is true only because all along it has been absolute Spirit bearing witness in finite forms to infinite truth. "The spiritual necessities of men vary according to their culture and free development; and so, too, the demand for and the trust in belief grounded on authority, varies according to the different stages of development reached" (ibid.). What philosophy can do is to recognize that the presence of truth even in finite form bespeaks the witness of absolute Spirit in the spirit of man; that human reason knows truth at all bears witness to the self-consciousness of infinite Spirit in man. Finite spirit can rise to the infinite, be infinitized, because infinite Spirit descends to man, finitizes itself in the very being of the finite, wherein infinite Spirit expresses itself. Religion too is consciousness and therefore involves finite consciousness whose finitude, however, is superseded; for the other which absolute Spirit knows is itself, and it is absolute Spirit only in knowing itself. The finitude of consciousness enters in, because Spirit differentiates itself. This finite consciousness, however, is a moment of Spirit itself, which is its own self-differentiation, its own self-determination, i.e.., positing itself as finite consciousness. Consequently, Spirit is only as mediated through consciousness or finite spirit, and this means that Spirit is to finitize itself, in order through this finitizing to become knowledge of itself. [VPR, I, p. 198] Not only philosophy, then, but also religion is activity of absolute Spirit in finite spirit, which is to say that, like philosophy, so too religion is not merely finite activity of finite consciousness. "Thus, religion is the divine Spirit's knowledge of itself through the mediation of finite spirit. Accordingly in the Idea in its highest form, religion is not a transaction of man, but is essentially the highest determination of the absolute Idea itself" (ibid.). What all of this points to and which is of utmost importance in coming to grips with Hegel's thought is the conviction that the "ascent" of the human spirit to the fullness of spirit and, hence, to the fullness of being in the absolute Idea is at the same time and necessarily a "being-lifted-up" (Erhebung) in the community of the divine and the human. It is precisely in the so-called "proofs for the reality of God" that this reciprocal movement is described and worked out.
This raising-up is the same as what is presented in a more abstract way in the proofs for the reality of God. In all these proofs the raising-up is one and the same; only the starting point and the nature of the Being in question are different. The ascent to God, who is determined in this or that way, is only one side. The other is the reverse: God who is determined in this or that way relates
< previous page
page_216
next page >
< previous page
page_217
next page > Page 217
himself to the subject which has raised itself up. What comes in here is the way in which the subject is determined; it knows itself as determined in God's way. [VPR I, p. 254] Here it is that the importance of moral consciousness enters in. The ascent to God will not be triggered by mere intellectual interest, fascination with the wonders of nature, or awe before the extraordinary capacity of the human spirit to think; only an orientation toward the goodness in which alone the self-realization of spirit can be accomplished will orient the human subject to the absolute, and only such an orientation to the good is thought in the most authentic sense of the term. The accents of Plato are unmistakable here. Superficially it could seem that: Thinking and thought would also be present in one who thinks the worstthat this too would constitute thought, would be the activity of thinking, etc. This, however, is incorrect; for nonV * thinks only itself, precisely because it is the most perfect [das Vortrefflichste]. It is the thought, the thinking of thought; therein unity of subjective and objective is expressed, and this is the most perfect. The absolute ultimate end, nonV, which thinks itselfthis is the good; it is with itself only, is for its own sake. [VGP II, p. 219] In the light merely of what has already been said this could seem unexpected, the ringing-in of an entirely new feature. If, however, we remember that Hegel has not completely rejected the legacy of Kantand particularly of Fichtethat God is the ultimate goal of moral striving, we should not be surprised. Hegel, it is true, will not be satisfied with a God who, as the object of this striving, is no more than a vague, indeterminate "moral order" of the universe, but he still sees, as he did in chapter VI of the Phenomenology, the universality of moral order as the springboard to religious consciousness and, ultimately, to the total self-consciousness and thus responsibility of "absolute knowing." The finite which here constitutes the point of departure is real ethical [sittliche] self-consciousness. The negation whereby it raises its spirit to its truth is the actually accomplished purification, in the ethical world, of its knowing from subjective opinion and the liberation of its willing from the self-seeking of desire. [EpW, no. 552] There will be no religion where there is no longing for moral goodness; only consciousness of self as a moral being leads to religious consciousness of God as fulfillment.
True religion and true religiousness proceeds only from morality and is thinking morality, i.e., a morality coming to consciousness of the self-determining
< previous page
page_217
next page >
< previous page
page_218
next page > Page 218
universality of its concrete essence. Only in consequence of this is the idea of God cognized as selfdetermining Spirit. Apart from the moral spirit, therefore, it is useless to look for true religion and religiousness. [ibid.] But, and this is of the utmost importance in measuring the distance Hegel has gone beyond Kant and Fichte, morality will find its consummation in religion, only if the God of religion is the true God, corresponding to the true Idea of God, which alone can be religion's object. "But, that the truly moral be the consequence of religion demands that religion have the true content, i.e., that the idea of God of which religion is conscious be the true one" (ibid.). It is philosophy's task to raise this Idea to its full truth in "knowing." It would be a mistake, however, to conceive of "knowing," as Hegel envisions it at this level as some purely cognitive process. Not only does it retain the object given to it in the religious consciousness which is faith, but it must be accompanied by the "feeling" which is inseparable from authentic religious consciousness. The head is not enough; the heart must be engaged too. We know, of course, how violently opposed Hegel was to the "romantic" intuitionism of Jacobi and Schleiermacher, according to whom God is the object primarilyif not exclusivelyof religious "emotion," but this opposition by no means precluded his reserving a place for profound emotion in religious and even philosophical consciousnesshow else does ''spirit" respond to beauty? Yet not only can there be a true content in our feeling; there should and must be, or as used to be said, we must have God in our hearts. Heart is, of course, more than feeling; the latter is momentary, accidental, transient. But when I say, "I have God in my heart," feeling is expressed as an enduring, permanent mode of my existence. The heart is what I am, not what I am at the moment, but what I am in general, my character. The form of feeling as a universal, then, signifies the principles or habits of my being, my permanent manner of acting. [VPR I, pp. 14445] It might, of course, be asked whether the element of emotion is not eliminated when the content of religious consciousness, God, is given the form of thinking adequate to it in "absolute knowing." Although in the tightly packed and very brief final chapter of the Phenomenology dealing with "absolute knowing" no mention is made of emotion, it cannot be without significance that in this chapterparticularly in its closing pagesHegel himself becomes very emotionally involved, poetic in his expression. The point is that emotionreligious or otherdoes not lose its purity when raised to the level of thought, nor need it be abandoned; emotion is of the spirit and belongs to its integrity (see EpW, no. 34, Zusatz).
< previous page
page_218
next page >
< previous page
page_219
next page > Page 219
One is tempted to say that Hegel is more concerned with the "passion" of religion than is Kierkegaard! If we look once more at Phenomenology of Spirit, we find that it is one long, complex study of the process wherein spirit comes to a more and more adequate consciousness of itself as the active source of its own consciousness of reality. In the penultimate chapter spirit comes to the awareness that only if it is consciousness of absolute Spirit, absolute reality, will it fulfill its vocation of being "all reality." In the final chapter, then, it comes to the realization that in knowing itself it is knowingnot simply being aware ofabsolute Spirit. In no sense does this mean, as we shall see in greater detail in chapter 6, that Hegel is identifying finite spirit and infinite Spirit; what he does is identify finite spirit's knowledge of itself with its knowledge of God, because the former knowledge ineluctably entails the latter. It is in this sense that even finite spirit's knowing is "absolute," because in knowing the "Absolute" who is the "object" of religious consciousness, finite spirit ''appropriates" that object in such a way as to be dependent on nothing outside itself in so knowing; its knowing the Absolute is its self-knowing. The reason why there had to be a Phenomenology of Spirit is that there is simply no way that the human spirit could know from the beginningas Fichte and Schelling would have itthat spirit's self-knowing would be the totality of its knowing. It had to make its laborious way through all the "forms" (Gestaltungen) of consciousness before it could know that it could even attain to an "absolute" form beyond which there is no need or possibility of going. What, at the culmination of this process, spirit can now do is to look back at all the "forms" (Gestalten)10 of consciousness, discern and discard in each what was not its own doing, thus retaining as the moments of its coming to complete self-consciousness all the Gestaltungen which are its own and which constitute the absoluteness of its knowing. Here it can be seen once more than, for Hegel, the stage of religious consciousnessindeed of the "absolute" or Christian religionis unquestionably essential to the ultimate in human self-consciousness. The "object" of religious consciousness is an absolutely self-conscious Being who gradually makes known to the human spirit what it is to be absolutely self-conscious spirit. This "making known," be it noted, cannot be an "effecting" of knowing from withouta sort of "infusion"which would not be a "knowing" in the proper sense of the term.
10. A certain amount of confusion is caused by Hegel's use of two terms here, Gestalt and Gestaltung, whose distinction can scarcely be rendered in translation. Although both are translatable as "form," Gestalt functions strictly as a noun and thus does not carry the dynamic participial overtones of Gestaltung.
< previous page
page_219
next page >
< previous page
page_220
next page > Page 220
The Growth of Consciousness What remains to be done is to recapitulate the "moments" of the process of self-conscious spirit in such a way as to recognize them as its Gestaltungen, that is, as the "forms" of spirit which spirit itself (spiritual activity) effectuates. On the level of religious consciousness it had been possible to see the universal Spirit, religion's object, as giving unity to all the manifestations of spiritTrinity, creation, Incarnationand to relate this unity to the development of human spiritFall, Redemption, and indwelling of the Spirit.11 Because, for Hegel, phenomenology is of the human spirit, all of this is to be seen as throwing light on the ''movement of human self-consciousness," wherein are reconciled and unified all the "moments" (Gestaltungen) which constitute the human spirit's knowing of itself, which is the very "manifest being" (Dasein) proper to it as spirit. The movement proves to be the "coming together" (concretion, from concrescere) of moments, which only "seemed" to be separate, in what is now called a special Gestalt des Bewusstseinsnot as a last but as the unity of them all"not only the contemplation of the divine but the self-contemplation of the same" (PdG, p. 554). If, then, it is possible for the human spirit to see that in being conscious of the universal self-conscious spirit it is conscious of itself, the goal of the movement has been reached. The self-consciousness which is "absolute knowing" is as universal (in its knowing) as is its "object" in religion (ibid.). Now human spirit can see each of its previous Gestalten as its own Gestaltung, "as a universality of knowing which is self-consciousnessas a self-consciousness which is simple unity of knowing" (ibid., p. 555). The form in which spirit now knows itself is that of "concept," the concretizing, all-uniting form, which alone is adequate to the concretizing, all-uniting, "absolute" Spirit. "Thus what in religion was a content in the form of representing an Other, is here the self's own doing; the concept brings it about (verbindet es) that the content is the self's own doing" (ibid., p. 446). The knowing is the human self's own doing, not a being-acted-upon, and this is true of knowing Godcall it "proving" if you wish, so long as that does not mean manipulating abstract concepts in order to produce an abstract conclusion. This sort of "knowing" is God's supreme self-revelation: "Spirit appearing to consciousness in this element or, what is here the same, produced by consciousness in this element, is science" (ibid.), which is to say, to know in the paradigmatic sense of "know" is to know God. In the sense in which it is now understood, then, "concept," the final form of spirit, is "absolute knowing," the ultimate "gathering together": "it is spirit knowing itself in the form of spirit, or it is comprehensive
11. See Lauer, "Human Autonomy and Religious Affirmation in Hegel," in Essays in Hegelian Dialectic, pp. 89106.
< previous page
page_220
next page >
< previous page
page_221
next page > Page 221
(begreifende) knowing" (ibid.). What is known has received the form of selfnot of othernessit has been con-ceived: "The content is conceived (begriffen) only because the I in its otherness is with itself" (ibid., p. 557). We might say, to borrow a page from Hegel's "theology" (see chap. 7), that the human spirit in its self-knowing shares the way God is in his creative self-knowing: for God to know himself is to externalize himself without ceasing to be himself; for human spirit to externalize itself in knowing what is other is to find itself in itself. This means, in the final analysis, that for the human spirit to find itself in a "knowing" which is ''absolute" is to find "absolute Spirit," God, the God who has antecendently revealed himself to religious consciousness: "The content of religion, therefore expresses sooner in time than does science what spirit is, but only science is its true knowledge of itself" (ibid., p. 559). We are fortunate not to have to rely on only this final chapter of the Phenomenology to know what Hegel means by "concept" (see chap. 2). It is important for us to note here that there is only one "reality" that corresponds totally with its "concept," that is, "infinite Spirit." Because, however, finite spirit is not a reality over-against infinite spirit but rather the latter's finite self-manifestation, then the human spirit is in a very significant sense the selfknowledge of infinite Spirit, such that for human spirit truly to know itself is to know God as knowing himself. The "concept" to which human spirit attains in "absolute knowing" is the "infinite" concept of spirit, without which self-knowing is meaningless. "In [absolute] knowing, then, spirit has rounded out the movement of its formings (Gestaltens: verbal noun), insofar as any of its forms is burdened with the unresolved distinction characteristic of consciousness. Spirit has achieved the pure element of its reality (Daseins), the concept" (ibid., pp. 56162). Thus, to know God, the absolute Spirit, is to overcome any fear that the human subject by going out of itself in knowing what is other will surrender itself to the domination of the other: instead it will precisely find itself, because it is in thus going out of itself that it is most authentically with itself; its being in the Absolute is its true being. There are various spiritual activities in which the human spirit can go out of itself and thus find itself: (1) in the contemplation of nature, surely, although the self it finds there is, so to speak, a nonconscious selfnature is not the product of finite spirit, only the "thinking" of nature is; (2) in art, morality, and legal and political action, where spirit produces the image of itself (modeled on its "concept") in which it can see its conscious self; (3) in religion, where through worship it unites itself consciously with the self which is the self of all selves; and (4) in the ultimate goal of adequate "knowing," what Hegel calls Wissenschaft, wherein it is totally "with itself" and therefore, in this sense "absolute" (VGP III, p. 460). To use a slightly different language, in religion man is conscious of being imago Dei,
< previous page
page_221
next page >
< previous page
page_222
next page > Page 222
in philosophical knowing man is conscious of what it is to be imago Dei (VPR I, pp. 16768, 187, 31112). Without going into the theological implications of this last statement, which can wait for chapter 7, we can, simply in terms of Hegel's Science of Logic, say that the "Infinite" (Spirit) manifests itself in innumerable finite ways, chief of which is human spirit, thus "finitizing" itself, only to return to its infinite self in the self-knowing of finite spirit (see WL I, pp. 12545). To see this "raising up" of the human spirit to the divine as culminating in Wissenschaft, may well seem and has seemed to many an over-intellectualizing of the divine-human relationship. If, however, we recall that, for Hegel, the divine, infinite Being is Spirit and Spirit only and that, therefore, he can be "for" spirit alone, then it is at least not illogical to say that infinite Spirit is "for" finite spirit preeminently in the most spiritual of the latter's spiritual activities, that is, thought. In addition, since Hegel sees philosophical knowing, Wissenschaft, as the apex of the spiritual activity of thought, it is not strange that he should locate ''knowing" God there. We may be disinclined to designate this by the term Wissenschaft, which is customarily translated by the English term "science," but it is not necessary to carry prejudices which are occasioned by the English language into an interpretation of a distinction which Hegel seems perfectly justified in making and for which he has considerable precedent, at least in the writings of the medieval Scholastics. The "science" of which Hegel speaks bears little resemblance to the contemporary notion of science, whose model is the mathematico-physical. Rather he is talking about knowledge in the fullest and strictest sense of the term, a knowledge which is not characterized by the "exactitude" of understanding but rather by the "comprehensiveness" of reason. If "science" cannot extend beyond the confines of the exactly "measurable," then the consequences to be drawn can be only "materialistic," leaving "spirit" out of the picture entirely.
In fact, our knowledge would be in a sad plight indeed, if with regard to such objects as freedom, law, morality, even God himself, just because these objects cannot be measured and calculated or expressed in a mathematical formula, we had to abandon the hope of exact knowledge and had in general to be satisfied merely with a vague representation of them, thus surrendering the particular details of them to the good pleasure of each and every individual, to make of them what he will. The practically pernicious consequences which result from such a position are immediately evident; on closer inspection this turns out to be . . . the exclusively mathematical point of view, which identifies quantity, a particular stage of the logical idea, with the logical idea itself, a point of view which is no other than the principle of materialism. [EpW, no. 99, Zusatz.]
< previous page
page_222
next page >
< previous page
page_223
next page > Page 223
The point Hegel is trying to make here has nothing to do with "exact" science in this sense; what he is seeking to bring out is that the "thinking" of God which takes place in religion is not "knowing" in the strict sense of the term; the "thinking'' of God which takes place in philosophy is. Everything Hegel has to say about "proofs" of God converges on that one point. Now, however, this must be taken into consideration: when it comes to speaking of God, what is in question is an object entirely different from a hundred Talers or from any particular concept, representation, or whatever else one may want to call it. In fact everything finite is this and only this: its reality is different from its concept. God, however, has to be precisely that which can be thought only as existing, whose concept included his being. [EpW, no. 51] To say, then, that "existence" cannot be contained in concept, as does Kant, is illegitimately to confine the meaning of "existence" to sensible existents only; and it is to confine the meaning "concept" to the representation which the finite mind forms to itself of things. It is not even logical to extrapolate from the conditions of sensible existence to that of the suprasensible. To say that the existence of the purely sensible cannot be conceived is not the same as saying that the existence of the nonsensible cannot be conceived. The nonexistence of the sensible does not make it inconceivable. The nonexistence of the absolute would make the Absolute inconceivable. If existence is not conceived, then what is in question is the non-conceptual, the sensorily perceived; and of course the non-conceptual is no concept . . . . Granted that the absolute Being does not have that kind of existence; or, rather, that that kind of existence has no truth, it is only a transitory moment. [VGP III, p. 362] More than that, it must be said that a prerequisite for thinking God at all is the "negation" of all sensible conditions (see EpW, no. 12). It is the task of logic, as we saw in chapter 2, to show that this can and must be done. To conceive of the Being from which absolutely all sensible conditions are absent, is to conceive of this Being (Spirit) as existingor it is not to conceive it at all. The Condition of All Conditions In a certain sense, strangely enough, in taking "proofs for the reality of God" seriously, Hegel is borrowing a page from the "transcendental philosophizing" of Kant and Fichte: What is an absolutely necessary condition for the very possibility of what we know to be the case we
< previous page
page_223
next page >
< previous page
page_224
next page > Page 224
also know to be the case. But, we know it to be the case that there are phenomena in consciousness, and it is a necessary condition of phenomena in consciousness that reality appear to consciousness. This even breaks down the wall Kant had so laboriously constructed between the noumenal and the phenomenal: An absolutely necessary condition for the very possibility of phenomena is that there be a subject, an "I," to which reality "appears""originally synthetic transcendental unity of apperception." What Kant would seem to be denying, of course, is that the absolutely necessary condition for the possibility of an apperceiving subject is that there be an ''absolute" Subject; but it is difficult to see how he can justify such a denialif, indeed, he ever considered the argument at all. Could a finite subject make sense at all, if there were no infinite (absolute) Subject? In any event it would seem to be an unjustified caution such as this of which Hegel speaks in the introduction to the Phenomenology where he says that the "fear of error" which prompts the caution is in effect a "fear of the truth." To speak of knowing the true without knowing the absolutely true, he tells us, is to play with words. This is not to say that the only knowing there is is absolute; but it does say that a knowing which is not ultimately oriented to the absolutely true is a truncated and, therefore, untrue knowing. There is finite knowing, of course, and there is knowledge of the finite, but it qualifies as knowing only because oriented to the infinite. Of course, the human mind can know particular truths, but only because it can also know absolute truth. This consequence, fear of truth, results, because the absolute alone is trueor the true alone is absolute. The consequence can be denied on the basis of the contention that a knowledge which admittedly does not, as science wishes it to, know the absolute is nevertheless true and that knowledge in general, even if it is incapable of knowing the absolute can still be capable of other truth. But we see quite clearly that this sort of talking back and forth runs aground on a fuzzy distinction between a true which is absolute and some other kind of true, whereas absolute, knowledge, etc., are words which presuppose meanings which have yet to be arrived at. [PdG, p. 65] Does Kant in fact know what he is talking aboutor what are the consequences of so talkingwhen he says the absolute cannot be known? What all this comes down to is that, for Hegel, all true thinking is interpretive; the mind does not simply reproduce in a universal way what has been presented to it in a particular way, it is driven to go beyond the given to the ultimate source of the possibility of reality or of thought, which is not to be found in reality qua finite nor in thought qua finite. This thought activity, of course, bespeaks a "logic" which few of Hegel's contemporariesand, perhaps,
< previous page
page_224
next page >
< previous page
page_225
next page > Page 225
fewer of our owncould accept, what James Yerkes calls an "onto-logic" or Martin Heidegger, somewhat snidely, an "onto-theologic."12 Thus, we may say that God is the ontological or metaphysical ground of the "essential" nature of things which Hegel speaks about by temporal analogy as God "before" the creation of the world. This means, speculatively speaking, that to know in a conceptually adequate manner the permanent, but ceaselessly dialectical structures or "essences'' of the world in its actuality, its Wirklichkeit, is also to know God as ontologic knows himas the infinite or ultimate condition of all possibilities actualized in it.13 Only such a logic, Hegel is convinced, can afford to speak of "proofs" of God's reality at all. It is a logic which he sees operative in the metaphysical thinking of Saint Anselm and other medieval Scholastics, a logic which he finds obscured by Anselm's attempts to formulate "proofs" according to the rules of an "abstract" logic of understanding. Hegel further points out, very interestingly, that the so-called proofs of the Divine Existence are not what they are ordinarily thought to be: purely affirmative reasonings in which what we start from furnishes a fixed, solid basis from which we pass on to something which has the same solidity as its premises.14 The action of thought is to negate the basis from which it starts, to show it up as not being self-subsistent, and so to have in it a springboard from which it can ascend to what is truly self-subsistent and selfexplanatory.15 Much has been written, and undoubtedly will continue to be written, about the "logical" inadequacy of all "proofs" for the existence of God. What is more, those who write thus reason quite correctly: If there is one and only one logic of proof, these proofs do not prove. For that matter there is no way of proving, by that sort of logic, the "existence" of anything, which is by no means to say that there is no way of "knowing" the existence of anythingalthough Hegel would say we have no way of knowing the existence of anything, if we do not know the existence of God, and that is where "proof" comes in. But, where existence is concerned "proof" means nothing, unless the thinking in question is "dialectical."
12. See M. Heidegger, Identity and Difference, trans. Joan Stambaugh, (New York: Harper & Row, 1969), pp. 59, 7071. 13. James Yerkes, The Christology of Hegel, (Missoula, Montana: Scholars Press, 1978), p. 273. 14. It is, in fact, precisely the nonsolidity of the premisses that demands a much more solid, "absolute" foundation, if they are to be thought of as true. 15. William Wallace, trans., Hegel's Logic, (Oxford: Clarendon, 1975), p. xii.
< previous page
page_225
next page >
< previous page
page_226
next page > Page 226
Those who expect all thought-advance to be that of the deduction of conclusions from firmly established premisses are quite incapable of dialectical thinking: in dialectics it is the insufficiency of the premises that leads to the more sufficient conclusion.16 The initial mistake made by all those who criticize "proofs" for the reality of God is not that of saying that they are not justified by the logical rules of inference. In fact, they are not. The mistake, rather, is that of taking the finite human reasoning process governed by the rules of inference legislated by an abstract formal logic as paradigmatic of "reason." Human ''reasoning" is but a particular manifestation of the process of "reason" which transcends all particular manifestations. If we remember what Hegel has said about the Being which transcends all beings, the Thought which transcends all thoughts, the Concept which transcends all concepts, the Spirit which transcends all spirits, we should have no difficulty in at least grasping what he is saying when he speaks of the Reason which transcends all reasonings. By the same token we should have no difficulty in comprehending what he is saying when he claims that the validity of any reasoning process depends on its correspondence with reason as such, not on its fidelity to a set of rules which finite reasoning itself has established. This is not to say that any and every flight of fancy is eo ipso valid and permissible. It is to say that rational thinking, when it is truly rational thinking, thinks what is true. It is a commonplace of all logic that strict adherence to the formal rules of logic is no guarantee of the truth of thinking. It is, on the other hand, anything but a commonplace that, when thinking seeks to think the Infinite, strict adherence to the rules of formal logic, geared as they are to the finite, constitutes an obstacle and not a help. This, of course, does not mean that, when formal logic has reached the limits of its usefulness, logic is then to give way to illogic; it does not even mean that formal logic is to retire from the picture; it does mean that, only if formal logic is aufgehoben in a dynamic logic will thought be able to come to terms with reality as totality. Thus a "proof" of the reality of the Infinite may be perfectly valid, corresponding to the demands of reason, even though its formulationin "propositions" and "syllogism"may not satisfy the constraints of formal logic. Unlike so many philosophers, both before and after him, Hegel had a great deal of confidence in the natural course of human reasonif followed out sedulously. It is as though he were to say, putting it colloquially, "if reason does what comes naturally, it will rise to the concrete infinite whose necessity forces itself on it," not because this "concrete infinite" is contained in the premisses of a syllogism but because thinking will have to throw in the sponge if this is not true. Thus, with regard to the "cosmological proof":
16. Ibid., p. xiii.
< previous page
page_226
next page >
< previous page
page_227
next page > Page 227
Man contemplates the world, and because he is rational in his thinking, finding no satisfaction in the contingency of things, he rises from the finite to the absolutely necessary and says: becaue the finite is contingent, there must be a self-existent Necessary, which is the ground of this contingency. That is the course which human reason, the human spirit, follows, and this proof of the reality of God is nothing but the description of that elevation to the infinite. [VPR I, p. 165] Quite obviously the validity of the "elevation" thus "described" is not tied to the adequacy of any syllogistic formulation. To "prove'' in this case, then, does not mean to justify syllogistically the "elevation"; rather the "elevation" is itself the proving, that is, that the being designated by the term God, "infinite Being," must be affirmed to have the determination "real" (or "exists") (see ibid., p. 163). If "elevation" to infinite Being is the necessary consequence of thinking "being" at all (Science of Logic), and "elevation" to "absolute Spirit" is the necessary consequence of thinking at all (Phenomenology of Spirit), then the affirmation of God's reality is necessary. It would seem that there is no way to get around affirming that finite reality exists. By the same token, however, there is no way that finite reality can be said to exist "of itself." The existence, then, of any reality, whether being or thought, is itself the proof of its prerequisite, infinite Being and Thought. To "think" what is "given" to the senses is to come up with this conclusion. Thought and thought alone has eyes for the essence, substance, universal power, and ultimate design of the world. What men call the proofs of God's existence are, rightly understood, ways of analyzing and describing the spirit's own movement, since it is a thinking spirit, which thinks the data of the senses.17 The elevation of thought beyond the world of sense, its passage beyond the finite to the infinite, the leap into the supersensible which it takes when it snaps asunder the chains of sense, all this transition is simply thought itself, and nothing but thought. Say there must be no such passage, and you say there is to be no thinking. [EpW, no. 50] Nothing could be clearer: As Hegel sees it, thought cannot but go beyond the data of sense (he has thrown down the gauntlet to both the empiricists and Kant), and, logically speaking, it cannot go beyond the data of sense without going all the way, to that Being which is the object of thought and thought alone. This is equivalent to saying that not to think religiously, not to think God, is to be illogical. It is this which explains what Hegel means when he criticizes Kant for employing a method which is "psychological"
17. Note carefully: it is not simply "human subjects" thinking; it is "thought" thinkingnot the psychology of it but the logic. Hegel is saying that the passage from the finite to the infinite object of thought is logically inevitable.
< previous page
page_227
next page >
< previous page
page_228
next page > Page 228
and "empirical" rather than "philosophical" (VGP III, p. 339). Kant will agree that the human mind inevitably thinks this way, but he will not admit that the necessity in question is "logical"; the human mind cannot, so to speak, help thinking what it cannot logically justify. Once again, for Hegel, it is not that the human mind in its essential finitude is so structured that it cannot but think this way; rather, it is thought, in its essential infinity, which either thinks this way or is unfaithful to its vocation as thought. Kant, Hegel tells us, "describes reason very well, but does so in an empirical manner from which thought is absent and which deprives itself again of its own truth'' (ibid., p. 333). It is not difficult to see, then, that Hegel is convinced that the traditional "proofs" for the reality of God do, in fact, "prove"so long as "prove" is not taken to mean employ "propositional syllogisms" in order to show that the relationship of concepts in the propositions coupled with the relationship of the propositions to each other necessarily entail the conclusion that "God exists." He very clearly states that no single syllogismor, for that matter, no set of syllogismscan prove that God really is, precisely because it is beyond the capacity of the syllogism to capture the necessary "ascent" of thought to the reality of God's being (see VPR I, pp. 31415). Nor is it difficult to understand why Hegel would contend that, ultimately, there is only one "proof," the so-called "ontological argument," to which all other proofs are reducible. The "ontological argument," however, is not to be conceived of as a movement (a "leap") from the finite mental existence of a "concept" of God to the mental affirmation that "reality" is to be "assigned" to that concept. The substance of this argument, as Hegel sees it, is not that, because thinking the infinite is a necessary condition for thinking the finite, therefore, if one thinks the finite one must also think the infinitewhich is about what the syllogistic form of the argument, even in Anselm's classical formulation of it does. What Hegel is saying, rather, is that, because the being of the infinite is a necessary prerequisite for the very possibility of thinking the finite, the infinite really isor else thinking is not. Knowledge and Experience The difficulty of understanding Hegel's positionto say nothing of accepting itwould seem to stem from a very laudable determination to get away from empty abstractions and root all knowing in experience. Reason can, in fact, not be satisfied with mere abstractions, and so the modern empirical instinct to place both feet on the ground and say, "show me," is both understandable and commendable (see EpW, no. 38, Zusatz). It is in fact a remedy for reliance on principles of merely abstract "understanding": "The here and now, this world of ours, should not be ex
< previous page
page_228
next page >
< previous page
page_229
next page > Page 229
changed for an empty other world, for the spiderwebs and misty forms of abstract understanding" (ibid.). It may seem strange, of course, to hear Hegel refer to this empirical world as "an infinite principlethat solid footing so much missed in the old metaphysic" (ibid.), but the point he is trying to make is that the "infinite principle," which it has always been the ''instinct of reason" to seek, is discoverable in the world of experience, if only reason knows how to look. "The infinite principle, therefore, is in the world for reason to discover, even though in individual, sensible form, not in its truth" (ibid.). The "truth" of the principle is in thought, and this is what empiricism, because it relies too exclusively on experience, runs the risk of missing. Nowhere is this last more obvious than in the effort (and this includes Kant) to give an "empirical" account of thought. If the thinking process is realand this, it would seem, empiricism has no intention of doubtingit must be observable (although nowhere is any reason adduced why the real must be observable), and so empiricism must content itself with seeking to describe what happens when oneanyonethinks, without a hint that the answer might be sought in the essence of "thought" and not in an "observation" of the unobservable. No one saw more clearly than Hegel that ultimate empiricism is untenable, precisely because it cannot verify empirically its own principles. It is Hegel's contention, then, that logic, and not psychology, can think the reality of thought and that, in so doing, it will discover thought's inevitable infinity, the "infinite principle," that is, the "concept," the "idea," for which the "instinct of reason" has been looking. Small wonder, then, that Hegel should cast his vote for the "ontological argument" in his endeavor, not to "prove," but to "discover the proof" for the reality of God! If the "reality" of God could be proved in the logic of empirical science, what is proved would be an unreal God. Unquestionably the world is there to be observed, in fact it is to be "conceived," if thinking is to do its job; but to "conceive" without penetrating to the reality of the "concept" would seem to be a rather fruitless endeavor. It may be difficult for us to understand how Hegel could say that the "concept" is independent of our thinking, but it would seem even more difficult to understand how anyone could say that the concept is dependent on its being contingently thought. To give but one example, it is surely inconceivable that the concept of the "human," what it truly is to be human, should be contingent on what Ior any number of "I's"think it to be. It would seem, then, that Hegel is making eminently good sense when he claims that knowing has to mean something more than subjectively producing, that is, "representing" a content which the mind on its own recognizance applies to reality. Knowing is, rather, thinking a content which is already thereand this can make sense only against the backdrop of an "infinite" reality which is already there. It is the work of "proofs" for God's reality, then, to carry on the march from
< previous page
page_229
next page >
< previous page
page_230
next page > Page 230
finitude to infinity, since the reality of the infinite is the condition for the very possibility of both the thinking and the being of the finite. "Proof" is a way of describing the movement of thought from the abstract to the concrete: "the abstract is finite; the concrete is truth, the infinite object" (VPR II, p. 226). The "proofs," then, are not proofs in the customary sense of that term: they are what Hegel's logic calls "comprehensive thinking" (das begreifende Denken) of a content which is inescapable, the unfolding of the ''Concept" in the form of thought. This is the specifically human relationship to the "infinite object," and the "logical element of this transition is contained in those so-called proofs" (ibid.). Thus, the proof of God is but the logical working out of what thought already knowsabstractly at first but progressively more concretely. When we say God we speak of him merely as abstract; or when we say God the Father, the Universal, we speak of him only in terms of finite existence. His infinitude consists just in this: that he supersedes this form of abstract universality, of immediacy, and in this way difference is posited; but it is just his very nature to supersede also this difference. Thus and only thus is he true reality, truth, infinitude. [Ibid., p. 227] The "ontological argument," then, is not a movement in human thinking from a finite concept, which the mind "represents" to itself, to an affirmation that what the concept represents is real. This would be an illegitimate leap from the presence of a merely subjective, formal concept to a real object of that concept. Rather, as Gustav Müller puts it in summarizing the sixth lecture on "Proofs of God's Reality," "the concept is in and for itself the proof of God."18 Or, as Hegel himself puts it in Science of Logic, the ontological proof is the concept's own selfdetermination to objectivity (WL II, p. 353). What this is saying is that God manifests himself in thought; the being of thought is the self-manifestation of God, because in thought and thought alone (philosophical thinking) the concreteness of the "God" in whom religion believes comes through. But, and this is the main point, the true being of God will not be recognized in a concept which is not God's own doing, and God's own doing is thought, the activity of that Spirit which is spirit and only spirit. Like all thought divine thought is self-determination, with this difference that God is self-determining in himself, "before creation," and the self-manifestation which is the existence of finite reality is a self-othering which in no way takes away from his identity with himself.
