IDEALISM WITHOUT LIMITS
Philosophical Studies in Contemporary Culture Volume 18 Senior Editor H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., Department of Philosophy, Rice University, and Baylor College of Medicine, Houston, Texas Editor Mark J. Cherry, Department of Philosophy, St. Edward’s University, Austin, Texas Assistant Editor Lisa Rasmussen, Department of Philosophy, University of North Carolina, Charlotte, North Carolina Editorial Board Stanley Hauerwas, Divinity School, Duke University, Durham, North Carolina Maureen Kelley, Department of Pediatric Bioethics, University of Washington, Seattle, Washington Terry Pinkard, Department of Philosophy, Georgetown University, Washington, D.C. C. Griffin Trotter, Center for Health Care Ethics & Emergency Medicine, Saint Louis University, St. Louis, Missouri Kevin Wm. Wildes, S.J., President, Loyola University, New Orleans, Louisiana
For further volumes: http://www.springer.com/series/6446
IDEALISM WITHOUT LIMITS Hegel and the Problem of Objectivity
by
Klaus Brinkmann Boston University, Boston, MA, USA
123
Klaus Brinkmann Boston University Dept. Philosophy Commonwealth Ave. 745 02215 Boston, Massachusetts USA
[email protected]
ISSN 0928-9518 ISBN 978-90-481-3621-6 e-ISBN 978-90-481-3622-3 DOI 10.1007/978-90-481-3622-3 Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg London New York Library of Congress Control Number: 2010935666 © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. Printed on acid-free paper Springer is part of Springer Science+Business Media (www.springer.com)
To say the truth, I am wont for my own part, to regard this work as a child of time rather than of wit. (Francis Bacon)
Preface
The manuscript of this book underwent a rather long metamorphosis before it finally saw the light of day. It was always to be a book about Hegel and the problem of objective knowledge, but it started originally with the problem of objectivity as it develops in the thought of the Pre-Socratic philosophers, in particular Heraclitus, Parmenides, and Zeno of Elea, and then found a preliminary resolution in Plato and Aristotle. The rationale for letting the narrative begin with the ancients was that Hegel saw himself as standing not primarily in a Kantian but in an Aristotelian tradition. As much as Hegel intended to complete Kant’s Copernican revolution, and as much as he acknowledges his debt to Kant (especially in a footnote in the Introduction to the Science of Logic and, later in that work, in the general introduction to the Logic of the Concept), he also sees the critical philosophy as only one moment, albeit the crucial one, in the unfolding of the history of thinking that starts with the ancients. This larger trajectory of Hegel’s argument can be seen particularly clearly in the Three Positions of Thought towards Objectivity in the Introduction to the Encyclopedia. I subsequently convinced myself that my original narrative required perhaps too long a breath to keep the reader’s attention, hence the beginning with Descartes in the present version. I also found that the Cartesian legacy is still very much alive in our contemporary world and that it is in many ways responsible for our cultural and philosophical difficulties. This is the reason why I replaced the original examination of the ancients with a discussion of some contemporary attempts at preserving a viable conception of objectivity. For a further characterization of the argument of this book I may refer the reader to the Introduction. I would like to express my gratitude to the many people who accompanied the growth and permutations of this book over the years. I am indebted to my colleagues at Boston University who supported my efforts so graciously and generously, as well as to the undergraduate and graduate students who participated in my Hegel courses. It is a gratifying thought that some of the latter now teach Hegel in the classroom themselves. I would like to thank my now retired colleague Henry Allison in particular for the discussions we had about the proper way to read Kant. The more intense they were, the more enlightened I came away from them, learning to differentiate ever more sharply between the Hegelian and the Kantian Kant. I owe an
vii
viii
Preface
immense debt of gratitude to my friend Thomas Bole III with whom I studied Hegel at the University of Tübingen under the guidance of our teacher Klaus Hartmann. Our long discussions of the true nature of Hegel’s argument have helped shape my view of Hegel’s project. I also thank the readers at Springer for valuable feedback on the manuscript. A special word of thanks is owed to H. Tristram Engelhardt whose unflagging encouragement helped me keep the faith. I would also like to thank the staff at Springer, especially Ms. Marion Wagenaar, for their assistance in the production and publication of this book. Finally, without my wife’s willingness cheerfully to endure countless evenings with me hidden away in my study this book could not have been written. Some debts cannot be repaid. Boston, Massachusetts
Klaus Brinkmann
Introduction
This book is primarily about Hegel. But the analysis I offer of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit and of his project in the Logic (the Science of Logic as well as the Encyclopedia Logic) is embedded in a larger context. First, there is the muchdiscussed relationship between Kant and Hegel. And second, there is the broader issue of how to secure universal standards of objectivity and normative principles of cognition and action. As I see it, Hegel came to the conclusion that Kant had pursued the Copernican revolution in philosophy only halfheartedly and had left it unfinished. On the other hand, Hegel saw no alternative to the completion of the Kantian project as he understood it. In this respect, he held on to the Kantian motive that it must be possible for concepts to determine objects a priori, if a normative basis for objective knowledge was to be preserved. Hegel based his conclusion on an immanent critique of Kant’s argument in the Transcendental Deduction. The element of empirical realism that Kant needed to retain in order to avoid empirical idealism eventually undermines the position of transcendental idealism and leads to a theoretical impasse. This meant that Kant’s transcendental project could only be sustained and brought to completion, if transcendental idealism was able to proceed without the element of empirical realism, i.e. without a heterogeneous material for cognition given independently of the subject of cognition. For Hegel, the task of developing such a homogeneous conception of idealism, an idealism without limits, as I call it, went under the motto of “overcoming the opposition of consciousness”, i.e., overcoming the epistemic hiatus between cognitive subject and object, mind and world. Although Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception in principle achieved just that, the subsequent introduction of an empirical manifold of sensation invalidates the original unity by showing it to be “burdened” with an “other” or limited by it. The Phenomenology of Spirit was designed to accomplish the unfinished task of leading from subjective thinking (whose measure is correctness or the adaequatio repraesentationis et rei) to objective thought (whose measure is truth or the adaequatio conceptus et rei) and to establish the platform for a homogeneous idealism that moves exclusively within the immanence of thought. If successful, this undertaking would be proof that transcendental idealism in the form of a “pure” idealism remains a viable position to take.
ix
x
Introduction
Second, there is the issue of Hegel’s potential contribution to contemporary philosophical debates and, more broadly, to contemporary culture. I believe that one aspect of our current situation is what I call the crisis of subjectivity. This crisis is the result of a profound insecurity of the individual as a cognitive subject and as a subject of agency, an insecurity that has its roots in our Cartesian legacy. Descartes’ privileging of the individual as the ultimate arbiter of truth represents a major reason for this crisis. Even if Descartes did not inaugurate this turn towards individual subjectivity, he brought out its significance and gave it momentum and direction. Kant in fact ratified this turn while also trying to preserve the possibility of objective knowledge. In this, he had no lasting success, nor did Hegel, for that matter. Today, there is a widespread consensus that objectivity is some kind of social construct or the outcome of an interpretive activity by a particular community of agents. Every community, however, is particularized. It has its own standards of objectivity and its own norms. The problem should be obvious: Without a universal consensus about common standards of objectivity and normative commitments as agents we run the risk of a dysteleological development. On the one hand, the lack of an overarching, universal framework that permits everyone to adjudicate truth claims across different communities encourages the development of parallel universes that may become incapable of communicating with one another. On the other hand, the pressures of globalization contradict communitarian fragmentation and may thus lead to destructive antagonisms among communities. In this situation, it seems, we need to renew the effort to establish a common commitment to objectivity and normative principles across particular communities. Obviously, philosophical reflection can only do so much in this situation. Still, I believe it to be an important task to look again at the roots of the current crisis in order to understand its nature and to examine some prominent contemporary proposals of how to deal with our Cartesian legacy. In the process, I have arrived at the conclusion that past efforts to overcome cognitive and moral fragmentation based on a transcendental approach broadly conceived could serve as a valuable point of orientation. In other words, there may still be lessons to learn from Kant and Hegel that bear on our current situation. As a result, the book’s argument is structured in the following way. I will first look at the nature and origin of the crisis of subjectivity (Sections 1.1 and 1.2) and briefly discuss some traditional responses to the challenges it poses (Section 1.3) in order then to turn to an examination of contemporary positions that have generally moved beyond Descartes’ mental immanentism to an immanence of experience in which the epistemic hiatus of mind and world is no longer an issue (Section 1.4). But because these positions have difficulty securing a non-relativistic conception of objectivity, I suggest that we look at a position that was designed to accomplish precisely that in the area of theoretical knowledge, viz. Kant’s First Critique (Section 2.1). Kant’s argument there defines our ontological commitments by means of the so-called restriction thesis that results from his complementarity thesis. However, internal problems with the Transcendental Deduction that Hegel first exposed in Faith and Knowledge call into question the viability of Kant’s particular version of transcendental idealism (Section 2.2 and Section 2.3). I claim that Hegel’s critique of Kant is an immanent critique, not a critique advanced from a standpoint alien to the Kantian project, independently of the fact that Kant
Introduction
xi