18. Gustav Müller, Hegel: Denkgeschichte eines Lebendigen (Munich: Francke, 1959), p. 368.
< previous page
page_230
next page >
< previous page
page_231
next page > Page 231
God as a living God, and still more as absolute Spirit, is recognized only in his activity. Early in his career man was directed to recognize God in his works; only from these can proceed the determinations which are called God's attributes, just as therein also his being is contained. [WL II, pp. 35455] If, however, we persist in recognizing as "real" only what can be experienced (seen, touched, possessed, like 100 Talers), God will in fact be unrecognizableto us. A philosophy which accepts no content not presented by the senses, not experienceable in this way, must stop short of God. "When a philosophizing does not raise itself to a being above the senses, by the same token, even in its concept it does not relinquish mere abstract thought; and this latter stands over against being" (WL II, p. 355). There is simply no way that infinite Spirit could be the content of such thinking. A thinking which "stands over-against being" can, admittedly, say nothing of the reality of what it thinks, not even of the reality of the sensible. On the other hand, a thinking which does "raise itself to a being above the senses" will not stop short of a pure suprasensible reality. All of this might seem to be an application, in relation to God, of a process of concretization which takes place in any passage from abstract formal conceptualization to an affirmation of the reality of that which is thus conceived. It is not, however, an affirmation of what is true of thinking; it is the paradigm of all thinking, as the process which is the process of reality. The "ontological argument" is not a proof which is justified by logic; it is the description of thought as the concrete march toward ultimate reality which justifies logic. Hegel's Science of Logic depends for its validity on the validity of the ontological argument. Still, in the exposition of the pure concept it has further been indicated that this same is the absolute divine concept itself. Thus, truly there would be no question of a relation of application; rather that logical process would be the immediate presentation of God's self-determination to being. [Ibid., p. 356] There is no attempt on Hegel's part to deny that the argument begins in concept; its validity lies precisely in beginning there, because reality is there. If we cannot get to God this way we cannot get to God at all. To begin with a reality which, by supposition, would not be God would be to condemn ourselves to stop short at an abstract God, at a Kantian limit-concept, an "ideal" from which neither the being nor the nature of God could ever be inferred. "All to the good," one might say, "let us leave it at that: Since the conditions for the verification of this concept are not available, we cannot, in effect, know God." As Hegel sees it, however, this would condemn us to not knowing anything, since all knowing would be empty abstraction, with nothing but contingent "appearing" to fill itwhich is, in fact, what it is for Kant.
< previous page
page_231
next page >
< previous page
page_232
next page > Page 232
The form which this mediation takes is that of the ontological proof of God's existence, wherein we begin from the concept. Now, what is the concept of God? It is the most real of all things, to be grasped only affirmatively, determined in itself. The content here has no limitation; it is all reality, and only as reality is it without limits, thus leaving over, as previously remarked, only the dead abstract. [VPR II, p. 208] Having seen as much as we have of Hegel's insistence on the "ontological argument" as the paradigm "proof" for the reality of God, we might be tempted to wonder whether he is being serious when, in the sixteen Lectures on Proofs for the Reality of God, which his editors appended to Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, he speaks in the plural of "proofs." In the precise sense in which he speaks of "proof"not of "proving''it would seem that only the ontological is truly a valid proof and that whatever other traditional proofs there are must be reducible to the ontological if they are to be viable at all. There is a sense, of course, in which this is true. To the extent that the other arguments are "proofs of understanding," they are not proofs at allbut, for that matter, neither is the "ontological" if formulated in the traditional syllogistic way, as we have seen.19 Only a "proof of reason" is adequate to the reality of God, and the ontological, the self-developing movement of the concept, is fundamental to the very possibility of proof. But because there is a fundamental element of contingency in human thinking, there is a diversity of possible starting points for the ascensio mentis in Deum which warrants speaking of a diversity of proofs, even though the fundamental movement of thought in each must ultimately be the same (ibid., pp. 10, 2024); God is not limited to only one way in which to reveal himself. In the thought which progresses from the finite and abstract to the concrete and infiniteor else it is not truly thoughtthere is an experience of God. This experience can be repeated, and in a variety of ways, because it is in continuity with a variety of initial experiences, which thought thinks throughand, thus, God manifests himself in a variety of ways. We might even say that the variety of ways is integral to the diversity of self-determination of divine thought which is revelatory of God. The Meaning of "Proof" In this connection it is necessary to say that the remark made earlier in this chapter (see "The Condition of All Conditions") about Hegel's borrowing a page from Kant and Fichte regarding the reality of God as a necessary condition for the possibility of finite reality could scarcely be ap-
19. It is for this reason, no doubt, that in speaking of Anselm's "proof" Hegel avoids the traditional expression "ontological argument." It is precisely its form of "argumentation" that he finds defective.
< previous page
page_232
next page >
< previous page
page_233
next page > Page 233
plied to more than the affirmation that God, the Absolute, is real. That the reality of the real is also revelatory of what God is demands a far more profound reasoningand it is precisely this more profound reasoning which concerns Hegel. Thus, he makes it abundantly clear that the initial revelation of God to man is through nature, not only in the sense that historically speaking man's relationship to God expresses itself in the form of "nature religion" but also in the sense that enduringly, the contemplation of nature as "God's handiwork" permits us to speak of God's "attributes," which are facets, as it were, of divine reality, that which men attribute to the God who reveals himself. We must bear in mind, of course, that nature reveals God only to man who alone can think, and we must also bear in mind that the revelation is not in nature but in the thinking of it; there is no revelation to nonthinking beings and, hence, no religion among them. Having said this, however, it is nevertheless important to stress that, for Hegel, nature is not merely the environing external world in which the human spirit is immersedincluding the ''human nature" which makes man a finite part of overall naturebut, even more significantly, the world of nature is a world in which man confronts God. This by no means takes away from the primacy, both ontological and logical, of the human spirit as revelatory of the divine, but it does indicate a sort of epistemological primacy in the contemplation of nature. "The relation has to be considered as belonging within the sphere of religion, and in such a way as to show that nature is for man not only the actual immediate external world, but a world in which man recognizes God; nature is thus for man a revelation of God" (VPR II, p. 249). This revelation, however, is least perfect, since it is at once an unveiling and a veiling. "Thus the consciousness of God on the part of the finite spirit is mediated through nature. Man sees God through nature; nature alone, then, is only an untrue embodiment of God which conceals him" (ibid.). The reason for this is that, at the level of nature, there is but a finite revelation to finite mindthe "Spirit" of God dwells not in nature but in "spirit," nor is God finitized in so indwelling. "It is the lesson of our consciousness, and particularly of our religious consciousness, that nature, no less than the spiritual world, is a revelation of God: but with this difference that while nature never gets so far as to be conscious of its divine essence,20 such consciousness is the express task of the spirit, which in this is initially finite" (EpW, no. 140, Zusatz). If, of course, the "essence" of nature is contained entirely within nature, then it provides no access to God. But, "all that God is he communicates and reveals; and he does so initially in and through nature" (ibid.). In saying what he says here Hegel is directly confronting those who say that nature, because it is finite and, as finite, a self-contained system,
20. The familiar Hegelian contention that the "essence" of the finite is in the infinite.
< previous page
page_233
next page >
< previous page
page_234
next page > Page 234
cannot be revelatory of infinite beingof course it could not be, were it not for the mediation of rational spirit. Reason, then, conceives of [versteht] proof in a way totally different from understanding, and so does sound common sense. Reason's proof, it is true, also has as its starting point what is other than God, but as it progresses it does not let this other persist as immediate and real; rather, because it shows that the other is both mediated and posited, it immediately becomes evident that God, as the one who contains in himself the transcended mediation, is to be considered the truly immediate, the self-contained source. [Ibid., no. 36, Zusatz] When, on the other hand, mere understanding addresses the question of affirming God on the basis of a contemplation of nature, it is caught up in the abstractness of an absolute distinction between finite and infinite, seeing in the latter only negation of the former and thus comes up with no more than deism's indeterminate "supreme being." When understanding thus considers God, its primary concern is what predicates do or do not apply to what we represent to ourselves under the title God. In this the opposition between reality and negation is taken to be absolute, with the result that for the concept as understanding takes it there remains in the final analysis only the empty abstraction of indeterminate being, of pure reality or possibility, the dead product of modern Enlightenment. [Ibid., no. 36] Acting in this way understanding can attribute no distinct, clearly delineated characteristics to God. As a consequence it takes refuge in quantitative metaphors, attributing to God finite qualities which it then simply "infinitizes" into meaninglessness. The characteristics [of God], since they are still supposed to be determinate and distinct, have in fact been swallowed up in the abstract concept of pure reality, indeterminate being. To the extent, however, that the finite world continues to be represented as a true being with God over-against it, then there enters the representation of different relations of God to the world. These relations, then, characterized as attributes, on the one hand, as relationships to finite circumstances, must themselves be finite (e.g., just, good, powerful, wise), and yet they are at the same time supposed to be infinite. From this point of view the contradiction in question allows of only a hazy solution by means of quantitative extension which pushes them to indeterminateness, to the sensum eminentiorem. In this way, however, the attribute is annihilated and all that is left of it is a mere name. [Ibid.] To say, however, that abstract understanding cannot speak in an in
< previous page
page_234
next page >
< previous page
page_235
next page > Page 235
telligent way of God's concrete relationship to a world of finite reality, is not to say what is the intelligible way in which reason can speak of that relationship. Here it is that what we might call Hegel's most fundamental insight, that of the unity of totality, comes into play. We all have a tendency to speak with considerable glibness of "the world" or of "the universe," without reflecting too profoundly on just what such language implies. That it implies at the very least an interrelatedness of parts of a whole, such that everything in a "world" or in the "universe'' is related to everything else, in a way that resembles the interrelatedness of the vital parts of an organic body, we may be willing to admit, if the parallel is not pressed too far. We may even be willing to admit that relationship and, a fortiori, interrelatedness makes sense only in a framework of thought, since relationship is intelligible only if thought can think itthat is what "intelligible meansand the fact that thought does think it is proof enough that thought can think it, and there we stop! The human mind has the capacity to unify the totality of the thinkable; what need is there to go further than that? But, just what does it mean to say that the mind can unify, if we do not know what it means to say that what is thinkable can be unified? Can finite thought unify the disparate, if the disparate is not antecedently unified in a thought which is infinite? As Hegel sees it, the whole question of the "objectivity" of thought lies right there. If there is unity there is concept, and if there is total unity there is total concept, the conceiving of which is not the activity of merely finite mind. The unity of reality, which cannot but make its imprint on the inquiring human mind, is clearly not the product of that inquiring mind. If it is not the product of mind, however, it is difficult to see what "unity" could possibly mean. It is, then, the task of philosophy, of "speculative thinking," to plumb the depths of unity in multiplicity in order to discover that even the imposition of abstract unity in finite understanding makes no sense unless unification in thought is seen to be reunification of the diversified product of originally unified thought. It is a fact that philosophy belongs to the sphere of thought; it deals, therefore, with generalities; its content is abstract, but only in point of form, of its manner of being [dem Elemente]. In its own being the idea is essentially concrete, the unity of diverse determinations. It is in this that rational knowledge distinguishes itself from mere understanding, and it is the business of philosophizing to show, contrary to understanding, that the true, the idea does not consist in empty generalities, but rather in a universal which in its own being is particular, determinate. [EGP, p. 30] There can be no question that abstract concepts, ideas whose only being is mental, cannot measure up to the reality of God. What thinking is to comprehend is not a dead abstraction of its own making by which it seeks to "represent" the real, but rather the concrete reality which is divine life, ac
< previous page
page_235
next page >
< previous page
page_236
next page > Page 236
tivity, movement. The mistake is to think of idea as having no other being than that which the mind gives it, and that leads to the further mistake of thinking that the only connection between the Idea of God and the reality of God is the connection which understanding thinks into it. The Idea is not something dead, not an abstract essence. It is, therefore, incorect, irrational, simply bad, to represent God, who cannot be something abstract, by means of abstract expressions like être suprême, supreme Being, about which nothing further can be said. Such a God is the product of understanding, is lifeless, dead. We must consider and distinguish in the movement, first the emergence from the one into duality and, secondly, the return to the one. We have to direct our attention to the fact that the distinction, to the extent that there is one, is disappearing, ideal, transcended, but only in order that the full concrete unity, not the empty unity of the understanding, may come into its own. [Ibid., pp. 11415). Idea and Reality Although, as we have already had occasion to note more than once, Hegel is convinced that Descartes had taken a step in the right direction in turning philosophical attention away from a contemplation of external reality, merely as external, to a contemplation of ideas, he is also convinced that by confining his attention to ideas in the mind, Descartes bequeathed to modern philosophy an insoluble riddle. Granted that, if mind is to discover the meaning of reality, it has nowhere to look but into itself, to its "ideas," to find that meaning. Descartes, nevertheless, had failed to provide a means of bridging the gap between ideas and the reality they were presumed to stand for, and it is precisely because he bequeathed this gap to those who followed him, that neither rationalism on the continent nor empiricism across the channel could come to grips with the fullness of thought. If ideas are nothing but the products of the human mind's own conceptualizing activity, there is simply no way for that mind to go beyond its own ideas to a reality which is the product neither of a finite conceptualizing activity nor of the ideas themselves. Cartesian ideas may very well be considered as "real," but they are clearly dependent on the activity of finite mind for their survival; and this is true even of ''innate" ideas. Reality, however, is equally clearly not dependent on finite mental activity for its survival. If ideas are not from the first identical with reality, there is no way to identify them with reality. The best Descartes can do is to be certain that mind is doing what it ought to be doing in thinking them. It was for this reason that Descartes had to take refuge in the veracitas Dei, not because he wanted to avoid ecclesiastical censorship (he was not a coward!) but because his thinking provided him with no other adequate guaranteehe was unquestionably keen enough to see that. Willy-nilly Descartes was still caught in the grip of a
< previous page
page_236
next page >
< previous page
page_237
next page > Page 237
causal metaphysics, which could shift the burden of proof to the reliability of the cause of ideas. So was Malebranche, so was Spinoza, so was Leibnizso in fact was Locke, and in his own peculiar way so was Berkeley. And then came Hume: The causal cognitive bubble had burst! Kant did his best to put Humpty-Dumpty together again, by appealing to what had to be true, if anything was to be true, to a "transcendental ego," which was more than any and every finite ego. On the theoretical level this was of no great help, since it replaced one wall with another between thought and reality. However, by revivingperhaps unbeknownst to himselfthe medieval elaboration of the Aristotelian distinction between the theoretical and practical intellect, Kant was able to point his followers in the right direction. Although theoretical concepts could not be identified with the reality they were calculated to "represent," practical ideas were themselves the reality which moral action was geared to embody. The notion of idea as antecedent to and condition for the valid positing of finite embodiment was at least on the drawing-board, enabling Fichte to transcend the vagueness of ''transcendental ego," with its overtones of dualism, in an intuition of the "absolute Ego" as the unconditioned condition of all conditions. This gave Hegel the opportunity, under the influence of Schelling's "system of identity," to do what neither Kant nor Fichte had done: not to synthesize, but to trace the self-synthesizing of the theoretical and the practical, of the idea as cognitive instrument and the idea as vibrant living reality. The concrete idea as the condition for the possibility of all thought, of all reality, and of their identificationthe "absolute Idea." "The absolute Idea is, in the first place, the unity of the theoretical and practical idea, and thus at the same time the unity of the living idea with the cognitive idea" (EpW, no. 236, Zusatz). Of itself the cognitive idea as idea posited in finite mind can only be abstract, but where cognition is process it is the living process of concretization which progressively reveals itself as the antecedent validation of what issues from it. "In cognition we had the idea in a biased, one-sided shape. The process of life has issued in the overthrow of this bias and the restoration of that unity, which as unity, and in its immediacy, is in the first instance the living idea" (ibid.). If, however, all we have is life, we have only an indicator of the unity of idea and reality, not concrete synthesis. "The defect of life is in its being only the idea implicit or natural: whereas cognition is in an equally one-sided way the merely conscious idea, or the idea for itself" (ibid.). In cognition there is idea oriented to an object which is not itself; in life there is the imperfect realization of idea; only in the idea which is both knowing and known, in the absolute Idea, is there the "supreme form of the idea," the knowledge of which is the necessary condition for the possibility of any knowledge whatever.21
21. It should be noted that "knowledge of which" is interpreted here as both objective and subjective genitive.
< previous page
page_237
next page >
< previous page
page_238
next page > Page 238
The unity and truth of these two is the absolute Idea, which is both in itself and for itself. Hitherto we have had the idea in development through its various grades as our object, but now the idea comes to be its own object. this is the nohsiVno&104;se&119;V, which Aristotle long ago termed the supreme form of the idea. [Ibid.] By this time it should be fairly obvious that what all this adds up toall that Hegel has said of "being" (finite and infinite), "thought" (finite and infinite), "reason" (finite and infinite), "speculative thinking," ''concept," "idea," "proof," and "lifting-up" (Erhebung) of the mind to its true objectis the contention that the so-called "ontological proof" of God's reality is not only the paradigm proof to which all other proofs are reducible, but that it is also a valid proof, precisely because it reveals the impossibility of any reality, thought, or knowledge which is not grounded on and authenticated by the reality of the Absolute. In this connection it might be well to emphasize here that, although Hegel frequently refers to the classical formulation of this proof in what has been traditionally called the "ontological argument," he sedulously avoids using the term "argument" (except in those instances where his use of Beweis might be translated as "argument"). Ordinarily, however, "argument" is used to designate that formula which a thinker constructs in order to prove a conclusionor, better still, to prove that a conclusion he holds is a true one. It is precisely for this reason that Hegel holds that the proof, which is in itself valid, is formulated by Saint Anselm (and others) in a defective wayor, perhaps, that to formulate it as an "argument" is a defective way to approach the issue. It is not that we "prove" the reality of God but that the reality of God "proves" to be undeniable, if we "comprehend" (begreifen) the unmistakable self-manifestation of God in the thinking of whatever we think. There can be no question that objects are constituted as objects by and in thought: that is what we mean by "object," that which thought has before itself when in thinking it objectifies. It may be necessary to say that objects do not depend on our thoughtor on any finite thoughtfor their objectivity; it does not seem possible to say that they do not depend on thought for their objectivitywhat else could "objectivity" mean? By the same token, if we wish to say that that which we think, the object of our thought, really is (and who in all seriousness contends that there are no such objects: myself, the world about me, those to whom I speak, those to whom I listen, those whom I expect to understand me when I argue that there are not) are we not saying that we can make reality the object of our thought? In so doing, however, we are not constituting the reality of the real (Kant himself made that unmistakably clear); only a thought which is the most really real can do that. Our affirmation, then, of any reality whatever constitutes our affirmation of that without which reality is inconceivable.
< previous page
page_238
next page >
< previous page
page_239
next page > Page 239
Strictly speaking, then, neither I nor anyone else "proves" the reality of God. If there is proving to be done, God does it by manifesting himself to and in thought, and the mind's eye which is open will, in seeing the manifestation, be true to itself in acknowledging the reality of God. We can, if we wish, say, with Anselm or with Hegel, that the "concept" of God containsor is identical withthe reality of God, but it would clearly be stretching it to say that our concept of God is identical with God's reality. What then, is our concept of God? It is the self-manifestation in us of the one and only concrete reality which is identical with its concept and which, therefore, necessarily is because its concept necessarily is. The question, however, remains, as to where "proof" comes in, since proof is meaningful only as proof to finite mind. We might say that "proof" is the culmination of "manifestation,'' which takes place only when finite mind has translated manifestation into its own conception; only then has mind come to grips (begreift) with the reality manifesting itself, and only in its own concept can the mind see that the reality of God is fully identical with the concept of God. With regard to the question of beginning with being, it is to be remarked that being presents itself as immediate, as a being of infinitely multiple determinations, a world in all its plenitude. This can be more precisely characterized as a collection of innumerable contingencies in general (in the cosmological proof) or as a collection of innumerable purposes and purposeful relationships (in the physico-theological proof). To think this fullness of being involves eliminating from it the form of singularities and contingencies, and to conceive of it as universal being, necessary in and for itself, being which is active in determining itself according to universal purposes, which beingas Godis different from the being with which we began. [EpW, no. 50] We can begin to see now what Hegel means when he says, as he does so often, that we do not of ourselves think God, know God, but that God knows himself in our thinking, which is at once our consciousness of objects and our consciousness of self. My concept is not identical with the concept of God, in the sense of a one-to-one correspondence, but in the sense that my concept of God, which is the issue of my thinking God's selfmanifestation, is the manifestation in my inmost being of God as real, not merely "existing." Thus the outstanding statement of Anselm's, in which one can see the character of Scholastic understanding in general, is a proof,22 not a comprehension (Begreifen) of God's reality. With proof in the former sense I have
22. Here Hegel employs Beweis more in the sense of "argument" than in his usual sense of "proof."
< previous page
page_239
next page >
< previous page
page_240
next page > Page 240
not attained to the ultimate, not to what I am looking for; what is lacking is the I, the interior bond, inferiority as inferiority of thought. This latter is contained only in concept, in the unity of individual and universal, of being and thinking. That this unity be comprehended it would be necessary to know that of itself being determines itself to concept and, that, on the other hand, thinking and being are identical. That is inferiority: not the necessary consequence of what is presupposed; it is not the nature of thinking and being which is here the objectwhat they are is presupposed. [VGP II, pp. 59192] What Hegel makes abundantly clear in his treatment of Saint Anselm (ibid., pp. 55460) is that the thinking (thought) he is speaking of is not that of any particular thinker (or of the sum total of finite thinkers) but the "pure thinking" which is identified with being. It is this which the individual subject is to appropriate, interiorize. That there is thinking, reasoning, knowing means that what is a necessary prerequisite to this finite activity is real. But, it means much more than that; it means that, if the concrete absolute thus manifests itself, the human mind can come to grips not only with the "existence" of God but also with the what of the God who manifests himself and that our knowing him is somehow a sharing in his knowing of himself. "Thus, when we contemplate the idea of God in the philosophy of religion, we have at the same time before us the manner of his being represented. He simply represents himself to himself; this is the aspect of the manifest being [Daseins] or existence of the Absolute" (VPR I, p. 33). The "Idea" of God, then, is not confined to our thinking; God is the self-revelatory Idea to which our thinking is the response. "In the philosophy of religion, then, we have thus the Absolute as object; not, however, merely in the form of thought, but also in the form of its manifestation" (ibid., pp. 3334). Our conceiving is itself revelation: "The universal Idea is thus to be comprehended in the purely concrete meaning of essentiality as such, as active in presenting itself, appearing, revealing itself'' (ibid., p. 34). None of this means, of course, that what we say of God from the point of view of philosophy will be different from what we say from the point of view of religion; it simply means that from the point of view of philosophy we stand a better chance of knowing what we are saying. Although everything we have seen thus far in regard to "proofs" of God's reality could be directed against those who reject God entirely, it is clearly not these that Hegel has primarily in mind. Rather he is concerned directly with those who reject the possibility of "knowing" God, thus relegating the response to the divine reality to some activity, however vague, other than thinking. We have already seen that Hegel considers a belief in we-know-notwhat to be scarcely a human response at all. Here, however, it has been a question of showing that a "thinking" which does not rise to
< previous page
page_240
next page >
< previous page
page_241
next page > Page 241
God is not really thinking at all; it is not true to itself as thinking. But that is not enough; in the context in which Hegel writes, that last statement is not really problematical: even Kant would admit that we cannot think without thinking the infinite. The problem arises when the contention is that thinking the infinite guarantees the being of the infinite. That finite thinking cannot of itself guarantee the being of the infinite is too obvious to need mention. If then, there is to be a conceptual guarantee of infinite Being, it must be found in a concept which is not the product of finite thinking and which finite thinking can (must) recognize as objective and, thus, identical with the being of its object. If it can be shown, and this, Hegel contends, "speculative thinking" does, that without infinite thought finite thinking would not be, then the identity of thought and being in the infinite is seen to be necessary, which is to say, finite spirit can know this. "That we cannot subjectively think the concept of God without at the same time thinking the reality of God, Hegel contends as a consequence of his onto-theology, is possible because the essence of God, his objective concept already contains in itself God's reality."23 This is what we mean when we say God, and this is what Anselm means when he says that to have the concept of God is already to know that God is real. This, of course, brings us around full circle to Kant's contention that reality (or existence) is not the content of any concept, to which Hegel replies that any concept which does not contain reality is not a true concept, in the fullest sense (VGP II, p. 559). One might want to argue that there are no true concepts, but with someone who argues that way there is no point arguing. It is true, of course, that no finite reality thoroughly coincides with its concept; it is the very nature of finite reality not to thus coincide with its concept, and it is for this reason that there is an element of untruth in all finite reality. "God alone is the thorough harmony of concept and reality. All finite things involve an untruth; they have a concept and an existence, but their existence does not meet the requirements of the concept" (EpW, no. 24). Not only does no particular finite reality need to exist; it must perish: ''For this reason, they must perish, and then the incompatibility between their concept and their existence becomes manifest" (ibid.). The point is that it makes absolutely no sense to infer from the noncoincidence of finite reality with its concept to the noncoincidence of infinite reality with its concept. More than that, it makes no sense not to argue from the noncoincidence of finite reality with its concept to the necessary coincidence of infinite reality with its concept; else reality as such makes no sense. To acknowledge the nonbeing of the finite is to recognize the necessary being of the infinite, and to philosophize in such a way as not to acknowledge this is not to philosophize.
23. Michael Theunissen, Hegels Lehre vom absoluten Geist als theologisch-politischer Traktat (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1970), p. 107.
< previous page
page_241
next page >
< previous page
page_242
next page > Page 242
Anselm, consequently, neglecting any such conjunction as occurs in finite things, has with good reason pronounced that alone to be the perfect which exists not merely in a subjective but also in an objective mode. It does no good to put on airs against the ontological proof, as it is called, and against Anselm's thus defining the perfect. The argument is one latent in every unsophisticated mind, and it recurs in every philosophy, even against its wish and unbeknownst to it. [EpW, no. 193] What, in the last analysis, Hegel is saying, then, is not that the reality of God can be "inferred" from the concept of God in finite mind, but that only the reality of God makes it possible for the finite mind to conceive God; if God were not real he would be inconceivableor, better still, conceiving would be impossible. Only by resigning oneself to the impossibility of knowing truth at all can one resign oneself to the impossibility of knowing that God is true reality. One can, perhaps, theoretically deny the human mind the possibility of knowing the true; practically one cannot, because one cannot live that way.24 What one cannot do, theoretically or practically, is simultaneously to affirm the mind's capacity to know truth and deny its capacity to know the truth of God's reality. In the so-called ontological proof of God's reality we have the same conversion of the absolute concept into being which has constituted the profundity of the idea in modern times, but which in our own time has been presented as the inconceivable. To do this, then, because only the unity of concept and reality is truth, is to relinquish knowledge of the truth. Because the consciousness which is understanding does not hold to this unity but stops short in a separation of the two moments of truth, it still admits in regard to an object such as this [God] a belief in this unity. [PR II, no. 280, Zusatz] Faith may well be necessary, if thinking is to get off the ground; it is not to be taken as an excuseor a refugewhen thinking refuses to get off the ground!
24. In PdG (pp. 15657) Hegel refutes skepticism, not by showing that it contradicts itself but that it contradicts life; in practice it refutes itself.
< previous page
page_242
next page >
< previous page
page_243
next page > Page 243
Chapter Six The Question of Pantheism Although it has to be granted that Hegel's "speculative logic" has made a good case for the necessity of affirming the reality of a concrete "absolute," without which there is no coming to grips with any reality at all, it is, nevertheless, still quite obvious that not all the questions which can be asked have been answered by that affirmation. We have seen (chap. 1) Hegel's contention that the Absolute which rational thinking is compelled to affirm is not other than the God in whom religious consciousness believes. We have seen also (chap. 2) the speculative buildup for that contention in the ultimate identification of rational thought and concrete reality. Again, we have worked through (chap. 3) the reasoning according to which neither the concrete absolute of philosophical thought nor the God of religion can make sense other than as Spirit, because the only thinking which can be reality is the self-thinking of spirit. This then led (chap. 4) to our grappling with the concept of the infinite, not as the endless repetition of the same but as the all-inclusiveness of the totality of differences. Finally, we have seen (chap. 5) Hegel's triumphant assertion that the human mind not only canor mustthink this Absolute, this Spirit, this Infinite, this God, but that what the mind must thus think must indeed be real. Hegel has indeed made a good case, but, the question might be askedand it has beenhas he made too good a case? Is the God who (Hegel's logic tells him) must be real, so real that all else is not real, so all-inclusive that he is simply to be identified with the totality of reality, so absolute that he is in no way relative; in short, is God's infinity such that it leaves no room for a finite reality which is not God? Is the God whom Hegel's rational thinking affirms not recognizable, not acceptable as God? To the religious mind Hegel may well seem to have taken the mystery out of God, made him so rational that there is no room left for adoration. To the scientific mind, on the other hand, Hegel's God may be too mysterious, too
< previous page
page_243
next page >
< previous page
page_244
next page > Page 244
contradictory to be scientifically acceptable, the logic not adequately logical, the proofs not scientifically compelling. To common sense, finallyand, as Descartes remarks,1 no one ever complains of having been granted too little of thatHegel's God would seem to be indistinguishable from the sum total of finite reality and, therefore, finite after all. One way or the other, then, the charge that has frequently been brought against Hegel is that in trying to understand God in a way that makes rational sense he has depicted for us a God who is no God, either because a God whose existence is inferred2 from the existence of finite reality is himself only finite or because the attempt to make infinite reality intelligible leaves no room for the reality of the finiteand the result in either case is "pantheism." When, however, we attempt to make sense out of the accusation we run into a difficulty: Is it a logical, a theological, a religious, or merely an emotional accusation? It is interesting in this connection that, in writing for the Century Dictionary of 1889, Charles Sanders Peirce defined "pantheism" as "the metaphysical doctrine that God is the only substance, of which the material universe and man are only manifestations. It is accompanied by a denial of God's personality.'' Peirce's definition would seem to be tailored to describe the metaphysics of Spinoza, without being grounded in any clear understanding of that metaphysics. It is Peirce's next sentence, however, which is of particular interest here: "Pantheism is essentially unchristian; and the word implies rather the reprobation of the speaker than any very definite opinion" (emphasis mine).3 It may or may not be significant that Peirce does not apply the definition to Hegel's position, but it does indicate the need of caution in applying it to any position, since it looks very much like an abstraction whose only reality lies in the mind of the accuserif it is not simply the only way the accuser can make sense out of reason's affirming God at all. I can, I think, illustrate the problem by referring to two incidents in my own life, events widely separated in time but closely related as milestones in an ongoing attempt both to affirm the reality of God and to know insofar as I could just what I was affirming. The first event occurred not many weeks after, as a young man of eighteen, I first set foot in the novitiate of the Society of Jesus. The novitiate was situated on the banks of the Hudson River three miles above Poughkeepsie, New York, a setting in which nature
1. Descartes, Discourse on Method, part I. 2. We have already seen (chap. 5), of course, that Hegel refuses to call "proof" of God's reality an "inference," but there are those who dispute his justification for so doing. 3. A rather more pedestrian definition of "pantheism" is to be found in Webster's New Collegiate Dictionary: "The doctrine that the universe, taken or conceived as a whole, is God; the doctrine that there is no God but the combined forces and laws which are manifested in the existing universe." The implication would seem to be that, if the being of God is not inferred from the being of the universe, it must be identified with the being of the universe.
< previous page
page_244
next page >
< previous page
page_245
next page > Page 245
was manifested in all its exuberant fullness, and I was a young man who had lived all eighteen years of my life in New York City. The time was late September, and for three weeks my senses had been bombarded by a beauty I had never previously been privileged to witness. Every tree, every leaf, every blade of grass, every rock, the river, the palisades, the stars in the deep blue sky undimmed by competition with city lightsall shouted to me, and what they shouted was "God!" Who can remain sane in a setting like that? One evening, the clearest of clear evenings, the beauty became so overpowering that I exclaimed to my companions, "God is . . . all that; all that is God!" I was quickly brought back to the world of commonsense reality by one of the older noviceshe must have been all of nineteen''What you are saying, Brother," he told me, "is pantheism." The thought was a sobering one; quite obviously I had said something silly, and equally obviously I did not know what I was saying. By the same token, however, I did not know what he was sayingnor have I found out in the meantime. The second event occurred seventeen years later. I was participating in a seminar on Hegel's Logic at the University of Freiburg im Breisgau. It was not my first exposure to Hegel, but it was my first detailed examination of his Science of Logic. The seminar discussion focused entirely on the first part, "The Doctrine of Being," and since I was not yet familiar with Hegel's "speculative thinking" or with his dialectical mode of predication, I was somewhat perplexed by his simultaneous identification and distinction of finite and infinite. One evening, as I was walking home with another student in the seminar, I ventured to remark, "I find all this very interesting, even fascinating, but to me it sounds like pantheism." My fellow student stopped walking, looked at me quizzically for a moment, and then inquired, "Is that supposed to be a dirty word?" Since that time I have been trying to answer two questions: "Was Hegel really a pantheist?" and "Is pantheism, in fact, a dirty word?" I have never found the answer to either question, which in recent times has prompted a third question: "Does the term 'pantheism' really have a meaning, in the sense that it refers to a position held by anyone?" Hegel's Critics Although I now seriously doubt that I shall ever get answers to my three questions, there can be no doubt that Hegel has frequently been accused of pantheism, chiefly, but not exclusively, by Roman Catholic authorsalthough one is led to suspect that those who, like Kierkegaard and Barth, find something frivolous in trying to approach God through
< previous page
page_245
next page >
< previous page
page_246
next page > Page 246
reason at all, might well agree with the charge, if they thought it worth the trouble to do so.4 In reading what Hegel's accusers have to say in this matter incidentally, one is struck by two significant characteristics of what they have to say: (1) none of them is quite sure just what "pantheism" means or whether any position can be unequivocally called "pantheistic"; and (2) they rarely, if ever, come out and say quite clearly that Hegel was a pantheist; they say rather that his kind of thinking ''leads to" pantheistic conclusions, because, as they see it, that thinking blurs distinctions which they consider essential to orthodoxy. One can quite readily appreciate the first of the above difficulties; it is a difficulty inherent in any attempt at all to think philosophically of God, of infinite Spirit, of absolute reality. Would a God who is not the totality of reality be an infinite being; or would an infinite being who is the totality of reality be the Creator of a universe of finite reality? But the whole issue has very subtly been falsified by the illegitimate insertion of the seemingly harmless articles "a" with God and "an" with infinite Being; both logically imply that "God," "infinite Being" is a one among many. In any event, two of the staunchest proponents of theism in its strictest sense have emphasized the difficulty of distinguishing definitively between theism and pantheismparticularly where the position in question is a philosophical one, where what is at stake is knowing God. Joseph Maréchal, who made heroic efforts to wed the "transcendental method" with the philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, admits, "Nothing is so difficult as to define pantheism in its necessary opposition to theism." The wording, it is true, is unfortunate, since it presupposes what has not been proved, that is, that there is a "necessary opposition" between pantheism and theism, even though pantheism has not been defined, but the meaning seems clear enough: "Nothing is more difficult than to define pantheism in such a way that it is seen to be necessarily opposed to theism."5 José Gomez-Caffarena, writing in the Maréchalian tradition at a later date, goes on to elucidate, "There is probably no final position which may be unequivocally called 'theistic' or 'Pantheistic.'"6 Hegel might have helped both authors by pointing out that, as we have seen, on the basis of a "transcendental philosophy" à la Kant there is no solution to their difficulty. A philosophy according to
4. It is interesting in this connection that Feuerbachwho did not charge Hegel with "pantheism," that is, could not, precisely because he would not distinguish Hegel's "reason" from "Enlightenment" reasoncame to the conclusion that reason could assert no more than "atheism." 5. Joseph Maréchal, Le point de départ de la métaphysique (Brussels: Desclée de Brouwer, 1944), Cahier IV, p. 430. My own revamping of Maréchal's statement seems imperative, if we are not to find him begging the question. 6. José Gomez-Caffarena, Metafisica Transcendental (Madrid: Revista de Occidente, 1970), p. 205. It might be well to point out that Gomez-Caffarena, too, is presupposing that, if there were such "unequivocal positions," they would be unequivocally op-posed.
< previous page
page_246
next page >
< previous page
page_247
next page > Page 247
which conceptual forms, without which there is no thinking or knowing, are essentially (1) forms of subjective thinking and (2) only forms, not content, of that thinking, is condemned either not to know the infinite at all or to know only a cumulative infinite, the endless repetition of finite instances. If such a philosophy, then, is to be theisticwhich Kant's is not qua philosophyit is difficult to see how its theism could be distinguishable from pantheism. By the same token, if the only criterion by which such a philosophy judges another position is its own internal logic, it is not at all difficult to see why its judgment of Hegel's "speculative thinking" is that it inevitably "leads to" a pantheistic view of God. There may, of course, be reasons for rejecting the very concept of a totally rational system, but the reason for so doing can scarcely be that such a system, on the basis of a logic which is not its own, would ''lead to" a pantheistic conception of God. The same argument, of course, might be applied to any philosophic conception of God. To illustrate the difficulty of coming to terms with Hegel's thought in terms of a logic which is not his own, we need cite but one exampleperhaps the classic exampleof the charge of pantheism leveled against Hegel. The words are those of Joseph Maréchal. The world, objective creation, becomes then a necessary moment in the internal evolving cycle of God. God achieves consciousness of himself and thus realizes himself fully only by making himself object [for himself] in creation. Ultimately not only is the world related to God but God is related to the world; the relation becomes reciprocal. By means of a verbal fiction God and the world, the absolute and the relative, are still opposed, but, when all is said and done, there is only one God, only one Absolutethe totality. To confuse the totality with the absolute is clearly what characterizes pantheism. Every philosophic conception which eliminates the contingency of creation leads inevitably to this. [Emphasis mine]7 Before coming to grips with the overall argumentation here, in which with slight variations Maréchal is followed by, among others, Auguste Grégoire, Franz Grégoire, Auguste Valensin, and, with slightly less assurance, by José Gomez-Caffarena, Henri Rondet, and Hans Küng,8 it seems necessary to engage in what might be termed a bit of "negative ex-
7. Maréchal, Point de départ, IV, p. 434. 8. Auguste Grégoire, Immanence et transcendance (Brussels: L'édition Universelle, 1939), pp. 211216. Franz Grégoire, Études Hégéliennes (Louvain: Publications Universitaires de Louvain, 1958), pp. 140217. Auguste Valensin, A travers la métaphysique (Paris: Beauchesne, 1925), pp. 97111. José Gomez-Caffarena, Metafisica Transcendental, pp. 204205. Henri Rondet, Hégélianisme et Christianisme (Paris: Lethielleux, 1965), pp. 6671. Hans Küng, Menschwerdung Gottes (Freiburg/Br.: Herder, 1970), pp. 32041.
< previous page
page_247
next page >
< previous page
page_248
next page > Page 248
egesis" of the passage just quoted. Not only are the language and the concepts not those of Hegel, but no justification is supplied for implying that Hegel should be bound by them. "The world, objective creation": the expression, "objective creation," belongs to a Scholasticism, which may well have its merits, but which carries overtones which are completely foreign to Hegel's way of thinking. It presupposes (1) an activity of God, "creation" (among other activities?), which is completely distinct from and unrelated to its term, ''what is created," that is, "the world"; and (2) a creative activity which is a kind of "making," resulting in a something over-against God, in no way continuous with God. This, then, "becomes . . . a necessary moment in the internal evolving cycle of God": having made the unexplained distinction between an "objective creation" and some other kind of creation, the author assumes that Hegel views what is external to God as "a necessary moment in the internal evolving cycle of God," as though "external" and "internal" are other than metaphorical terms in their application to God. "Necessary moment" and "internal evolving cycle" are emotional expressions calculated to prejudice the audience. "God achieves consciousness of himself": there is an unmistakable note of both temporal succession and the employment of means in the term "achieves," and there is an assumption that we all know exactly what God's "consciousness of himself" is. "By making himself object [for himself] in creation" carries on the "means" motif and implies that "creation" and "consciousness of himself" are somehow distinct activities in God. The next sentence contains a note of horror, "The relation becomes reciprocal," the supposition being that the author has made sense out of the concept of "nonreciprocal relation" and that Hegel is at fault in not sharing his enthusiasm for the concept. The "verbal fiction" in the next sentence is predicated on the assumption that Hegel has made no senseas in Kantian terms he could notin what he says of reconciling contradictions in the infinite. This, then, permits the author to claim that what Hegel does is "to confuse the totality with the absolute"which, as we have seen, Hegel claims is exactly what a "metaphysics of understanding" must doand that this "is clearly what properly characterizes pantheism." The final sentence, then, carries the full thrust of the whole charge against Hegel: "Every philosophic conception which eliminates the contingency of creation leads inevitably to this." If by "creation" (presumably a noun in the context) is meant the totality of that which is not God, and if by "contingent" is meant that which is not necessary, and if the only being of which "necessary" is an attribute is God, then to speak of "creation" (participial) as necessary (noncontingent) is to blur the distinction between God and the totality of what is not God. But that a difficulty yet remains, which "transcendental thinking," if it wishes to remain theologically orthodox, is in no position to resolve, should be obvious. Not only (1) is it necessarily
< previous page
page_248
next page >
< previous page
page_249
next page > Page 249
true that creation, whether taken participially or nominally, as activity or the product thereof, is divine, but (2) it is also necessarily true that, although the creative activity cannot be distinguished from the infinite being of God, it is of the very essence of the product of that activity to be finitewhich, of itself, does not say "contingent." What distinguishes the world from God, then, is its finitude, not its contingency. If one wants to argue that a noncontingent world militates against God's "freedom," the issue is no longer that of "pantheism," and it demands a far more subtle analysis of the concept of "freedom" than has yet been manifested by Hegel's opponents. Be all this as it may, what is being said in criticism of Hegel is that there are three principal characteristics of pantheistic thought, all three of which are manifested in what Hegel says of God. (1) God creates necessarily (which may or may not be synonymous with "God necessarily creates") and, therefore, the created world is necessary; the contingency of the world has been eliminated. It should be noted that Hegel's opponents have no intention of denying the simplicity of God, according to which there can be no real distinction between God's necessary being and God's activity, including his creative activity. What they are denying is that the product of this creative activity, the world, need be; that would negate God's freedom in creatingGod would need the world as much as the world needs God (assuming, presumably, that "necessary" and "needed" are synonymous); to be God he would have to create. Equivalently, then, a noncreator God who, admittedly, is not the God who isand the only God who isis a possibility; whatever abstract "possibility" can mean in the context. How the finite human knows that it is possible for God not to do what he does is an issue which the critics pass over rather blithely. They can, of course, argue that God can do or not do whatever does not contradict their concept of God, but in saying that they have painted themselves into a Kantian corner. "Their'' concept of God would seem inevitably to be subjective, and in rejecting, along with Kant, the "ontological proof" of God's reality, they would seem to have cut off from themselves that avenue of escape. If their appeal is to God's revelation of himself they are still in a somewhat uncomfortable positionthat of asserting rather categorically that they understand God's self-revelation better than Hegel did, which is at least open to dispute (but that will have to wait). (2) The second pantheistic characteristic which, we are told, mars the purity of Hegel's concept of God has to do not so much with the necessity of the created world in itself as with the necessity (again equated with "need") of a created world for God's consciousness of himself. Because God's consciousness of himself is identified with God's creative activity, and because Hegel blurs the distinction between the necessity of the creative activity and the contingency of its product, the world which God creates
< previous page
page_249
next page >
< previous page
page_250
next page > Page 250
becomes necessary if God is to be a self-conscious, spiritual being. Thus, the relationship of God to the world is as necessary as is the relationship of the world to Godpresumably the relation is one of dependence on both sides. Ultimately this means that, if there is no distinction between God's consciousness of himself and his consciousness of the world, there is no distinction between the self of which he is conscious and the world of which he is conscious. That this conclusion, which may or may not be legitimate according to a logic which is not Hegel's, completely misses the point of all that Hegel is trying to say in Phenomenology of Spirit, the critics seem to ignore. (3) Since a position is designated "pantheistic" according to the manner in which it conceives of God, the charge must ultimately focus on what Hegel has to say about human reason's knowledge of God. If, as Hegel says, to know God is to know the totality of reality, it must also be true to say that to know the totality of reality is to know God, and this, we are told, is equivalent to identifying God and the totality of reality. Although it might be argued that all of these charges stem from a theological and not a philosophical position, that is, that the God Hegel claims to know philosophically is theologically unacceptable, it is interesting to note that all the authors referred to here are convinced that by adhering to the authentic philosophical theism of Thomas Aquinas one can avoid the pantheistic pitfalls of which Hegel has been the victim. Whether or not even Thomas Aquinas is safe, when the "transcendental method" has been grafted on to his philosophy, is another question. The Contingency of the World Before going on it seems necessary to note that in effect all three points made in the indictment of Hegel are reducible to the first, that is, to the claim that Hegel denies the contingency of the created world, which in turn implies that the being of this created world follows logically from the being of God and that God's knowledge of himself follows logically from his knowledge of the created world. The difficulties this creates, however, stem from certain inevitable ambiguities in the use of language; if Hegel is saying one thing, then he must be saying a second thing which, his critic knows, follows from the first. Thus, if it is true to say, as even the most ardent theist must, that God's knowledge of the created world is indistinguishable from God's knowledge of himself, both because there can be no distinction among God's activities and because the only adequate object of God's knowledge is himself, then, to employ a language which cannot but be ambiguousif not falseGod's knowledge of himself is a necessary condition for his knowing the created world. To state this in even more ambiguous language, if God knows the worldand a "theistic" God doeshe must
< previous page
page_250
next page >
< previous page
page_251
next page > Page 251
necessarily know it in knowing himself; there is no other way. Among theists who have not abandoned their faith in reason there is general agreement on this. Still, the employment of such terms as "condition" or "must" in language about God runs a great risk, especially if it accompanies the claim that this is what someone else is saying (or has to be saying!). It can be made to look as though if one says that in knowing the created world God must be knowing himself, it then follows that one is also saying that in knowing himself God must be knowing the created world. Very subtly knowledge of the created world has been turned into a condition for knowing himself (even though this does not logically follow from the preceding statement). It takes but a very elementary awareness of logic to see that the second "must'' (or "condition") does not follow from the first. But that is precisely the point: If the second statement does not logically follow from the first, it is worse than arbitrary to say that if Hegel does make the first statement he must also be making the second. Mutatis mutandis the logic of drawing invidious conclusions from what Hegel does say about human reason's knowledge of God should be examined with the same care. What, then, did Hegel himself have to say regarding the charges of pantheism which were leveled at him during his own lifetime? We have already seen (chap. 2) that in 1830, while writing the preface to the third edition of the Encyclopedia he responded with a rare emotional outburst against those who arrogated to themselves the right to determine exactly what is and what is not compatible with Christian orthodoxy and who judged his philosophy precisely from this point of view as unchristian. In 1829 he had promised reviews of five works containing specific criticism of his philosophy. Only two of these reviews appeared, and in both of them he defended himself vigorously against the charge of pantheism. The main point that he makes in these two defenses is that his critics, who, wrote from the theological rather than the philosophical point of view, had failed to grasp the distinction between a speculative metaphysics of reason and an abstract metaphysics of understanding and had therefore illegitimately judged his philosophy from the standpoint of the latter. The point Hegel is making, however, is not so much a defense of his own position as it is an attack on the prejudice that any attempt to come to grips with God philosophically will end up in pantheism, precisely because finite human reason cannot properly distinguish between the infinite reality which is God and the finite reality which is the world. If, of course, the only infinite with which human thinking can come to grips is the mathematical infinite of endless extension of the finite, then any attempt to identify such an infinite with God would terminate in an identification of God and the sum total of finite reality. It is precisely this sort of pantheism, however, that Hegel rejects in no uncertain terms. The chief text in this regard is contained in the surprisingly
< previous page
page_251
next page >
< previous page
page_252
next page > Page 252
long no. 573 in Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, where he makes the point, among others, that it is the pietistic religionists, who fear reason, and the metaphysicians of understanding, who misconstrue reason, who accuse genuinely rational philosophy of being inevitably pantheistic. It is significant in this connection that no. 573 constitutes both a long introduction to and a summary of the third part of what Hegel calls "The Philosophy of Absolute Spirit," which embraces art, religion, and philosophy, all three of which have as their subject matter the ultimate reality who is God. It is Hegel's contention that a philosophy which does not culminate in God is no philosophy at all, but it is also his contention that the God who is philosophy's object is one and the same God who is the object of both art and religion. Art "makes present" to sensible intuition under a variety of forms one and the same "substantial content," which is absolute Spirit, God (EpW, no. 572). Religion ''represents" to thought the "self-unfolding" of the same "absolute content," which in philosophy is "lifted" to the content of "self-conscious thinking" (ibid.). "Thus, this knowing (Wissen) is the concept of art and religion known (erkannte) in thinking. Herein what is diverse in the content is known to be necessary, and the necessary is known to be free" (ibid.). Philosophy, then, does what neither art nor religion can do: it can recognize both the rational necessity of the "represented" absolute object and the rational necessity of art and religion as approaches to this object. Philosophy can do this precisely because its "form" of rational thinking is the form proper to the absolutely necessary content. "This knowing (Erkennen) is thus the recognition (Anerkennen) of this content and of its form, and it is the liberation from the onesidedness of the [other] forms, lifting them to the absolute form which determines itself as content and remains identical with the content. In this way it is the knowing of that necessity which is in and for itself" (EpW, no. 573). Only when the absolute Spirit" to which art and religion are oriented is "known" are art and religion "completed" (vollbracht) (ibid.). It is philosophy's task to "explain" what art can only "present" in external form and religion can only "represent" interiorly. It is here that "understanding" pulls up short. Religious belief can put up with the patent contradictions of the Absolute which is the content of art and religion. "Understanding" not only cannot put up with such contradictions but it has an easy task pointing out the contradictions in reason's "exposition" of faith. This is what "rationalism" does, and in so doing it "finitizes" the religious content, thus in effect eliminating it. "Religion, then, is thoroughly within its rights to defend itself against this sort of reason and philosophy and to treat it as the enemy" (ibid.). Hegel's point is, however, that authentic philosophy is not rationalistic but "speculative" and that it is thus truly "religious," in a way that "rationalistic"
< previous page
page_252
next page >
< previous page
page_253
next page > Page 253
philosophy simply cannot be. "It is something else again when religion opposes comprehending reason and philosophy as such, particularly when it opposes the sort of philosophy whose content is speculative and thus religions" (ibid.). True philosophy, then, is attacked from two sides: from the side of "pietism" and from that of "rationalism''; "for the former it has too little of God in it, for the latter too much" (ibid.). To put this another way we might say that for the pietist a God whom reason demands is no God, since God far exceeds the capacity of reason; for the rationalist metaphysician a reason which demands God is no reason, because reason is essentially oriented to the finite. In the final analysis both pietism and rationalism agree in completely finitizing reason. On these grounds Hegel goes on to say that the charge of "atheism" frequently leveled against philosophy in earlier times has in his own day become rare. Neither pietists nor rationalists complain that philosophy has "too little" to say about God; that is as it should be, because for both reason is not capex infiniti. For the very same reason, however, he claims that the charge of "pantheism" has become more popular, because for the rationalist the only meaning that "infinite" can have is "totality" of finite reality, while for the pietist the only meaning that "reason" can have is finite thinking. The former, then, sees "speculative reason" as a process of infinitizing the finite, while the latter sees it as a process of finitizing the infinite. Having said this much about "pietists" and "rationalists," Hegel turns his attention primarily to the "new pietism, the new theology," which simply takes it for granted that a philosophy which seeks to know God will identify God with "the all." Such an antiphilosophical religious piety, however, runs a double risk: (1) that of engaging in a critique of a philosophical position without the equipment for so doing, and (2) that of handing over the affirmation of God's reality to "subjective feeling" rather than to "knowledge," with the result that its God is inevitably an extremely vague reality "without objective determination." The point Hegel is here making is similar to that with which he began no. 573: Only philosophy can "comprehend" the rational necessity of what religion says of God. Philosophy, it is true, can very well recognize its own forms in the categories of the religious mode of representation as well as, by the same token, its own content in the content of religion, and it can grant that both the forms and the content are legitimate. The converse, however, is not true: for the religious mode of representation does not apply to itself a critique of thought and, thus, does not comprehend itself, because its grasp is exclusively immediate. [EpW, no. 573] Because this piety relies on "subjective feeling" alone, thus eliminating all
< previous page
page_253
next page >
< previous page
page_254
next page > Page 254
knowledge of God's concrete nature, it actually has no interest in a determinate and therefore real God. An abstract God can be represented in any number of ways, and if thought were to adopt these many modes of representation uncritically it might very well culminate in an identification of God with everything. If determinate being is other than God, then to affirm a determinate God is to identify God with what is other than God. But (and here Hegel grows sarcastic) pantheism is too ridiculous to be foisted on any philosophy, and "it is only their own absence of thought and a consequent falsification of concepts which produces the notion or assertion of pantheism" (ibid.). Now, if the accusers are incapable of seeing thisand since it is a question of comprehending concepts, they are obviously incapablethey ought at least to have the good grace "to establish it as a fact that any philosopher or, for that matter, any man has attributed to all things a reality and substantiality in and for themselves and has then looked upon these things as God" (ibid.). Pantheism, Hegel says, exists only in the "heads" of the accusers.9 There might, of course, be the remote possibility that someone misled by language might understand the term "world" to designate one single thing which, since it is all inclusive could be identified with God as the totality of the real (if indeed one can perform the mental gymnastics of thinking of either the world or God as "things''). The burden of proof would still be on those who claim that in fact anyone does thinkor has thoughtof the world in this simplistic way. The world is a multiplicity of disparate, empirically observable things which can be gathered together under one heading as a linguisticperhaps even conceptualconvenience, but the likelihood that anyone would identify this with a determinate God, Hegel holds, is remote. It is, however, only such a confusion with empty unity that makes possible the introduction of so deficient a notion as that of a pantheism. Only the notion coming out of the indistinct blue of the world as one thing, the all (dem All) could be looked upon as linkable with God; only as a result of that would it be possible that anyone would hold that what is meant is that God is the world. For, if the world is taken as it is, as everything (Alles), as the endless conglomeration of empirical existences, no one would in fact have held it to be possible that there should be a pantheism, which would assert of such a content that it is God. [Ibid.] If there are philosophies that give the impression of stating precisely such an identification, Hegel goes on to say, that stems from the need common to all philosophies and all religions to come up first with a notion of God and then with a notion of the relationship between God and the world. An
9. The not uncommon phenomenon in the history of thought of attributing to the words of another a meaning those words would have only if uttered by the critic.
< previous page
page_254
next page >
< previous page
page_255
next page > Page 255
adequate philosophy will see that the determinate nature of God defines God's relation to the world, a relation intrinsic to God, not attributed to him by rationalistic thinking. If, however, the mistake is made of separating God and the world in such a way that they stand over-against each other as mutually exclusive, the infinite over-against the finite, then comes the difficulty as to how the two relate to each other (if, indeed, the number "two" can make sense in the context). "It is this connection which, by those who wish to know nothing of God's nature, is called the incomprehensible" (ibid.). This, then, brings us back to our long second chapter on the nature of the "concept" as the all-embracing, concrete, dynamic unity, the comprehension of which is the comprehension of reality. To say that to know God in concept is to know the world in concept is not to say that what is known is one and the same. It is to say that the totality of reality is not composed of God and the worldcomposition here makes no sense whatever. The pious theologians who accuse Hegel of pantheism are "hoist by their own petard"; their faith tells them that God is ''omnipresent," but their thinking does not permit them to distinguish between omnipresent and identical withbetter not to think! Because, however, they would ascribe to God an effectiveness on and in the whole of occupied space, on and in the world in his relation to it, they would have the endless fragmentation of divine actuality into endless materiality. They would have the deficient notion, which they call pantheism or the all-onedoctrine, as in fact simply the properly necessary consequence of their own deficient notions of God and the world. [Ibid.] So much for Hegel's opinion of those who accuse him of "pantheism"or of "leading to" pantheism. Their accusation stems from their inability to understand the concepts at the heart of his philosophy, from their insistance on interpreting what he does say in the framework of thought forms proper to a "metaphysics of understanding," not of "speculative metaphysics." "Speculative" Philosophy and Religion It may well be, of course, that Hegel's speculative mode of philosophizing does not sit comfortably with any philosophyor theologyother than Hegel's own (as we shall see in the next chapter, Hegel's philosophy and theology are practically indistinguishable). It is nevertheless true that we should make every effort to come to grips with this sort of philosophizing precisely because of Hegel's claims that speculative philosophizing (1) has the merit of not burdening religious faith with unresolvable contradictions, and (2) at once preserves the distinctness of God and the world and yet avoids either infinitizing the world or finitizing God in a relationship which
< previous page
page_255
next page >
< previous page
page_256
next page > Page 256
cannot but be extraordinarily intimate. The "theologians" who accuse Hegel of being a "pantheist" believe to a man that God is the "Creator" of the world, even though, again to a man, they are inevitably vague as to just what it can mean to say that God "creates" the world. No one, it would seem, can be particularly happy with the notion that God "makes'' the world, simply because apart from God there is nothing out of which God could "make" a world. How, then, does "infinite Reality" bring into being "finite reality" without finitizing himselfor does he, perhaps, finitize himself without ceasing to be infinite, and is this an unresolvable contradiction? In his Lectures on the History of Philosophy Hegel seeks to resolve the contradiction by appealing to what is a constant in his thought, to the concept of God as the concretely universal, that is, universal by embracing, not by eliminating, all differentiation. "The concrete, however, is the universal which particularizes itself and in this particularization, finitization, still remains in itself infinite" (VGP II, p. 412). It is characteristic of the authentically infinite that in "othering" itself it does not cease to be itself, that is, does not cease to be infinite. Although Hegel does not employ the terminology, this is reminiscent of the Platonic "form of the Good" or of the medieval concept of "the Good" which is "diffusive of itself." The God of "pantheism," on the other hand, is an abstract God, separated from his creation in such wise that his self-outpouring can be expressed only through the metaphor of "emanation." On the contrary, in the case of pantheism there is a universal substrate, a universal substance, which finitizes itself and in so doing steps down. It is characteristic of emanation that the universal by particularizing itself, God by creating the world, degrades himself in the particular, sets a limit to himself, finitizes himselfand this self-finitization involves no return to self. [Ibid.] To speak of the infinite "othering" itself, going out of itself, is meaningful only if the going-out is also a remaining-with. Hegel is speaking here of the difference between a God who is only infinite "substance," for which the reality of another substance would be a limitation, and the God who is infinite "activity," infinite "Spirit," whose selfothering is not self-limiting. Strictly speaking this language is intelligible, as we shall see in the next chapter, only in the light of Hegel's trinitarian theology, according to which there is a continuity of God's self-othering in himself and his self-othering in creation. This, in turn, raises the question whether Hegel's point of departure is his logic of "being" or his theo-logic of "infinite being," to which we shall have to return later. In any event what we see occurring here is a striking reversal of roles between Hegel and his critics: The accusation that by making creation necessary Hegel is being "pantheistic" is countered with Hegel's contention that to hold for a non
< previous page
page_256
next page >
< previous page
page_257
next page > Page 257
necessary creation would be pantheistic. A finite reality which is only other than the infinite would limit the infinite (see VPR I, p. 178); the finite which "is but an essential moment of the infinite" is at once other than and a necessary consequence of the infinite (ibid., p. 191). One might, of course, be tempted to argue that in all of this Hegel simply wants to have his cake and eat it. The fact is, however, that he is trying (whether successfully or not is another matter) to strike a delicate balance between according the world too much reality and according it too little.10 In a long Zusatz to no. 151 of the Encyclopedia Hegel comes across as revealing a certain ambivalence in regard to Spinoza on precisely this issue. Spinoza, he tells us, has been charged with "atheism," but in fact the reverse is true: By downgrading the difference between the finite world and infinite substance Spinoza is not an "atheist" but rather an "acosmist." By the same token, however, Spinoza is not a "pantheist'' either, "if pantheism means, as it often does, the doctrine which takes finite things in their finitude and in the complex of them to be God." On the other hand, because Spinoza's "acosmism" equivalently "denies truth to finite things and the world as a whole" (ibid.), it cannot be completely acquitted of pantheismfor Spinoza only God is real! The point is, of course, that if God is "substance" and substance only, and if God is infinite, there is no other substantial reality (see VPR I, p. 191). On the other hand, Hegel is convinced, if God is activity, "Spirit," then the "substantial" reality of the world of things is saved without equating this substantial reality with God. Hegel is further convinced that the reality of infinite activity, infinite "Spirit," is no threat to the reality of finite activity, finite "spirit" (see chap. 4). All of which brings us back to the characterization of spirit we have already seen, that in going out of itself it remains with itself, returns to itself. Having come this far in our discussion we are, it would seem, faced with three questions which, even though they may turn out to be not completely answerable, can nevertheless help clear the atmosphere. (1) Is anyone, in fact, really a pantheist in the sense either of holding that God absorbs the whole of reality or of identifying the totality of finite reality with infinite reality? Perhaps the real question here is whether meanings can be assigned to the terms in such a way that the question is intelligible at all. One could, for example, take Spinoza's Deus sive natura as an expression of either atheism or pantheism, but to do so would be to ignore the distinction which Spinoza makes between natura naturans and natura naturata. Hegel, it would seem, is convinced that Spinoza is moving in the right direction in making the distinction but that he does not go far enough, since the characteristic of the personal is absent from Spinoza's God. (2) Does
10. The reverse, so to speak, of the complaint noted previously, which his opponents register regarding his philosophy having either "too much" or "too little" of God in it.
< previous page
page_257
next page >
< previous page
page_258
next page > Page 258
anyone who claims to find evidence for the reality of God in an admittedly finite universe lay himself open to the charge of pantheism? Does not evidence of the infinite in the finite either infinitize the finite or finitize the infinite? On the other hand it might be asked whether anyone really thinks it is possible to make sense out of a merely finite universe, with no appeal to the infinite. What could a universe which depends only on itself possibly be? It could be argued, of course, that there is no compelling reason to demand that the human mind should make sense out of the universe, but it is doubtful that such an argument could satisfy a philosophercertainly not a Hegel. (3) Does the claim that Hegel's philosophy is pantheistic stem from an attempt to interpret Hegel's thought on the basis of a logic which is not Hegel's own "speculative logic"? Perhaps there is a hidden claim here that such a speculative logic cannot possibly make sense, since it violates the infallible logic according to which nothing can be stated in the conclusion of a syllogism which is not contained in its premissesand "infinite reality" is not contained in the premisses of any ''proof" of God's reality. It is doubtful, however, that one can get away with this kind of reasoning, despite the fact that it is so frequent in all philosophical criticism. To take what Hegel does say and to conclude from it that, if I were on the basis of my principles to say the same, I should be uttering a pantheistic statement, is scarcely an adequate reason for claiming that the same is true of Hegel. In a very significant sense Hegel is saying that the reality of the infinite is contained in the finitude of the finite, because the finite points to the being of the infinite without which its own being would not be intelligible. God Makes a Difference One thing is abundantly clear: Hegel is very much concerned that the God of whom he speaks make a difference to the world in which he lives and which he seeks to understand, and a God who simply transcends reason will not make that difference.11 On the other hand, a God who is in no way really distinguishable from that world will make no difference either; he adds nothing to any possible account one could give of the world. It is relatively easy, and undoubtedly true, to say that only if God truly transcends the world can he be immanent in it and, conversely, that only if God is truly immanent in the world can he be said to transcend it. What Hegel is attempting is (1) to show why reason finds this to be true and (2) to draw out the implications of this truth. To have said this, however, is once more to bring up the question of the point of departure of Hegel's enquiry or, as Hegel himself would put it, the
11. It is not enough to say that the world in which we live tells us something about God. Knowing God also tells us something about the world in which we liveand this we shall not know if we do not know God.
< previous page
page_258
next page >
< previous page
page_259
next page > Page 259
point of departure of philosophical enquiry as suchrecognizing that the point of departure will largely determine the point of arrival. But to answer this question is not nearly so simple as it might seem, if for no other reason than that, for Hegel, "point of departure" can have two almost antithetical meanings. In Science of Logic, for example, he initially asks, "with what must the science begin," to which he gives the answer, "with being.'' Then at the end he announces that the real starting point is the culminating point, the "absolute Idea," because the "goal" is the "principle" of the whole process of enquiry. Only at the end can we see what was the "principle" all along. With regard, then, to his philosophical enquiry into the reality of God, which, as we have seen (chap. 5), he says is an enquiry closely related toif not identical withlogic, we might say that the point of departure is the God in whom faith (and Christian faith at that) believes, and the process is one of showing that precisely this God is a demand of reason.12 In the process it becomes clear that Hegel is saying that a reason which does not have the Absolute as its object is not truly reason and that the Absolute to which reason is oriented is the God who is religion's object. From another point of view it can be said that the point of departure for Hegel's process of enquiry is thought and that only when thought and reality are thoroughly identified, as they are in the Absolute, in God, is the process complete. From still another point of view it can be stated that the point of departure is the reality with which philosophical enquiry seeks to come to grips and that to engage in the enquiry is to find it impossible to come to grips with reality short of affirming the reality of the God in whom religion believes. As so often happens when we seek to find out what Hegel meansor what he is trying to dowe are forced to turn back to Phenomenology of Spirit, which is not only the introduction to Hegel's "system" but also, more importantly perhaps, the constant underpinning of the system, since it is in the Phenomenology that he seeks to know what "reason" is, which would seem to be foundational for knowing what reason "demands." In the initial stages of his phenomenological investigation Hegel looks upon consciousness as simply the awareness of what is other than itself. Rather rapidly, however, this consciousness becomes aware that in looking to a reality which is presumably outside itself it is looking into itselfthere is nowhere else, to "look." The major portion of the Phenomenology, then, is devoted to the progressive awareness that in looking into itself consciousness finds all the reality that is to be found, and this is the discovery that in being thoroughly true to itself, consciousness is not merely consciousness, not even merely consciousness of itself, but is "reason"; it
12. It should be pointed out again that Hegel never does say that the God of faith can be discovered by human reason independently of faith. What he does say is that, given the God of faith, it can be seen that this God fulfills the demand of reason.
< previous page
page_259
next page >
< previous page
page_260
next page > Page 260
becomes aware that it itself "gives" itself all that of which it is aware, that its knowing is its own doing, which is not to say that the real is not real, but that the knowing of it is the activity of spirit, not a being-acted-upon. This discovery is signalized by the triumphant, even though as yet very vague, "notion of reason" in which the chapter on "Self-Consciousness" culminates; that is, "the certainty of consciousness that in its singularity it is absolutely in itself, or that it is all reality" (PdG, p. 171). This refrain is carried over in the introduction to the next four chapters wherein the realization of reason is spelled out: When reason is all that it truly is, that is, ''Spirit," "Religious Consciousness," and "Absolute Knowing," it is indeed "all reality," for there is no reality which is not reason's. Reality issues from reason, but this can be so only if reason is in the last analysis "infinite." What infinite Reason demands is so, and thus to know what reason demands is to know infinite "Reason," infinite "Spirit," "God." To say, however, that "infinite Reason is all reality" is not to affirm a static identity of God and all reality; it is to recognize that all reality is God's "doing. " Once again, then, we have to remind ourselves that, in Hegel's view, if infinite Reason is the culmination of the enquiry, it is also its "principle," that toward which the enquiry was moving from the beginning. When all this has been said, it would still seem that Hegel is not yet out of the woods. What is at issue is not, strictly speaking, whether God is real or not, whether the world is real or not, whether God is infinite and the world finite, not even whether God and the world are distinct. The real question is whether the finite human mind can legitimately make the move philosophically from its own finitude and the finitude of its world to an affirmation of infinite Being, which involves knowing what "infinite" is, without running the risk of confusing the reality of God and the reality of the world. It is all very well to say that reason itself does not make sense if there is not, ultimately, infinite Reason. It is someting else again to say that finite spirit can know infinite Spirit without, so to speak, cutting the infinite down to size or, perhaps, blowing up the finite to infinity. Is there an intelligible sense in which finite reason is infinite, at least in its capacity to know, such that it cannot be satisfied with less than an infinite object? To which might be added the further question: Is there any justification for saying that human reason should be satisfiedis not "faith" enough for us poor mortals? As a provisional answer to the second question we might say that a "faith" in a we-know-not-what could scarcely be enough and that it is not a question of whether human reason should be satisfied but rather of whether if can be satisfiedespecially if faith cannot be satisfactory if reason is not.13 With regard to the first question Hegel's
13. Lest it be argued, theologically, that faith is a "gift" which enables human spirit to do what as reason it cannot do, it should be noted that reason too is a "gift" and that its "rising" to the infinite is a "being-liftedup," an Erhebung, beyond its own finitude.
< previous page
page_260
next page >
< previous page
page_261
next page > Page 261
answer, as we have seen (chap. 4), is quite unequivocal: Reason in man shares in the infinity of "universal reason." To take "proofs" for the reality of God seriously at all is to hold for an "infinite'' activity of human reason; that there is human reason at all, that is, not merely understanding, is itself a revelation of divine Reason. If from God's side there is no obstacle to his being known, then it is but human arbitrariness, affectation of humility, or something of the kind, to insist on the finitude of human knowledge, on human reason only in its opposition to divine reason, on only the radical limitations, absolutely fixed, of human reason. . . . It is not so-called human reason with its limitations which knows God, but rather the spirit of God in man; it is, according to the speculative expression previously used, God's self-consciousness which knows itself in man's knowing. [BDG, p. 49] The question might well seem to fall into the trap prepared for Hegel by his adversaries, but the point is precisely that, just as the being of the finite is a manifestation of infinite beingor, of the being of the Infiniteso finite knowing, which is ultimately self-knowing, is a manifestation of God's infinite self-knowledge. God can be known only if he reveals himself, but the knowing is the revelation, by virtue of what Hegel calls "the community of Spirit with spirit." It is not as though God's self-revelation and man's appropriation of it can be separated. This consideration is the profoundest, the most sublime and therefore the most difficult object; it does not come across in finite categories, which is to say that the modes of thinking we are accustomed to in everyday life, in handling contingent things, and even in the sciences, are not adequate to this object. These last have their foundation, their logic, in relationships of the finite like cause and effect; their laws, classifications, and modes of inference are mere relationships of the conditioned, which on this higher level lose their significance. They must, it is true, be used, but in such a way that they are constantly taken back and corrected. The object, the community between God and man, is a community of Spirit with spirit. [Ibid., pp. 11617] In saying what he says here, Hegel is arguing with Kant and Jacobi who claim to know that a reason which is finite cannot know God.14 In opposing Kant and Jacobi, it should be noted, Hegel is opposing all those who say that God could be known only if his reality could be inferred from the finite reality men do know, and if the rules of inference were precisely the same as those which are successful in the "sciences." Hegel is stating without
14. See Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik, ed. Georg Lasson (Hamburg: Meiner, 1963), vol. I, p. 38; vol. II, pp. 103, 38990, 440, 486; William Wallace, trans., The Logic of Hegel, (London: Oxford University Press), nos. 9, 41, 50.