would never have approved of the direction in which Hegel took the Copernican revolution. If Hegel’s critique is convincing, however, the question becomes what it would take to complete the transcendental project successfully. I propose that Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit holds the answer to this question (Sections 3.1, 3.2, 3.3, 3.4, 3.5, 3.6, and 3.7). The Phenomenology, however, is only a propaedeutic in that it tries to prove the general point that thinking is capable of “objective thoughts” but does not itself offer a universal framework for assessing our ontological commitments. The reconstruction of such a comprehensive framework by way of a systematic critique of the concepts that determine our ontological commitments is left to the Logic. In the concluding chapter, I consider first the complicated relationship between the Phenomenology and Hegel’s system (Section 4.1). Next I turn to a characterization of Hegel’s intentions in the Logic based primarily on the 1831 Preface and the Introduction to the Science of Logic and the Introduction to the Encyclopedia. Much of modern and contemporary theoretical philosophy is predicated on the mind-world relationship and consequently on the referential relationship between concepts and propositions and the objects they are supposed to be about. From within such a theoretical framework, it is difficult to appreciate Hegel’s very different immanentist or non-referential approach. I therefore try to highlight Hegel’s concern with the intelligibility of concepts rather than their reference. The difference is one between the “correctness” of my representations as compared to what is the case “in the world” on the one hand and the adequacy or “truth” of a given categorial “take” on being or reality on the other. Hegel’s concern with the intelligibility and explanatory “truth value” of the categorial concepts that determine our ontological commitments explains, among other things, why intuition plays no role in the explanation of objective knowledge and why Hegel’s critical reconstruction of the ontological frameworks that determine our ontological commitments is able to move entirely within the immanence of thought (Section 4.2). (Section 4.3) argues for a reading of Hegel in terms of a categorial theory and in that context addresses the debate about the metaphysical vs. the non-metaphysical Hegel. I suggest that there is a metaphysical Hegel in addition to the non-metaphysical Hegel. However, the metaphysical Hegel, I submit, is not to be found so much in the “esoteric” Hegel of the Science of Logic and the text of the Encyclopedia as published by Hegel himself as in the “exoteric” Hegel of the lecture hall who is reflected in the Lectures and the Additions to the Encyclopedia. In my opinion, the core of Hegel’s thought and intentions is best expressed in the 1831 Preface to the Science of Logic and in its Introduction as well as the Introduction to the Encyclopedia. That Hegel is primarily about the critical examination of the categories or concepts that explain and determine our ontological commitments. The book’s final section (Section 4.4) proposes to view Hegel’s Logic not only as a form of ontological monism but also as an integrative pluralism. As I point out in conclusion, however, the integrative capacity of Hegel’s dialectic has its limits when viewed against the background of contemporary pluralistic societies. Page references to Hegel in the original German are as follows: The Phenomenology of Spirit is quoted in the Moldenhauer/Michel edition, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1969–1972, by volume and page number after the reference to the
xii
Introduction
sections of the Miller translation, e.g. PS § 135/3, 109. References to the German text of Hegel’s Science of Logic are to the edition by Georg Lasson in two volumes, Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1967, following the page reference to the Miller translation, e.g. SL 39/WdL I 19 or SL 584–585/WdL II 221–229. References to Kant’s works are to the Academy edition by volume and page number. However, as is customary, I refer to the A and B editions of the Critique of Pure Reason without adding the volume number. For abbreviations to all other works by Hegel and to works from the history of philosophy I refer the reader to the list of Primary Sources in the bibliography. References to Hegel’s Encyclopedia and Philosophy of Right are by section number only, omitting page numbers (e.g. E § 6, PR § 100). I am grateful to Continuum International Publishing Group, London, for allowing me to reprint a slightly altered version of “The Dialectic of the Inverted World and the Meaning of Aufhebung,” which appeared in The Dimensions of Hegel’s Dialectic, edited by Nectarios G. Limnatis (2010), as Section 3.3 “Perception and Understanding: The Immanence of Thinking and the Meaning of Aufhebung.” I am also grateful to Yapi Kredi Publishing, Istanbul, for permission to reprint with slight changes the article “Does Hegel’s System Need the Phenomenology of Spirit?” that is due to be published in Cogito, a Turkish quarterly journal of philosophy and the social sciences, and which appears here as Section 4.1 entitled “Interlude: Does Hegel’s System Need the Phenomenology of Spirit?”
Contents
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity . 1.1 The Objectivity Problem and the Crisis of Subjectivity 1.2 Descartes and the Roots of the Crisis of Subjectivity . . 1.3 Some Traditional Arguments in Defense of Objectivity 1.4 Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity . . . . . 1.5 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
1 1 7 14 21 37
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
41 41 56
. . . . .
71
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
79 79 100
. . . . . . . . . . . . . .
117 154
. . . . . . .
189
. . . . . . .
194
. . . . . . .
204
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
221 221
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
233 244 259
Bibliography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
267
Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
275
2 Kant and the Problem of Objectivity . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.1 Kant’s Transcendental Idealism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.2 Hegel’s Critique of Kant: The Transcendental Deduction 2.3 Beyond the Matter-Form Distinction: Hegel as a Philosopher of Radical Immanence . . . . . . . . . . . . 3 The Argument of the Phenomenology . . . . . . . . . . 3.1 Methodological Presuppositions . . . . . . . . . . . 3.2 Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal . . 3.3 Perception and Understanding: The Immanence of Thinking and the Meaning of Aufhebung . . . . . . . 3.4 The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason . . 3.5 Methodological Interlude: Overcoming the Opposition of Consciousness . . . . . . . . . . . 3.6 The Internalization of Spirit: From Ethical Substance to the Spiritual Individual . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3.7 Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic . . . . . . . . . . 4.1 Interlude: Does the System Need a Ladder? . . . . 4.2 Hegel’s Paradigm Shift: From Referentiality to Intelligibility of Thought . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4.3 The Metaphysical and the Non-Metaphysical Hegel 4.4 Hegel’s Integrative Pluralism and Its Limits . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
. . . . . .
xiii
Chapter 1
The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
1.1 The Objectivity Problem and the Crisis of Subjectivity In Chapter 1 of Problems of Rationality entitled “The Problem of Objectivity,” Donald Davidson establishes an argument to the effect that thought – in the sense of a thinking activity that makes truth claims about its objects – is dependent on the concept of objectivity (Davidson, 2004, pp. 3–18; originally published in 1995). Davidson’s reasoning is pretty straightforward and it would in my view be difficult to dispute it. I have no intention of doing so; instead, I endorse its basic conclusions. Davidson’s argument runs roughly as follows: To think means, among other things, to use concepts in various ways, for instance in making judgments, attributing properties to objects, characterizing situations or events, etc. None of this would be possible, however, without also possessing the concept of truth, since making statements or entertaining propositions of this kind means to make a truth claim. To think, then, would be impossible without being aware of the difference between truth and falsity, since such thoughts or propositions must necessarily be either true or false (independently of the question whether their truth or falsity can ever be established). Making a truth claim presupposes an understanding of the distinction between truth and falsity, since to claim something to be true also means to be aware of the possibility of getting it wrong. Now to grasp the distinction between true and false statements one must understand the conditions that make a statement true (or false, as the case may be).1 This requirement is stronger than one might think for, as Davidson argues, “it is not possible to grasp or entertain a proposition without knowing what it would be for it to be true” (2004, p. 9).2 In other words, merely to understand the meaning of a proposition already presupposes that one have an idea of the context or scenario in which it would be true, i.e. it requires that along with the concept of truth one also possess the concept of a fact of the matter that would make the proposition true. Thus
1 As Davidson also points out, to understand this thought implies that one also understand countless
other thoughts. He calls this the “holistic” nature of thought (Davidson, 2004, p. 11). as Thomas Nagel puts it, it must be true “in a nonrelative sense”: see Nagel, 1997, p. 5. I will come back to Nagel’s defense of “objective thought” (4) and the “objectivity of reason” (7) below.
2 Or,
1 K. Brinkmann, Idealism Without Limits, Philosophical Studies in Contemporary C Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Culture 18, DOI 10.1007/978-90-481-3622-3_1,
2
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
“to have a concept, to entertain propositions, to be able to form judgments, to have command of the concept of truth” (2004, p. 9) and to understand the truth conditions of a proposition are all equivalent in the sense that they imply and presuppose each other. Furthermore, the concept of truth is indissolubly linked to that of objectivity, since the truth conditions of a proposition must hold independently of whether I or anybody else would like my proposition to be true or false. Or, to put it another way, the truth claim made by making a statement must be able to be judged on its own merits and independently of my or anybody else’s preferences. But that just means that a truth claim must be true or false objectively or “independent[ly] of one’s beliefs or interests” (Davidson, 2004, p. 10). Thus there exists a direct connection between thinking (in the sense of making truth claims) and a commitment to objectivity. Someone who claims to be expressing a thought (in the form of a statement or proposition) commits him- or herself to the true-false distinction and therefore also to the idea of an objectively obtaining fact of the matter. That the fact of the matter obtains objectively means that it obtains independently of anybody’s personal views or preferences. Thus, for something to be true means for it to be objectively true, such that truth is synonymous with objectivity.3 Again, this does not mean that the truth of a statement or the conditions that would make it objectively true can in fact be established for a given statement or in a given instance or under the given circumstances.4 Nonetheless, thinking, in making truth claims, is committed to acknowledging the validity of the nexus between thinking, truth and objectivity. Let me now develop what I consider to be some of the consequences of Davidson’s argument, independently of whether Davidson would have agreed with them or not.5 As I see it, objectivity now turns out to designate whatever must objectively be the case for the true/false distinction to work. More specifically, objectivity designates the ensemble of states of affairs or matters of fact that makes all true statements materially true and all false statements materially false.6 There must be
3 Note
that this rules out that something could be true “for me only” in the sense that the scope of the truth of a proposition would be limited to myself only and could not be true for anybody else. This case is not to be confused with the other in which it could be said that a proposition is true “for me” only in the sense of being specifically about me. Thus, if I am the only child of my parents it is true only of me that I have those parents. 4 For instance, we may forever be unable to determine the truth or falsity of the claim that our current universe is the only one that exists or ever existed, simply because some of the conditions that would allow us to decide the matter one way or the other may forever be unavailable to us. Many of our claims about the past or the exact sequence or causal connection among events in history similarly elude our ability to ascertain their truth. 5 Davidson goes on to draw out further implications such as the holistic nature of understanding concepts and propositions and the primordial nature of the linguistic community: “. . . the acquisition of knowledge is not based on a progression from the subjective to the objective; it emerges holistically, and is interpersonal from the start” (Davidson, 2004, p. 18). 6 I say “materially” in order to indicate that truth and falsity here are not a matter of mere logical coherence.
1.1
The Objectivity Problem and the Crisis of Subjectivity
3
a fact of the matter, so to speak, the appeal to which lets us decide whether a truth claim is true or false. Taken in this sense, objectivity is equivalent to what philosophers and non-philosophers alike somewhat loosely also call “reality.” Hence, some conception of reality must be acknowledged to be valid for getting the practice of making truth claims off the ground. This conception of reality cannot be relative to any particular speaker or community of speakers, instead, it must be a conception of an objective world that is the same for everybody. Following Thomas Nagel’s argument in The Last Word, our conception of an objective reality that is the same for all logically precedes the idea of subjective perspectives within this objective framework. For it is possible to show that the notion of a truth that is true only for me or for a limited community of individuals but not for others is incoherent (see Nagel, 1997, pp. 15–16).7 Indeed, without the presupposition of an objective truth or an objective world the distinction between different subjective points of view would not be possible.8 Furthermore, such a conception of reality cannot be simply the sum total or aggregate of all the empirical sentences that we believe to be true. Instead, it will have to be a meta-level conception of what reality truly is and/or ought to be like. To be sure, such a conception would not be invulnerable; it would remain subject to further corrections or alterations in the light of new empirical findings. But the important point is that it would not and could not be a mere summation of empirical knowledge. The relationship between the sum total of our empirical knowledge and the meta-level conception underlying it would be that of a priori framework and empirical theory, analogous to that of theory and empirical findings. At this point, it is important to address an objection to the argument so far developed. It might be said that while the nexus between truth, objectivity, and reality can indeed be established in this way, this does not by itself say anything as yet about our ability to establish what such an objective reality is, let alone must be, like. Or, the conception of an objective reality might be a mere postulate, conceptually necessary, it is true, but basically empty or, if not empty then at least entirely hypothetical. In reply to this objection I would like to point out that as a matter of fact our conception of objective reality is never empty or entirely hypothetical. We always already entertain some notion of what we believe objective reality to be. In other words, our conception of objective reality is always characterized by certain background assumptions that need not be explicitly stated but that are operative as a matter of course and that are not fundamentally questioned. Such background assumptions are essentially of two kinds, viz. methodological and ontological, and they are different
7 Clearly,
a belief can be held only by me or exclusively by some community. But this fact, if it is a fact, is then universally true. 8 Peter Strawson famously made this point in connection with his interpretation of Kant’s distinction between a subjective and an objective unity of consciousness in his 1966 study of Kant’s First Critique, The Bounds of Sense. While individually we chart our own subjective route through the world, this world is a shared objective world, and without a conception of such a shared objective world the localization of distinct individual routes through it would not even be possible (see Strawson, 1989, p. 104).
4
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
for different areas of theoretical and practical activity. Thus one might point out that there is a common sense view of the world according to which we make certain assumptions about what is objectively the case as we move through this world as ordinary everyday agents going about our lives. These assumptions may include the belief in relatively stable objects that are located in space and time, forming part of events and subject to change in a predictable manner but also exposed to contingent and unforeseeable alterations. They may also include a certain confidence in the general stability of our form of life and the general trustworthiness of others. A certain measure of skepticism would be exercised in relying on these assumptions such that we would never blindly trust either our actual perception or our memory or the assurances of others except in cases in which experience had given us no reason for diffidence. If, by contrast, we look at the world with the eyes of a scientist, we would probably make somewhat different background assumptions about what counts as objective reality, perhaps qualifying many of the ontological assumptions of common sense as relating to mere surface phenomena and submitting ourselves to much more stringent methodological requirements, before we claim that a certain theory about the nature of physical reality had been well established. In general, we are well aware of the fact that jurists, doctors, scientists, artists, religious communities and a host of other groups look at our world in ways different from that of the relatively uniformed layman or outsider. Or perhaps we should say that they look at parts of our common, shared world in different ways. Whether these differences are always due to differences in ontological and methodological background assumptions would be a matter for further investigation, as would be the question, which points of view we would recognize as representing the major conceptual frameworks whose methodological and ontological background assumptions are different enough to constitute a framework in its own right. One might argue that the way in which a religious person, an artist, and an engineer understands the world is significantly different in methodological and in ontological terms for their points of view to constitute separate frameworks. At the same time, there will likely be enough overlap between these views such that elements of the respective frameworks would be identical across different points of view. Alternatively, one might assume that there is a general commonsense framework in which we all participate, and that more specialized views of the world are so to speak additional layers parasitic upon a shared conceptual framework. It is also possible to argue that the overall outlook on the world of a certain era or civilization is guided by a specific interpretation of what “true reality” is like or what truly matters, be it a scientistic understanding of the world or the idea that a certain political or economic system is historically privileged. We need not enter into a discussion of such questions here.9 Suffice it to say that there is a plausible case to be made that different conceptual frameworks exist and
9 Different
typologies of objective worlds have been suggested, such as Karl Popper’s “three worlds” or the Husserlian conception of a life-world. Whether these can serve a useful role in this context would have to be examined as well.
1.1
The Objectivity Problem and the Crisis of Subjectivity
5
that some of their differences are a direct consequence of the different methodological and ontological background assumptions that enter into their formation. In other words, we do not start with a tabula rasa nor with pristine, immediately given data that are untouched by any “addition” or alteration effected by the subject of cognition. In this sense, subjectivity enters into the formation of objectivity from the start. Objectivity is a product of the activities of the subject of cognition.10 Rather than undermining the possibility of objective knowledge, subjectivity, on the contrary, is its foundation. If there is any hope of demonstrating the possibility of objective knowledge, it must involve the active input of cognitive subjects, since there is no objectivity other than as an object of knowledge. Objectivity and objective knowledge are interchangeable concepts. Arguably, this last point raises the real problem. The real problem is not that the subject of cognition always already makes certain methodological and ontological background assumptions but rather that, if this is so, objectivity seems forever to recede out of reach. If subjectivity is in some critical sense the ground of objectivity, then any conception of objectivity seems to be hopelessly tainted by a subjective bias that undermines the possibility of genuine objectivity from the start. This conclusion appears to be inescapable even, once we have understood that whatever we mean by objectivity, it must in any case be a conception of reality generated by a thinking subject. Objectivity is not a picture of reality passively received because, first of all, there is no such passive reception of reality in which subjectivity or thinking has not already actively participated, and second and perhaps more importantly, because objectivity is itself the result of a process of reasoning and reflection. Once this is understood, we can see that this insight has the potential to cause an aporia. An objectivity that is the product of reasoning and reflection seems to be vulnerable to the skeptic’s objection of being viciously circular, since to try to prove any conception of objectivity to be true or genuine would require to check it against another conception of objectivity that is equally the product of reasoning and reflection, and hence a product of the cognitive subject. It almost seems as if the very idea of objectivity carries the worm of self-destruction within itself from the start. The price of objectivity is the acknowledgment of its dependence on the subject’s cognitive acts, from which develops the crisis of subjectivity, i.e. the inability of the subject to certify as objective what it knows to be the result of a subjective process. To use a metaphor, this seems like the expulsion of the subject of knowledge from the garden of objective truth. Systematically speaking, the insight that subjectivity is the source of objectivity is the root of skepticism in philosophy. It has led philosophers past and present to believe that claims to objective knowledge have to be put in limbo. Such claims, they argue, must be qualified as merely subjective. Their truth, if it could be established, would be problematic or fallible. And since something that is believed to be
10 Obviously,
this is precisely the circumstance that Kant acknowledged, but which he thought could also become the basis of an argument in favor of objective knowledge. Hegel took the same approach: see E §§ 22–25.
6
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
probably or problematically true is not known to be true, the concept of truth cannot really be employed under these circumstances. As we shall see, even some of those who try to uphold the concept of objectivity argue that objectivity can nonetheless never be conclusively established such that all claims to objective knowledge must remain problematic. But again, if claims to objective knowledge cannot conclusively be shown to be true, the concept of objective knowledge undermines itself. Probable truth is not yet truth. To be sure, it could be argued that a truth claim that is put forward on the basis of legitimate methodological and ontological background assumptions qualifies as a potential truth. But this only pushes the problem back one level. The issue would then be to account for the legitimacy of those background assumptions and this cannot be done simply by accumulating more evidence based on those very assumptions. This path is circular in the vicious sense and thus leads to the loss of the concept of truth and hence to that of objectivity as well. Such a position is in fact theoretically unsustainable, because it denies the possibility of ever reaching a standard that would allow us to determine how close we got to the truth. To determine the latter, we would need to be able to evaluate a given conceptual framework in terms of its potential for truth, something we can do only if we possess a definitive standard of truth or are able to develop one. What this means is that the legitimate employment of the concepts of truth and objectivity can only be upheld, if we find a way to generate objective knowledge with its claim to universal validity by taking subjectivity as our point of departure, while also finding a way critically to evaluate the potential for truth of any given framework of knowledge and its background assumptions. This is not going to be possible, if we assume that we do not already have access to an objective point of view. We can construct a path from subjectivity to objectivity only if we know where this path starts and where it leads. In other words, we need to work on the assumption that we either already possess the coordinates of our subjective point of departure, or that we will at least be able to discover them once we get out of the woods, so to speak. Therefore, the construction of our path will in any case have to be a re-construction. When Davidson says that “the acquisition of knowledge is not based on a progression from the subjective to the objective; it emerges holistically, and is interpersonal from the start” (Davidson, 2004, p. 18), he must mean just that. The acquisition of knowledge is not based on a progression from the subjective to the objective, if the objective is understood as falling entirely outside the sphere of the subjective and to be beyond its reach. The acquisition of knowledge of the objective that starts from the subjective is, however, possible if the subjective is already part of the objective or of a shared interpersonal framework. The subjective and the objective are on a continuum such that the subject gradually comes to understand its viewpoint as a perspectival modification of the whole while at the same time being able successively to form a conception of the whole itself. It will become clearer in the following section that this is not simply a return to Aristotle’s progression from what is familiar and more knowable to us to what is more knowable by nature.11 The reason for this is that due to Descartes’ privileging
11 See
Phys, I 1, 184a 16–21.