< previous page
page_261
next page >
< previous page
page_262
next page > Page 262
equivocation that, when there is question of coming to know God as real and not as some sort of abstract possibility there can be no question of "inference." Where there is question of "proof" of God there is no question of a subject constructing an argument which will justify the conclusion that something is the case, not only because God is not some-thing, but also because the "what" of what is the case could not possibly be contained in the premisses of such an argument (see ibid., pp. 1517). This is not to say that the notion of "inference" (das Schliessen), as Hegel uses it, is easy to pin down. That "inferred'' knowledge is "mediated" knowledge is clear enough, but since for Hegel all knowledge is mediated (i.e., not immediately "given"), this does not help much. What he is trying to get away from in describing the process of coming to know God is seeing it as a process in which the knowledge that the finite human spirit has of God would follow from and be dependent on an antecedent knowledge of finite reality, what Hegel calls "dualism," that is, making finite and infinite two realities "over-against" each other. This is not to say that we can know God without knowing finite reality, but it does say that it is not because we know finite reality that we know God. What Hegel is in fact saying is rather the reverse: Only because we know God do we really know finite reality (see Ep W, nos. 95, 112). But, and this is important, there is no unmediated knowledge of God; that would not be knowledge at all (see BDG, p. 26; Ep W, nos. 7475). To recognize the infinite is to have mediated knowledge, but it is not inference (Schliessen), rather it is "revelation" (Scheinen) (BDG, pp. 7677), and the rational elaboration of that knowledge is integral to the revelation, since "reason" in man is revelation, the presence of the divine in man. Only One God Hegel also states without equivocation that there is only one God to be known, the God who reveals himself to faith. In this he is throwing down the gauntlet to Fichte, Schelling, and any form of Romantic intuitionism, which would grant that the human mind can know only an utterly indeterminate absolute, a God without meaningful predicates, which, if they are supplied at all, are supplied by faith.15 It is interesting to note in this connection that the "intuitionists" give no explanation of how, even through faith, finite mind could be the recipient of a revealed infinite content. What Hegel is leading up to, however, is something far more important: There can be no so-called "God of the philosophers," who would somehow be other than the God who really is. Philosophy cannot know a God who is a sort of abstract possibility, who might do what God does not do or who
15. WL I, pp. 33839; II, p. 757; EpW, no. 36; BDG pp. 9, 2324.
< previous page
page_262
next page >
< previous page
page_263
next page > Page 263
might not do what God does.16 An abstract God is one about whom nothing intelligible can be said. But, by the same token, the concrete God must be one about whom whatever is said must be intelligible to man, or else nothing is being said (see BDG, p. 172). What this ultimately means is that there is continuity between Christian faith (the only "faith" there is for Hegel) and rational thought.17 This key notion of "continuity," as we have seen and shall see throughout this study, is extremely important; it is precisely what Hegel's illustrious predecessors had denied. More than that, Hegel will insist, even God can reveal himself only to reason, since reason alone is capex infiniti, and to have God as the object of thought is not authentically "human" if the thought in question is not rational thought. A revelation of which reason does not know the meaning is not, properly speaking, a "revelation.'' To say that reason can tell us that God (an empty term) is, but that only revelation can tell us who or what God is, is to talk nonsense. Is it indeed possible to distinguish the knowledge of "what" God is from the knowledge "that" God is, if the term "God" is to have any meaning? "God is; but just what is this that is supposed to be?"18 The overriding theme of Hegel's Science of Logic is that to know is to know being as infinite, or else it is to know only partially, which is really not "knowing" at all.19 But, quite obviously, it makes no sense to speak of knowing being as infinite and not knowing what it is for being to be infinite, and to know what it is concretely for being to be infinite is to know God. If, as Science of Logic would have it, the very being of the finite makes no sense except in relation to infinite being, then knowledge of finite being makes no sense except in relation to infinite being. Since, however, this makes finite and infinite mutually implicative, the specter of "pantheism" once again raises its ugly head.20 Here the distinction between "concrete" and "abstract" becomes supremely important. There can be danger of identifying God and world only if both are abstract; there is no danger of identifying concrete God and concrete world, because a mutual implication which is dynamic (concrete) bespeaks not identity but continuity.21 Although the term "continuity" is by no means prominent in Hegel's vocabulary, the concept, it seems to me, goes a long way toward resolving the contradictions which a thinking confined to "scientific understanding" finds in Hegel's notions of "dialectical relationship" and "speculative thinking." This is particularly true if we employ in a metaphorical sort of
16. See BDG, pp. 5, 42, 5051, 81, 17677. 17. See BDG, pp. 5, 9, 17677. One wonders, for example, how Karl Rahner (Spiritual Exercises [London: Sheed and Ward, 1967], p. 48) can know that "God could certainly have created another world." Just what can "could have" possibly mean? 18. BDG, p. 57; see pp. 1213, 1517, 2324. 19. WL I, pp. 31, 144; II, pp. 15960, 441. See EpW nos. 12, 51, 86. 20. See WL I, pp. 41, 80, 109, 117, 126, 128, 143, 145; see EpW nos. 36, 112. 21. See, once more, EpW, nos. 389, 573; VA I, p. 470.
< previous page
page_263
next page >
< previous page
page_264
next page > Page 264
way the term "continuous"as opposed to "contiguous"to a variety of dynamic relationships which are calculated to integrate rather than disintegrate reality.22 In the third book of Science of Logic (i.e., the second half of volume II) Hegel, without employing the term, seeks to explicate dynamic continuity on three levels: subjectivity, objectivity, and idea (as the synthesis of subjectivity and objectivity). (1) On the level of "subjectivity" he finds continuity (integration) in the conceptual mode of knowing, and this he does by explicating the dynamic passage from concept to judgment to syllogism. This is opposed to the disintegrating function of ''understanding," which sees "concept" as no more than a subjective form unifying objective diversity, "judgment" as no more than the subjective combining of concepts, and "syllogism" as no more than subjective "inference" from premisses to conclusion. Hegel speaks of the integrating function of "reason," which sees into (speculare) the successive selfarticulations of the concept in (a) "judgment" (the unfolding of concept) and (b) "syllogism" (the grounding of judgment). (2) On the level of "objectivity" Hegel moves from less adequate models to the more adequate models of integrating relationship in (a) the "mechanical" model (relationship of cause and effect), (b) the "chemical" model (relationship of selective affinity), and (c) the "teleological" model (relationship of purposeful movement). (3) On the level of "idea" he presents successive stages of continuity, with the first two calculated to clarify the third: (a) the idea of "life," both the organic continuity of the living animal and the continuity of life in all organisms; (b) the idea of "cognition" in its essential orientation to both the true and the good; and (c) the "absolute" idea, which is the all-embracing unity-continuity of the totality of reality-thought. This quick summary obviously does not resolve all the difficulties of Hegel's identification of the identical and the different, but it does help to bring the language into focus. It is doubtful whether it is possible to make any sense at all of either "finite" or "infinite," if what is designated by the terms are realities lying, so to speak, side-by-side (contiguous). However, if the terms connote a continuity in which they are intelligible only in relation to each other, it ceases to be barbaric to say either "the finite is infinite" or "the infinite is finite," whether what we are speaking of is "being," "thought," "concept," "reason," or "spirit." To speak, then, of a "lifting-up" (Erhebung) of finite thought, reason, spirit to infinite reality is not necessarily to speak only of a supernatural elevation; it is simply to say that the movement of thought is more than the activity of the individual finite subject. There is a continuity between the finite subject and infinite "subjectivity," such that the finite subject realizes itself as what it is and what it does only in its ultimate elevation to the infinite, and that elevation
22. It is in this sense that Charles Sanders Peirce so often employs the term.
< previous page
page_264
next page >
< previous page
page_265
next page > Page 265
is its knowing, not merely its believing, and, above all, not merely its feeling or intuiting, or whatever other activity may be designated as capax Dei. Response of "Human" Spirit There is no question in Hegel's mind that faith is a human response to divine self-revelation, nor that the response and the revelation are continuous. He is convinced, however, that the response is inadequately human, inadequate to the "spirit" in man, if it is not a "thinking," a "knowing'' response. Those who would dignify God by putting him beyond the reach of human knowing are not upgrading God by shrouding him in mystery; they are downgrading man by wrapping him in a cloud of mystification. It is not the mystery of God but the mysteriousness of human language which makes God approachable by faith but unknowable by reason. Nor is this all too different from the irrationality of a rationalism which so absolutizes the finitude of reason that it renders the very intelligibility of an infinite object impossible. There may be something sublime in an irrationality which seeks to upgrade God and something tawdry in an irrationality which seeks to downgrade man, but in effect they are both rooted in the same denial of the continuity of the finite and the infinite, the human and the divine, believing and knowing. Hegel's basic conviction, then, is that God does in fact reveal himself to man and that faith is a response of man to that divine self-revelation (see BDG, pp. 44, 4748). But if man does not understand the revelation,23 the believing is empty, and the revelation is scarcely revealing. Granted that both the believing and the understanding are finite human activities, that creates no insuperable difficulties. God's self-revelation to anyone but to himself will necessarily be finite (see chap. 7); it will not for that reason be discontinuous with the infinity of the revealer; in revealing himself to man God renders himself finite, without ceasing to be infinite. Faith, then, must not only seek understanding, it must also find understanding, and this it does when it knows what on the level of religious consciousness it only believes; that is, it represents to itself on the basis of an external revelation the God who in ultimate rational knowing presents himself internally (renders himself present) to man. Both the believing and the knowing are products of God's self-revelation, but the believing will remain empty if man does not know what he believes. How, then, does God reveal himself? To answer that question we must first of all turn again to Phenomenology of Spirit, the whole purpose of which is to investigate how spirit manifests itself as spirit. Spirit manifests itself as what it is by its activity; of no being is it more true than of spirit to
23. Here there are no pejorative connotations to "understanding."
< previous page
page_265
next page >
< previous page
page_266
next page > Page 266
say that its being is its doingand that doing is inevitably self-revealing activity;24 spiritual activity is selfmanifestation, and it manifests not only that but also what spirit is. If, however, the activity in question is to be revelatory of infinite Spirit, it must be possible for man to know that the activity in question could not be other than divine. But this kind of knowing can, in turn, make sense only if there is continuity between religious consciousness, the initial awareness of the divine, and rational consciousness, the articulation of religious consciousness. Here the distinction between "finite" and "infinite" becomes tremendously significant. Precisely because the finite being who is man is not totally spirit, there can in man be only partial identification of being and activity, of being and "concept"; it is essential to finite being that its "actuality" be not identifiable with its concept, while it is essential to infinite being that its actuality be identical with its concept. The point, however, is not simply that divine (infinite) being and divine activity are identicalthis, after all, is a commonplace of Christian faithbut rather whether human reason can know this identity. Narrowly scientific reasoning (what Hegel calls Verstand) can see in such identification only contradiction; only authentic rational (speculative) thinking (what Hegel calls Vernunft), which is essentially oriented to the infinite, can comprehend that, where there is question of infinite being, the identification of being and activity or of internal and external activity (self-knowing and selfmanifestation) involves no contradiction at allor, at least, no unresolvable contradictionbecause the very concept of infinite being demands the identification. Anything short of this would contradict infinity, here understood as complete self-containedness, whose self-manifestation to another in no way derogates from its enduring beingwith-itself. If, then, it makes sense to look upon creation as divine activity and upon the product of that activity as the finite manifestation of infinite Spirit, it makes equally good sense to say that human reason in understanding God's selfrevelation is itself the finite manifestation of infinite Reason. As we have seen, Hegel again and again calls precisely the rational grasp of infinity a "being-lifted-up" (Erhebung), which signifies the presence of the divine Spirit in the human spirit, which need not be confined to a "supernatural" divine indwelling. "Our theme, the elevation of subjective spirit to God, immediately involves that in it what is onesided in knowing, its subjectivity, is transcended, that the elevation itself is essentially the transcending."25 Human rational knowing, then, is a revelation of God to man, and to conceive of reason as no more than the formal activity of the individual subject
24. Only in this way is it possible to come to grips with PdG, chap. VIII, "Absolute Knowing." 25. BDG, p. 44; see pp. 1213, 50, 78, 81, 122.
< previous page
page_266
next page >
< previous page
page_267
next page > Page 267
is to miss this entirely. To recognize religious consciousness in man as God's work in human consciousness is affirmed by pietists and denied by rationalists. Hegel will go beyond both in affirming that mediated (rational) knowledge of God is such an elevation: "This elevation which is consciousness is thus of itself mediated knowing" (BDG, p. 81). Thus, what had traditionally been taken as the prerogative of the theologians to expound, the indwelling of the Spirit, Hegel has turned into a philosophical truth. He does not say that reason has the capacity to discover this truth, in the sense that independently of religious consciousness reason could see its necessity, but he does say that in virtue of the continuity of faith and reason, "speculative thinking" can grasp what the truth means and can see it as fundamental to the very possibility of reason functioning as reason. If the being of God and the activity of God are identical, and if the "activities" of God, no matter how variously named, are all one, as Christian theology reflecting on revelation tells us, then the activities of self-knowing, selfrevelation, and creation (traditionally accepted as divine attributes) are all one and the samethey are what God is. Moreover (as we shall see in the next chapter), Hegel identifies as one "continuous" activity the "procession" in the Trinity through knowledge and love (God knowing and loving himself and thus being "three" without ceasing to be ''one") with creation, the incarnation of the Son, the redemption of the human race, and the descent of the Holy Spirit to dwell in the Christian religious community (see PdG, pp. 53448). Up to this point no Christian theologian would find fault with Hegel; this is all traditional Christian teaching. When, however, Hegel finds all this philosophically intelligible in the light of his own Science of Logic, the theologians tend to part company with himeven though the theological tradition itself has had to reflect rationally on the revelation in order to come up with such conclusions. That Hegel does make them nervous may be understandable, but, if nothing else, his contention makes it clear that his claim to think within the framework of the Christian revelation is to be taken seriously.
The standpoint where we find ourselves is the Christian one. Here we have the concept of God in its full freedom [self-determination]; this concept is identical with being. Being is the most impoverished abstraction, and the concept is not so poor as not to contain within itself this determination. We are not to consider being in the poverty of abstraction, in deficient immediacy, but being as God's being, as thoroughly concrete Being, distinguished from God. The consciousness of finite spirit is concrete being, the material for the realization of the concept of God. Here there is no question of being as an addition to the concept or of a unity of being and conceptsuch expressions are misleading. The unity is to be understood rather as absolute process, as the vitality of God, such that both sides are also distinguished in it, but that this is the absolute activity of eternally producing itself. Here we have the concrete notion of God as
< previous page
page_267
next page >
< previous page
page_268
next page > Page 268
the Spirit. The concept of Spirit is the concept which is in and for itself, knowing: this infinite concept is the Spirit's negative relation to itself. . . . In the Christian religion it is known that God has revealed himself; and God is precisely this, to reveal himself; to reveal is to differentiate oneselfwhat is revealed is precisely this that God is the manifest. [BDG, p. 176] It is clear, then, that Hegel's interpretation of revelation and his overall logic of the concept run parallel. What is not perfectly clear is whether his logic is an articulation of his understanding of Christian revelation or whether his interpretation of that revelation is an application of his logic. If we take him at his word, the whole truth, which is God, is first made manifest to religious consciousness, subsequently to be elaborated in speculative thinking. In any event, as Hegel sees it, revelation is intelligible only in the light of logic, and logic is adequate only if its content recapitulates the revelation. Logic is at once the total framework of thought and the total framework of divine selfrevelation, for God reveals himself only to and in thought. The question can now be asked: In how many ways does God reveal himself in his activity? It is clear enough that, if the human mind can know divine activity as divine, it can know God. The question, as should be obvious, cannot mean, How many different activities are there wherein God reveals himself to man? Rather, it must mean, In how many ways can the human mind recognize divine activity as divine and thus come to know God? The answer to the question reads like a description of Hegel's "system" of philosophy. Logically speaking, God reveals himself first in creating finite mind which, in thinking, necessarily ascends to infinite being, even though chronologically speaking that ascent may initially be no more than a vague "religious" awareness of an ''absolute" transcending man. To speak of the mind ascending "necessarily" quite obviously cannot mean a psychological or epistemological necessity, according to which no human mind could fail to ascend to God.26 Apart from the fact that there could be no way of knowing such a necessity, it is too clear that many a human mind either does not ascend to God or is not aware that it does. The "necessity" of which Hegel speaks is logical, such that the failure to ascend to God is a failure in logic.27 It is for this reason that Karl Löwith could describe Hegel's Science of Logic as a "continual defining of God."28 Nor does this mean that finite thinking necessarily infers from the empirical fact of its
26. Unless, of course, one wants to say that, in knowing at all, the human mind willy-nilly has God as its ultimate object. 27. If we follow the logic of Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit, we might say that, even if not each and every human mind does ascend to God, the human spirit cannot fail to do so. 28. Karl Löwith, Von Hegel zu Nietzsche (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1950), p. 39. (Löwith is quoting Karl Rosenkranz.) Cf. Gustav E. Müller, Hegel: Denkgeschichte eines Lebendigen (Munich: Francke, 1959), p. 386: "The concept is in and for itself the proof of God."
< previous page
page_268
next page >
< previous page
page_269
next page > Page 269
own existence the existence of infinite thought. Rather it means that the human mind which truly thinks logically sees (speculare) in the activity of thinking the reality of infinite thought, without which the very being of thought would be inconceivable. In the introduction to his Science of Logic Hegel speaks, as we have seen, of logic as "the presentation of God in his eternal essence, before the creation of the world or of a single finite spirit." In these words Hans Küng reads "unmistakable echoes of the eternal Logos of the Johannine prologue."29 If God is infinite Spirit there is no more to be read in his "eternal essence'' after creation than before (if indeed "before" and "after" have other than a logical meaning). Whether any logic, including Hegel's, can present a total framework within which being is intelligible may well be a question. The point is that Hegel is convinced that the framework can be elaborated without appeal to the empirical reality of the created world, merely from following out the implications of thought as such and that what this reveals cannot be other than the divine thought which is the paradigm of all thought. What has been said here about the inconceivability of any thought whatever if infinite thought is not real is, of course, but an elaboration of the "ontological proof," which is the model of all proofs from divine activity. Another way in which the human mind can read divine activity is in the contemplation of "nature." Not, again, because the being of finite nature leads the mind to infer the being of an infinite God who must be the cause of it. There is simply no way of inferring the existence of an infinite cause from the existence of a finite effect. The mind, however, can see that nature makes sense only as created and that "creation" is an activity which can only be divine, infinite activity.30 Nature is unquestionably real, but its reality is conceivable only as contained in spirit: no spirit, then no nature, and no infinite Spirit, then no Nature, as totality. Nature reveals itself as essentially dependent on Spirit, and the Spirit in question must be infinite, because only infinite Spirit is totally independent. Nature is contained in spirit, is the product of spirit, and despite the illusion (Scheins) of its immediate being [its giveness], it is of itself merely something posited, produced, ideal in spirit. When in the process of knowing the move is made from nature to spirit, and nature is characterized as simply a moment of spirit, the result is not a true plurality, a substantial two, one of which would be nature and the other spirit; rather the idea, which is the substance of nature, when immersed in spirit, holds in this infinite intensity of ideality that content [nature] in itself and is richer by the determination of this ideality itself, which is in and for itself spirit. [BDG, p. 64]
29. Küng, Menschwerdung Gottes, p. 319. 30. See BDG, pp. 2728, 64, 8889, 11819.
< previous page
page_269
next page >
< previous page
page_270
next page > Page 270
"Creation," then, is indistinguishable from divine self-determination, not because it is causal activity but because it is love-activity, the same activity which "generates" the divine Son. "God is, it is true, correctly characterized as Creator of the world, but he is more than this: the true God is such that he is his own mediation with himself, that he is this love" (ibid., p. 28). This, incidentally, means that God is truly understood as God only if he is understood as Creator of the worldand once more the theologians begin to shake their heads: Does this mean that God cannot not create? It certainly means that a noncreator God would not be the God who is real. What more it might mean we can defer until the next chapter. Suffice it to say here that Hegel sees a logical necessity of reading in nature ''created," and that this bespeaks God as "Creator"but not a Creator who simply puts into existence a world apart from himself; in the very activity of creation God returns to himself (ibid., p. 27; see VPR II, pp. 9495, 21618). Hegel is also convinced that the human mind can read a revelation of God's presence in the overall course of historical events, where the divine activity in question is called "providence." This is not to say that human history is not the product of human activityMarx was simply wrong in his criticism of Hegel on this count,31 as even a cursory reading of Lectures on the Philosophy of History or "Philosophy of Objective Spirit" in the Encyclopedia would show. What Hegel does say is that the working out of human purposes in the course of history effectuates an overall purpose which transcends all individuals, all peoples, all civilizationsand that what such an overall plan reveals is "rationally necessary," even though its individual events are contingent.32 It is precisely this reading of "rational necessity" in history which has stirred up controversybut not from theologians, even though Hegel is equivalently saying that a philosophy of history is inseparable from a theology of history. In effect he is but enunciating his interpretation of the traditional theme of God's "omnipresence" in both space and time: "God is everywhere present, and the presence of God is just the element of truth which is in everything" (VPR II, p. 241). Human purposes are contingent, but in God there is no room for contingency. Unsophisticated religious consciousness speaks of God's eternal and immutable decrees, and in so doing implies an express recognition that necessity forms part of the essence of God. Because he is different from God, man, with his own particular opinion and will, acts according to arbitrary caprice, and thus it often happens that what results from his acts turns out to be something quite different from what he had intended and willed. God, on the contrary,
31. See Karl Marx, Writings of the Young Marx on Philosophy and Society, ed. Easton and Guddat (New York: Doubleday, 1967), pp. 314, 317, 31920, 322, 33234. (Economic and political manuscripts of 1844.) 32. The principal theme of Hegel's Reason in History.
< previous page
page_270
next page >
< previous page
page_271
next page > Page 271
knows what he wills, is determined in his eternal will neither by accident from within nor from without, and what he wills he also irresistibly accomplishes. [EpW, no. 147, Zusatz] There is also a self-revelation of God, in the most commonly accepted sense of the term "divine revelation," in the word which God speaks through the divinely inspired prophet or writer. Although Hegel has no elaborate theory regarding this kind of revelation, he quite clearly thinks of Scriptureparticularly the Gospelsas revealing God, and at key points he quotes the New Testament, chiefly John's Gospel, in support of his own "rational" position. The word spoken in Scripture is a word spoken not only to the early Christians to whom it is directly addressed but also to those who thereafter will build their faith on it. Clearly, then, the revelation in question has to do primarily with "religious" rather than ''rational" consciousness, but once again we must remind ourselves of the principle of "continuity." Precisely because the revealedand revealingword of God is seldom unambiguous, and because it is a word which will speak to the human spirit only if human thinking "appropriates" it, comprehends its meaningand "speculative thinking" is ideally suited to this comprehensionthe revelation must be thought out, rationally interpreted. Here the theologians need not take umbrage; Hegel is speaking of what they themselves do constantly. Saint Thomas Aquinasnot the least among theologianssays in his prelude to the whole discussion of the Godquestion, "Now it can be shown how God is not, by denying of him whatever does not befit him."33 The theologians' "rational principles" may not be those of Hegel, but they are rational principles nonetheless. Nor need we think that Hegel is being unduly "Lutheran" in his approach to Scripture (even though he quite clearly states that his faith is Lutheran).34 He is not saying that each individual is entitled to his or her "private interpretation" of God's wordno more than Karl Barth is in writing his Dogmatics. The word is spoken primarily to the believing community and only derivatively to individuals, and so the task of interpretation is primarily a community task (see PdG, pp. 54348). The implications of this, it is true, Hegel does not elaborately spell out. There is, finally, the revelation God gives of himself in the person of his Son, the Incarnate Word. He it is who unites in himself the human and the divinehe is the paradigm of this union, infinitizing the finite, just as creation finitizes the infinite. Jesus, then, is the revelation not only of divine being but also of authentically human being. Because, however, his incarnation is confined to one individual, the divine revelation wherein the divine
33. Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I, 3, introduction. 34. See EpW, preface to the third edition (Sept. 19, 1830).
< previous page
page_271
next page >
< previous page
page_272
next page > Page 272
Spirit speaks to the human spirit is not complete in the historical Jesus. He must dieHegel finds rational necessity even in thisin order both that the abstract concept of God may die, to be revitalized in concretion, and that the divine Spirit may come to dwell in the believing community, the Spirit who "will lead you to all truth" (EGP, p. 180). Here it is that Spirit speaks to spirit, because Spirit dwells in spirit. Properly speaking, all of this belongs to the next chapter on the relation of philosophy and theology, but it is also pertinent here because of what might be looked upon as its "pantheistic" overtones. Spirit Speaks to Spirit It might seem, however, either that Hegel has weakened his case for the infinity of "rational" knowing by introducing an "indwelling" of the Spirit which is theologically considered "supernatural" or that he has desupernaturalized the indwelling by making too rational a case for it. But to say that is, once more, to miss the point of "continuity''of the natural and the supernatural. It is neither a downgrading of human reason to claim that precisely as human it demands the presence of the divine, nor a downgrading of the supernatural to claim a natural demand for iteven finite "spirit" is, for Hegel, elevated above mere "nature." It is for this reason that he sees all human knowing, if it is to be authentically knowing and authentically human, as God's doingjust as is all "creation." Short of a knowing which is in some sense divinetherefore infiniteand short of a knowing whose object is infinite, hence divine, human knowing is not knowing in the full sense, "absolute knowing." By the same token, short of a presence of God in the human spirit, whereby that spirit knows the divine, human knowing is not human in the full sense (see PdG, pp. 54964). Again the theme of "being-lifted-up" is prominent: "God is movement toward the finite and is thus elevation of the finite to himself; in the I, that which transcends itself as finite, God returns to himself and is God only as this return" (VPR I, p. 192). The sentence which follows this, "Without a world God is not God" (ibid.), it is true, causes the theologians many problems, but it need not. As we have already noted more than once, Hegel is speaking of the only God there is, the Creator God, whom human thinking will never comprehend if it does not see "Creator" as an essential predicate of God.35 Now, although it might be argued that the "lifting-up" of the human spirit need not logically (whatever "logically" can mean in the context) demand the presence (whatever "presence," too, can mean) of the divine Spirit, it is clear that Hegel sees the Erhebung as itself divine activity. "It is
35. We might paraphrase thus: "To speak of a God who is not creator of the world is not to speak of the only God there is."
< previous page
page_272
next page >
< previous page
page_273
next page > Page 273
not so-called human reason with its limitation which knows God, but it is the Spirit of God in man" (BDG, p. 49). "The spirit of man knowing God is simply the Spirit of God himself" (ibid., p. 117). This is the way God, who is "omnipresent," is present inand tofinite spirit, as "the element of truth" in it. All human knowing, then, is divine self-revelation, and, since God cannot contradict himselfhe is all truth and only truthno human knowing, if it is to be truly knowing, can contradict divine revelation, nor can God be known other than as he reveals himself. The God reason knows cannot be in any sense other than the God faith believes, and what is necessarily true of God must be necessarily true for both faith and reason. It is, of course, too obvious to need mentioning that, because both believing and thinking are finite, subjective operations which are therefore fallible, both can be mistaken and thus can contradict each other. But that is not the point; God's self-revelation in faith cannot contradict God's selfrevelation in reason. More than that, just as faith cannot stop short of reason if it is to be authentically faith, so reason cannot dispense with faith, if it is not to go astray: "By the same token there is no thinking [God] without faith. Faith is always the basis, is presupposed'' (BDG, p. 9; see p. 5). Faith and reason, then, must necessarily be in agreement; there is only one God to whom both can ascend. It scarcely seems necessary to stress once more that there is no question here of psychological or epistemological necessity; finite reason does not have to see that the God of faith is identical with the God of reason; but reason is untrue to its own logic as reason if it does not. What Hegel is at pains to bring out is that the relationship of the human spirit to the infinite, to God, to absolute Spirit, is characteristically human. That human activity, however, which is most chacteristically human is thought; it is that which distinguishes the human from all that is less than human (see WL I, p. 10; EpW, no. 2). If, then, the relationship to God characterizes man, that relationship must be a thinking (thought) relationship, which is to say it must be a rational affirmation. Whatever is distinctively human is so by virtue of the element of thought inseparable from it. Thus, since art, morality, law, and religion are distinctively human, it is the element of thought in them that makes them so. Believing, too, is distinctively human, which means that it must be characterized by thought; a believing which is not thought out is something less than human, unworthy of man. Unthinking belief, therefore, is not authentic belief, because it is not "continuous" with thought. It is a mistake, however, to take as the paradigm of thinking narrowly scientific thought, which can see in the affirmations of faith only contradictions. If, in fact, faith is both true and authentically human, that is, a thought-out faith, there will be in it no contradictions. What Hegel calls "speculative reason" is precisely the thinking which resolves apparent contradictionsbetter still, the contradictions will resolve themselves, if the
< previous page
page_273
next page >
< previous page
page_274
next page > Page 274
thinking is authentically rational. To the "scientific" mind that God should be both three and one, that being should be both finite and infinite, that creation should be both necessary and free, that thought should be both human and divine, may be patent contradictions. To the authentically rational mind they are not: they are the inevitable complementarities of absolute Spirit, of being, of divine activity, of thought itself. If the only being there is is the being of finite individual beings, if the only thought there is is the thinking of finite individual human minds, then both being and thought are essentially finite. But, just as being necessarily transcends the finite, the individual (the particular), or else it is not, so too thought transcends the finite, the individual, or else it is not. Infinite (divine) Being is the being of all beings; infinite (divine) Thought is the thought of all thought. Hegel does not employ the Platonic concept of "participation" to explicate this relationship, but he does see in the Platonic "Idea" the model of this infinite unity in multiplicity. If this be "pantheism,'' then Hegel is a pantheistbut so too are all those who seek to give some sort of rational account of the relationship between the finite and the infinite, the human and the divine, the world and God. We can sum up Hegel's position in the following seven points: (1) There is finite reality, and this reality, even the totality of it, is not identical with God. (2) The true being of this reality, however, is not self-contained; it is in God, the only thoroughly self-contained reality there is. (3) The very reality of the finite, then, is to be God's selfrevelation, such that self-containedness and self-manifestation are continuous. (4) Furthermore, all of finite reality is God's self-revelation; finite reality both is and is what it is by virtue of God's thinking it. (5) Although it might be argued that God need not manifest himself to any spirit other than himself, he is constrained, so to speak, by "love" to communicate both being and knowledge of himself to spirits other than himself. (6) Thus, God reveals himself to finite spirit (to spirit alone can he reveal himself) in his infinite activity, which is at once that of creating, becoming incarnate, redeeming (i.e., reintegrating disintegrated man), and dwelling within the human spirit as the divine Spirit who "elevates" the finite to the infinite. (7) In short, divine activity, even though infinitely self-contained, is essentially self-revelatory activity. As all of this is spelled out in the next chapter we shall see not so much that the lines between faith and knowledge, theology and philosophy, are blurred, as that Hegel's "speculative thinking" enables him to read a "logic" in the whole of divine self-revelation. Back to "Pantheism" At this point, it would seem, we are brought around full circle to the charges raised against Hegel's "rational account" by those who claim that,
< previous page
page_274
next page >
< previous page
page_275
next page > Page 275
despite his own demurrers, he is a pantheist. How can he read so much of the infinite in the finite without identifying them? The first objection has to do with the necessity of creation, with the contention that the very logic of infinite reality demands the being of finite reality. The charge is motivated by a legitimate concern that the admittedly perplexing concept of creation be not "explained" in such a way as to compromise God's "infinity" (a scarcely less perplexing concept); an infinity which must, if it is to make sense, include divine "freedom." It should be noted, incidentally, that raising the objection presupposes that the objector knows what the concepts "infinity,'' "creation," and "freedom" must mean, when said of God. It also presupposes both that the metaphysics espoused by the objector is adequate to the discussion of God and that Hegel's metaphysics must obey the rules of the objector's game. The basic supposition of the objection is that, if God "necessarily" creates, he does not create "freely"either necessarily or freely, not both. If God is under constraint to create, God needs the world (and finite spirit) in order to be truly God, which in turn means that God's own being is not self-sufficient but dependent and, therefore, not truly infinite. On the face of it the objection would seem to make senseprovided that the concepts on which it is based have the same meaning for Hegel as for the objectors; that is, provided they are quite sure they know what Hegel has to mean. The proviso, however, introduces the importance of distinguishing from the very first between "necessity" and "need." If God indeed "needs" the world and man in order to be truly God, then God is a dependent being, and a dependent being cannot be infinite Being. But, Hegel is very explicit in denying that God "needs" the world or man. Only if God has to create a reality which stood in its own self-sufficiency over-against him would his relationship to that reality be one of "need" (see BDG, pp. 2628). To say that God is related to created reality is not to say that in addition to creating the reality God is also related to itthe way a finite cause is related to its effectbut that creation is the relation of God to created reality (see ibid., pp. 5859). It is only abstract "understanding" that has to analyze the relation according to finite categories, thus breaking up the continuity between the infinite activity" of God and the finite "being" of the world.
Dualism, which makes the opposition of finite and infinite insurmountable, fails to make the simple observation that in this way the infinite, too, is only one of the two, that thereby it is made into a merely particular in relation to which the finite is the other particular. Such an infinite, which is only a particular alongside the finite, has by that very fact its boundary, its limit, in the latter. It is not what it ought to be; it is not infinite but only finite. In such circumstances, where the finite is here below and the infinite up there, the first placed here, the other there, to the finite is ascribed the same dignity of sub-
< previous page
page_275
next page >
< previous page
page_276
next page > Page 276
sistence and autonomy as to the infinite. The being of the finite is made into an absolute being; in such a dualism it stands by itself. [Ep W, no. 95] It might be argued, of course, that Hegel is the one who is guilty of inconsistency in positing a distinction which is no distinction at all, but the distinction he does make bears careful examination. He does say, it is true, that "if there were no world God would not be the creator" (BDG, p. 131). The logic of this remark is so obviously impeccable that it risks being trivial: God cannot be creator and not create, nor can he "create" nothing; unless, of course, the remark means that to speak of a God for whom there is no world is not to speak of the only God there is, the Creator. It might make sense to say that in the abstract the concept "Creator'' is not a necessary predicate of "God." A noncreator God would not be a contradiction, or at least finite human reason could not of itself see the contradiction. One wonders, however, if the expression "a God" is not contradictory: If all reason knows is "a God," reason does not know God, the only God there is. If the God reason claims to know is not creator, he is not God; he is only an abstraction taking the place of God; to say not creator is to say not God.36 If this abstraction is all that finite reason can "know," then Kant is right: human reason cannot "know" God. It must also be said that whatever is concretely true of God is also necessarily true; it makes no sense to speak of "contingent" predicates of God. If, then, it is true that God is Creator, it is necessarily true that God is Creator. It might be objected, of course, that this is precisely what merely rational thinking cannot know. The objection, however, would then be against the possibility of rational knowledge of God, not against the inevitably "pantheistic" character of Hegel's God. (It might be well to reiterate here that Hegel never speaks of reason discovering the reality of God, but only of "speculative thinking" seeing the rationality of the God of faith.) Having rung the changes on the nonsynonymity of "necessary" creation and the "need" to create, we might here try to find out what anyone means by saying that God creates "freely." Our thinking is inevitably anthropomorphic (nor is that necessarily a defect)we tend to say of God "something like" what we experience on the level of the human. For the most part, then, "freedom" is taken to mean "freedom of choice." But it is definitely problematic whether one can make sense of the concept of choosing" if it is to be applied to God's activity. If there is to be choice, it would seem that there must be an "agent" who is faced with a set of alternatives, one of which he chooses rather than the others; the choice being based on motives which make one alternative preferable to another. Can
36. Theological thinking finds, it would seem, no difficulty in agreeing that we can speak meaningfully of what God cannot not behe cannot not be God, not be triune, not be omnipotent, etc. Is it stretching the point too much to say that he cannot not be creator?