1.2
Descartes and the Roots of the Crisis of Subjectivity
7
of the first person perspective together with the hiatus he creates between ideas and their referents the hiatus between subjective certainty and objective truth has become all the more pronounced. It is the assumption that objectivity must fall entirely within the subjective that has been the basis for the crisis of subjectivity, which, it seems to me, is still very much ongoing and is part of the signature of modernity. We should try instead to see subjectivity as falling within the objective, as an articulation of the objective from a particular vantage point.12 The cooperation within an objective order allows us to come together; the idols of the cave segregate us. In order to remind us of the historical origin and the systematic reasons for the development of the crisis of subjectivity, I suggest that we briefly inspect its roots in Descartes. I will then turn to a discussion of some traditional and contemporary attempts to defend the possibility of objective knowledge. From this discussion I will conclude that even some of the most advanced contemporary positions fail to do justice to the requirements of objectivity and that only those positions that embrace a so-called transcendental strategy have a chance to respond successfully to this challenge. I will therefore investigate Kant’s problematic combination of transcendental idealism and empirical realism and try to show why only a purely homogeneous, idealistic position à la Hegel offers a coherent strategy to respond to the challenges posed by the problem of objectivity.
1.2 Descartes and the Roots of the Crisis of Subjectivity It is not particularly original to point out that the realization that subjectivity grounds and underwrites all claims to objectivity constitutes the fundamental paradigm shift from ancient to modern philosophy. Still, the consequences of this development in philosophy are so significant that it is worth dwelling on this point for a moment. The crisis of subjectivity starts as soon as subjectivity has been discovered as the true theme of philosophy. That this is so, becomes clear in an exemplary fashion with Descartes’ response, in the Objections and Replies to the Meditations, to the mistaken characterization of the “Cogito, ergo sum” as a syllogism that only lacks the major premise. Descartes’ comment is highly instructive, for he argues that the argument could not be a syllogism because the major premise could not be formulated unless one had already grasped in one’s own mind that thinking and existing are immediately connected.13 Without intuitively understanding this connection, i.e. without experiencing it in one’s own mind, one could not know that the conceptual implication between thinking and existing obtains as a matter of fact. I take Descartes to mean by this that the conceptual implication expressed in the major 12 Famously,
according to Leibniz each monad mirrors the same universe, albeit from a different angle and with more or less clarity: “It is not in the objects of their knowledge, but in the modes of this knowledge that the monads are limited. All of them have a confused knowledge of the infinite, that is, of the whole; but they are limited and distinguished by the degrees of distinct perception” (Leibniz, Monadology § 60). 13 Cf. CSM II 100/AT VII 140–141; see also CSM II 217/AT VII 205–206.
8
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
premise according to which everything that thinks must also exist as a thinking being rests on a synthetic relationship between the concepts of thinking and existing. The fact that this relationship does in fact obtain, however, cannot be known without experiencing the connection intuitively in one’s own mind.14 The mind qua thinking being must therefore behold it in itself in order to know it to be true. From its first person perspective, the subject here certifies the truth of a conceptual relationship that is in and of itself universally valid, but whose truth must first be verified by the individual. In this sense, subjectivity underwrites objective truth by confirming that this truth does in fact obtain. Furthermore, for a truth to obtain seems to require that it be instantiated, i.e. true in a given case, and hence true of something that exists. It is thus shown to be true not only hypothetically and conceptually, but also actually and existentially. So there are two reasons why “Cogtio, ergo sum” is not a syllogism: (a) the conceptual implication between thinking and existing must be actively grasped by the mind before we can know that it holds; and (b) we must be satisfied in our own case that it is true, before we can generalize this insight and construct a major premise purporting to be true of all thinking beings. Descartes’ subordination of the third person to a first person perspective based on his argument that subjectivity underwrites all claims to objective truth plunged philosophy into a prolonged crisis. Arguably, this crisis is still ongoing. It consists in the modern predicament of having lost confidence in the possibility of objective knowledge because knowledge requires the active interpretive input of the subject. Hegel reportedly called this predicament the sickness of our time.15 Or perhaps one should say that today the sense of crisis has passed, but the predicament persists and has come to be accepted as the normal, unalterable condition in which human cognition finds itself. My earlier claim that our conception of objective reality is in fact never empty is obviously far from being a response to the skeptical question that can always be raised, namely, whether any conception of objectivity is in fact true and can be demonstrated to be so. In other words, our initial argument according to which we always already possess a conception of objective truth begs the question as long as we are unable to answer the skeptical question how we can know that our subjective conception of objectivity is in fact a conception of objectivity. Before I turn to this vexed issue, I propose to expand a little on the reasons for the Cartesian paradigm shift. First, there is the rupture, purposefully and methodically engineered by Descartes in the First Meditation, between the inner sphere of consciousness with its ideas and
14 This would be a connection of conjoined terms called “res copulata” at Regulae 13,3/AT X 432, which are perceived by intuition or “immediate inference” (immediate concludere, Regulae 3, 8/AT X 370). 15 “The sickness of our time, which has arrived at the point of despair, is the assumption that our cognition is only subjective and that this is the last word about it. But the truth is what is objective, and this truth ought to be the rule governing everyone’s convictions . . .” (E § 22, Addition). I say “reportedly,” because the text of the Additions (Zusätze) was compiled by Hegel’s students after his death. And although the compilation was based on students’ notes and Hegel’s own manuscripts, it cannot therefore be said to have been directly authorized by Hegel.
1.2
Descartes and the Roots of the Crisis of Subjectivity
9
its mental life on the one hand and the objects that purport to be the referents of those ideas on the other, a rupture between mind and mind-independent world, but also a rupture between individual certainty and impersonal truth. We may call this rupture the ontological hiatus between mind and world. All objects, those of mathematics included, are excluded from the mental realm of consciousness, and with the referentiality of any and all ideas in doubt there is no way of telling whether the ideas are true of anything. Note that we can see Descartes’ conception of objective truth emerge at this point: a thought is true, if it is true of an object or objective realm that as such does not form part of the mental realm itself. Let us call this the referential conception of truth. It says that a thought or proposition is true, if it is true of a state of affairs or some objective correlate that exists independently of the mind’s ideas and mental activities.16 Due to the ontological hiatus, the referential conception of truth is in jeopardy.17 Descartes will try to remedy the situation by developing his ingenious proof of the existence of God in the Third Meditation, which indirectly re-establishes the existence of the objective correlate of the mind and its ideas. How little is gained by this rehabilitation of metaphysical realism can be seen in the Sixth Meditation. According to Descartes’ argument there we can only manage to secure an objective correlate in general. Without further assumptions about the causal role of God (e.g., with respect to motion) and a theory of perception, not much more can be said about the world than that its ontological makeup is that of an extended substance. Descartes’ “bracketing” of all objective correlates of the ideas in the mind (and thus of the entire mind-independent world of things and states of affairs), i.e., his hypothesis that none of them might exist, has a double effect. On the one hand, it exposes what is normally overlooked due to the intentionality of consciousness, viz. consciousness’ internal workings. For while we are normally immersed in the objective correlates of our ideas and thoughts, bracketing these correlates makes us aware of the mental sphere as the source and foundation of our belief in
16 It
is worth pointing out that Descartes has another conception of truth as well according to which ideas can be materially true but formally false (cf. CSM II 30/AT VII 43–44). This means that his distinction between a mental sphere that includes the mental life of consciousness as well as its ideas is not parallel to the Husserlian distinction between a noematic and a noetic sphere. Descartes’ ideas as they exist in the mind constitute mental contents – they are, in Husserl’s language, real content, “reeller Bestandteil” of consciousness – but they are nonetheless also noematic objects, since they possess objective reality and are materially true. If they possess noematic correlates, i.e. if they are true of something, they are formally true. However, they may not be true of anything existing independently of the mental sphere, i.e. they may not refer to anything as their objective correlate, in which case they are materially true but formally false. Conversely, they may be materially false and then by definition cannot be formally true, i.e. they cannot be truly predicated of something. Formal truth is propositional truth and concerns the relationship between propositions and mind-independent states of affairs. Material truth concerns the existence or non-existence of mental contents as distinct from the mere sign (word, name) for it. 17 The thought “I think, therefore I am” is exempted from this problem, since the referent, the ego, is included in the mental sphere itself and its existence is thus beyond doubt.
10
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
a mind-independent reality.18 On the other hand, Descartes’ methodological procedure, i.e., his employment of the method of doubt, simultaneously creates the ontological gap between the subjective ideas and the mental activities thus exposed on the one hand and their uncertain objective correlates on the other. It thus happens that as subjectivity is discovered in its role of certifying all truth claims it is also and at the very same time being cut off from the objective correlates that provide the material conditions that can make those truth claims true. That these two moves happen simultaneously therein consists the Cartesian revolution. For it is only because of the coincidence of these two moves that the crisis of subjectivity can unfold.19 While the ontological hiatus is overcome (at least programmatically, if not in fact) through Descartes’ proof of the existence of God, there is yet another hiatus that is not derivative of the method of doubt and the privileging of subjectivity. This hiatus instead concerns Descartes’ view of the relationship between sensations and their causes. We can call this the epistemological hiatus. Based on the certainty that a mind-independent objective world does in fact exist, Descartes can be both a metaphysical and an epistemological realist, but because of his theory of perception he cannot be a direct, but only an indirect or inferential epistemological realist. The sensory relationship between mind and world is problematic, because it is indirect and not based on likeness. Famously, according to the Optics the condition of the cognitive subject is like that of a blind man with a stick in a forest.20 The information about the blind man’s environment is communicated to his mind through a chain of intermediary instruments, and the stimuli that his senses pick up contain an encoded message that the mind needs to decipher with the help of the imagination and on the basis of both empirical research in optics and fundamental principles of physics that have been established independently of sensory information. Consequently, our sensory information is more like a symbolism than a likeness of things and does not give us direct access to how things are. Perceptions represent things but do not resemble them.21 On the basis of encoded information we need to figure out what things are really like in the world of extension. The picture we thus draw of the world is based on inference and is very different from what things seem to be like according to our immediate perception of them.22 It is this epistemological hiatus 18 This
obliviousness regarding the inner workings of the mind was also noted by Locke, who saw that it took a special intentio obliqua to become aware of it: “The understanding, like the eye, whilst it makes us see and perceive all other things, takes no notice of itself; and it requires art and pains to set it at a distance and make it its own object” (Essay, Introduction § 1). 19 That such a gap is not the result of simply adopting the perspective of consciousness can be seen in Husserl who has no need to account for the existence of a mind-independent world beyond consciousness. 20 Cf. CSM I 153/AT VI 83–85; see also CSM I 165–166/AT VI 112–114. Our perceptual condition is much like that of a flight by instruments of an airplane at night. 21 Cf. CSM II 56–57/AT VII 82–83. Locke issues a similar warning prompted by the distinction between ideas of primary and secondary qualities: see Essay II 8, 15. 22 Descartes makes this point repeatedly in the Optics, the Principles and the Sixth Meditation where he warns us not to rely on immediate sensory information (a feeling of pain may have a
1.2
Descartes and the Roots of the Crisis of Subjectivity
11
between our direct sensory experience and the nature of things in space and time that prompts Descartes to caution us that for the most part we can claim only “moral certainty” or probability for our beliefs about the world. He does, however, think that he has found a way to go beyond moral to “absolute” certainty in his metaphysics.23 His argument marks an important bifurcation in the justificatory strategy of philosophers that may be discussed at this point. The bifurcation amounts to a differentiation between the attempt to account for empirical truth on the one hand and “metaphysical” truth on the other. Whereas empirical truth claims remain fallible, metaphysical truth claims are supposed to be true independently of what is empirically the case. They can only be supported but not contradicted by empirical evidence, since they are not subject to empirical verification. Instead, the metaphysical framework delimits the range of possibility for what can count as empirically true by determining the principles in accordance with which empirical objects must behave (at least at a very general level24 ). The distinction foreshadows that between a posteriori and a priori truth claims that is gradually being worked out in different contexts and with variations from Descartes through Kant.25 To understand better what is meant by metaphysical truth claims and their absolute certainty, let us turn to the final paragraphs of the Principles of Philosophy. Descartes there advocates the possibility of establishing a body of a priori truths about the world, a normative metaphysics. From a set of “innate ideas” and “just a few principles” he deduces what he believes to be the fundamental structure of the physical world.26 But he realizes that he can offer no guarantee that the principles themselves are absolutely true. Although it lets everything “fit into a coherent pattern,” the theory may be only “morally certain,” i.e. have “sufficient certainty for application to ordinary life,” but may be “uncertain in relation to the absolute power of God” (CSM I 289–290/AT VIIIA 327). The reason for this is that coherentism ensures intelligibility, but not absolute certainty, i.e. unconditional truth or objectivity. Descartes illustrates his point with the following analogy: Suppose . . . that someone wants to read a letter written in Latin but encoded so that the letters of the alphabet do not have their proper value, and he guesses that the letter B should be read whenever A appears, and C when B appears, i.e. that each letter should be replaced by the one immediately following it. If, by using this key, he can make up Latin words from the letters, he will be in no doubt that the true meaning of the letter is contained in these
source very different from the felt location in our body, the thirst of a person suffering from dropsy should be resisted, the heat we feel is not in the fire, etc.). 23 See CSM I 290–291/AT VIIIA 327–329. 24 Thus Descartes derives the empirical principles by which the coordinates of bodies are determined from general assumptions about the nature of motion and matter (a body is in motion or at rest not absolutely but only relatively to other bodies). 25 For instance, Leibniz speaks of truths of fact vs. truths of reason, Hume of matters of fact vs. relations of ideas. Kant applies the distinction specifically to judgments and together with the analytic/synthetic distinction produces a third type of judgments, viz. synthetic a priori ones. 26 Cf. CSM I 290/AT VIIIA 328.
12
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity words. It is true that his knowledge is based merely on a conjecture, and it is conceivable that the writer did not replace the original letters with their immediate successors in the alphabet, but with others, thus encoding quite a different message; but the possibility is so unlikely<especially if the message contains many words>that it does not seem credible (CSM I 290/AT VIIIA 327–328).
Unlikely, but not impossible; coherence makes truth very probable, because “it would hardly have been possible for so many items to fit into a coherent pattern, if the original principles had been false” (ibid.). And yet, high probability is not equivalent to absolute certainty. So in the end Descartes asks himself what it would take to turn moral into absolute certainty. His answer (added in the French translation):
(CSM I 290/AT VIIIA 328).
Such certainty requires a “metaphysical foundation,” namely, that God is supremely good and in no way a deceiver, and hence that the faculty which he gave us for distinguishing truth from falsehood cannot lead us into error, so long as we are using it properly and are thereby perceiving something distinctly. Mathematical demonstrations have this kind of certainty, as does the knowledge that material things exist; and the same goes for all evident reasoning about material things (ibid.).
In other words, coherence of the theory as a whole together with the exclusion of all other alternatives (“that it is wholly impossible that something should be otherwise than we judge it to be”) would make a theory absolutely certain while working only from inside the theory, so to speak, but accepting in an initial act of faith God’s supreme goodness. Under these conditions, Descartes believes that the results of his metaphysics stand a fair chance of being admitted into the “class of absolute certainties, if people consider how they have been deduced in an unbroken chain from the first and simplest principles of human knowledge” (ibid.). His hopes for more than moral certainty remain predicated, however, on the metaphysical assumption of a supremely good being and the ability to exclude all other alternatives. Not only that. More importantly, Descartes’ hopes for absolute certainty remain predicated on the ability of the epistemic subject to ascertain the truth of those metaphysical claims by relying entirely on its own resources. These resources are made up of the elements of faith in the goodness of God, the natural light of reason (which yields principles such as that the formal reality of a cause must be at least as great as the objective reality of the effect), a set of innate ideas, i.e. a basic ontology, and a number of assumptions about the physical universe such as the nature of matter and the laws of motion (that are ultimately based on assumptions about God’s decisions in creating the world). There is, of course, no accounting for why the act of faith in the goodness of God is warranted or why the innate ideas are what they are. The method for deriving metaphysical truth claims about the structure of the physical universe is limited to “evident reasoning,” i.e. immediate and mediate inference that obeys the formal strictures of the principle of non-contradiction and issues in a “coherent” theory. No criteria are offered for what constitutes coherence, and there is no way of telling whether or not all alternative scenarios have effectively been
1.2
Descartes and the Roots of the Crisis of Subjectivity
13
excluded. The epistemic subject is thus left entirely to its own devices. The natural light of reason, it is true, implies an appeal to a sphere of objective truth, but there is no specific explanation of what kinds of truth claims can or cannot be supported by the natural light. Not only empirical, metaphysical truth claims, too, are ultimately underwritten by the experience of certainty. There is thus no difference in their method of verification. But certainty and truth are not synonymous and can fall apart.27 The interpretation as well as the application of the measures Descartes invokes in order to certify metaphysical truth claims are entirely dependent on what appears to be evident to the epistemic subject. The interpretation and application of these measures is, in this sense, entirely “subjective.” But one may wonder whether there could possibly be any other way of ascertaining the truth of a claim, proposition, or statement than that of a “subjective” experience based on some kind of evidence.28 Does not all believing and knowing trivially involve the active contribution of the epistemic subject? A terminological distinction Hegel uses in the Phenomenology of Spirit may be helpful here. He distinguishes between what is true “for” consciousness and what is true “in itself”.29 For something to be known to be true what is true in itself must evidently also be “for” consciousness, but what is true for it is not for that reason also necessarily true in itself or true per se. Indeed, Hegel’s argument is to say that what is true for consciousness is only putatively true in itself as well, and that consciousness must learn through a laborious process of self-correction that what is true for it is merely a partial or one-sided apperception of what is true in itself – until in the end, the two perspectives are supposed to coincide. Obviously, one of the difficulties consists in successfully making the argument that there comes a point at which what is true for consciousness is no longer different from what is true in itself. Likewise, we need a convincing argument that what is true in itself is in fact knowable from a first person perspective.30 It is important now to put the two basic thoughts developed in this and the previous section together and derive the necessary criteria for how to proceed. First, if the argument of the previous section is correct that the objective is prior to the subjective, then we must examine the possibility of establishing this priority. Second, if Descartes’ point that all knowledge must be certifiable from within a first person perspective is likewise correct, we must find a way of demonstrating how objective knowledge becomes accessible from a first person perspective. That is to say, there ought to be a path that leads from the subjective to the objective and along which 27 As
a precondition for reconstructing the structures of objectivity, Hegel will therefore try to transform certainty into truth in the Phenomenology of Spirit. We will discuss his argument at some length below (see Section 2). 28 Husserl’s phenomenology is perhaps unique in that it is built around the idea of truth as experience (Erlebnis) and the noetic and noematic components that make experiencing truth possible. 29 See PS § 82, pp. 52–3/PdG 76–77. 30 I will take up this question again in the context of the discussion of Hegel’s attempt to provide a connection between subjective and objective thinking (see Section 4.3 below).