< previous page
page_276
next page >
< previous page
page_277
next page > Page 277
we, however, make sense of such concepts as "choice, "alternative," "motive," or "preferable" when we speak of God? The identity of being and activity in God precludes the possibility that the determinant of God's activity be other than the very being of God. Now, if the essence of freedom lies not in the element of choice but in that of self-determination, then the necessity of the determination, like the necessity of God's being, need in no way be in conflict with its being self-determination, nor is "necessary self-determination" a contradiction in terms. To say that the being of God is ''necessary" and that the activity of God is identical with his being, whereas the activity of God is not necessary raises too many logical riddles, which are not solved by distinguishing between the activity and the term of the activity, since the term of activity is continuous with the activity. When we state the problem in this way, however, we are back where we were in the difficulty of distinguishing the finite and the infinite while maintaining their "continuity." Just as the finitude of the finite is no impediment to the continuity of the infinite and the finite, so the contingency of the finite is no impediment to that contingency's being continuous with the necessity of the infinite. By the same token, there seems to be no reason to declare incompatible the contingency of "things" in the created world and the necessity of "creation" or the necessity that there be a created world. Once again, then, the difficulty arises not from some presumably "pantheistic" implications in Hegel's conception of God, but from the effort to conceive creation in any way that is not highly problematic. The difficulty is only compounded if "creating" is conceived of, again anthropomorphically, as a "making" in the mode of efficient causality, for which there is no analogy which does not limp so badly that it obscures rather than clarifies the concept. There just does not seem to be any adequately intelligible sense in which God can be said to "make" the worldScripture actually makes more rational sense when it speaks of God creating the world by his "word." There is, after all, a highly intelligible way in which we can speak of God knowing and loving himselfhe could scarcely be God if he did not. If, then, theologians can say that in knowing himself God as "Father" "generates" the "Son," his "Word," who is both other and not other than himself, and that in the mutual love of Father and Son God "breathes" the "Spirit," so that in this activity of knowing and loving God determines himself as Father, Son, and Spirit, may not philosophers say that "creation" becomes intelligible if it is seen as the very same self-determining knowledge and love expressing itself in the being of a world and of a finite spirit which knows and loves, such that the world and the human spirit are both other than God and have their being in God? Hegel's position may be too theologicaltoo Christianto satisfy philosophers who do not share his theology, but it is not for that reason unintelligible, nor need it be interpreted so metaphorically as to be no longer Hegel's posi
< previous page
page_277
next page >
< previous page
page_278
next page > Page 278
tion. One wonders whether, in the final analysis, Hegel does not turn out to be far more "theistic" than "pantheistic." In any event, it is clearly not nonsense to say with Hegel that in knowing himself God knows all there is to be known. But neither is it nonsense to say that in knowing all that is to be known God knows himself. Nor need either of these statements mean that God and the world of finite reality are one and the same. Nevertheless, for the critics, Hegel's cardinal sin comes not so much when he speaks of God's knowledge of himself and the world, but rather when he speaks of man's knowledge of God. Apart from those who, like Kant, deny that man has "speculative knowledge" of God at all, or those who deny that there is any God for man to know, there are a host of those who, while granting that man can "know" God, feel that Hegel has simply gone too far. It is all very well to say of God that in knowing himself he knows the world or even that in knowing the world he knows himselfthe "mystery" of God and of divine knowing is preserved. But has Hegel not overreached himself when he claims that what we know in knowing God is what God knows in knowing himself? This means, among other things, that in knowing God we know the world and that in knowing the world we know God. Is this not, once more, to identify God and the world? This becomes even harder to swallow when we recall that, for Hegel, all consciousness is consciousness of self, with the result that in knowing God and the world we are knowing ourselvesand vice versa!37 If to this we add that God's knowledge of himself, the world, and us becomes identified with our knowledge of God, the world, and ourselves, there seems to be an unjustified identification of all that we know and all that God knows in knowing himself. Hegel would, in fact, seem to be saying that God "needs" our knowledge of him in order to know himself! "Man knows God only to the extent that God knows himself in man; this knowing is God's consciousness of himself'' (BDG, p. 117). At the very least he would seem to be saying that God knows himself only "because" human beings know him. Unless, of course, what Hegel is saying is that, because there is no distinction between the activity wherein God is conscious of himself and the activity wherein he reveals himself in human consciousness, we must try to comprehend rationally this concrete identification of activity. At least this will free us from such utterly tendentiousand falseexpressions like "in order to" and "because." There is simply no question of "dependence" on or "need" of man's knowledge of God for God's knowledge of himself. Rather, the creative act whereby human consciousness is an actuality is God's self-knowledge, and human self-knowledge is the finite actualization of God's self-knowledge. One need not experience any great difficulty going along with Hegel, if what he is saying is that man's knowledge of God
37. Phenomenology of Spirit is but one long "demonstration" of this.
< previous page
page_278
next page >
< previous page
page_279
next page > Page 279
would not be knowledge of God as he truly, concretely is, if it were not God's self-knowledge actualizing man's knowledge. This is but another attempt on Hegel's part to articulate the concept of human knowledge of God as an "elevation" (Erhebung). That man should know God is not man's doing aloneman does not lift himself up to God by his own bootstrapsit is the doing of the Spirit of God in man, without whom man would not even be, much less know, and this presence is self-conscious divine doing. At this point the first objection against Hegel's interpreting "creation" in such a way that he seems to be making a created world a necessity for God begins to shade over into the second major objection, that is, that in God relations to the world and to man are real. The second objection makes sense only if the first objection is assumed to be valid; only if it is purely contingent that there be a world would a real relationship of God to the world of his creation be an addition to Godand to infinite being there can be no addition! Even the most traditional of traditionalists admit that the activity of God is creative activity (although not solely creative), that God really creates the world (whether it even makes sense to say that God "created" the world is a moot question). By the same token it is traditionally claimed that there are relations in God, but these are the relations of the Persons in God, which constitute them as Persons and imply no imperfection in God and need not, therefore, be excluded. This contention, in turn, is based on the further supposition that a metaphysics of being is alone adequate in dealing with the God questionand that a metaphysics of becoming is simply out of the question. That this constitutes a reintroduction of the Eleatic concept of being, where the being of God is concerned, does not seem to have been observed. According to this metaphysics of being (what Hegel calls a Verstandes-metaphysik), then, immanent activity and transient activity are opposed in such a way that even in God the one cannot be the other. God's activity must be one or the other; for it to be both would be contradictory. It is still said, of course, that God creates, that he loves human beings, that he is omniscient, omnipresent, that he has revealed these truths to man; and it is maintained that when we enunciate such predicates of God we are saying something meaningful and not merely uttering sounds. The meaning, admittedly, is rather obscure, but that is as it should be; we are dealing in ''mystery." It is as though one were to say, God speaks indeed, but when he does he does not talk to anyone other than himself; that would be beneath his dignity. The problem here is, however, that the objectors cannot have it both ways. If the only direct object of God's knowledge is God's essence, and if the only direct object of God's love is God's goodness (knowing and willing, essence and goodness, of course, being themselves only rationally distinct), then God can know and love what is other than himself only to the extent that what is other than God is in God. Being as both finite and infinite is dynamically
< previous page
page_279
next page >
< previous page
page_280
next page > Page 280
"continuous," not statically "identical"but only a dynamic logic of process can come to grips with this. From this it follows that the only being of their own that things have is apparent being; the real being is in Godwhich is what Hegel says.38 It is what Hegel further says, however, that causes the difficulty. The apparent being of a world of reality, he tells us, is the appearing of true being, its self-manifestation.39 The being of the world, then, is the selfmanifestation of Godto man. And since the self-manifestation of God is concretely identical with God's selfknowledge, then man's knowledge of God is concretely identical with God's knowledge of himself. As metaphysically reprehensible as Hegel's position may be to some, it has the advantage of not making nonsense out of the words of Scripturewhose every line speaks in a manner which cannot but make the "metaphysician" writhe. Perhaps it all comes down to saying that metaphysical reprehensibility is a small price to payfor comprehensibility. Relationship in God to what is other than himself would be an imperfection in God only if it bespoke an addition to God's reality. If a created world is not an addition to God's reality, why must a real relationship of God to that world be an addition? At this point we are forced to say that the first two objections count as objections only because in them the third, the real objection, constantly looms large on the horizon. The very logic of Hegel's position, it would seem, compels him to identify God with the totality of reality. In considering this difficulty we may justifiably begin by changing our approach and trying not to identify God and the totality of reality. Presumably both God and the world are real. Does this mean that the reality of God plus the reality of the world equals more than the reality of God? In this case God would be part of the totality of reality, infinite being would be part of the whole of beinga rather uncomfortable stance to take. Or, the question might be asked, Is the totality of created (finite) reality a reflection of the infinite totality of reality which is God? How this could fail to imply a finite reality over against God, which God is not, is not easy to see. Nor is it easy to see how God would not be limited by that which is but which he is not. Perhaps we can look to Thomas Aquinas for a solution to the difficulty. Speaking of God's omnipresence Aquinas says, "God is in things as containing them." Later he explains this by saying, "All things must be in him [God] according to an intelligible mode." It may, of course, be countered that what Aquinas is saying is that all things are in God according to an intelligible mode
38. See BDG, pp. 11821; see also pp. 8889, 95, 103. 39. Ibid., p. 172. When Hegel says that the being of the finite is only "appearing" (or "apparent" being), he is not saying that the finite only seems to be but is not; he is saying that true being which is infinite appears finitely. He is manifest to himself infinitelyin three personsand he is manifest to others finitely. Still, only if the finite manifestation reveals the infinite is it true manifestation.
< previous page
page_280
next page >
< previous page
page_281
next page > Page 281
("before creation") but that all things are in themselves according to an existential mode ("after creation"). However, this quite clearly leaves the difficulty where it was, and it is not easy to see in the context that the "before" and "after" creation are not temporal rather than logical designations. If, on the other hand, we take Hegel's interpretation of the ''before creation" which we find in Science of Logic, which is not essentially different from "after creation" except insofar as the process of divine self-manifestation progressively reveals the God who is complete truth "in himself" before creation, we are at least meeting the difficulty head-on.40 All being is in God, because the being of all reality is to be in God, the way the being of reality is to be in spiritin divine Spirit as creative, in finite spirit as "recreative." It is this last contention, however, that suddenly reveals the true nature of the traditionalists' charge against Hegel. It is not really his "pantheism"which is far too problematicalthat bothers them; it is his "pan-logism." Hegel wants to know too much; he has taken the mystery out of God my making God fit into his logical system. There may, of course, be some truth in thisprovided it is true to say that the "logic" precedes the theologybut it is also true of every attempt to give a rational account (however partial) of God, since only if human reason attempts to interpret what revelation says and what faith believes of God, will revelation make sense of God; it is reason's task to interpret what faith believes. To paraphrase Kant: "Reason without faith is empty; faith without reason is blind." It is not incomprehensible, however, that Hegel's words would make some theologians fear that his attempt to know God rationally is an attempt to subject the content of faith to the autonomy of reason. The heart of the problem would seem to be that, in effect, Hegel wants "logical reason" ("the logical idea") to tell revelation what it must mean. But there is nothing really new or startling in that. Do not theologians tell us that when Scripture says that "Jesus Christ sits at the right hand of the Father," Scripture is speaking metaphorically, since God has no hands, no right or left side? Is it not reason which tells the theologian that this is metaphorical language, that the literal sense of the words does not "make sense"? We can go further and say that any attempt to apply reason to the content of faith will try to show that the latter does not conflict with reason or that reason can to some extent at least explicate the content of faith. It is the theologian's task to explicate the "logos" of faith. What is new and startling in what Hegel is saying is not that logical reason should seek to appropriate (in the etymological sense of "make its own") what faith is saying. What is new and startling is his contention that the language of faith
40. See BDG, pp. 17677; cf. J. N. Findlay, Hegel: A Reexamination (New York: Macmillan, 1958), p. 354.
< previous page
page_281
next page >
< previous page
page_282
next page > Page 282
demands an essential (concrete, dynamic) logic of thought (concept) to interpret it and that the logic he has elaborated is equal to the task. There is to be no unthinking (unlogical) faith, but a static formal logic of being is not going to make faith logicalonly a dynamic logic of becoming can do so. What Hegel is not saying, then, is that logic lays down the law for understanding the meaning of faith. What he is saying is that in understanding faith we find logic confirmeda logic that would really contradict faith would be a bad logic.
< previous page
page_282
next page >
< previous page
page_283
next page > Page 283
Chapter Seven Philosophy and Theology To those who share neither Hegel's faith nor his theology it cannot but be disconcerting to find him so consistently employing a language which is intelligible only to Christians. It is not only the language, however, which is disconcerting; even a relatively superficial familiarity with Christian theology will reveal that his speculative logic too has its roots there. But how is it possible to take seriously a philosopher who proclaims more emphatically than any other the autonomy of human reason and in the very same breath makes that reason fit into the procrustean bed of a theology which is all too clearly trinitarian and incarnational, which reasons in terms of a disintegrating "fall" of the human spirit and a reintegrating "reconciliation" through the death of the God-man, and which makes the presence of the "Holy Spirit" in the spirit of man integral to reason's capacity to come to grips with truth? Is this not to utterly confuse faith and reason, theology and philosophy, in such a way as to make each thoroughly alien to itself? Or perhaps it is not Hegel at all who is at fault, but me, as I persist in taking what he says too literallyas many of my critics would have it. One solution to the difficultyand it has been tried again and againis not to take what Hegel says literally at all. The language of theology has simply provided him with a convenient vocabulary in which to express a "speculative philosophy," which is in reality thoroughly secular. When Hegel says "God" he does not mean the concrete Absolute who must be personal (Spirit) or else not be at all; when he speaks of "divine Spirit" he does not mean the Spirit who transcends the sum total of finite "minds''; when he refers to the "God-man" he is not speaking of an individual who ever really existedthe list of metaphors could be extended indefinitely. A solution such as this, however, poses a number of other difficulties which it makes no serious attempt to solve. (1) Apart from accusing Hegel of remarkably poor taste in employing the language of a faith he does not
< previous page
page_283
next page >
< previous page
page_284
next page > Page 284
share in constructing a philosophy which is destructive of that faith, it accuses him of equally poor judgment in employing a clumsy vocabulary which is not calculated to do the job he wants it to do. (2) As a matter of fact, it is possible to make eminently good rational sense out of Hegel's "theologizing"provided one has no a priori commitment to the view that no theology can make good sense. (3) An interpretation which requires torturing Hegel's words in such a way that they are made to say something other than what they rather patently seem to be saying demands more evidence from Hegel's writings than is given of what Hegel in fact intends. It might be argued, of course, that Kant and Jacobi shared Hegel's faithif indeed that be truebut they did not share his rational optimism that what faith believes reason can know. But that is precisely the point: There is no room in Hegel's philosophy for a Kantian reason which is discontinuous with faith, just as there is no room in his religion for a faith which is discontinuous with reason. It is not without significance, after all, that the final four chapters of Phenomenology of Spirit (more than two-thirds of the book) are grouped under one inclusive heading, "Reason," and that "Spirit," "Religion," and "Absolute Knowing'' are all integral to the continuous onward march of "Reason" coming to consciousness of itselfwithout religious consciousness the line of march would have turned out to be a dead-end street! Another possible solution, perhaps, to the difficulty of coming to terms with Hegel's "theologizing" (or "christianizing") philosophy might be to say that he is an interesting curiosity in the history of philosophy, a "seminal" thinker who can give others the impetus to a thinking which is radically different from his own but who cannot seriously tempt us with his theologizing of philosophy. Feuerbach and Marx, after all, have made it abundantly clear that Hegel's method can be eminently fruitful, independently of the content of his system; and Kierkegaard has shown us what becomes of Christian faith when it is "speculativized" à la Hegel. It may be that to Hegel Christian faith makes eminently rational good sense, but one need share neither his faith nor his concept of rational good sense. If one does not share his faith there is little likelihood that one will find he has made rational sense of it, but there is equally little likelihood that one will make sense of Hegel's philosophy at all. It would seem, however, that no serious thinker today is quite willing to say that Hegel simply is not a significant philosopher. If we are to say, then, that he is a significant philosopher, we cannot avoid taking cognizance of the close connection in his thoughtand expressionof philosophy and theology. What then are we to say of the seeming contradiction of an explicit affirmation of the autonomy of reason coupled with insistence on a theological content of rational thinking? Perhaps the answer is to be found in his equally strong insistence on the nonsynonymity of rationality and rationalism. The
< previous page
page_284
next page >
< previous page
page_285
next page > Page 285
autonomy of reason no more bespeaks the narrow rationalism of eighteenth century "Enlightenment" than it does the essential finitude of both reason and reason's object as presented in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.1 Hegel was quite consistent in his refusal to accept that the safeguarding of rational autonomy demanded progressive opposition to basic Christian faith, as did, for example, the triumphal rationalism of the Enlightenment. It is true that one could, as Hegel did, repeatedly lecture on the philosophy of religion without compromising one's conviction that reason is completely autonomous. One could even, like Kant, write a Religion within the Limits of Mere Reason, without altering one's conviction of the essential finitude of reason, especially if the light of reason is turned only on the subjective response called religion and not on the infinite object to which religion is the response. One could hardly, however, be convinced, as Hegel was, of the thoroughly rational character of the content of religious consciousness, thus making it an essential object of philosophical enquiry, and at the same time regard faith and reason, theology and philosophy, as radically discontinuous. For Hegel it was not inconsistent to theologize philosophy; his philosophy demanded precisely that. It might not be amiss to turn here to Emil Fackenheim, who can in no way be suspected of sharing either Hegel's faith or Hegel's theology and who shares Hegel's philosophical convictions only minimally, but who, nevertheless, has provided us with extraordinarily sensitive insights in his work, The Religious Dimensions of Hegel's Thought. There is no need, Fackenheim tells us, to agree with Hegel in order to be able to see that the consistent goal of his philosophy is the truth which is not partial, and this can only be infinite Truth. For Hegel, the difference between philosophy (it is doubtful whether the term "metaphysics" should still be used) and the whole remainder of human life (both theoretical and practical) is one of standpoint. All other human activities are truly in contact with reality, but reach partial truths only, because they are limited to finite standpoints. Philosophyor at any rate the true or final philosophyrises to an infinite or absolute standpoint, and to encompass and transfigure the partial truths of the finite standpoints into a Truth no longer partial is its sole aim.2 Hegel, then, has no difficulty in recognizing the reality of the finite or the truth of the partial truth, precisely because he can view the finite and partial against the backdrop of the infinite and whole.
1. Hegel himself was remarkably aware as early as Glauben und Wissen (an awareness which carries over to PdG, WL, and EpW) that both "pietism" (or "fideism") and atheism have their roots in one and the same ''Enlightenment" rationalism. 2. E. Fackenheim, The Religious Dimension in Hegel's Thought (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967), pp. 1617.
< previous page
page_285
next page >
< previous page
page_286
next page > Page 286
First, Reality is dialectical in that the finite at once points to an Infinity which contains it while yet retaining its own reality. For Hegel, as for Schelling of 1801, "the ideality of the finite is the main principle of philosophy." But to Schelling this means that the finite merely appears real at finite standpoints and is seen as absorbed in infinity at the absolute standpoint. To Hegel it means that the finite is overreached by the Infinite and that it must be real as well as "merely ideal," if the overreaching Infinite is not itself to suffer loss of all reality. It is this conviction which forces Hegel to recognize the partial truth of finite thoughte.g., natural sciencewhen Schelling can merely oppose or ignore it.3 It is thus that, for Hegel, ultimate philosophical thought cannot stop short of the concrete infinite. One might, of course, wish to argue that this "concrete infinite" need not be identified with the "incomprehensible" God of faith or theology, but it is difficult to see how anyone could argue that Hegel does not ''comprehend" the identification as necessary. This is the lesson both of Phenomenology of Spirit and of Science of Logic. The Phenomenology "will watch 'consciousness examine itself,' a process in which each finite standpoint, which is fragmentary because it is finite, will point to one higher because it is less fragmentary, until finally, at the standpoint of absolute knowledge, all fragmentariness is transcended."4 This realization is not too different from the pervading theme of the Logic, wherein finite reason can comprehend itself precisely as finite only because it is not merely finite. This reflection results in the discovery that, in recognizing the limits of the examined reason, examining reason transcends these limits. Hegel's Logic completes this philosophical process, which is doublyexamining because it attends to both the examined and the examining Reason. His work both recognizes and indeed presupposes the categories of finite thought, and alters these categories, so as to integrate them into the infinitely self-active thinking which it performs.5 To put all of this in a slightly different way, we might say that, for Hegel, as we see in the Phenomenology, it is essential to the integrity of human consciousness that it be religious, that it be consciousness of the Absolute, the Infinite, who is God. It is, furthermore, essential to the consciousness of God that it be theological, that is, a thought-out consciousness, if it is to be authentically human. But a thinking which is not philosophical is not, properly speaking, theological, because, as Hegel sees it, only philosophical thought is supremely rational. Philosophical knowledge, however, will be
3. Ibid., pp. 2728. 4. Ibid., p. 34. 5. Ibid., p. 226.
< previous page
page_286
next page >
< previous page
page_287
next page > Page 287
supremely rational only if its object is the supremely rational, absolute Spirit, and this meansalong traditional theological linesthat a knowledge of God makes sense only if its paradigm is God's own absolute knowing, which is absolute precisely because its object is absolute, God himselfthe paradigm of all knowing is God's absolute selfknowing. Faith and Knowledge Now, even if we follow Hegel this far, we seem to run into the most insurmountable difficulty of all. If the "absolute knowing," the acme of human consciousness and self-consciousness in which Phenomenology of Spirit culminates, is modeled on God's infinite self-knowing, it would seem either to swallow up faith or to do away with the need of faith altogether. If philosophical thinking can know what faith believes, what need is there of faith? Even if we were to go along with J. N. Findlay who likens absolute rational knowing to "mystical" union, the difficulty would seem to remain; what need is there of faith when union with God has been achieved? According to Findlay: Hegel's conception of the reasonable being what it is, it is not hard to see why he should liken it to the mystical in religion. The mystics are precisely the people who tolerate a species of near contradiction in reporting their experiences, and who reject those firm oppositions between God and the soul, the infinite and the finite, eternity and the passing moment, on which ordinary piety and theology lay such stress.6 One might point out, of course, that the mystics themselves are the first to insist that, without faith, mystical union would be inconceivable, but that is scarcely a philosophical answer to a philosophical difficulty. More to the point, it should be emphasized that the difficulty is a difficulty only if faith ceases to be faith once it has achieved a rational comprehension of its own content, but this would be true only if faith is radically discontinuous with knowledge, which is precisely what Hegel denies. We might explicate this further by swinging back to the overall pattern of the Phenomenology. There can be no question that, as Hegel sees it, rational thought transcends sensation, perception, scientific understanding, and immediate self-consciousness. That it transcends these, however, does not mean that it has no need of them; what rational thought does is to transform them by "appropriating" their content at a higher level, all the while remaining continuous with them; it does not dispense with them. By the same token, rational thought could neither reach the culmination of its
6. J. N. Findlay, Hegel: A Reexamination (New York: Macmillan, 1958), p. 65.
< previous page
page_287
next page >
< previous page
page_288
next page > Page 288
development, nor in that culmination have God as its object, as it does both in "absolute knowing" and throughtout Science of Logic, if it did not constantly have faith as its underpinning. If this be the case, then philosophical knowing neither swallows up nor dispenses with faith; it simply transforms faith into an explicit awareness of its own implications. In so doing, admittedly, Hegel's "speculative philosophy" makes it difficult for those who do not share his faith to share his philosophical experiencejust as does "mystical union"union with a God in whom one does not believe cannot make sense to one who does not believe. All of this becomes more explicitly theologicaland, therefore, more difficult to sharewhen Hegel interprets those words of the Fourth Gospel, "The Spirit shall teach you all truth," as meaning that the divine Spirit will not simply speak to the human spirit but will speak in the human spirit (nor will his speaking be simply the words of the Bible). Thus the "absolute knowing" of the Phenomenology which is to be explicated in the subsequent "system," is the actual presence of the divine Spirit in man. Here it is that it becomes particularly difficult for those who share neither Hegel's faith nor his theology to share his philosophical position. In both Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion and Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Hegel makes it quite clear that, in his view, neither theology nor philosophy could be adequate to the whole truth until the advent of Christianity, the "Absolute Religion."7 Thus, for Hegel, it is necessary that there be the leap to Christian religion, to Christian revelation, a revelation of what it is for God to be man and, therefore, of what it is for the human to be divine (a truth which no mere words in a book could tell). Only thus can we know what it is for man to be truly man, the ''God-bearer," truly spirit. Whatever one's reactions to Hegel's "Christian philosophy" may beno one has to agree with himone thing is clear: For Hegel the ultimate goal of philosophical thinking is knowledge of God, which alone is knowledge of ultimate truth. If he is also convinced that there is a progressive self-revelation of God in human religious consciousnessfinding the divine in the working of nature, portraying the divine in the works of human artistry, listening to the divine voice speaking to the inner ear of human spiritit should come as no surprise that Hegel insists on identifying the God who reveals himself in religious consciousness and the God who reveals himself in speculative thinking. The all-important questionand we are back where we beganis whether human reason can know God. Under the influence of Kant and Fichte the "theologians" of Hegel's daywith Jacobi and
7. Lest it be argued that both series of lectures, coming to us as they do, not from the pen of Hegel but from the notes of his students, are not reliable witnesses to his nuanced thinking, it should be pointed out that neither Science of Logic nor the sections on "Logic" and on the "Philosophy of Absolute Spirit" in the Encyclopedia are intelligible except in the light of this conviction of Hegel's.
< previous page
page_288
next page >
< previous page
page_289
next page > Page 289
Schleiermacher in the vanguardwere opting for an intuitive grasp, an emotional response, a worship of they knew not what; but Hegel would have none of this. He preferred the attitude of the medieval Scholastics, whose philosophy was continuous with their theology, who did not have to contend with the opinion that the divine could not be begriffen (BS, p. 80). "What is theology without a knowledge of God? Just what a philosophy is without the same, sounding brass and tinkling cymbal" (ibid., p. 81). It is a question of knowing God as he is in himself, not of knowing the countless predicates men have attributed to him (VPR II, pp. 22425), not of applying to the incomprehensible the categories of mere understanding which are inadequate to him (BS, p. 351). The medieval theologians were nearer to the truth than were Hegel's contemporaries, because their thinking was both theology and speculative philosophy. The essential, unique object of theology as doctrine of God is the nature of God; and this content is of an essentially speculative character; thus such theologians can only be philosophers. Philosophy alone is science of God. Among them philosophy and theology counted as one, and it is the distinguishing of them which constitutes the transition to the modern period, i.e., the time when it was thought that something could be true for thinking reason which would not be true for theology. In the middle ages themselves, on the contrary, the basic principle was that there is only one truth. [VGP II, p. 543] Once again it should be noted here that there is no question of confusing religion and theology or theology and philosophy; to say that theology and philosophy are "one" is not to say that the terms are synonymous, it is to say that there is one continuous movement which begins with the reception of a revelation from "outside," so to speak, to which the assent, for reasons which can scarcely be analyzed, is ''immediate." The authentic human being, however, cannot rest content either with an immediate assent or with the vagueness of the content to which assent is given; thinking, meditation, and reflection must follow. If the thinking human follows through on this, the assent becomes the sort of thought out rational assent which we can justifiably call "knowledge." Inasmuch as the doctrines of the Christian religion are present in the Bible, they are thus given in a positive way; and when they become subjective, when the Spirit bears witness to their truth, this can happen in a purely immediate way, such that man's innermost being, his spirit, his thought, his reason is struck with their truth and assents to it. [VPR II, p. 199] There is no question here of finding reasons for believing but rather of finding the meaning of that which is believed, and this will ultimately mean not
< previous page
page_289
next page >
< previous page
page_290
next page > Page 290
dispensing with the immediate assent but transforming its immediacy into mediated rationalityas becomes the human spirit. What must further be said, however, is that, precisely because man is a thinking being he cannot rest in this state of immediate assent to the testimony, but also he takes himself to thoughts, meditations, and reflections on it. This accordingly leads to a further development in religion; and in its highest and most developed form it is theology, scientific religion; it is this content, the testimony of the spirit, known in a scientific way. [Ibid.] There is clearly a danger that insistence on the incomprehensibility of God will degrade theo-logy from a doctrine about God into a "historical" knowledge of what has been said about himpresumably by other people who did not quite know what they were saying! One might well ask how one can know that the object of a non-knowing is true. If the reply is that we do not know that it is true, we only believe that it is, we may well wonder what meaning the truth of what we believe can have, if all rationality has been removed from it. The result is simply the denial that there is any "theology" at all, which may well be precisely what both ''pietists" and "rationalists" want to say; it can scarcely be what Hegel wishes to say. Still, in recent times it is at the same time asserted that religion is authentic and true only after the manner of religious emotion, only as an emotion. If, however, any insight into concepts with religious content is denied, then so is any theology denied; for theology as a science has to be knowledge of God and of the relation of man to God, a relation which is determined by the nature of God. Otherwise theology would be merely historical acquaintance. The emotion in question has also been called the source of science and of reason; but it is the absence of knowledge. If the emotion is to be true, then there must be reason in it; in fact, the emotion itself must be the product of conviction and isight. [EGP, p. 194] Hegel has no intention of denying that Christian religion has a "dogmatic" content, so long as "dogma" is not taken to mean unthinking statements which are unthinkingly accepted. On the assumption that the statements are true they ought to be capable of being reasoned out both by those who make them and by those who accept them. Nor does it detract from the rationality of either group that the "reasoning out" is not separated from, but is "continuous" with, the witness of the indwelling Spirit who makes rationality to be rationality and not mere arbitrariness. If, however, all that both those who make and those who accept dogmatic statements have to go on is "scientific" understanding, they will find in them unresolved contradictions. Perhaps it is better to prefer no reason at
< previous page
page_290
next page >
< previous page
page_291
next page > Page 291
all to that kind of reason. But what if there is a "speculative reason" which resolves the contradictions, precisely because it is more in tune with the non-contradictoriness of infinite Truth? The other subject matter, however, contains not only its own true content, which also constitutes the interest of philosophy in view of the proper mode of its knowing, but this content at the same time retains in itself an immediate connection with what is formal in speculative thinking. Under this heading I should like here to mention the dogmatic content of our religion, because this content not only contains truth in and for itself but also contains it as so thoroughly caught up in (entgegengehoben) speculative thinking that it itself immediately involves the contradicting of understanding and the rejection of rationalizations. [BS, p. 546] The real danger is that religious truths, precisely because for our accustomed way of thinking they involve contradictions, will be presented in such a way that the contradictions are not resolved but merely shunted aside, with the result that the truth itself is reduced to a meaningless blandnessand it is the refusal to think the truth out philosophically that produces this result. Whether or not, however, this content is to have the sort of coherence which is firmly constructed on the basis of speculative thinking depends on whether in the presentation of religion the church's dogmatic teaching is not somehow handled as a merely historical matter, whether in general truly profound reverence for it is not inculcated, but rather the principal emphasis is put on deistic generalities, moral teaching, or even merely on subjective emotions. When this is the way the Church's teaching is presented, more often than not an attitude opposed to speculative thinking is created, the self-deception of understanding and arbitrariness are given first place, and this either leads immediately to a simple indifference toward philosophy or, worse still, falls victim to sophistry. [Ibid.] What Hegel is saying, ultimately, is that religious truth, revealed truth, will be emptied of all meaning if speculative philosophical thinking is not brought to bear on it. Revealed truth cannot simply be poured in from outside and passively accepted; its meaning must be actively recreated in the human mind thinking for itself (see VGP II, p. 55). On the other hand if this mind really thinks with the freedom that constitutes thought, it will find the truth about God revealed to it inescapable (see VPR II, p. 118). Human consciousness and self-consciousness is "other" than God's only to the extent that God, infinite Spirit, "others" himself in it; otherwise finite spirit makes no sense at all (see ibid., pp. 44, 202).