14
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
the first person comes see itself as capable of objective knowledge. To what extent current defenders of objectivity are able to mount a successful argument in support of these two requirements is the issue we will investigate next. I will start with an examination of some traditional responses to the objectivity challenge first (Section 1.3) and will then consider some contemporary proposals.
1.3 Some Traditional Arguments in Defense of Objectivity There is a widespread consensus today that objectivity is some kind of construct or the outcome of some act or acts of interpretation. Thus it has been claimed that constructionism is the epistemological position of choice in modern philosophy31 or that there is no reality at all for human beings that is not the result of an interpretation.32 Representative statements to this effect are, for instance, that the concept of an uninterpreted reality as something that exists beyond all schemata and all science completely lacks plausibility,33 that there is no presence [in human experience] of anything that would be absolutely free of interpretation,34 that everything that exists for us is mediated by a system of signs and interpretations,35 or that talk of a “reality in itself” is possible only insofar as it is conditioned by an interpretive scheme and that the objects we assume to be the referents of our talk about the world are only presumed to be real (Lenk, 1995, pp. 85, 248). I would argue that most of these beliefs are probably true, some perhaps trivially so. However, this does not mean that something like objectivity is therefore impossible. Part of the argument of this book is to show how despite the subjective mediatedness of all knowledge objective knowledge is nonetheless possible. The roots of the antirealist attitude just described go back at least to Descartes and his understanding of perception as an encrypted form of contact with the world that results in the epistemological hiatus referred to earlier, i.e., the problematic referential relationship between ideas and their objective correlates.36 Ever since then, philosophy has tried to deal with the crisis of subjectivity as described in the previous sections. Arguably, the history of Western philosophy up to at least Kant and German idealism has been determined by a desire to account for the possibility of objective knowledge despite Descartes’ privileging of the first person perspective. These metaphysical and transcendental philosophies sought knowledge
31 Cf.
Welsch, 2003, p. 280. Wiesing, 2004, p. 137f. 33 Cf. Davidson, 1984, p. 282. 34 Cf. Röd, 1991, p. 37. 35 Cf. Abel, 2004, p. 242. 36 To remind the reader, the relationship is not problematic in the sense of doubting the existence of those objects, but in knowing how accurate our representation of them really is. 32 Cf.
1.3
Some Traditional Arguments in Defense of Objectivity
15
transcending our individual and even our human perspective.37 The metaphysical systems of the past, in particular those of Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz, grew out of this endeavor. It is, however, not difficult to find fault with these foundationalist positions, since they were based on a combination of ad hoc assumptions about reality as a whole (such as that everything must have a sufficient or determinate cause) and indispensable logical principles such as the principle of non-contradiction. Leibniz’ fundamental assumption that there must be monads since without them the unity of phenomena cannot be explained is a case in point.38 It represents an instance of the application of the principle of sufficient reason to a more specific ad hoc assumption about the nature of reality, viz. that it is made up of compounds that require simples, if they are to form wholes. Monads are metaphysical, not physical “atoms,” because physical matter is in fact infinitely divisible.39 This follows from the analytical relationship between extendedness and divisibility. Here the ad hoc character of the argument can be seen quite clearly: divisibility or discreteness of extended things is privileged over their continuity. The continuity or oneness of things is declared to require a metaphysical principle, since unity in the physical is assumed to be a derivative phenomenon. This is not the place for a critical review of the ad hoc character of the basic assumptions in traditional metaphysical systems. It is easy to understand, however, that as the metaphysical realism and rationalist objectivism of these philosophies had been undermined by the Cartesian privileging of the first person perspective, the pressures in the direction of an immanentist position become irresistible.40 Immanentism as I understand it in the context of pre-Kantian philosophy means that we adopt the position of mental immanence, such that anything we say about objects or the world transcending this immanence is a more or less well founded conjecture. Mental immanentism is only one of the forms of immanentism that I will be discussing.41 The other two forms will be immanentism of consciousness or experience (Abel, Lenk, Rescher) and immanentism of experience and thought (Kant, Hegel). We will see that the problem of modernity and the crisis of subjectivity
37 Cf. Kutschera, 1993, pp. 285–286. Husserl, too, was still motivated by this ideal as witnessed by
his motto “To the things themselves!” Leibniz, Monadology §§ 1, 2. 39 Matter is not only potentially divisible ad infinitum but actually infinitely divided according to Leibniz: cf. Monadology § 65. 40 It could be argued that the mental immanentism of the British empiricists is the real successor to Descartes, whereas the so-called rationalists on the Continent tried to salvage a way of doing philosophy that had already been seriously undermined by Descartes himself. 41 I choose the expression “immanentism” deliberately so as to avoid confusion with the discussion between internalism and externalism among antirealist and immanentist positions. Internalism and externalism concern the dependence or independence of mental states from physical (i.e. external) states, for instance in the case of perceptual judgments. For an in-depth review of this discussion see Birke, 2001. He offers a concise definition of internalism and externalism on pages 15–6; see also the diagram at p. 21. 38 See
16
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
referred to above are essentially expressions and consequences of the fundamental immanentist shift inaugurated by Descartes. Mental immanentism needs to account for the possibility of reference to a mindindependent reality and the possibility of making truth claims about that reality that can be verified at least in principle. But how does one do this from a position of mental immanence? Such a position is immediately threatened by skepticism about the existence of a mind-independent world and as a consequence likewise by solipsism, which in turn runs the risk of developing into relativism. To be sure, an immanentist also has the option of some form of internal realism, a position that allows for the construction of an objective world and an entire ontology “on the inside,” so to speak. Indeed, most moderate immanentists will want to defend some kind of immanent objectivity. Nonetheless, such theories remain vulnerable to serious complications to be discussed soon. Before I address some contemporary responses to the objectivity problem, I propose to take a brief look at how the problem has traditionally been dealt with in the history of modern philosophy. The usual traditional antidote to solipsism, i.e. the encapsulation of the epistemic subject in the cocoon of its own mind, is to hold on to something “given”, given, that is, independently of the epistemic subject and received by it either passively or with some cooperation of the cognitive faculties of the mind. Despite its being part of the mental space, the given is understood as coming from the outside, so to speak. It is experienced as something that made its way into the more or less “empty cabinet”, as Locke called it, by way of the senses or, as in the case of the Cartesian innate ideas, by divine intervention. Evidence that this material is subject-independent is often said to consist in its involuntary presence, the fact that we cannot help having visual, auditory or other impressions when we open our eyes or ears, etc., that we cannot will to have them or not to have them. We find the positing of such given material in Descartes, the empiricists, but also in Spinoza and Leibniz, although the latter are immanentists of a different kind that allows them to be metaphysical realists as well. In many cases, contemporary philosophers likewise posit a given, even though they often reduce it to a mere sensory stimulus that has no determinable characteristics independently of the subject’s interpretation of it.42 The problems with the traditional concept of a given material or sensory stimulus are numerous. Sensory input might be hallucinatory or very much like dream experiences and thus caused by the epistemic subject rather than some mind-independent reality. Descartes used these possibilities to undermine any trustworthiness of the senses, thus eliminating any immediate external “given.” He concluded in the Third Meditation that there was only one idea in the entire mental space, viz. the idea of
42 For
Quine, a visual stimulus, as distinct from the meaning that comes to be associated with it, is nothing but a “pattern of chromatic irradiation of the eye” (Quine, 1960, p. 31). Apparently, such a stimulus is a physical phenomenon occurring in the sense organ, one that we do not even perceive as such, since what we perceive is already a sound, say, but not a sound wave, or a color patch, not rays of light.
1.3
Some Traditional Arguments in Defense of Objectivity
17
God, that could not possibly have been produced by his own mind, since its objective reality was greater than his own formal reality as a finite thinking being. There had thus to be a mind-independent cause of this idea adequate to account for its objective reality. Only after establishing the existence of this divine cause was he then able to re-admit the given, albeit merely in the form of an as yet uninterpreted sensory input. As a result, the true nature of the cause of those sensory data could be determined only by way of inference based on ad hoc assumptions about the nature of matter and motion and empirical theories about the mechanics of the subject’s perceptual apparatus. By contrast, Locke believed that there clearly is a given in the form of simple or particular ideas that contain their own independent conceptual information that is not the result of the subject’s interpretive acts but the undistorted and unmanipulated basis for all subsequent operations of the mind.43 However, as Berkeley quickly pointed out, the causal link that is still supposed to exist between the idea as effect and some mind-independent object X as its cause becomes problematic, since there is no way of ever comparing an object with an idea – ideas can only be like or unlike other ideas. Mental immanentism tends to undermine the referentiality of concepts and thus the entire notion of truth as agreement of idea and object. It thus encourages Berkeley’s radical immanentism usually referred to as empirical idealism and Hume’s agnosticism with respect to the external causes of impressions.44 The situation is again different in Kant who makes use of an as yet undetermined empirical manifold that is first structured by the forms of intuition and then further conceptually determined by various syntheses, but that does not in and of itself contain any conceptual information. Kant’s procedure will be discussed in greater detail in the next chapter. The examples so far suggest that not much is gained by introducing a given that comes with or without conceptual or non-conceptual sensory information. From the perspective of mental immanence there is no telling whether the stimulus is genuinely “given”, i.e. deriving from a subject-independent source, or whether it is perhaps the result of the subject’s self-affection. Nor can one really tell, whether it contains any subject-independent information or not, not to mention the problem of explaining what subject-independent information might mean here. Similarly, it is not possible to ascertain that a causal connection between the stimulus and the sensory datum is responsible for the sensory input, since any evidence to that effect
43 Cf. Locke, Essay II 2, 2; II 7, 10. The crux with Locke’s simple or “particular” ideas is whether they are supposed to contain conceptual information or are purely non-conceptual sensory data. The comment at II 2, 1 that the perception of simple ideas “contains in it nothing but one uniform appearance or conception in the mind” suggests perhaps the former rather than the latter. 44 Obviously, it does not follow that Berkleyan empirical idealism is the answer to this situation. Locke seems to have been more cautious when he declared truth to be the result of the comparison of our ideas among themselves, while still holding on to an essentially realist foundation of his epistemology, which accepts mind-independent causes of ideas. Still, the nature of those causes must largely remain a matter of conjecture for Locke.