< previous page
page_291
next page >
< previous page
page_292
next page > Page 292
Christology Once more we are back to the Christian context within which alone Hegel's philosophical thinking on God is intelligible. In this connection it is not without significance that in recent years a number of theologians have turned their attention to what they call "Hegel's Christology." God who is Spirit, if he is to reveal himself, can reveal himself only to man who is spirit. In one sense we can say that the very being of man as spirit is divine revelation, but the paradigm of divine self-revelation is to be found in the divine-human, the God-man, who, Hegel assures us, is Jesus Christ. He is not about to deny that Jesus is a person who is truly human nor that, as human, he is an individual to whom can be assigned a place in the temporal course of history, but he is insistent that the truth of Jesus Christ is not exhausted in his humanity. It is not enough to know who Christ was; we must also know what Christ is, that is, a human individual inseparable from the divine nature, the paradigm of God's self-revelation in human nature. In the Christian religion . . . the person who is Christ is a determination belonging to God's nature. From this point of view, then, he is not historical. Taken merely as a historical person, e.g., as a teacher, like Pythagoras, Socrates, or Columbus, what he was would be just as much, as it is with the others, a matter of indifference, uninteresting. But, according to Christian religion this person, Christ himself belongs in his character as God's Son to the very nature of God. The who of revelation, to the extent that it says nothing of God's nature, would not be a universal divine content, but it is a question of the what, the content of the revelation. [EGP, p. 174] What Hegel finds strange is that in his own day this truth which fits in so well with "speculative philosophy" has been lost in "theology," to which the person of Christ says nothing about the "incomprehensible" nature of God. It is as though the moral teaching of Christ could tell us what man's relation to God should be, could even inspire in us a "feeling'' of devotion to God, but could not bring us any nearer to "knowing" God. One can see that this Christian teaching, including the concept of Trinity, which in its fundamental characterization is contained in what has been said, has found a refuge in speculative philosophy, after having been brushed aside by the exegetical and rationalistic theology which, in the Protestant Church, is almost exclusively dominant. Thus the appearance of Christ has been degraded to a mere object of remembrance and of moral foundations. Thus too, God as unknowable has been relegated to what is in itself an indeterminate empty out-there-God, a non-revealed being outside actuality. [BS, p. 186] Perhaps there is a fear among "theologians" that in recognizing Christ as a
< previous page
page_292
next page >
< previous page
page_293
next page > Page 293
divine "person" they will anthropomorphize God, thus likening him to the all-too-human gods of the Greek Pantheon. Hegel's point is that it is precisely by making himself truly human in Christ that God most adequately manifests himself as both "absolute" and "personal.'' This is "anthropomorphism" in the very best sense, far more anthropomorphic than any Greek god! "For in Christianity God is in his truth and because of that is represented as in himself thoroughly concrete, as person, as subject, and, to be even more explicit, as Spirit. What God is as Spirit is explicated for religious apprehension as Trinity of Persons, which in its innermost reality (für sich) is at the same time one" (VA I, p. 101). To be both "absolute" (infinite) and "personal" God must be three Persons. But Hegel is saying more than that; he is saying that the continuity of the infinite and the finite, of God and creation, must also be a continuity of the divine and the human, in such a way that a God who so completely transcended the human as to be unable to express himself humanly would not be the personal God of Christianity, the only God who can be. A divine person who has nothing in common with the human person would be neither person nor divine. Now, in order that spirit attain to its infinity it must likewise emerge from merely formal and finite personality to the Absolute, i.e., the spiritual must present itself as the subject which is at once the fulfillment of the purely substantial and thereby is self-knowing and self-willing. Conversely, the substantial, the true, may not, therefore, be taken to be simply beyond humanity, such that the anthropomorphism of the Greek view is completely eliminated; rather the human as actual subjectivity must be made into a principle, and the anthropomorphic, as we have already seen, only thus brought to perfection. [VA II, p. 129] We may feel that Hegel has chosen a very tortuous way to say what he has to say, but we must remember his overarching concern, manifested par excellence in Phenomenology of Spirit, both to comprehend the human spirit in the light of the divine and to comprehend the divine Spirit in the light of the human. In chapter VII, "Religion," the self-conscious human spirit comes to a grasp of what it is to be spirit in contemplating the divine Spirit; in chapter VIII, "Absolute Knowing," the same human spirit fills out its religious contemplation of the divine by seeing in itself the infinite worth of being self-determining spirit and thus comes to a better comprehension of the divine. It is only through Christian religion that man comes to appreciate what it is for man to be spirit; it is only with speculative philosophy that man comes to a comprehension of what it is for God to be Spirit, the Spirit who dwells in man and thus lifts him to the divine. According to Christian teaching:
< previous page
page_293
next page >
< previous page
page_294
next page > Page 294
The [human] subject is the object of divine grace; each subject, man as man, has infinite value, is oriented to the indwelling of the divine Spirit, to the union of his own spirit with the divine Spirit, and this latter is God. Man is destined to be free and is thus recognized as in himself free. [Still] this freedom of subjectivity is as yet only formal, based on the principle of subjectivity. [VGP II, p. 500] This gives the religious side of the story. When the light of speculative thinking is turned on this it is at once informed of a truth it did not discover and uncovers the more profound meaning of that truth. The second point is that the principle of the Christian religion be developed for thought, be appropriated in thinking knowledge, be thus actualized, so that the knowledge become reconciled to the divine idea it has in itself, that the wealth of thought culture belonging to the philosophical idea be united with the Christian principle. For, the philosophical idea is the idea of God, and the development of thinking knowledge must be united with the Christian principle; for thinking has the absolute right that it be reconciled or that the Christian principle correspond with thought. [Ibid., pp. 500501] But just what is the "Christian principle" of which Hegel speaks? Quite obviously it has to be "faith," but it cannot be simply thatdespite the fact that in other places Hegel calls Christian faith the only "faith" in the proper sense of the term. Above all it cannot be simply faith philosophically defined. "Firstly, the Christian faith comprises in it an authority of the Church," which means that it rests not on "a personal revelation'' but is a definite content revealed to the believing community. "And, secondly, the Christian faith is a copious body of objective truth, a system of knowledge and doctrine" (Ep W, no. 63). But the question has not yet been answered: In the broad compass of that faith what is the "Christian principle"? It can only be the middle-point around which revolves "the spiritual fullness of Christian faith, whether we look at that faith in the heart of the believer and the indwelling of the Holy Spirit, or in the system of theological doctrine" (ibid.). The "middle-point" can only be the incarnation of the "Son" of God, the theological and philosophical explication of which involves "a copious body of objective truth, a system of knowledge and doctrine."
That is also why, in terms of its ultimate content, "theology"read, an adequate and true theologyis only throughout what philosophy is, an attempt to articulate a true knowledge of God. And thus from the perspective of its speculative interest, such a theology as a philosophy of religion based on the Christian fact rests on the "speculative middle point" of the doctrine of the Incarnation. Both a "right theology" and a "right philosophy" begin with the intuitive conviction that the Vorstellungen representing this event in history
< previous page
page_294
next page >
< previous page
page_295
next page > Page 295
have a final and consummate "disclosure significance" in relation to the question of God's essential nature and his relation to the world.8 The Function of Speculation We must, of course, remember that Hegel was not by profession a theologian; he was thoroughly convinced that the contribution he could make to the reintegration of the fragmented European culture of his day was as a philosopher. He was also convinced, however, that precisely as a "philosopher" he had something important to say to the "theologians," that his own speculative philosophy was more a "science of God" than was the "theology" of the theologians. More than that, he was convinced that this philosophy was appropriate for the explication of ''the christological understanding of God and his relation to man and the world already normatively implicit in the already present faith and witness of the Christian communityto which as a Lutheran he claimed to belong."9 Like the Scholastic theologians of the Middle Ages whom, as we have seen, to a great extent he admired for their ability to combine theology and philosophy, he did not think that either the Bible or the authority of the Church could tell us all we need to know about God. The appropriate philosophy"speculative thinking"was, in his eyes, an important hermeneutic instrument for opening up the meaning of what "faith" teaches. If philosophy is indeed "science of God," then faith is indispensable to it; but, by the same token, philosophy is indispensable to the understanding of what faith believesa progressive understanding. Philosophy, however, need not provide the truth which it explicates: "In fact philosophy does no more than to comprehend (begreifen) this idea of Christianity." As soon as what is called explanation begins, as soon as an attempt is made by inference and exegesis to find out what the words of the Bible mean, then we pass into the region of reasoning, reflection, and thought, and then the question comes to be whether the thinking is correct or notjust how one goes about thinking. It is of no use to say that these particular thoughts or these principles are based on the Bible. As soon as they cease to be anything more than the mere words of the Bible, a definite form is given to their content; this content gets a logical form, or, to put it otherwise, certain presuppositions are formed in connection with this content, and we approach the explanation of the passages with these presuppositions which guide us in the explanation given; they are
8. James Yerkes, Hegel's Christology (Missoula, Montana: Scholars Press, 1978), p. 277. 9. Ibid., p. 290.
< previous page
page_295
next page >
< previous page
page_296
next page > Page 296
constants in the explanation. The explanation of the Bible presents its content in the form or style of thought peculiar to each particular age. The explanation which was first given was wholly different from that given now. [VPR II, pp. 199200] By way of gloss on this passage we might remark that an explanation based on an Aristotelian metaphysics of "being" is not likely to be the same as one based on a Hegelian metaphysics of "becoming." But whatever the philosophy may be that grounds the explanation, that explanation will be more truly "theological" than will one which abandons philosophical hermeneutic altogether. Because, as Hegel sees it, the theologians have abdicated their role of guardians of the faith, it becomes necessary for "speculative" philosophers to do their work for them. What Hegel wants to reject is the idea that a fully adequate "scientific" theology is merely, to borrow Schleiermacher's terms, "an account of the Christian religious affectations set forth in speech," an in-house confessional description of Christian beliefs fideistically expressed, but speculatively disinterested or agnostic about the necessary, universal truth about God open to public philosophical discussion. This is a theology which has lost its speculative nerve, its conviction that man has been made rationally in the imago dei. It has lost its apologetic confidence that Christianity is the "revealed" and "absolute" religion, and the philosophical confidence that adequate speculative reasons can be given to justify this.10 It may or not be paradoxical, but it is certainly interesting, that the Christian theologians of the Middle Ages could base their explanations on the philosophy of Aristotle, a professed pagan, whereas the theologians here in question had to reject the philosophical foundations of Hegel, a professed Christian. What it comes down to is that Hegel in fact believes more firmly than do the "theologians" that God has revealed himself and that the revelation is intelligible. At the same time, however, he is quite clear in his conviction that the revelation could not be intelligible to those who have as a heuristic instrument only an abstract philosophy of "understanding." This is the final standpoint which today has attained to great external importance. The enlightened, abstract understanding, abstract thinking demands only the abstract. With regard to God it knows only that he is, it has an indeterminate notion (Vorstellung) of God. That is the content-less. Thus, when theology is grounded merely on abstract understanding, it has as little content as possible, has leveled dogmas off, has itself been reduced to the minimum. But, the religion which is to satisfy the spirit must in itself be essentially concrete, it must be something content-full. Its content must be what has been
10. Ibid., p. 258.
< previous page
page_296
next page >
< previous page
page_297
next page > Page 297
revealed of God in the Christian religion, i.e., it must be a dogmatic [theology]. Christian dogmatic is the sumtotal of doctrines which manifest what is distinctive of Christian religion, doctrines which make known God's revelation, the knowledge of what God is. [EGP, pp. 19899] This, incidentally, is not to say that there is no knowledge of God in other religions; Hegel is simply saying that the Christian religion renders explicit the truth about God which is implicit in other religions. He goes so far as to see "historical necessity" in the advent of Christianity, precisely as the culmination of religious consciousness of God: "In the context of previous forms [of religion] it has been shown that this idea of Christianity had now to emerge, and in fact had to become universal consciousness of the world" (VGP II, p. 497). The Meaning of "Revelation" When Hegel speaks of divine self-revelation, he refers primarily not to the words of the Bible but to the story these words tell, and the story is essentially that of God's being in the world as " God-man, " the synthesis of the divine and the human, the infinite and the finite. In one sense, as we have seen, Hegel's entire philosophy can be seen as a philosophy of God, since to know, ultimately, is to know God. In another sense, however, Hegel's philosophy is from beginning to end a philosophy of man; a response, so to speak, to the Delphic oracle's "know thyself." Nor is there any contradiction in this bipolar description of the Hegelian endeavor: to know man fully is to know him in the light of our knowledge of God; to know God adequately is to know him as the process of spiritual selfdetermination which culminates in God's relationship to man and his world. The "story" of this is told in the Bible. The "speculative reenactment"to use an expression of James Yerkes11is the ''theo-logical" interpretation of the story. Now, the "speculative reenactment" can be carried on in two ways: (1) "phenomenologically," by retracing the process which begins with the incarnational event and then tracing out the implicationstrinitarian, creational, and redemptiveof this event, the reenactment contained in the seventh chapter of the Phenomenology; (2) "logically," by looking first to the inner life of the divine Spirit who, in knowing himself, "generates" his own perfect image, the Son, and in the mutual love of Father and Son "breathes" the Spirit. The rest follows from this: (a) the inner life of the divine Spirit expressing itself outwardly in the creation of the world and of finite spirit; (b) the movement of the finite away from the infinite in the
11. Ibid., p. 290.
< previous page
page_297
next page >
< previous page
page_298
next page > Page 298
fragmenting "Fall," as preparation for and pointing to (c) the reintegrating incarnational event, which articulates itself in (d) the reconciling self-sacrifice of the God-man and (e) the elevation of the finite spirit through the indwelling of the divine Spirit. This reenactment is the summary of the whole "system." We can begin, then, a detailed examination of what can be called Hegel's "theology" with the rather summary account he gives in Phenomenology of Spirit (pp. 52848). In examining these pages we must remember that Hegel is attempting to give an account not so much of the ultimate meaning of what God has revealed of himself but rather of what this revelation means to the finite human spirit in search of adequate self-awareness precisely as spirit. Having examined the degree of religious awareness which man gains from a contemplation of nature and from the production of works of art which "embody" the divine, Hegel turns to the Christian religion, which he considers to be the culmination, both historically and religiously, of the progressive development of religious awareness, affording the highest degree of self-consciousness which religion as such can. He is impelled, then, to interpret Christian religious consciousness in such a way that it elucidates all that any religion can regarding the reality of human consciousness as "spirit." This religion is ''absolute religion" in the sense that religous consciousness qua religious simply cannot go beyond it; there is no religious "beyond." If there is a consciousness of the absolute beyond Christian religious consciousness, it must be, so to speak, a suprareligious (not, be it noted, a nonreligious) consciousness. Before going into the question of such a suprareligious consciousnesswhich, if there be such, would have to be continuous with the religiousHegel seeks to interpret "spiritually" five major themes of Christian revelation, with a view to showing that the "mysteries" in question, when properly"spiritually"understood, constitute a revelation of consciousness as spirit and of self-consciousness as a consciousness of what it is to be spirit. In the context of Hegel's elaboration we can understand "spiritual interpretation" in eitheror bothof two ways: (1) as roughly the equivalent of "demythologization," where the language of the revelation is stripped of its inevitable metaphorical character in order to uncover its true meaning; or (2) as a discovery of its meaning for spirit. The five mysteries which Hegel has chosen to interpret thus are Incarnation, Trinity, Creation, the Fall, and Redemption.12 Hegel has quite obviously chosen wellif we understand the death and resurrection of Christ, the coming of the Spirit, and the sacramental life of the Church to be included under "Redemption." It might be argued, of
12. As we have noted before, Hegel very rarely employs the familiar term "Redemption," which in German is Erlösung, preferring the "speculatively" far more congenial term "Reconciliation" (Versöhnung).
< previous page
page_298
next page >
< previous page
page_299
next page > Page 299
course, that the themes of Creation and Falleven of some sort of Redemptionare not uniquely Christian, nor need they be. If, however, the mysteries as interpreted are meaningful only in the uniquely Christian incarnational context, as Hegel claims they are, then all five themes are Christian and only Christian. Incarnation is, clearly, the central event of Christianity, not only in the sense that from it Christianity derives both its name and its character, but also in the sense that it is the central revelational event which renders the other four mysteries intelligible. The trinity of "Persons" in God is necessary if God's entry into human history while remaining "with himself" and thus transcending history is to be possible at all. Creation is necessary, if there is to be a history into which God enters. The movement away from God in the Fall is necessary, if there is to be a reason for incarnation. Redemption is necessary if incarnation is to be an effective presence of God in history, significant for the self-awareness of human spirit. Incarnation. In Christian religious consciousness the Incarnation is a uniquely concrete union of the divine and the human in the individual God-man, whom history calls Jesus and whom Christians call the Christ. According to Hegel Jesus Christ is the most totally human of all humans precisely because he is divine, the model of the integrally human, because only the man who is more than merely natural man is integrally human, spiritual.13 Gone, says Hegel, is the fragmented divinity of the Greek pantheon whose only unified intelligibility is the abstract unity of divine "substance," a sort of "class" to which all the "gods'' belongor from which, perhaps, all are derived. This sort of substantial unity bespeaks no unity of self-consciousness either on the side of divinity or on the side of a humanity related to the divine. The incarnation of the God-man, Jesus Christ, reconciles divine substance and human self-consciousness. In Jesus the divine substance "empties" itself (the Pauline cenwsiz), becoming a concrete human self and thus revealing a concrete selfhood in God. It is thus that Jesus reveals that God is Spiritnot merely substance or "supreme being"and reveals too what it is for man to be essentially spirit. As Hegel sees it, however, precisely because in Jesus Christ God is sensibly present in individual bodily form, Jesus is not yet fully what he is; his body must die that his Spirit may live in the Christian community. Trinity. The God of the philosophers, whether of Plato, Aristotle, or Plotinus, whether the deistic God of the Enlightenmentor even the God of Kant, Jacobi, and Fichte, to whom philosophical thought cannot at-
13. The term "integrally" is employed here advisedly. Hegel might call it one of those "speculative" terms which combines many meanings, all of which are simultaneously operative. In it are contained the themes of wholeness as opposed to fragmentation; of reconciliation as opposed to falling-away; of integrity as opposed to onesidedness (or wrong-headedness).
< previous page
page_299
next page >
< previous page
page_300
next page > Page 300
tainis no more than an abstract "supreme being." The concrete God of Christianity is a trinity of "persons," revealed, not in the Incarnation alone, but in the Incarnation and the descent of the Spirit consequent on the death of the God-man. Because the Spirit is present in and to the human spiritin the communitythe enspirited community can see the man Jesus as the human revelation of the divine. The divinity revealed in and through Jesus is triune: the divinity in itself, the Father; the divinity in the individual Jesus, the Son; and the divinity in the believing community, the Spirit. Herein there is a reconciliation of transcendence and immanence only because the transcendent Father is immanent in the Son, whose Spirit is immanent in the community, extended in both space and time. To grasp conceptually (begreifen) the divine reality, human consciousness finds that its awareness of God is of a God articulated into a related triplicity (Trinity). To articulate this triplicity in language, the Christian community employs names to designate the members of the triplicity. Thus, the namesFather, Son, Spiritare metaphors based on human relationships. The distinctions of persons are meaningful only if they are at the same time grasped as non-distinctions in a reality of dynamic movement, self-movement, with which only ''speculative thought" can ultimately come to grips. When religion, even "absolute" religion, gives names to the "persons" of this trinity, it is articulating this self-movement, which is SpiritGod as Spirit. The "moments" of this spiritual movement, says Hegel in an effort to transcend the metaphors of "names," are "being," "knowledge," and "love," united in the dynamic unity of self-comprehension which he calls "concept," thus foreshadowing the dynamic unity of totally interrelated reality and totally interrelated conceptual thought. Having given his "spiritual" interpretation of the Incarnation as the movement of God's supreme self-revelation, a movement which extends through the whole earthly life of the God-man culminating in his physical death and resurrection whereby the Spirit comes to dwell in and animate the community, Hegel has been able to interpret the Trinity as self-movement in the interior life of God. This, then, enables him further to interpret a series of figurative terms which occur in Christian theological speculation in the language of the "concept" understood as a movement of "concrescence." "Creation," "Fall," and "Redemption" are themselves figurative terms, and in their explication theology employs other figurative terms which demand interpretation. Creation. If the term "create" is taken to mean "make out of nothing," a making which is, as ordinarily understood, in the mode of causal efficacy, Hegel contends, then it is a "representational" (metaphorical) term designating God's spiritual activity in relation to the world's coming-to-be. This divine activity Hegel sees as a "knowing"with its distinctively Hegelian overtones of "conceiving," which is comprehending by concretely
< previous page
page_300
next page >
< previous page
page_301
next page > Page 301
putting together. The Phenomenology has sought to establish that all knowing is a knowing of self. Thus even God's knowing is a knowing of himself, and his knowing of the world is the explication of that self-knowledge in conceiving and thus bringing into being a world as the outward expression of God's own being. If human knowing is to be truly a knowing, then, it must be analogous to divine knowing, such that man in knowing his world knows himself and in knowing himself knows his world in a manner parallel to God's "creating." Creation, then, is the work of reason knowing, bringing into being and putting together what it knows. The world is the creation of divine Reason and is, thus, rational, revealing both in its spatial dimensions (nature) and in its temporal dimensions (history) reason as its source. By the same token the world grasped in human knowing is the re-creation of the world in human reason; the primordial unity of divine creation having been fragmented by the abstractive activity of scientific understanding is put together again by the creative (re-creative) activity of reason. Thus, human recreative reason whereby the human reason knows itself is a sharing in the divine Reason whereby God knows himself. The Fall. If it is true to say that the phenomenon of the human is a sharing in the divine, then it would seem reasonable to say also that human failure to express the divine is a falling away from that which makes the human to be integrally human. This, however, is not the way Hegel interprets the biblical account of the Fall. Rather, he sees the creation of man as initially man's mere being in the world and man's "innocence" as no more than his lack of responsibility for that world. Becoming responsible, then, is the movement which explicates creation; negatively expressed, it is the loss of "innocence." It is worth noting that the German term for "in-nocence" (Schuldlosigkeit) is literally translated ''faultlessness," a state which is proper to nature, not to spirit. Thus, if man is to pass from nature to spirit, nature must, so to speak, be "faulted"; fault becomes a condition for the movement from being innocent to being good. In this context the "tree of knowledge of good and evil" becomes the symbol of that knowledge which puts an end to innocence; the "fruit" which the first couple, as comprising all humanity, pluck and eat is the symbol of that self-knowledge which is the beginning of responsibility for a world of reality as known; and the "Angel of Light" (Lucifer) who opens the eyes of humanity's first couple symbolizes the awakening of consciousness which will ultimately culminate in the authentic life of spirit. It is all one movement, but at the same time it is but the first faltering steps of a larger overall movement. Thus, the Fall itself is the first step toward reconciliation; to know good as good and evil as evil is to be on the road to reconciliation, and the felix culpa is truly "happy" because it sets the scene for "redemption." Redemption (reconciliation). Looked at from the side of God, "creation" is not an instantaneous act but a movement wherein man, who
< previous page
page_301
next page >
< previous page
page_302
next page > Page 302
has come into being in a world of reality which is over-against him and unknown by him, makes that world of reality his own by progressively sharing in the divine creative activity. Looked at from the side of man, that same process can be looked at as the one overall movement of "redemption." Here, once more, "incarnation" becomes central; incarnation is redemption. The abstract being of a God who is seen only as "Creator" is expressed in time in the concreteness of a human self-consciousness. Creation, then, is the beginning of externalization of an otherwise abstract God, and incarnation is the further concretization of the God who takes upon himself human self-consciousness in order that man may take to himself concrete God-consciousness and thus be redeemed. Incarnation, howeverand thus creation, toois not complete until the individual God-man dies physically in order to rise spiritually in the community which is to live his life. The Movement of Spiritualization Whether or not this Hegelian systematization of salvation history, in which all events are "moments" of one connected movement, can prove fruitful in coming to terms with religious mystery we can leave to the theologiansor historians of theology. That, despite its sometimes quite obviously fanciful exegesis, it tells us a great deal about Hegel's conception of the progressive "spiritualization" of human reality is unmistakable. It is also clear that Hegel means to be taken seriously when he articulates the moments of this process "religiously." How religious all this really is is disputed by manyon both sides of the religous divide. Secularists like Marx and Feuerbach see the whole thing as illegitimate, precisely because Hegel takes God and the divinization of man seriously. Secularists like Kojève, Kaufmann, and Findlay legitimize Hegel's account by seeing in it the complete secularization of what is only metaphorically called "religious consciousness.'' Religionistsand their name is legiontend to condemn Hegel because he has destroyed religion altogether. No one, however, denies that Hegel has provided us with a fascinating, grandiose, and in some ways compelling panoramic vision of human development. It is, perhaps, more difficult to go along with Hegel when he describes this very same developmentwith only one change in the order of presentationin terms of "logical necessity." We must try to recall, however, just what "logical necessity" means for Hegel. It is, first of all, not the necessity of formal-logical or mathematical entailment, which both regulates and even compels the subjective assent of the finite human mind, but is, rather, the necessity of the "moments" of organic process. Secondly, it is not the sort of necessity which could be discovered or seen by the logically functioning mind antecendently to the revelation of its content. Given the revela
< previous page
page_302
next page >
< previous page
page_303
next page > Page 303
tion, however, Hegel claims to "see in" (speculare) it the rational necessity of the "movement" described. It is important to note here, once more, that the fullness of the revelation is not contained in the words of the Bible which are frequently metaphorical, nor is it, for that matter, contained in the words of the Church's teaching: Without the inner witness of the Spirit there is no revelation. We might put it this way: If it is the presence of the Spirit, "who will teach you all truth," and not mere human words (spoken or written) which makes known to the early community the divinity of Jesus Christthe Gospel does not "prove" thisthen it is reasonable to say that it is the ongoing presence of the Spirit in the believing community that continues to bear witness to that same truth. When we turn now to the "logically" first of the "mysteries" concerning God, the revelation that the inner life of God as infinite Spirit requires a triplicity of persons, related to each other as different and yet the same, we can say that the words of the New Testament make it abundantly clear that this was the belief of the primitive community. The words, however, are not by themselves the revelation of the truth; it is the events of "incarnation" and "outpouring'' of the Spirit (which also throw light on the event of "creation") which, through the witness of the indwelling Spirit, reveal the triplicity of "persons" in God. It is the same indwelling Spirit who, through the "Fathers" and the councils of the Church, guides the theological articulation of the mystery of the inner life of God. But there is no "theological" articulation without "speculative" philosophical reflection. What Hegel is saying, then, is that when reason reflects on God's self-revelation as trinity of persons bound together in an infinite unity, reason can see in (speculare) the revelation the truth that God cannot not be three persons. To put this another way, reason can see the rational necessity that, where there is question of infinite divine Spirit, there must be infinite "three-inoneness"but it cannot see this independently of revelation or of the witness of the indwelling Spirit. What God has revealed of himself is the true "Idea" of the God who cannot be other than "triune." For a "metaphysics of understanding," of course, all of this is shot through with contradiction, and thus those whose only "rational" approach to the Trinity is through "understanding" have only two alternatives: (1) to declare the trinitarian "Idea" of God incomprehensible to reason and so to take refuge in faith; or (2) to reject the Idea entirely. The first alternative is chosen by those whom Hegel calls "modern theologians."
Thus it [understanding] says: this cannot be comprehended; for the principle of the understanding is abstract self-identity, and not concrete identity, according to which these differences exist in something which is one. For the
< previous page
page_303
next page >
< previous page
page_304
next page > Page 304
understanding God is the one, the Essence of Essences. This empty identity without difference is the false representation of God given by the understanding and by modern theology. God is Spirit, that which gives itself an objective form and knows itself in that. This is concrete identity, and thus the Idea is also an essential moment. From the point of view of abstract identity, however, the One and the Other exist independently, each for itself, and are at the same time related to each other, and there is the contradiction. [VPR II, p. 230] Those who choose the second alternative are the "Deists" of the Enlightenment. What is true is that the finite, and the Infinite which stands over-against the finite, have no true existence, but are themselves merely transitory. To this extent this is a secret for the sensuous way of representing things and for the understanding, both of which struggle against what is rational in the Idea. Those who oppose the doctrine of the Trinity are men who are guided merely by their senses and understanding. [Ibid., pp. 22829] For Hegel, neither the first nor the second alternative is "Christian": "Similarly the definition of God, given by what is called Deism, is merely the mode in which the understanding thinks God: whereas Christianity, to which he is known as the Trinity, contains the rational concept of God" (Ep W, no. 182). What it comes down to is that those who can conceive only according to finite categories are incapable of conceiving the coexistence of identity and difference which is proper only to infinite Spirit. The copulative verb "to be," which indicates the identity of subject and predicate, is nowhere better employed, nowhere corresponds more to the truth, than where it expresses the "being-in-each-other" [circumincession, pewicwrhsiz *] of the divine Persons . . . to the extent the other is identified with the one related to it.14 As we saw so abundantly demonstrated in chapter 3, Hegel is convinced that the only true way of conceiving God is as "Spirit"; but he is further convinced that only as "triune" does "divine" Spirit make sense: ''God is, thus, known as Spirit, only because he is known as triune" (WG, p. 722). What is more, it is precisely this trinitarian concept of God which makes Christianity radically different from and "speculatively" superior to all other religions.
14. Friedrich Malmberg, Ein LeibEin Geist (Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder, 1960), pp. 160, 176; quoted in Jörg Splett, Die Trinitatslehre G.W.F. Hegels (Munich: Alber, 1965), p. 146.
< previous page
page_304
next page >
< previous page
page_305
next page > Page 305
It is this Trinity which makes the Christian religion stand on a higher level than the other religions. Were Christianity without it, it might be possible that the thought [of God] would be found more adequate in other religions. Trinity is the speculative in Christianity, and it is as a result of this that philosophy also finds in Christianity the idea of reason. [Ibid., p. 59] "Concrete" God as Triune It may very well be that, precisely because Hegel speaks thus of the "speculative" superiority of Christianity," because he conceives of Trinity as "the speculative in Christianity," the suspicion could be created in some minds that Hegel is doing no more than finding in the Christian Vorstellung of God as triune Spirit a convenient peg on which to hang his own speculative philosophy of the human spirit. This suspicion might even be increased by the fact that Hegel devotes considerable space in his ''Philosophy of Subjective Spirit" (EpW, no 381, Zusatz) to a comparison between the rational movement of finite spirit and that of infinite Spirit. What he is trying to show is that the progressive spiritualization of finite spirit is a movement toward infinity, whose quality is "ideality." The movement is, of course, reminiscent of the movement seen in the Phenomenology, which passes through religious consciousness, in which the multiplicity of idealized objects is united in the one Idea, to philosophic thinking which "perfects this idealization of things by cognizing the precise manner in which the eternal Idea, which constitutes their common principle, exhibits itself within them." In this idealization finite spirit "returns to itself," but only inchoately: "It is in absolute Spirit that it is first perfected." The transition to absolute Spirit, however, demands that the consideration of the nature of spirit transcend the ordinary consciousness in religious consciousness, only to rise to a higher level of philosophical consciousness, to a comprehension of "absolute Idea." One could certainly get the impression from this treatment in EpW that "ordinary consciousness" needs "religious consciousness" in order to ascend to the "absolute Idea," but that "philosophical consciousness" does not. Once again, however, we must remember the principle of continuity. It is neither a question of philosophy not needing faith in order to rise to the Idea, nor is it a question of the idea of spirit being independent of the content which is manifested in religious faith.
What we have said above about the nature of spirit is to be demonstrated and has been demonstrated through philosophy alone, needing no confirmation by means of ordinary consciousness. Still, to the extent that our nonphilosophical thinking requires, for its part, that the developed concept of spirit should be more representational, we can remind ourselves that Christian
< previous page
page_305
next page >
< previous page
page_306
next page > Page 306
theology too conceives of God, i.e., the truth, as spirit, and it regards spirit not as a quiescence, a persistence in empty uniformity,15 but as necessarily entering into the process of differentiating itself from itself, of positing its other, and as first coming to itself not through relinquishment but through the preserving supersession of this other. As is well known, theology expresses this process in the following representational manner: God the Father (this simple universal being-in-self), putting aside his solitariness, creates nature (that which is external to himself, self-externality), begets a Son (his other ego), but by virtue of his infinite love, beholds himself in this other, recognizes his image therein, and returns in this image to unity with himself. This unity is no longer abstract or immediate, but concrete, being mediated through difference in that it is the Holy Spirit proceeding from the Father and the Son, and attaining perfect actuality and truth in the Christian community. Thus must God be grasped in his absolute truth as the actual beingin-and-for-self of the Idea. It is thus that he has to be known, not simply in the form of the mere concept, of abstract being-for-self, or in the equally untrue form of an individual actuality in non-agreement with the universality of its concept, but in the full agreement of his Concept with his actuality. [EpW, no. 381, Zusatz] Clearly, then, as Hegel sees it, only as triune is God the concrete God who is. Such a theological comprehension of God as triune Spirit is far from being a convenient peg from which to hang a philosophy of human spirit; its content is the paradigm of concrete spiritual reality, whose movement the human spirit must follow if it is to be spirit at all (see VPR I, pp. 43839). There are, nevertheless, some expressions in the long passage just quoted which could cause difficulty for those who are not thoroughly accustomed to Hegel's mode of thinking and expression. (1) "God the Father (this simple universal being-in-self)": not that the Father as Person is an "abstract" person, but that to conceive of God only as Fathereven "our Father"is to conceive of him abstractly; to conceive of God concretely is to conceive of the mutual relationships of Father, Son, and Spirit. (2) The Father "creates nature" external to himself and "begets a Son'': not that "begets a Son" is somehow subsequent to or dependent on "creates nature," but that to conceive of creating, "self-othering" in nature, as discontinuous with God's self-othering in the infinite "Other" who is the Son is to conceive very naively of "creating." (3) "It is the Holy Spirit, proceeding from the Father and the Son and attaining perfect actuality and truth in the Christian community": not that the Holy Spirit as divine "Person" waits on, so to speak, the Christian community for his full concrete realization, but that the revelation and conceiving of God as concrete in three Persons is completed only in the Spirit dwelling in the community as love. All of this is
15. Far from being mere "persistence in empty uniformity," divine Spirit is paradigm of self-conscious activity.
< previous page
page_306
next page >
< previous page
page_307
next page > Page 307
summed up more briefly in, of all places, Hegel's Philosophy of World History. First of all Father, power, the abstractly universal, as yet incomprehensible. Secondly, he is as object to himself, an other of himself, a self-duplicating, the Son. This other of himself, however, is just as immediately himself; he knows himself and contemplates himself thereinand precisely this self-knowing and self-contemplating is, thirdly, the Spirit himself. This means, the whole is Spirit, not one or the other independently. God, expressed in the language of emotion, is eternal Love, i.e., having the other as his own. [WG, pp. 5859; see EpW, no. 567] We can now begin to understand what Hegel means by saying that speculative philosophy "comprehends" (begreift) the Idea which the Christian religion "presents" to faith. The uniquely Christian dogma of the Trinity is the model of "spiritual" comprehension of the truly real, in comprehending which philosophy learns what it is to comprehend.16 "In the Christian religion the absolute Being is represented but not comprehended as absolute" (VGP II, pp. 408409); the grasp is not yet adequately "spiritual.'' "In fact philosophy does nothing but comprehend this Idea of Christianity" (ibid., p. 409), or else it is not truly philosophy. There follows in this text from Lectures on the History of Philosophy one more attempt to express "speculatively" the dogma of the Trinity, Hegel's conviction being that "speculative" philosophy can "conceive" of God only as triune. Whether or not Hegel has been successful in reconciling conceptually a "three" which is at the same time "one," or a "one" which is at the same time "three," may still be a question in the minds of those for whom the cardinal rule of logic is the principle of abstract noncontradiction. Or it may be asserted that Hegel is playing fast and loose with number concepts, if indeed when applied to infinite Being they are really "number concepts" at all. In any event he is well aware that he is not engaged in mathematics and that to say "three" and "one" of infinite "being" is not the same as saying "three" and "one" of finite "things"the language of "things" is not adequate to the naming of "spirit"internal spiritual relations are simply not comparable to the external relations of "things" to each other. It is much the same when understanding attackes the notion (Vorstellung) of the Trinity. In this notion, too, the inner thought-relation is conceived of in an external fashion, for number is thought in the abstract form of externality. But here understanding holds fast the externality only, stops at numeration,
16. As we saw in the Introduction (pp. 910), the initial response of faith to revelation is the "immediate" Vorstellung, which must be progressively purified of all links to the sensible or to images in "speculative" thinking.
< previous page
page_307
next page >
< previous page
page_308
next page > Page 308
and finds each of the three externally complete in relation to the others. Now, if this quality of number be made the foundation of the relation, it is undoubtedly a complete contradiction that those who are perfectly external in relation to one another should at the same time be one. [VPR I, p. 155] Although in his later writings Hegel does not, as he did in Theologische Jugendschriften, Glauben und Wissen, and Differenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen Systems der Philosophie, put such copious emphasis on the internal spiritual relation of love as the force identifying plurality and unity, the concept is not absent, and it retains its significance. Love is a relationship of persons in which each gives itself to the other, is person in relation to another, because giving is not giving away as it is with things. Where the persons are finite the self-giving can never be complete, and a certain externality of one to the other remains. Where the persons are infinite, on the other hand, the self-giving is total, and the one is absorbed in the other in such wise that, although one is distinguished from the other, their multiplicity and unity are identified. It is just this achieving of personality by the act of absorption, by the being absorbed in the other, which constitutes true personality. Such forms of the understanding directly prove themselves in experience to be of those which transcend themselves. [VPR II, p. 233] If "understanding" asserts that, where there are three persons, there are three individuals, it would seem commonsensical to say also that, where there are three infinite Persons, there are three Gods. Not so "reason." In love, in friendship, it is the person or individual who retains himself, and by means of love has the subjectivity which is his personality. If here, in connection with religion, the idea of personality is clung to in an abstract way, then we get three Gods, and the infinite form, absolute negativity is forgotten, or if personality is regarded as not dissolved, then we have evil [polytheism], for personality which does not yield itself up to the absolute Idea is evil. In the divine unity personality is held to be dissolved, and it is only in appearance that the negativity of personality is distinguished from that whereby it is superseded. [Ibid.] Creative Love The theme of "love" becomes crucially important when we turn now to the theology of "creation." As we have seen (chap. 6), Hegel has been accused of making creation ''necessary" and therefore of making it impossible to distinguish between the "infinite" activity of creation and the "finite" term of that activity. Where, however, the necessity in question is
< previous page
page_308
next page >
< previous page
page_309
next page > Page 309
that of love, even though that be called "rational necessity," it is at least legitimate to ask whether the "necessity" of which Hegel speaks is the same as the "necessity'' in the minds of his accusers. Here it is that we must make a very nuanced distinction, not in the activity of creation, which is one and continuousboth in itself and in continuity with the trinitarian movement of divine Spiritbut in that which is created, the world of "nature" or the world of "finite spirits." Thus, when in the introduction to Science of Logic Hegel speaks of "the presentation of God in his eternal essence before the creation of the world or of a single finite spirit," the distinction is important. What does it mean, then, to say first of all that God "creates" a world of nature, a world composed of interrelated material parts? The question has to be asked in the context of a God who is "absolute," "infinite," self-subsistent, selfsufficient, needing nothing outside himself for the completeness of his being. It simply makes no sense to speak of God as one who organizes a "world" out of a mass of preexisting materials, a sort of Masonic, Deistic "divine architect of the world." The atheists are right in dispensing with that kind of Godor, for that matter, with that kind of world. On the other hand, however, is it possible to make sense out of the notion that God "creates" a world "out of nothing"? Only if the term "create" has an intelligible meaning which is other than that of "make," "produce," "form," "construct," "bring into being" is it possible. Moreover, the conception of matter as originally present and as naturally formless, is a very ancient one; it meets us even among the Greeks, at first in the mythical shape of chaos, which is represented as the unformed substratum of the existing world. Such a conception must of necessity tend to make God not the Creator of the world, but a mere world-molder or demiurge. The deeper insight reveals God as creating the world out of nothing, and that teaches two things. On the one hand it enunciates that matter, as such, has no independent subsistence, and on the other that the form does not supervene upon matter from without, but as a totality involves the principle of matter in itself. This free and infinite form will hereafter come before us as the concept. (EpW, no. 128, Zusatz].17 We might begin by recalling that, according to Hegel, the "categories" of finite thought cannot be applied to God at all; they cannot but distort our view of God. If God, then, can be said to create, "creation" must be an activity which is peculiar to God alone, to absolute Spirit, to infinite Spirit, to pure Spirit; creation must be purely spiritual activity (see VPR I, p. 144). In addition, infinite spiritual activity in God cannot be different from the purely spiritual activity whereby (wherein) God is what he is. But the activity wherein God is what he is is the "spiritual" activity of "knowing" himself,
17. See in addition, VA I, p. 481; BS, pp. 35051; EpW, no. 163.
< previous page
page_309
next page >
< previous page
page_310
next page > Page 310
the Father "begetting" the Son, and the activity of "loving" himself, the Father and Son ''breathing" the Spirit (of love). To get back to the notion of "creation" being "out of nothing," there is no other than God out-of-which God could create; if there be an other of God, it must be God's "self-othering." The model, once again, is the Trinity, the selfothering in God, where there is no introduction of externality in God. If there be that which is external to God, and there is, it can only be God's "self-externalization." "God creates out of nothing but God himself." The necessity that God is the positing of his power is the birthplace of all that is created. This necessity is the material out of which God creates; it is God himself, and, he therefore does not create out of anything material, for he is the Self, and not the immediate or material. He is not one as against an other already existing, but is himself the other in the form of determinateness, which determinateness, however, because he is only One, exists outside of him as his negative movement. [VPR II, p. 55] Finite self-othering in creation is continuous with infinite self-othering in the Trinity, both because there is no real distinction of activities of God and because divine activity, identical with divine being, is essentially eternal. By the same token, however, just as the very being of the infinite Other in God is one and the same identical eternal being of God (the mutual being-in-each-other of the divine Persons), so too the being of the finite other outside God is one and the same eternal being of God, the activity which eternally returns to itself. So the world as God's other does indeed externalize what he is in himself, and yet the world does not exhaust God's subjectivity . . . for God's being consists in the eternal trinitarian movement of externalizing himself, interiorizing what has been externalized, and remaining in all these identical with himself.18 Although the language Hegel speaks in giving this account of the what of creation, geared as it is to an explanation of the being of a finite world immersed in matter, is complex and sometimes enigmatic, what he says is not too foreign to what traditional Christian theology teaches. When he comes to treat, however, of the why of creation, looking for answers to the question in the "speculative logic" of the absolute "Idea," it becomes rather more difficult to reconcile what he says with traditional theology. Is he asking a question that cannot be answered? Strictly speaking, only God himself can answer the question, and it is not easy to show that he has answered the
18. Raymond K. Williamson, Hegel's Philosophy of Religion (Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Newcastle, New South Wales, Australia, 1979), p. 470.
< previous page
page_310
next page >
< previous page
page_311
next page > Page 311
question, unless, of course, man's speculative rationality is part and parcel of God's self-revelation. It is Hegel's contention that the unwillingness to askand answerthe question constitutes "arbitrary dogmatism" and not "humility" in face of the "unsearchableness of God's decrees." When our religious consciousness, resting on the authority of the Church, teaches us that it is God who by his almighty will created the world, guides the stars in their courses, and vouchsafes to all his creatures their existence and their well-being, the question, why, is still left to answer. Now it is the answer to this question which forms the common task of both empirical and philosophical science.19 When religious consciousness, failing to acknowledge this task or the right it entails, appeals to the unsearchableness of the divine decrees, it is taking up the same agnostic ground as is taken by the mere Enlightenment of understanding. Such an appeal is no better than an arbitrary dogmatism, which contravenes the express command of Christianity, to know God in spirit and in truth, and is prompted by a humility which is not Christian, but born of ostentatious fanaticism. [EpW, no. 136, Zusatz]20 Clearly this question will not be answered at all, if all we look at is the created physical world, as Hegel has demonstrated so brilliantly in section A of chapter V of Phenomenology of Spirit, "Reason Observing." It will be answered, if at all, only when reason has looked into its own depths, only to find that there are no depths to look into except in the process of becoming what it is to be spirit, and that the process of becoming spirit is inadequate until religious consciousness has told it what it is to be spirit in the full sense of the word. Religious consciousness in turn will prove to be inadequate, until it has been completed in an "absolute knowing," which is the concrete presence of "absolute Spirit" in human knowingthe unfolding of the "absolute Idea." We come, then, to the second aspect of creation, the creation of "finite spirit.'' What is thus created, this being-other, of itself splits itself into two sides, physical nature and finite spirit. What is thus created is therefore an other, and is placed initially outside of God. It belongs to God's essential nature, however, to reconcile to himself this something which is foreign to him, this special or particular element which comes into existence as something separated from him, just as it is the nature of the Idea which has separated itself from itself and fallen away from itself, to bring itself back from this falling away to its truth. [VPR II, pp. 21314] The theological teaching that God has created man in his own image
19. Presumably "empirical science" can explain the rationality of the created world's being constituted in the way it is. 20. One is reminded of the emotional outburst of the preface to the third edition of EpW!
< previous page
page_311
next page >
< previous page
page_312
next page > Page 312
Hegel consistently took quite seriously (see BS, p. 187). This does not mean that in looking at human reason, human spirit, we find a kind of faulted reproduction of divine Reason, divine Spirit, but that finite spirit finds in itself that which enables it to know infinite Spirit, precisely because the human spirit is finitized infinity; it is embodied spirit which is destined to transcend the sensuous conditions of embodiment in its capacity to comprehend God's revelation of himself. Creation is not merely an act of divine "power"; it is the act of divine self-revelation which can be revelation only to spirit. More than that, since it is of the "essence" of spirit to reveal itself, the self-revelation is not simply an arbitrary decision: A spirit which is not manifest is not spirit. We say that God created the world, and in so saying we state this is an action which has happened once and which will not happen again, and we thus ascribe to the event the character of something which could be or not be. By the same token, we say God could have revealed himself or not revealed himself. The character we ascribe to God's revelation of himself is that of something arbitrary, accidental as it were, and not that of something belonging to the concept of God. But God as Spirit is essentially this very self-revelation; he does not create the world once for all, but he is the eternal Creator, this eternal self-revelation, this actus. This is his concept, his essential characteristic. [VPR II, p. 193] If, however, there be no spirit to whom God reveals himself, there is not self-revelation; that is, it is the essence of the revelation that it be to a spirit who is capable of comprehending it, which means that the creation of finite spirit is the creation of one capable of "imaging" the infinite. Human reason, human spirit, is unquestionably finite; but it does not stand in its finitude over-against the infinite as wholly "other." Precisely because finite spirit is the selffinitizing of infinite Spirit, is it possible to speak of the former as in this very special way "image" of the latter (see EpW, no. 441). Hegel goes so far as to say that the "image'' of God is the "divinity" of man. God, who is infinite Spirit, accords wholly with the "concept" of spirit; man, who is finite spirit, accords only partially with the same "concept," but man is truly spirit, the finite manifestation of infinite Spirit. "To manifest means to become for another. As becoming for another it enters into opposition, distinction as such and is thus finitizing of Spirit."21 "In accord with its concept or truth, however, spirit is infinite or eternal in the concrete or real sense of remaining absolutely identical with itself in its difference. This is why spirit has to be considered the image of God, the divinity of man" (EpW, no. 441, Zusatz). Finite spirit, then, is oriented to knowledge of infinite Spirit; it is infinite Spirit's finitized self-revelation.
21. Michael Theunissen, Hegels Lehre vom absoluten Geist als theologisch-politischer Traktat (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1970), p. 220.
< previous page
page_312
next page >
< previous page
page_313
next page > Page 313
"Rather than the finitude of spirit being regarded as something absolutely fixed, however, it must be recognized as a mode of the appearance of spirit which in no way limits its essential infinitude" (ibid.). Knowing God, which is the same as knowing the very concept of spirit, absolute Spirit and absolute Idea, is then finite spirit's transcending of its own finitude. "This contesting of what is finite, the overcoming of the limitation, marks the divinity in the spirit of man and forms a necessary stage of infinite Spirit" (ibid.). Rational Necessity and Absolute Idea Now, what has been presented up to this point as an interpretation or elucidation of "theological" teaching, Hegel contends can be seen as "rational necessity" in the development of the ideaabove all the ''absolute Idea." This is what "rationality" is all about, as we can see in the very last chapter of Science of Logic, "The Absolute Idea" (pp. 483506). It is essential to Idea that it "other" itself, that is, manifest itself as determinate actuality, only to return to itself in its very self-othering. It is the intellectual world, the divine world, the divine life in itself, which develops itself; but these spheres of its life are the same as those of the world's life. This latter, which is the divine life in the mode of appearance, or phenomenal existence, in the form of finiteness, is contemplated in that eternal life in its eternal form and truth, sub specie aeterni. Thus we have finite consciousness, finite world, nature, that which presents itself in the phenomenal world. It is precisely this which constitutes the antithesis between the other and the idea. In God there is present also the other of the simple idea which exists still in its substantiality. In God, however, the idea retains God's determination of eternity, and thus continues to abide in divine love. This other which remains in the condition of being in and for self, is, however, the truth of the other as it appears in the form of the finite world, and as finite consciousness. The element of matter, the necessity of which we have already considered, is therefore in and of itself the same, both as it presents itself absolutely in the divine Idea and as it appears as the wealth of the finite world; for the finite world has its true and ideal being only in that world of the Idea. [VPR I, pp. 11314] Hegel never tires of stressing that there is no independent matter out of which God shapes a world; matter, so to speak, "inheres" in the very creative Idea out of which a world as finite manifestation of the Infinite is formed. If, then, it is possible to unfold the logic of the idea even in finite form, it will be found not to differ from the overall logic of the "absolute Idea""before the creation of the world or of a single finite spirit." To speak of "creation," then, is to speak of a relationship, intrinsic to
< previous page
page_313
next page >
< previous page
page_314
next page > Page 314
God himself, to a finite world and to finite spirit. Both the world of nature and finite spirit, however, are time conditioned in their existence. This means, first of all, that creation is neither an instantaneous event nor an event which took place in the past (whatever that could mean in the context); it is God's enduring relationship to the world and to man. Secondly, from the point of view of Hegel's "speculative" logic, divine Reason is manifested not only in the rational structure of naturemirrored in human reasonbut also in the temporal sequence of events which constitute history. There is no need here to go into the elaborate presentation of this which constitutes Hegel's Lectures on the Philosophy of Historylucidly introduced by what has come to be called "Reason in History." Our concern here is Hegel's interpretation of Christian "theological'' teaching. Suffice it to say that Hegel's "rationalization" of historical process is his way of interpreting the theological doctrine of divine "providence." To speak of "reason in history" is to speak of God's continuous guidance of the overall historical process. The truth, then, that a providencea divine Providencepresides over the events of the worldaccords with the principle in question; for divine Providence is wisdom, endowed with an infinite power, which realizes its aims, i.e., the absolute rational purpose of the world. Reason is thought determining itself with perfect freedom. [VPG, p. 25] We have already seen that, even in the brief account of Christian religious consciousness in the Phenomenology, Hegel touches on the doctrine of the "Fall" (or "Original Sin"). Unlike most theologians, however, he does not look upon the Fall so much from the point of view of the finite spirit falling away from its moorings in the infinite, losing its essential orientation to infinite Spirit. Rather he is concerned (1) with the place of sin and "evil" in the overall guidance of man through Providence (a sort of prelude to "redemption"), and (2) with the, so to speak, necessary evil of man "faulting" nature, losing "in-nocence," and thus regaining the truly "spiritual," which is not the mere absence of fault but a positive striving for the good. A harmonious integrity which is simply there, simply natural, is scarcely adequate to the life of even finite spirit, which must achieve integrity through knowledge and action. Hegel's interpretationdemythologization?of the Bible story is no doubt fanciful; he seems to be merely using the story to make another point in his "rational" account. It does, nevertheless, highlight the difference between the merely natural and the spiritual, the dynamic movement of spirit, finding itself through consciously alienating itself from the natural, and the importance, in spiritual growth, of knowledge as opposed to mere acceptance of authoritative teaching.
< previous page
page_314
next page >
< previous page
page_315
next page > Page 315
Childlike innocence no doubt has about it something attractive and touching, but only to the extent that it reminds us of what the spirit must win for itself. The harmoniousness, which we look upon as natural in children, is to be the result of the labor and cultivation of the spirit. And so the words of Christ, "Except you become as little children," etc., are very far from telling us that we must always remain children. [EpW, no. 24, Zusatz 3] It is not without significance that, apart from the treatment of the Fall in the Phenomenology, a book wholly concerned with the movement from "natural consciousness" to the fullness of spirit in "absolute knowing, the most detailed account of the biblical story is to be found in the three long Zusätze to no. 24 of the Encyclopedia where his concern is with the "objectivity" of thought in the profoundest sense of thought. As Hegel sees it, then, the story is concerned with the relation of knowledge to the life of the spirit: "Upon a closer inspection of the story of the Fall we find, as was already said, that it exemplifies the universal relation of knowledge to the spiritual life" (ibid.). If spirit is to become what it truly is it must transcend innocence and mere immediate simplicity: "In its instinctive and natural stage, spiritual life appears initially as innocence and unaffected trust; but the very essence of spirit implies the transcending of this immediate condition" (ibid.). The immediacy must be negated, if the truth of spirit is to be realized. "The spiritual life separates itself from natural, and more especially from animal life, in not merely continuing to be what it is in itself, but in realizing its selfness" (ibid.). Separation, however, is disharmony and cannot be the final stage; spirit must by its own efforts regain harmony, and it is thought which achieves this. "The final harmony then is spiritual; that is, the principle of restoration is found in thought itself. The hand that inflicts the wound is also the hand that heals it'' (ibid.). Having emphasized so often, as we have seen, that man is created in the "image" of God, Hegel wishes to make it clear that to be "image of God" is a vocation to be actively realized, not a mere "given" to be acceptedand it is through "philosophy," in the highest sense, that man realizes his vocation. "Philosophy is knowledge, and it is through knowledge that man first realizes his original vocation, to be the image of God" (ibid.). Having eaten of the "tree of the knowledge of good and evil," man had become like God; knowledge divinizes, infinitizes. "When the record adds that God drove men out of the garden of Eden to prevent their eating of the tree of life, it only means that on his natural side certainly man is finite and mortal, but in knowledge infinite" (ibid.). It may well be that the exegesis is forced, that it is "eisegesis" rather than "exegesis," but it does bring out a profound "theological" truth in philosophical language: Theology cannot be concerned with knowledge of God if it has nothing to
< previous page
page_315
next page >
< previous page
page_316
next page > Page 316
say about the "image" of God. After all, the precise import of the story is up for grabs! What Hegel is trying to do, and he returns to the task briefly in Lectures on the Philosophy of History, is to draw philosophical meaning for the development of the human spirit from the biblical story. What Adam"the man"has learned from God, "Behold Adam has become as one of us, knowing good and evil," ''man" must confirm for himself: The reconciliation (harmonization out of discord) which is hinted at here, man must appropriate in a knowledge which will orient him to God, to the good. Implicitly and explicitly, then, we have the truth, that man through spiritthrough cognition of the universal and the particularcomprehends God himself. But it is only God that declares thisnot man: the latter remains, on the contrary, in a state of internal discord. The joy of reconciliation is still distant from humanity; the absolute and final repose of his whole being is not yet discovered to man. It exists, in the first instance, only for God. As far as the present is concerned, the feeling of pain at his condition is regarded as final. [VGP, p. 390] The process of reconciliation will effectively begin only when God himself enters history in order to make the "lifting-up" (Erhebung) of man actualin the Incarnation. As Hegel sees it, the Incarnation can be characterized as the infinitizing of one single human individual, thus enabling that one individual to realize in himself at once what God truly is and what man truly is. As we saw before, in treating the doctrine of the Trinity, God as Spirit necessarily knows himself and, in knowing himself, God as "Father" necessarily begets the "Son," who is God's concrete self-knowing, the whole content of that selfknowing. God is not revealed, however, in the Son"revelation" can only be to anotheruntil the Son is present to the human spirit in the human form of the God-man, Jesus Christ. "According to Christianity, God has revealed himself through Christ, his only begotten Son" (EpW, no. 383, Zusatz). It would be a mistake, however, to think of God "using" Christ, so to speak, as an instrument of revelation: "In the first instance, representational thinking takes this proposition to mean that Christ is merely the organ of this revelation, as if that which is revealed in this manner were something other than the revealer" (ibid.). What God reveals is himself in his Son, who is incarnate in Christ, and to reveal himself thus as what he is is to make known absolute Spirit.
The true meaning, however, of the above proposition is that God has revealed that it is his nature to have a Son, i.e., to differentiate, to limit himself, yet to remain with himself in this difference; to contemplate and reveal himself in the
< previous page
page_316
next page >
< previous page
page_317
next page > Page 317
Son, and through this unity with the Son, through this being-for-self in the other, to be absolute Spirit. Consequently, the Son is not the mere organ, but the very content of the revelation. [Ibid.] What this means, then, is that, just as in the inner trinitarian life of God, the Son is the concrete self-knowing of God, so in the order of manifestation to another, Christ, who is the Son, is the concrete self-revelation of God. Now, if we go back to what Hegel has said about "knowing" God, that is, that only if man knows God does he truly know at all and, consequently, only if man knows God does he truly know himself (and God wants man to know himself, to be reconciled with himself), we can say that in revealing himself as incarnate God also reveals to man what man is; the divinity of Christ reveals the divinity of man. Christ is in a very special way the selfrevelation of God, but so too is finite man, finite human spirit. Furthermore, we see this abstract form in its most concrete manifestation, in its supreme actuality, i.e., as the revelation of God, and this not in the formal, more superficial sense that God reveals himself in nature, in history, in the destiny of each individual man, etc. Rather it is to be taken in the absolute sense that there is brought to human consciousness that unity of the divine and human nature, as it is originally and divinely in Christ, which is, consequently, the revelation of what the nature of God is and what the nature of man is, along with the consequences which follow from that. [BS, p. 185] This is what Hegel means when he speaks, chiefly in Lectures on Aesthetics but also in Lectures on the Philosophy of History, of the "anthropomorphism" of Christian religion. The religion which expressed itself in the form of classical Greek art was anthropomorphic only in the sense that it attributed to its gods human characteristics and portrayed them in human shape, but Christianity is anthropomorphic in the much more profound sense that its God actually is a concrete human individual: "for according to Christian teaching God is not a merely humanly figured individual but an actual single individual, thoroughly God and thoroughly an actual man, having taken upon himself all the conditions of [human] existence" (VA II, p. 23). From this Hegel draws a consequence that many will find hard to swallow: In creation man becomes the image of what God is, and in the Incarnation God becomes the image of what man is (to be)"As man was originally the image of God, now God is the image of man, and who sees the Son sees the Father, who loves the Son loves the Father; God can be recognized in actual human existence" (ibid., p. 112). The point is that the divine-human unity in Christ is a paradigmatic revelation, to those who can read it, of the divine-human unity in authentically
< previous page
page_317
next page >
< previous page
page_318
next page > Page 318
spiritual man (ibid., p. 152). From one point of view it can be said that if God is to manifest himself in sensible form at all, it must be in human form, since only the human form is also spiritual; from another it can be said that precisely in manifesting himself in human form God reveals the true spirituality of the human (see VGP, pp. 304305). The Son is the purely spiritual "image" of the Father: the Son incarnate in Christ is the individual sensible "image" of God; each man is at once finite and, through Christ, infinite "image" of God. It was then through the Christian religion that the absolute Idea of God, in its true conception, reached consciousness. Here man, too, finds himself comprehended in his true nature, taken up in the determinate conception of "the Son." Man, finite when regarded for himself, is yet at the same time the image of God and a fountain of infinity in himself. He is the purpose of his own beinghas in himself an infinite value, an eternal destiny. Consequently he has his true home in a super-sensuous worldan infinite interiority, gained only by a rupture with mere natural existence and volition, and by his labor to break their power within him. This is religious self-consciousness. [Ibid., p. 403; see VPR II, p. 141] Jesus Christ, then, this concrete human individual who lives and dies on this earth as the uniquely actual unity of the divine and human, is the perfect image of God. As Son he is other than the Father yet fully God, and while manifesting himself in human nature is nevertheless wholly divine. This being at once both other and the same is what is characteristic of absolute Idea. This, too, we recognized as present in the divine Idea; for the Son is other than the Father, and this otherbeing is difference, for if it were not, it would not be spirit. But the other is God and has the entire fullness of the divine nature in himself. The characteristic of other-being in no way detracts from the fact that this Other is the Son of God, and is consequently God; and so, too, it does not detract from the divine character of the Other as it appears in human nature. [VPR II, p. 272] In Jesus Christ, then, the divine Idea is fully revealed (see ibid., pp. 31011). His history is "the explication of the nature of God" (VPR I, p. 216), "the unfolding of the divine nature itself" (VPR II, p. 291). He is uniquely the perfect revelation of the divine Idea, but he is also the perfect revelation of the universal vocation of man to mirror that divine Idea, which is what the reconciliation of fragmented man is. In the sense, then, that the unfolding of the absolute Idea is rationally necessary, Hegel can see the incarnational event as rationally necessary, not, be it noted agian, with the necessity of some sort of compulsionif that indeed could even have a
< previous page
page_318
next page >
< previous page
page_319
next page > Page 319
meaningbut with the necessity of God's essential character as "love." What is never quite clear in Hegel's presentation is whether the interpretation of revelation is guided by the logic of the absolute Idea or whether the logic of the absolute Idea is somehow derived from the revelation. What is very clear, with regard to the Incarnation, is that it is not motivated by the need of redemption as though God were somehow determined by events beyond his control, but that it belongs integrally to the process of unfolding the divine Idea, a process which embraces Trinity, creation, fall, Incarnation, and redemption (reconciliation). If Hegel can see in the Incarnation the kind of rational necessity we have described, he can, by the same token, see the same sort of necessity in the reconciling death of Christ on the cross, precisely because it too is a "moment" in the unfolding of the "divine Idea." In the Phenomenology Hegel had spoken of the necessary "death of God," of the man who is God, from two points of view. (1) Christ had to die, that the abstract concept of a God "out-there" who either stood aloof from the affairs of men, like the God of the ''diests," or was so transcendent as to be incomprehensible to man, like the God of the "theologians," might disappear. (2) Christ had to die so that the unique union of the divine and the human in one individual might make room for the universal vocation of man to live in the Spirit, through the indwelling of the Holy Spirit in the Christian community and, consequently, in its individual members. This twofold necessity presented in the Phenomenology, however, is not really different from the necessary unfolding of the divine Idea which is being considered here, and which is rooted in the most fundamental of all Christian doctrines, that of the Trinity. There is the sharpest of contrasts with Lutheran faith and with overall Christian faith, when today professional theologians wish to be still committed to the Christian doctrine of reconciliation and at the same time deny that the doctrine of the Trinity is the foundation of the doctrine of reconciliation. Without this objective foundation the doctrine of reconciliation can have only a subjective sense. [BS, p. 259] Only if man seeks to achieve in himself the image of the triune God can "reconciliation" have any "objective" meaning whatever. The Question of Reconciliation The question, then, is that of reconciliation, and the need for it stems from the fragmentation of man in the "Fall," symbolic both of the estrangement of man from the abstract integrity of "nature" and of the not-yet-achieved reintegration in "spirit." Basically this means that man has the task of finding his true self not in his own merely "immediate" sub
< previous page
page_319
next page >
< previous page
page_320
next page > Page 320
jectivity but by achieving objectivity in uniting himself with the only subjectivity which is at the same time totally objectivethe divine subjectivity. Through Christ God who is love shows the way, takes the initiative. If then in the Christian religion God is also known as Love, because in his Son, who is one with him, he has revealed himself to men as a man among men, and thereby redeemed them, this is only another way of saying that the antithesis of subjective and objective is implicitly overcome, and that it is our affair to participate in this redemption by laying aside our immediate subjectivity (putting off the old Adam), and learning to know God as our true and essential self. [EpW, no. 194, Zusatz]22 In what follows, it may seem strange to rely so heavily on Hegel's Lectures on Aesthetics, but if we remember that to reconcile is to harmonize the discordant, it may not seem so strange. There is something peculiarly aesthetic in the concept of reconciliation-redemption as Hegel develops it. There is something strikingly discordant about clinging to one's mere finitude to the extent of refusing to accord with the infinite which alone can give meaning to the finite. In the Incarnation God took upon himself finitude, thus showing man that the unity of infinite and finite is not an ideal of harmony impossible to achieve; finite man can rise to the infinite who is God. For as God initially separates finite actuality from himself, so too finite man, who by himself begins outside the divine kingdom, is given the task of elevating himself to God, of sloughing off the finite, eliminating his nothingness and as a result of putting to death his immediate actuality becoming what God in his appearing as man has made objective as true actuality. [VA II, p. 134] The process, which Hegel calls "the process of negativity," corresponds with the life, suffering, and death of God in order to make possible man's reconciliation with God. Now man must go through the same process "in order to make the reconciliation actual in himself" (ibid., pp. 14647). By becoming an individual man God shows man what human dignity really is. "This means that the human spirit in itself, according to its essential concept, is true spirit, and, therefore, that each individual subject as man has the infinite vocation and dignity of being a purpose of God, united with God'' (ibid., p. 148). Man must strive to fulfill this vocation, and when he has done so, "then within himself he is free infinite spirit" (ibid.). Thus is
22. The risk of Feuerbachian interpretation of this passage taken only by itself should be obvious.
< previous page
page_320
next page >
< previous page
page_321
next page > Page 321
described the movement from mere individuality (the one God-man) to universality (the divinizing of the community through the indwelling of the Spirit)(ibid., pp. 14849). To speak of man's "infinite vocation" is to speak of his orientation to being reconciled with himself by being reconciled with God. What this ultimately means is the process of moving from the merely natural to the truly spiritual, the voyage described at length in Phenomenology of Spirit. Now, because in the salvation history of Christ the negativity of immediate individuality stood out as the essential moment of spirit, then only by means of the conversion of the natural and of the finite personality will the individual subject be able to elevate itself to freedom and harmony in God. [Ibid., p. 160] Reconciliation, however, does not mean that man ceases to be man, a contingent being, immersed in his own finitude. Just as God does not cease to be infinite in taking on finitude, so man does not cease to be finite in rising to infinity (see VA III, p. 13). The Church It is here that the Church comes in: The merely individual spirit, without ceasing to be individual, is universalized in the Spirit of the community. The link, then, which binds individual spirit to universal Spirit is that function of the spiritual community wherein infinite Spirit "returns" to itself; that is, "worship": ''Worship, thus, is the relation of the finite spirit to the absolute Spirit" (VPR II, p. 218). Worship, then, is the acme of religious consciousness in man. That this, too, must be superseded by that "presence" of the divine which Hegel calls "absolute knowing" we have already seen. We have also seen, however, that the Aufhebung of religious consciousness in philosophical knowing does not mean "dispensing with" religion; if religious consciousness is not "retained" it is not aufgehoben; it is the continuing condition for the very possibility of authentic knowing. Thus, the Christian theological teaching of the "indwelling" of the Holy Spirit is continuous with Hegel's philosophical conviction that only the presence of the divine Spirit in man makes knowing Godand, consequently, knowing at allpossible. We must remember Hegel's constant contention that Christian theology"when indeed it is theology"tells us the truth about God, about God's relation to man and man's relation to God. That this truth is more firmly, more fully, more humanly comprehended in the light of the movement of the "abstract Idea" does not detract from the validity of that contention. If we bear this in mind we can, perhaps, begin to understand
< previous page
page_321
next page >
< previous page
page_322
next page > Page 322
what Hegel means by saying that only with Pentecost, with the coming of the Holy Spirit, do the Apostlesthe "community"comprehend the truth about Jesus Christ, who is the concrete revelation of the truth about God. As a condition for the definitive spiritualization, not of the one man Jesus Christ, but of "man"; the one man who could be seen, heard, touched, believed, had to die in order that his "spirit" might live on in those whose "vocation" it is to rise to the infinite. Not until the feast of Pentecost were the Apostles filled with the Holy Spirit. For the Apostles, Christ as living, was not that which he was for them subsequently as the Spirit of the Church, in which he became to them for the first time an object for their truly spiritual consciousness. By the same token, we do not adopt the right point of view in thinking of Christ only as a past historical personality. . . . If Christ is to be looked upon only as an excellent, even impeccable individual, and nothing more, the conception of the speculative Idea, of absolute Truth is denied. [VPG, pp. 39394; see VGP II, pp. 52627] That final sentence strikes the keynote of the whole story, as Hegel sees it: The divine Spirit who comes to dwell in the Churchtaken, so to speak, as representative of the whole human familyis the "absolute Idea," the "absolute Truth," which makes "speculative knowing" a possibility. The truth is expressed religiously, theologically; but it is also truth for philosophical thinkingif it is to be comprehended, philosophy must come to the aid of religion. "The real question is as to what the content essentially is, is in-and-for-itself. The true Christian content of faith is to be justified by philosophy, not by history" (VPR II, p. 318). It should be emphasized here that the Spirit of which Hegel speaks is the Spirit as ''Love," without which knowledge is not knowledge, because without love spirit is not spirit. Thus this love is the Spirit as such, the Holy Spirit. It is in them, and they are and constitute the universal Christian Church, the communion of saints. Spirit is infinite return into self, infinite subjectivity, not as the represented but as the actual, present Divinity, and thus it is not the substantial reality of the Father, not the true presence in the objective form of the Son, but the presence which is subject and actual, which, precisely as thus subjectively present is the outpouring culminating in the objective contemplation of love, with its infinite pain, which in that mediation is return. This is the Spirit of God, or God as present, actual Spirit, God dwelling in his Church. [Ibid., p. 305] The divine Spirit appearing in Christ is present to the Apostles; the Spirit of God as "love" is present in the Apostles, and he it is who guides them into all truth. God in sensible form must disappear in order that God as pure Spirit may be present in the community. What Christ has taught them the
< previous page
page_322
next page >
< previous page
page_323
next page > Page 323
Apostles comprehend only through this presence of the Spiritand this, Hegel is convinced, is intelligible through the intelligibility of "absolute Idea." From this point of view the character of the text is to be looked at more closely, it contains the manner in which Christianity first appears, this it describes. Now this first appearance cannot yet contain very explicitly what lies in the principle of Christianity, only the merest hint thereof. This too is explicitly stated in the text, Christ says: "When I am no longer with you I shall send the Comforter to you; he, the Spirit will guide you into all truth"companionship with Christ will not, nor will his words. Only after him and after his teaching contained in the text, will the Spirit come into the Apostles, only then will they be full of the Spirit. . . . If Christ is to be God for man, God in men's hearts, then he cannot have sensible, immediate presence. [VGP II, pp. 504505] This situation we can call the domination of the Spirit, but not in the sense that the divine Spirit, so to speak rules over, dominates, the human spirit. Because the human is truly spirit, the presence of the divine Spirit must be much more intimate, "such that the Spirit in the subjective spirit is reconciled with itself" (ibid., p. 533). The "kingdom of God" is the Spirit of reconciliation which unites God and man. The theme is one which is familiar to Hegel from his reading of Jakob Böhme: the kingdom of the Father, the kingdom of the Son, the kingdom of the Holy Spirit. With Hegel, however, the theme takes on a special twist, what we might call a ''philosophical" twist: The kingdom of the Spirit is that situation in which the human spirit is liberated to authentic rationality, made capable of knowing "absolute Truth." To this reconciliation belongs that not only subjective consciousness, feeling, heart, but also the kingdom of this world, its laws and institutions, human life, etc., to the extent that all of this stands in the Spirit, become rational. We have seen in Plato's Republic the idea that philosophers should rule. It is now time to say that the spiritual should rule. [Ibid.]23 We have finally come around full circle: The philosophy of which Hegel
23. It is interesting to note that in this passage Hegel continues with a play on words which might seem to be not to the point. After saying that "the spiritual" (das Geistige) should rule, he remarks that the meaning has changed, and that "spiritual" (Geistige) has been interpreted as "clerical" (das Geistliche), such that "clerics" (die Geistlichen) are seen as rulers. The point is actually a good one: to identify the principle, "the spiritual," with certain types of individuals is to falsify the principle.
< previous page
page_323
next page >
< previous page
page_324
next page > Page 324
speaks has turned out to be startlinglyfor some, perhaps, frighteninglytheological, and yet, for all that it is not less but all the more philosophical. If it is possible to identify God with infinite "Reason," absolute "Spirit," then it must be said that God, in what he is and what he does, is supremely rational, that he is infinite "rationality." To know God, then, is man's rational goal, and to be thoroughly rational is to know God. But this can make sense only if human reason is somehow "divine," continuous with "infinite'' Reason, since "reason" is one, not many.