18
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
can only be based on more putative causation by stimulus. The causal theory operative as a background assumption is a mere hypothesis.45 Hence there is no telling whether the inference to the unobserved and unobservable cause of the stimulus can legitimately be made. Most importantly, if the stimulus is assumed to contain no conceptual information at all, it becomes difficult or even impossible to avoid the conclusion that all conceptual information must, therefore, be contributed by the epistemic subject. What, then, prevents the subject from interpreting the stimulus in accordance with expectations, psychological needs, or personal biases, i.e. non-objectively? After all, Hume set a powerful precedent in explaining our belief in the objective, quasi-scientific validity of the fundamental concept of causation by invoking a psychological mechanism that inclines us to find more regularity in our observations than observation can really warrant. Also, mental immanentism is not equipped to deal with Bacon’s thesis (which in some ways sounds astonishingly Kantian) that the human mind might be like a distorted mirror that in trying to apprehend the nature of things always mixes its own nature with that of the objects.46 It is safe to conclude, then, that the chief problem with these attempts to secure a basis for objective knowledge is the adoption of the position of mental immanence by Descartes. In his Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Richard Rorty characterized this Cartesian shift towards mental immanence as the invention of mentalism and made it responsible for the rise of epistemology as the core philosophical discipline.47 This is an excellent point. And yet, mentalism is only the weakest of the immanentist positions, as we will see, so the story told by Rorty is more complex than he seemed to think. The decision to position oneself inside mental space inevitably generates an epistemological hiatus between that space and a mind-independent reality that has the paradoxical characteristic of serving both as the basis for underwriting truth claims and as an inaccessible sphere outside of that mental space. To avoid the paradox, philosophers (especially the empiricists, but also Descartes) posit a mind-independent given whose genuineness and informational content they cannot, however, reliably establish (resulting in some cases, as in Berkeley’s, in the abandonment of any extraneous given at all). From what has been said, it is plausible to infer that the position of mental immanence will need to be overcome one way or another, if we want to regain a secure footing for making claims to objective knowledge. We should keep in mind, however, that we cannot simply return to a position of direct realism, either metaphysical
45 Apparently,
Locke was unaware of this. Having adopted the position of mental immanence, he nonetheless believes that he can assume the existence of mind-independent causes as a matter of course. 46 See Bacon, Novum Organon I 41: “. . . the human understanding is like a false mirror, which, receiving rays irregularly, distorts and discolors the nature of things by mingling its own nature with it.” Despite this seminal insight, Bacon remains methodologically naïve. For how, if the distortion is constitutional and systematic, could we ever hope to correct our findings simply by more or even more careful observation? 47 See Rorty, 1980, 17ff, 131ff.
1.3
Some Traditional Arguments in Defense of Objectivity
19
or epistemological. Because the active contribution of the epistemic subject in the constitution of objectivity is indispensable, objectivity makes sense only in the form of a conceptualization of “reality”, such that reality is precisely what is conceptualized or conceptualizable. What is thus conceptualized is therefore necessarily of the nature of a theoretical view or framework that is part of the space of knowledge. That space must, at a minimum, include what mentalism excludes from the mental space, viz. the extraneous, mind- or subject independent sphere. It will thus make the objective correlate of the mind an integral element of the immanence, not of the mind but of consciousness or experience. To distinguish between mind and consciousness may at first seem counterintuitive. However, consciousness, at least in its more recent employment in Husserlian phenomenology, but also as it is used in Kant and German idealism, is characterized by two poles, so to speak, a subject pole and an object pole, where the object pole is not “in the mind” and yet in consciousness, viz. as its so-called intentional object.48 Consciousness thus exhibits a dual structure made up of an object-consciousness and a mental space. The mental space contains both the mental activities of the epistemic subject (such as sensing, perceiving, feeling, willing) as well the way in which the intentional objects of those activities are presented and present to the subject, i.e. the way the objects appear to or are given to the subject. Insofar as the mental activities are consciously experienced by the subject, they are likewise direct or immediate intentional objects (such as a feeling of pain). Other aspects of the mental are not direct or immediate intentional objects but can become so in reflection (such as a belief that is suddenly called into question and becomes the subject of doubt). Yet other aspects of the mental become intentional objects normally only through philosophical reflection, such as the mental activities themselves (sensing, perceiving, remembering, judging, willing, etc.) as well as the mediating role the appearance of things plays with respect to our beliefs concerning their “true nature” or the way they “really” are. The mental space, then, can likewise be made an intentional object and thus become part of the object pole in the sense that I can specifically direct my attention and awareness to whatever goes on in my mind. However, to the extent that I do so, I must assume that there is some mental activity I am not simultaneously able to focus on as an intentional object, since it is the activity that makes it possible for me to be presented with the intentional object of my current awareness. This need not lead to an infinite regress, as long as the presenting activity is interpreted as simply the consciousness of the way in which the object is present to me such that the presenting activity itself shows up as a modification of the givenness of the object (for instance, a scene is present as remembered rather than as actually lived through). But then the possibility of reflecting on the mental presupposes a self or self-consciousness that is able to objectify the mental space and reflect on its own activities as well as the way in which the object-world (including the subject’s
48 According
to the Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie this structural interpretation of consciousness was first introduced by Wolff: see HWPh I 891.
20
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
own mental space) is given to it.49 The mental is thus the subject’s inner life that is experienced and can be reflected upon by, and hence made an object for, the subject. The self or I or ego is the source of awareness or the consciousness both of the subject-independent object world as well as the subject’s own mental life. Consciousness, by contrast, is not only a mental “forum internum.” It includes the object world as it is experienced by the subject and as it is thought to be in itself independently of the subject. The subject is also capable of objectifying thoughts, feelings, inner experiences etc. by becoming aware of or reflecting on them. The mental space is part of the structure of consciousness as that which belongs to the subject, in particular the experiences of which one is aware in one’s own mind, but also the “representations” that mediate between the mind and the objects. In this sense, Reinhold famously distinguished three elements within consciousness, viz. the self, the objects of consciousness that are experienced, and the mediating representations by means of which they are experienced. According to his “principle of consciousness” (Satz des Bewußtseins), “in consciousness, the subject distinguishes the representation from the subject and the object, and relates the representation to both” (Reinhold, 1790, 167). This conception already expresses the intentionality structure of consciousness as does Hegel’s characterization that in consciousness one thing exists for an other (i.e., an object exists for consciousness = the aspect of knowing). At the same time, however, what exists for consciousness is understood to exist not only for consciousness but also outside of this relationship or in itself (= the aspect of truth) (PS 84/77). In other words, consciousness distinguishes constitutionally, so to speak, between how the object appears and what it is like in and of itself, and both conceptions are available to it, even though what the object is like in itself is based on how it appears to the subject. After these clarifications we can better see what Descartes was doing when he questioned the reliability of the relationship between the mind’s intentional acts and their objective correlates. He in fact showed thereby that intentionality is a structural, i.e., an essential feature of consciousness – that consciousness is always consciousness of some object or other that is not “in the mind”. His radical doubt concerning the existence of any such object pole turns out to be an artificial maneuver designed to isolate the inner mental space in which the immediate identification of thinking activity and self is unproblematic since, as he believed, no hiatus exists between thinking activity and the subject or cause of thinking. In other words, the intentionality structure of consciousness does not apply to this inner sanctum of the mind.50 However, the hiatus between the mind’s objective correlates and its thinking
49 These
considerations prompted Sartre to conclude that the subjective is just as public as the objective and that consciousness as the source of all object awareness can never be objectified: see Sartre, 1988, p. 76–77. 50 In this, Sartre claimed, Descartes was mistaken (cf. Sartre, 1943, p. 20). For the identification of the activity of thinking and the self as its author requires an objectification that transforms the active self into an intentional object that is a thought, not the activity thinking the thought. Hence the self at the bottom of the activity of thinking always escapes objectification. It remains forever an elusive pre-reflective cogito.