< previous page
page_324
next page >
< previous page
page_325
next page > Page 325
Epilogue When all that has been said in these pages has been said, might it still be argued, as it has been, that Hegel's philosophy cannot shake off its this-worldly, non-transcendent character? Could it be that exculpating Hegel of the charge of "pantheism" means no more than that Hegel's "Absolute"be it "absolute knowing," "absolute Spirit," or "absolute Idea''is but a "logical" absolute which cannot be "ontologically" identified with religion's God? If it can consistently be so argued, then Chapter 6 above is rendered unnecessary because not to the point. By the same token, however, Chapter 7 too is rendered otiose, because, on this showing, the "theo-logy" we seem to have discovered in Hegel's thinking refers to human "speculative philosophy" and to that alone, and this "speculative philosophy" is the only "absolute" there is for Hegel. The "de-mythologization" of Christian theology we have been following reveals no more than that Hegel found in the language of Christian theology a convenient matrix for the expression of a logic which is only logic. But, the thrust of the argumentation goes deeper than that. Its ultimate claim is that this whole book has been a waste of timefor both author and reader. What Hegel has done, and it needed to be done, is to break definitively with both the naively ontological significance of "absolute Spirit" and the abstractly noetic view of "absolute knowing." It is true (Chapter 1) that Hegel does identify the content of religion and the content of philosophy, but this shows, not that the God of philosophy is identical with the God of Christian religion, but rather that the God of Hegel's "religion" is no more than the "logical Idea" which "absolute Spirit" (Reason) comprehends, and "absolute" expresses logical necessity, and no more than that. The "Logos" with whom Hegel identifies God is not the Johannine Logos, it is only Hegelian Reason. It would seem, then, that Chapter 2 also goes down the drain. "The Con
< previous page
page_325
next page >
< previous page
page_326
next page > Page 326
cept" of which Hegel speaks is "absolute" with an absoluteness other than that of God. It is "concrete," yes, and its activity is self-manifestation, but that says no more than the "concrescence" which characterizes "speculative thinking'' and the systematic exposition of its eternal logical structure. One wonders, too, whether Chapter 3 can hold up under the attack. There is no question that Christian religion affirms that God is Spirit; nor is there any question that Hegel speaks of "absolute Spirit" as God. But, are we justified in equating a spirit which is clearly "this-worldly" with the God who, religion says, is transcendent? Hegel can be interpreted not as presenting the rational conceptual exposition of the God in whom faith believes but as "deifying" reason itself. With this Chapters 4 and 5 come tumbling down also. If "the Infinite is but a new way of defining the Absolute," then at Hegel's hands the Infinite has suffered the same fate as the Absolute. The logical infinity of speculative philosophy, which is always on the march, always in process, has nothing in common with the infinite transcendent God who is at once the object of Christian faith and the goal of Christian striving. By the same token "proofs" of God's reality are no more than proofs of reason's infinity as it comes to a progressive awareness that it is concretely all reality. At this point one does have to wonder, of course, just what the terminology of such argumentation means. What is an "absolute" which is only logical and not ontological? Is it, perhaps, "the dark night in which all the cows are black"? Or, is it the clear light of a reason which has been infinitized by fiat? It may be that the Hegel of the Theologische Jugendschriften (which he wisely did not publish) was in search of a religious substitute for Christian religion and an absolute substitute for Christianity's God, but the Hegel of the preface to the 1830 Encyclopedia and of the Berliner Schriften would seem to indicate that he had abandoned that early quest. If the argumentation in question is to hold water, we must at the very least conclude that Hegel showed remarkably poor taste in employing a Christian theological language in elaborating a conceptual system which does not need that language. Perhaps the best way to approach this whole issue is to pass in review, very briefly, just what Hegel does say about the identification of "absolute Spirit" and God, rather than to focus on what he must have meant. There can be no question that Hegel does say over and over again, even in his most "mature" writings, "Absolute Spirit is God," "God is absolute Spirit." The identification, then, is no problem; but there is a problem as to whether he is saying, "absolute Spirit is the same as God," or "God is no more than absolute Spirit." The question, of course, is answerable, only if we are capable of comprehending the Absolute (Infinite) as all activitywith no passivitynot merely an infinite "substance" which acts, but an infinite
< previous page
page_326
next page >
< previous page
page_327
next page > Page 327
"subject" which is act (Hegel even dares to use the Scholastic expression actus purus). To this we might add that, although Hegel never claims that faith is purely rational activity, he does claim explicitly that the content of faith is an eminently rational content. It is true, of course, that this is but another way of saying that the content of both faith and reason is the logos of being in its infinity, but this is precisely the point: is the logos of being to be construed as merely "logical," or is the logos concretely real? Nor is there any need to claim here that this logos does, in fact, correspond to the Christian Godonly that Hegel intends it to correspond. It might, of course, be argued that the "Absolute'' of which Hegel speaks in the seventh chapter of the Phenomenology as the object of religious consciousness is not truly religion's God, or that "the presentation of God" of which he speaks in the introduction to the Science of Logic is not truly religion's God either, but it is not easy to make sense of that claim. It would seem to be equally frivolous to claim that when he says "For philosophy, too, has no other object but God and is, thus, rational theology" (VA I, p. 139), he intends a God who is not Godeven if one thinks that Hegel's God does not measure up. The crux of the difficulty experienced by those who claim that Hegel's "Absolute" is a purely logical, not an ontological Absolute, it seems to me, is that despite the fact that, although they agree in distinguishing the logic of speculative thinking (Hegel's) from the logic of scientific thinking, they surreptitiously impose on his thinking conclusions which would be true only if his logic were scientific and not "speculative." Thus, to say that a logical absolute is clearly not an ontological absolute is, for a logic of scientific thinking (Verstand), unquestionably true: the logic of scientific thinking is unabashedly abstract. By the same token, however, to claim that Hegel's absolute is logical and not ontological is to claim that it is abstract, not concrete, the opposite of what Hegel claims. One wonders indeed how Hegelor anyonecould claim that a merely logical absolute could be "personal," as he does in his critique of Spinoza. Hegel is, then, making a claim which to some may be too enormous to acceptflying, as it does, in the teeth of Kantthe claim that the mind is necessitated (logically) to affirm what speculative thinking sees to be trueeven if what it sees to be true is the reality of the God of faithunder pain of being irrational if it does not. Nor does "rational" refer only to the way mind (all minds) necessarily thinks; it also takes in the way reality necessarily is; reality reveals to and in rational thinking what reality's own rationality is. This, however, cannot be, if the only thinking there is is finite human thinking (even the totality of it), or if the only reality there is is finite reality (even the sum-total of it). What this means is, at the very least, that the thought which rational thinking investigates consists of a unified totality which is both antecedent to (logically) and the source of (ontologically)
< previous page
page_327
next page >
< previous page
page_328
next page > Page 328
finite reality and finite thinking. The structures of thought are the structures of reality, because subjective rational thinking and objective rational reality are products of the thought which transcends and embraces both. This, in turn, means that the transcendent Concept (the producing) and the transcendent Idea (the produced) are identical and constitute both the reality of the real and the truth of thoughtnohsiznohsez. Concepts (plural), then, are "moments" of the Concept, each deriving its determinateness from identification with the whole, "absolute Spirit," the all-unifying concrete concept. This is the Spirit, wherein the initial total abstractness of mere "being" is progressively concretized. In this context human subjectivity is the finite expression of infinite Subject, the Absolute, the perfect subject-object. The ''ideal" content of the Idea, then, is the same as that of the fully determined Concept, the former as total objectivity, the latter as total subjectivity; and they are identified. Hegel comes to the conclusion that the truth of reality is not "represented by" ideas (plural) but rather "contained in" ideas, to the extent that they are all embraced in the absolute unity of "absolute Idea," which is at the same time "absolute Reason," "absolute Thought," "absolute Subject," "absolute Spirit"again, nohsiznohsewz. It seems abundantly clear, then, that, for Hegel, to conceive of God other than as Spirit is simply not to conceive of God. If to this we add that to conceive of "spirit" without conceiving of it as infinite (concrete) is not to comprehend spirit, not to know what spirit is (which is true also of "being," "reason," "thought"), it will take considerable mental prestidigitation to see in this a nonidentification of "infinite Spirit" and God. It may be that Hegel is speaking of the "infinity" of the human spiritwhich he also clearly acknowledges to be finitebut it would seem that he could not do that at all, with no reference to the Spirit who is unqualifiedly infinite, which is, patently, not to say that God is the only referent of the term "infinite," but that he is the paradigm referent. The qualifiedly infinite is, after all, intelligible precisely as infinite. With his own peculiar employment of the copula "is," with which we are all familiar, Hegel does not hesitate to say, "Thus finite spirit is itself posited as a moment of God. . . . Man is God only to the extent that he transcends the naturality and finitude of his spirit and elevates himself to God" (VPG, p. 392). As Hegel sees it, then, spirit is thinkable only because it is unthinkable that absolute Spirit should not be. To say that the human spirit thinks absolute Spirit, however, is not to say that the human mind forms to itself a conception of absolute Spirit; that is not at all the way absolute Spirit is objective. "The divine is not to be conceived of as merely universal thought, or as something inward and only potentially real. The objectifying of the divine is not to be conceived of simply as representing the manifold forms of the spiritual in general which the absolute Spirit has in itself and which has to advance until it reaches the form of the Is, which is immediacy; that
< previous page
page_328
next page >
< previous page
page_329
next page > Page 329
development would not be contained in that kind of objectivity" (VPR II, pp. 27576). There is no question that, for Hegel," absolute Spirit" is concrete, not abstractly universal, real and not merely ideal, the unique concretely infinite, Absolute. This is the "concrete" absolute Spirit which, according to the Phenomenology of Spirit, human spirit must know if it is to know itself as spirit, if its "knowing" is to be ''absolute," which is, precisely, knowing and not merely being-conscious-of "absolute Spirit." Perhaps the conclusion to all this is that the interpretation presented in these pages represents the only way I can make sense of what Hegel saysassuming that it is risky not to make sense of what he says. Does this put me back in the embarrassing position of saying that what Hegel says is what I say he says? Yes. But it also puts everyone in the position of judging which interpretation makes sensein itself and as an interpretation of Hegel. I leave it to the reader to decide which interpretation makes more senseof Hegel and of sense itself.
< previous page
page_329
next page >
< previous page
page_331
next page > Page 331
Bibliography Barrett, William. The Illusion of Technique. New York: Doubleday, Anchor, 1979. Easton and Guddat, (eds.), Writings of the Young Marx on Philosophy and Society. New York: Doubleday, 1967. Engels, Friedrich. Ludwig Feuerbach und der Ausgang der klassischen deutschen Philosophie. Berlin: Dietz, 1951. Fackenheim, Emil. The Religious Dimension in Hegel's Thought. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967. Findlay, J.N., Hegel: A Re-examination. New York: Macmillan, 1958. Gomez-Caffarena, José. Metafisica Transcendental. Madrid: Revista de Occidente, 1970. Grégoire, Auguste. Immanence et transcendance. Brussels: L'Édition Universelle, 1939. Grégoire, Franz. Études Hégéliennes. Louvain: Publications Universitaires de Louvain, 1958. Harris, H.S. Hegel's Development. Oxford: Clarendon, 1972. Hartman, Nicolai. Die Philosophie der deutschen Idealismus. Vol. II, Hegel. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1929. Heidegger, Martin. Identity and Difference. Translated by Joan Stambaugh. New York: Harper & Row, 1969. Herder, Johann Gottfried. Schriften, edited by Walter Flemmer. Munich: Goldmann, 1960. Kant, Immanuel. Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft. Hamburg: Meiner, 1956. Küng, Hans. Menschwerdung Gottes. Freiberg im Breisgau: Herder, 1970.
< previous page
page_331
next page >
< previous page
page_332
next page > Page 332
Lauer, Quentin, S.J. Essays in Hegelian Dialectic. New York: Fordham University Press, 1977. Lauer, Quentin, S.J. God Knowable and Unknowable. Edited by Robert J. Roth, S.J. New York: Fordham University Press, 1973. Lauer, Quentin, S.J. Hegel's Idea of Philosophy. New York: Fordham University Press, 1971. Lauer, Quentin, S.J. A Reading of Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit. New York: Fordham University Press, 1976. Löewenberg, Jacob. Hegel's Phenomenology: Dialogues on the Life of Mind. LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1965. Lowith, Karl. Von Hegel zu Nietzsche, Second Edition. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1950. Malmberg, Friedrich. Ein LeibEin Geist. Freiberg im Breisgau: Herder, 1960. Maréchal, Joseph Le point de départ de la métaphysique. Brussels: Desclée de Brouwer, 1944. Metzke, Erwin. Hegels Vorreden. Heidelberg: Kerle, 1949. Müller, Gustav. Hegel: Denkgeschichte eines Lebendigen. Munich: Francke, 1959. Petry, M.J. Hegel's Philosophy of Subjective Spirit, Vol. I. Boston: Reidel, 1978. Rahner, Karl. Spiritual Exercises. London: Sheed and Ward, 1967. Ricoeur, Paul. De L'interprétation. Paris: Seuil, 1965. Rondet, Henri. Hégélianisme et Christianisme. Paris: Lethielleux, 1965. Schacht, Richard. Hegel and After. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press, 1975. Splett, Jörg. Die Trinitätslehre G. W.F. Hegels. Munich: Alber, 1965. Theunissen, Michael. Hegels Lehre vom absoluten Geist als theologisch-politischer Traktat. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1970. Valensin, Auguste. A travers la métaphysique. Paris: Beauchesne, 1925. Voegelin, Eric. "On HegelA Study in Sorcery," Studium Generale 24 (1971). Wallace, William, trans., Hegel's Logic. Oxford: Clarendon, 1975. Williamson, Raymond Keith. Hegel's Philosophy of Religion. Dissertation, University of Newcastle, New South Wales, 1979. Yerkes, James. Hegel's Christology. Missoula, Mont.: Scholars Press, 1978.
< previous page
page_332
next page >
< previous page
page_333
next page > Page 333
Index of Names A Anaxagoras, 204 Anselm, 26, 33, 37, 58, 99f., 192, 194, 212, 225, 228, 232, 238-42 Aquinas, 33, 37, 79, 246, 250, 271, 280 Aristotle, 23, 26, 46f., 66, 77, 79, 98, 105ff., 115, 118, 141, 156, 181, 197, 204, 238, 296, 299 Augustine, 33 B Barrett, William, 19 Barth, Karl, 2, 245, 271 Berkeley, 69, 79, 205, 237 Böhme, Jakob, 49, 323 D Descartes, 16, 49, 78, 87, 99f., 115, 205, 236, 244 E Engels, 5, 63 F Fackenheim, Emil, 6, 36, 39, 52, 55, 285 Feuerbach, 2, 5f., 45, 52f., 118, 146, 150, 167, 284, 302 Fichte, 2, 16f., 23ff., 30, 40f., 43, 45, 49, 52, 55, 58, 73, 79, 102, 115, 169, 187, 206, 217ff., 223, 232, 237, 288, 299 Findlay, J.N., 2, 168, 287, 302 G Gomez-Caffarena, José, 246f. Grégoire, Auguste, 247 Grégoire, Franz, 247 H Harris, Henry, 39 Hartmann, Nicolai, 113
Heidegger, Martin, 225 Heraclitus, 71, 204 Herder, 24 Hume, 69, 78f., 115, 195, 205, 237 Husserl, 79 J Jacobi, 2, 16f., 23, 30, 43, 49, 58, 169, 218, 261, 284, 288, 299 James, William, 11 K Kant, 2, 3, 16f., 23ff., 28, 30, 33, 40f., 43, 45, 48f., 52, 55, 58, 64f., 68f., 78f., 96, 105ff., 115, 169, 171f., 194f., 205-214, 217f., 223f., 227ff., 231f., 237f., 241, 246f., 261, 276, 278, 281, 284f., 288, 299, 327 Kaufmann, Walter, 2, 168, 302 Kierkegaard, 2, 45, 48, 169, 219, 245, 284 Kilmer, Joyce, 151 Kojève, Alexandre, 2, 168, 302 Küng, Hans, 2, 247, 269 L Leibniz, 101f., 115, 205, 237 Lessing, 45 Locke, 66, 69, 195, 205, 237 Loewenberg, Jacob, 21 Löwith, Karl, 85, 268 M Malebranche, 205, 237 Maréchal, Joseph, 2, 246f. Marx, 2, 5f., 11, 45, 52, 118, 146, 150, 270, 284, 302 Metzke, Erwin, 12 Müller, Gustav, 85, 230, 268 N Nietzsche, 2, 45 P Parmenides, 71, 181
Peirce, Charles S., 244, 264 Petry, M. J., 141
< previous page
page_333
next page >
< previous page
page_334
next page > Page 334
Plato, 18, 23, 26, 47, 79, 104, 115, 159, 170, 191, 197, 204, 217, 299 Plotinus, 26, 181, 299 Pythagoras, 292 R Rahner, Karl, 263 Reinhold, 69 Ricoeur, Paul, 2, 4, 6 Rondet, Henri, 247 Rosenkranz, Karl, 68 S Sartre, Jean-Paul, 2, 110 Schacht, Richard, 40, 168 Schelling, 23, 49, 73, 79, 115, 187, 206, 219, 237, 286 Schleiermacher, 16, 23, 30, 43, 49, 58, 218, 289 Schopenhauer, 45 Socrates, 104, 170, 204, 292 Spinoza, 23, 26, 45, 49, 79, 87, 99f., 115, 155, 181, 205, 237, 257, 327 T Theunissen, Michael, 75, 138 V Valensin, Auguste, 247 Voegelin, Eric, 45 W Whitehead, 16 Williamson, Raymond, 144f. Y Yerkes, James, 47, 225, 297
< previous page
page_334
next page >
< previous page
page_335
next page > Page 335
Analytic Index A Absolute (see also Infinite), 40, 47, 92, 101, 103, 113, 185, 189, 268 the Absolute, 22ff., 41, 50, 53f., 70, 73f., 102, 114, 136, 145, 172, 180, 183, 185, 189, 208, 219, 224, 238, 240, 247, 259, 283, 286 Abstract, 35, 42, 64, 68, 70, 86, 88f., 92f., 98-101, 105f., 116, 139, 164, 179, 182, 186, 192f., 230, 234, 254, 262f., 272 abstraction, 41, 52f., 70, 72, 81, 84f., 103, 159, 172, 174f., 193, 196, 228, 234, 296, 306, 319, 327 Activity, 26, 42, 109, 122, 124, 133, 141-45, 150f., 156, 158f., 171, 207, 248f., 256f., 260, 266-69, 277, 300, 306, 309f Actual, 3, 63, 83f., 118, 147, 155, 322 actuality, 17, 63, 114, 143, 150, 160, 266, 292, 306, 313, 320 actuality as "effectiveness", 62, 64 actualization, 82 Affirmation, 32, 89 Alienation, 13 Anthropomorphism, 317 Appearance, 70, 313 Appropriate, 37, 72, 128f., 195, 219, 240, 261, 271, 287, 294 Art, 131, 135, 153, 196f., 199f., 221 Atheism, 5, 6, 257, 285 atheist, 47, 155 deism, 152, 304 pantheism, ch. 6 (243-82 passim) theism, 5, 152 Aufheben (supersede, transcend), 11, 30, 36, 83, 93, 101, 105f., 111f., 134, 143f., 147, 321 Aufhebung (supersession): 36, 57, 103, 321 B Being, 46, 49f., 53, 76, 80, 82, 86f., 90, 98-101, 110, 122ff., 130, 139ff., 165, 168, 170, 176, 180f., 194, 206, 214f., 228, 231, 238, 240f., 249f., 261, 277, 280, 296, 300
Belief. (See Faith) C Category, 50, 61, 68, 159, 163, 179, 213, 261, 286, 289 Cause, 38, 66, 78, 84, 106, 110, 237, 269 causality, 77, 79, 104f. Certainty, 23, 73, 78, 123 certitude, 99 Christianity, 8, 34, 164 Christianity as "absolute religion", 34, 164, 188, 191 Church, 10, 137, 295, 298, 303, 311, 321-24 Community, 187, 196, 303, 321f. Comprehend (begreifen), 3f., 31, 51, 58, 140, 152f., 161, 191, 193, 200f., 238, 240, 253, 293, 295, 307 comprehension, 3, 37, 136, 211, 255, 287 Concept (Begriff), 19, 34ff., 50, 52, ch. 2 (57-127, passim), 135, 137, 143, 159, 174, 191, 194, 199, 211, 237, 241, 243, 254, 266f., 300, 304, 306, 309, 328 Concrete, 11, 28, 35, 39f., 52, 64, 72f., 81, 86, 89f., 92f., 95, 97f., 104, 111, 114, 116, 118, 139, 145, 148f., 158f., 164, 168, 182, 186, 192f., 195f., 201, 208, 210, 230, 235f., 240, 243, 254ff., 263, 286, 296, 299, 304ff., 317, 326, 329 Consciousness, 41, 51, 61, 65, 70, 99, 102, 132, 184ff., 216, 220, 239
religious consciousness, 6, 21-24, 26f., 29, 37, 85, 145, 155ff., 160, 166, 198,
< previous page
page_335
next page >
< previous page
page_336
next page > Page 336
212, 215, 219, 233, 243, 267, 284f., 288, 297f., 311 self-consciousness, 27, 133, 154-58, 181, 186, 188, 190, 208, 210, 216 Contingent, 63, 65, 70f., 75, 93, 97, 107, 112, 136, 248f., 261, 270, 276, 279, 321 contingency: 232, 250 Continuity, 7, 30, 73, 156f., 263-67, 272, 277, 293, 305 Contradiction, 6f., 69f., 86, 93, 101f., 105, 121, 143, 175, 179, 190, 213f., 234, 252, 255f., 266, 273, 276, 291, 297, 303f. contradictory: 7, 116, 135, 156 Creation, 40, 54, 82, 149, 156, 188, 220, 248, 266, 269f., 275, 277, 279, 293, 300f., 308ff., 313 Culture (Bildung), 13, 48, 52, 55, 294f. D Definition, 18, 52, 59f., 81, 93, 114, 120, 136, 151, 156, 170, 304 Determination, 83f., 88, 90, 94f., 98, 103, 122f., 133, 143, 168, 170, 172, 201, 214, 227, 230f. determinancy, 83, 172 determinate, 50, 163, 172, 235 determinateness, 51, 82, 86f. Dialectic, 10, 14, 43, 69ff., 81f., 87, 93, 103, 113, 116f., 121, 124f., 135, 160, 198, 225 Divine, 14, 16, 21, 26, 43f., 46, 53, 85, 134, 136, 139, 151, 182, 230, 249, 274, 293, 299, 313 E Emotion, 8, 31, 54, 165, 218, 290 Enlightenment (the), 5, 12f., 16, 26, 30, 33, 37, 55, 205, 234, 285, 299, 304 Essence, 28, 53, 68, 70, 82, 87, 90, 94, 125, 134, 142, 145, 154, 173, 233, 312 Evil, 63, 199, 314 Experience, 18, 21, 29, 65f., 70, 75, 78, 130ff., 150, 162, 171, 174, 204f., 209, 228-32, 288 F Faith, 17, 29f., 46, 53, 164, 166, 169, 200f., 204, 206, 208, 212, 259f., 262f., 271, 273, 282, 284f., 287-91, 294f., 305, 307 Fall, 298, 301 fault, 301, 314 sin, 314
Finite, 24, 29, 35, 47, 58, 66, 68, 83, 85, 93, 95, 100, 102, 104, 110, 112, 116f., 132-37, 140, 142, 144, 146f., 242, 244, 308, 312 finitude, 27, 43, 89, 119 Form (Gestalt, Gestaltung), 144, 219f. Freedom, 39, 46, 53, 76, 93, 141ff., 189, 249, 267, 275f., 291, 294, 314, 321 G Goal (aim), 14, 44, 75, 174, 259, 288, 324 Grace, 16, 294 Grammar, 18f. H Harmony, 315, 320f. History, 17, 30, 44, 74, 161, 299, 301, 314 Humility, 43, 164f., 311 I Idea, 61, 64, 73f., 86, 103, 106, 112f., 116-22, 236-42 absolute Idea, 4, 30, 50, 64, 81, 91, 99, 122-27, 146, 192, 196, 208, 259, 310, 313-19 the Idea, 73 ideal, 64, 82, 101, 103, 110, 112f., 173, 180f., 190, 210 idealism, 79, 129, 176, 207 ideality, 173, 180, 182 Image of God, 40, 151, 312, 315, 317f. Immanent, 6, 87, 258, 300 Immediate, 22, 32, 100ff., 123ff., 136, 154, 170, 176, 289f., 315 immediacy, 71, 118 Immortal, 77 immortality, 191 Incarnation, 140, 146, 191, 220, 294, 299, 316, 319 Indeterminate, 33, 40, 89, 98, 109, 163, 292 indeterminacy, 3, 99 indeterminateness, 160, 163 Individual, 21, 38, 48, 67, 83, 88, 109, 118, 146, 167, 173, 187, 191, 210, 240, 274, 317 Infer, 268f.
inference, 60, 184, 193, 261f. Infinite, 24, 38, 47, 50, 100, 112f., 116f., 132-37, 144, 146f., ch. 4 (162-202, passim), 228, 243f., 253, 308 the Infinite, 68, 313 infinity (actual), 7, 51, 140, ch. 4 (162-202, passim), 214, 286 infinity (mathematical), 3, 163f., 169f., 173, 190 infinite Being, 4, 33, 260 infinite reason, spirit. thought. (See Absolute) Innocence, 301, 315 Integration, 51, 264 disintegration, 16f., 51, 264, 283 fragmentation, 51, 55, 319 re-integration, 16f., 51, 283, 295, 298, 319 Integrity, 286, 314, 319 Intelligible, 19, 61, 75, 114, 122, 136, 143
< previous page
page_336
next page >
< previous page
page_337
next page > Page 337
149, 158, 183f., 186, 235, 263, 283 intelligibility, 3f., 59, 90, 121, 129, 147, 162, 171 Intuition, 31, 43, 69, 165f., 170, 262 J Jesus Christ, 271f., 292, 299, 303, 316, 318, 322 Judgment, 84, 86-91, 105, 124 K Knowing, 100, 119, 121 knowledge, 29f., 40, 46, 103, 115, 235, 251, 300 L Language, 2, 17f., 45, 60f., 80f., 164, 166, 175, 178, 193, 201, 254, 264f., 283, 300, 325f. Law, 16, 51, 59, 65, 68, 70, 74, 82, 96, 184, 261 Life, 39f., 51, 106, 117ff., 121, 313 Logic, 2ff., 22, 37, 49, 61, 68, 70, 76, 78f., 81f., 85, 87f., 95, 120, 126, 131, 138, 168, 176, 206, 214f., 223-26, 229, 244, 247, 251, 256, 259, 269, 273f., 280ff., 307, 313, 325 Love, 270, 274, 277, 300, 306f., 308-13, 319f., 322 M Meaning, 36, 54, 58f., 61, 80f., 83, 87ff., 101, 116, 162, 169ff., 187, 232, 257, 275, 282, 289, 297f. Mediate, 32, 98, 123, 133, 170, 177, 214, 262, 290 mediation, 62, 70f., 85, 89, 95f., 118, 134, 176, 198f., 234, 322 Metaphysics, 11, 41, 46, 68, 248, 275, 279, 285, 296 Mind, 171, 213ff., 243, 283 Moment, 73f., 80f., 83-88, 91, 95, 97, 101f., 107-10, 113, 116, 118, 124ff., 132f., 141, 144f., 147ff., 151, 156, 220, 242, 257, 302, 304, 329 Moral, 44, 140, 205, 217f., 291 moral consciousness, 217f. morality, 28, 217 moral law, 26f., 187 moral order, 140, 187 Mystery, 8, 203, 205, 265, 278f., 298f., 302f.
mysterious, 2, 5 mysticism, 49 mystical, 287 N Nature, 23, 29, 38, 40, 53, 59, 74, 82, 124, 126, 128, 130f., 135, 140f., 150f., 153, 178f., 201f., 221, 233, 269, 272, 301 human nature, 14f. Necessity, 6, 44f., 60, 63, 65ff., 70, 76, 78, 83, 91, 93f., 120, 136, 138, 151, 190, 192, 199f., 205f., 215, 243, 249, 253, 268, 270, 277, 297, 302f., 309f., 313-19, 325 necessary, 64, 74, 84, 87, 90, 94, 136, 162, 200, 227, 232, 239, 248, 257 Negation, 27, 95, 105, 107, 123, 136, 148, 158-61, 171, 179, 214, 223, 234 negate, 71, 99, 225 negativity, 171, 320 Notion (Vorstellung), 41, 136, 296 O Object, 6, 21f., 28f., 41f., 48, 50ff., 54, 57-60, 65ff., 69, 71, 75, 85, 87f., 96f., 107, 110ff., 118, 121, 132, 142f., 147, 162, 167, 170, 196, 208, 219, 230, 238, 259, 285, 287 objective, 24, 77, 103, 106, 122, 177, 242, 253 objectivity, 82, 92, 95f., 99, 101, 119, 121, 140, 205, 235, 315, 320 Opinion, 31, 34, 46, 73 Opposition, 52 Organic, 118 organism, 67 P Person, 84, 148, 155, 167, 279, 293, 299f., 306, 308 personal, 257, 293 personality, 155, 158f., 293, 308, 321 Philosophy, 11, 17, 28, 30, 41, 48, 53, 59, 72, 187, 199, 201f., 215f., 235, 252, 262, 315 Pietism, 30, 45f., 285, 290 Posit, 83f., 87f., 90, 105f., 108f., 112, 119, 121, 123ff., 141, 143, 149, 181, 188, 190, 193, 214 Presupposition, 3, 75, 77, 79, 119, 122, 195, 202, 295 Principle, 45f., 72f., 81, 133, 140, 148, 228f., 259, 323 Process, 117-22, 144, 151, 160, 226, 259, 267, 286, 297, 302, 320
Proof, 38, 60, 85, 107, 120, 136, 192, 195f., ch. 5 (203-42, passim) Proposition, 76, 87, 89, 95, 105, 109, 162, 192, 194, 228 Providence, 54, 63, 111, 270, 314 Psychological, 67, 87ff., 94 Purpose, 99, 101, 103-9, 270, 314 R Rational, 24, 26, 30f., 38, 48, 58, 62f., 77, 79, 81, 92, 111, 134, 164, 171, 173
< previous page
page_337
next page >
< previous page
page_338
next page > Page 338
178, 184, 204, 209, 226, 235, 243, 252, 272, 284, 301 objectively rational, 31f., 42 rationalism, 5, 8, 45f., 78, 205, 211, 236, 265, 284, 290 rationality, 16, 49, 65, 91, 128, 140, 187, 203, 313, 323, 327 Real, 63, 81, 96, 180, 186, 210, 227 realism, 129 reality, 3f., 29, 58, 64ff., 77, 79, 81f., 85, 88f., 91, 94f., 99f., 103f., 106, 108, 110f., 120f., 129, 136, 151, 161, 168, 174, 179f., 182, 186f., 194, 225, 231, 233-42, 244, 246, 249, 251, 253, 256, 259f., 275, 280, 285, 327 Reason, 9, 11, 24, 29-32, 35, 38, 42f., 48, 52, 66, 81f., 91f., 100, 111, 119, 122, 134, 139, 154, 156, 159, 161, 164, 169, 178, 181, 186f., 193, 202, 205-8, 210, 212, 226, 228, 234, 238, 250ff., 259f., 263, 273, 283, 286, 290, 301, 305, 324 Reconciliation (redemption)(Versöhnung), 298, 301f., 316, 319ff. Reflection, 34, 50, 62, 64f., 67, 83, 87, 94, 116, 124f., 289 Relation (Beziehung), 213, 250, 255, 275 relationship (Verhältnis), 54, 88, 97ff., 134, 136, 143, 149, 157, 177, 181, 190, 222, 233, 235, 273, 280, 314 Representation (Vorstellung), 9, 14f., 28, 34-38, 40, 49, 54, 59, 61, 64, 83, 85, 96, 99f., 106, 109, 114, 134, 139, 166, 172, 200, 211, 215 Revelation, 4, 8, 37, 43, 46, 128, 151, 154, 156, 188, 190, 197ff., 220, 233, 239f., 261ff., 265, 267f., 271, 273f., 281, 288, 296-303, 312, 316ff., 322 S Science, 29, 37, 65, 68, 74, 78, 95, 103, 166, 187, 222 Sensible, 9, 61, 81, 184, 197, 200, 223, 318, 322f. sensibility, 138f. Soul, 110, 118 Speculative, 6f., 10, 17, 21ff., 28, 32, 39f., 42, 44, 50, 58f., 66ff., 72, 76, 81, 99, 101, 106, 108, 116, 123-26, 131, 136, 147f., 159, 166, 169, 198, 200, 215, 235, 238, 241, 247, 251, 253, 255-58, 263, 266, 271, 273, 276, 283, 288f., 291ff., 303, 305, 307, 310, 322 Spirit, 13, 16, 21, 23, 26, 29ff., 39, 44, 48, 50, 53, 66, 69, 72, 102, 114, 118, 122, 124, ch. 3 (128-61, passim), 202, 214, 234, 243, 260, 269, 272ff., 301, 328 absolute (infinite) Spirit: 5, 13, 17, 19, 21, 26f., 32, 42-45, 50, 58, 76, 81, 99, 115, 143, 150, 155, 157, 160, 164, 177, 186, 188, 192, 196f., 200ff., 207, 210, 215, 221, 246, 256, 260, 266, 272ff., 283, 287f., 305f., 309, 312, 316, 324, 328 Holy Spirit, 267, 283, 319, 321f. human spirit, 5, 16, 19, 21, 24, 40, 43, 59, 76, 151, 153, 167f., 171, 183, 187f., 190ff., 200, 221f., 233, 265-72, 283, 291f., 305, 316f., 323
Subject, 87f., 142f. subjective, 24, 77, 94f., 98, 102f., 106, 116, 122, 142, 177, 207, 242, 253 subjectivity, 92, 96, 102, 119, 121, 149, 193, 205, 320 Substance, 15, 103, 136, 141, 149, 152, 155ff., 256f., 299 substantial, 117, 121, 292 Syllogism, 91-96, 198f., 201, 228, 258 System, 17, 19, 22, 73f., 114, 122, 126, 131, 167, 208, 247, 259, 285, 288, 294, 298 systematic, 36f., 126 T Teleology, 103, 105, 107, 110, 112, 120 Theology, 58, 156, 188, ch. 7 (282-324, passim) Thinking, 8, 10f., 36, 46, 69f., 83, 88, 91, 98, 138, 142, 164, 166f., 174, 179ff., 186, 211, 225, 240f., 247, 252, 291 thought, 17f., 26, 50, 82, 100, 103, 115, 138, 177, 186, 207, 218, 228, 230 Totality, 52, 68, 72ff., 79f., 84f., 90f., 95ff., 101, 107f., 113f., 119, 121f., 125f., 132f., 167, 171f., 176, 179, 187, 193, 201f., 235, 246f., 250, 254, 264, 280 Transcend, 79, 82f., 91, 95, 98f., 129, 140, 142, 179, 199, 214, 234, 258, 266, 272, 283, 286f., 312 transcendence, 4, 6, 300 transcendent, 2, 4f., 12, 80, 124, 326, 328 Trinity, 149, 191, 220, 293, 299f., 303, 305, 307, 310, 319 Truth, 11, 22f., 27ff., 46f., 51, 54f., 59, 61, 76, 78, 83, 91, 94, 102, 113f., 121, 145, 156, 165, 175, 177, 200, 242, 268, 270, 273, 283, 288, 291, 294, 303 absolute truth, 42, 44, 48, 57, 224, 285, 322 U Understanding (Verstand), 6, 18, 24, 35, 38, 40f., 43, 46, 52, 64, 69f., 80, 82-85, 91f., 95, 106, 116, 119, 147, 156, 165,
< previous page
page_338
next page >
< previous page
page_339 Page 339
173, 179, 186, 200, 208, 228, 234ff., 248, 251f., 255, 263, 275, 289f., 296, 301, 303f. V Value, 45, 294 W Willing, 119ff., 142, 147, 161 World, 66, 149-53, 250, 254ff., 258, 260, 277f., 280, 297, 313 Worship, 36f., 157, 289, 321
< previous page
page_339