1.4
Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity
21
activity remained a presupposition of the entire subsequent argument. The intentionality structure had to be artificially re-validated as a hypothesis rather than a feature that comes with the nature of consciousness. To be sure, Descartes believed that his proof of the existence of God and the subsequent rehabilitation of the intentionality of consciousness reinstated the object pole of consciousness as a necessary structural element. But then all depends on the viability of that proof. If it is not tenable, intentionality remains a hypothetical feature and objectivity thus becomes a construct based on a precarious assumption. With the object pole an original part of the structure of consciousness, the given is no longer a problem. Whatever is given is now always given as this or that and its way of givenness is distinguished from what it is understood to be in and of itself. What the given is in and of itself, i.e., independently of its givenness, can be determined only on the basis of its being given as this or that. But that does not prevent us from establishing its “objective” nature, just as the scientist establishes the physical structure of our galaxy by interpreting the data gathered about it. The room for radical skepticism becomes very narrow indeed. The immanence we have now reached is what Hegel called “the inner and outer world of consciousness” (E § 6). It is the space of human experience comprising sensory impressions, perception, perceptual and other everyday beliefs, the vast body of empirical knowledge, the experience of art and religion, etc. It is the world of experience in the immanence of consciousness. This is in effect the position that contemporary constructionists and interpretationists generally adopt. How, on this basis, are they trying to reclaim objectivity for knowledge? We will explore this question in the following section.
1.4 Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity The historical positions discussed in the previous section were characterized by an immanentism in the form of mental immanence. They either try to preserve a realist element by positing a given from which some subject-independent information is to be extracted (for instance, Lockean ideas of primary qualities) or they develop into strictly immanentist positions, as with Berkeley’s idealism or Hume’s agnosticism about the nature of mind-independent reality. There is thus a pull towards some form of antirealism built into an immanentist position. In this section, we will be looking at positions for which the immanence of experience describes the limits of the world.51 These immanentist positions are essentially forms of antirealism that do not want to be confused with idealism, although some of them see themselves as continuing a Kantian agenda broadly conceived, that is to say, an agenda
51 In
a variation of Wittgenstein’s famous dictum, Günter Abel states: “The limits of my/our interpretation represent the limits of my/our world and of my/our sense [Sinn],” where “interpretation” means the individual and communal being-in-the-world of a community of language users (Abel, 1995, p. 267).
22
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
with transcendental aspirations, but without Kant’s two-aspect ontology.52 Because mental immanentism has a tendency to reject any form of direct realism, either epistemological or metaphysical, reference to a mind-independent reality becomes conjectural at a fundamental level. By contrast, today’s forms of antirealism such as constructionism and interpretationism generally try to avoid fundamental uncertainty about the existence of a mind-independent reality.53 Nor do they assume that some interpretation-free information about “reality” can even be had. The concept of interpretation-free information would in any case seem to be illogical. Their reference to “reality” is not conjectural but semiotic. This means that the world is directly present in experience as being understood or interpreted in a certain way.54 The world is always seen under a certain interpretation, and there is no reality that exists independently of being experienced in a certain way. This may seem tautological, since the world of experience is always experienced in a certain way. However, the point is that the notion of a transcendent reality beyond all interpretation is thereby excluded, since it is strictly speaking an empty thought. The idea of a reality beyond the reality of experience, i.e., the idea of a thing-in-itself world plays no role. The world of experience is not anchored in some supra-experiential realm outside experience. It is strictly self-contained. Any transcendence is a transcendence within this immanence. The more immediate sources of inspiration for these forms of antirealism are relatively recent.55 We may broadly distinguish a North American and a European, primarily German, branch. The former has its roots in American pragmatism and in a critique of empiricist epistemology that resulted in Wilfrid Sellars’ famous indictment of the “myth of the given.”56 The latter grew out of a combination of Nietzschean interpretationism and Gadamerian hermeneutics, coupled with an interest in the pragmatist and constructionist developments in the United States.57 Major proponents of American constructionism or semantic interpretationism, as we
52 Cf. Abel, 1996, 1995, p. 281. Lenk, 1995, p. 48 expresses sympathy for Kant’s “activist” key idea
that knowledge is “made” (zurechtgemacht) and structured (strukturiert) by humans. He prefers to call his version of interpretationism “methodological,” but is not averse to incorporating elements of a “quasi Kantian transcendental interpretationism” (Lenk, 1993b, p. 608). 53 See Putnam’s famous anti-skeptical argument “Brains in a Vat,” in Putnam, 1981, pp. 1–21. 54 As one of the protagonists of interpretationism puts it, interpretationism is “externalized”; i.e., interpretation does not just happen “in the head”: cf. Abel, 1995, p. 281. 55 It should be mentioned that there is also a highly advanced debate between realists and antirealists in the philosophy of science that we cannot touch on here. 56 See Sellars’ 1956 University of London Special Lectures on Philosophy titled “The Myth of the Given: Three Lectures on Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind,” later published as Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind (Sellars, 1997). 57 For an account of the transformation of Gadamer’s hermeneutics into contemporary interpretationism and a critique of the latter see Krämer, 2007. Krämer calls interpretationism an antirealist hermeneutics: Krämer 2007, 14, n. 6. – On Nietzsche’s theory of interpretation see Abel, 1984, p. 133f, J. N. Hofmann, 1994, pp. 61–90, and Röd et al. 2002, 87ff.
1.4
Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity
23
might call it,58 in various forms besides Sellars are Richard Rorty, Nelson Goodman, Donald Davidson and Hilary Putnam. Leading figures of German interpretationism are Günter Abel and Hans Lenk. However, a word of caution is in order since the variety of positions between, say, metaphysical realism on the one hand and radical constructionism and interpretationism on the other is enormous. Most philosophers who lean towards some form of constructionism or interpretationism because they find that arguments in favor of antirealism and against metaphysical realism have merit, also want to hold on to some element of realism and some notion of objective knowledge. We will be interested precisely in authors who despite their basic interpretationist or constructionist orientation nonetheless try to defend a position that allows for the possibility of some form of objective knowledge. We may call them moderate constructionists or interpretationists. Their difficulty to account for objectivity successfully will prompt us to recall earlier attempts at securing a foundation for objectivity in Kant and Hegel. My primary focus here will be on Günter Abel’s philosophy of interpretation (Interpretationsphilosophie) worked out in a number of books and articles since the late 1980s.59 Abel calls his position philosophy of interpretation in order to indicate that for him interpretationism has the status of a prima philosophia that grounds all other philosophical analyses, even if as a philosophical theory interpretationism is objectively speaking on a par with other philosophical theories about the nature of our being-in-the-world. That is to say, although interpretationism claims to be the contemporary philosophical theory of choice, it acknowledges that it is still one interpretation among others. Moreover, interpretation itself is either more basic than understanding and using language or the latter represents only one form of interpretation.60 Interpretationism is a foundational form of philosophy, because “interpretivity”, i.e. the activity of interpreting experience, is a primordial trait of human existence (Abel, 1995, p. 271; Abel, 2004, p. 151). One might compare it to what Kant calls the spontaneity of the understanding. Interpreting experience starts at a deep level, prior to learning any particular language and prior to what we normally call interpretation, which is a conscious effort at understanding a text or other phenomenon in a new, authentic, original, or simply a different way from the way it has so far been understood. Normal interpretation allows for the distinction between
58 “Semantischer
Interpretationismus” is the expression used by Barth, 2003, p. 201ff. Labels are tricky here since there is also another meaning of interpretationism as a method with which to infer the intentionality or meaning behind actions, a position developed by Davidson as well (see Child, 2003) in response to Quine’s notion of radical translation. 59 See in particular Abel’s 1993 detailed account in Interpretationswelten. The list of Abel’s publications on the philosophy of interpretation is long. For our purposes it will suffice to focus here on a couple of concise article-length statements and his recent presentation of the theory in his 2004 book Zeichen der Wirklichkeit. Abel’s response to criticisms by Graeser, 1996 and Löhrer, 1996 in Abel, 1996 offers useful clarifications of Abel’s position. 60 Cf. Abel, 1995, p. 267 and pp. 268–269.
24
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
an interpretandum that can be described independently of its interpretation, either because it has not yet been “interpreted” or because it has received an interpretation that is to be replaced or superseded by a new interpretation that is somehow more adequate, more original, more intelligible etc. Primordial interpretation, as I suggest we call it, does not allow of this distinction, because there is no difference between the phenomenon interpreted and the phenomenon apart from its interpretation. The phenomenon must be interpreted in order to be a phenomenon in the first place – an expression of the quasi-transcendental status of the theory. Hence the statements quoted earlier61 that for these positions there is strictly speaking no interpretationfree reality. Reality coincides with interpreted reality: “All there is, is interpretation, and interpretation is all there is.”62 Or, to coin a phrase, “To be is to be interpreted or to interpret”. However, interpretationism in the form presented by Abel (and also Lenk) does allow for re-interpretation of primordially interpreted phenomena. After all, if primordial interpretation presents us with basic or primitive data, we need to be able to perform further interpretive operations on them to reach some level of complexity. In other words, we re-interpret what was already the result of (primordial) interpretation. Furthermore, we sometimes arrive at a better or more accurate understanding of phenomena previously thought to be already understood (there can be paradigm shifts, for instance, as in the natural sciences). Consequently, we must distinguish between different levels of interpretation. According to Abel, we need to differentiate between at least three levels of interpretive practice (Abel, 1995, p. 268), viz. (1) a primordial level called interpretation1 that comprises the most basic “actively constructional components” of our interpretation of the world such as basic categorial distinctions (for instance, between thing and property), logical principles such as the PNC, as well as principles of individuation that are presupposed by all other interpretations of experiential phenomena; this level is also called “categorializing interpretation” (Abel, 1996, p. 272); (2) an intermediate level called interpretation2 that comprises the conventions and language games of a particular language, but also the social and cultural patterns embedded in a particular form of life, the habitual and customary ways of interacting with others and with the world; and
61 See
p. 22 above. called “the principle of interpretation” (Satz der Interpretation): “Alles, was ist, ist Interpretation, und Interpretation ist alles, was ist” (Abel, 1989, p. 11). For a clarification of its meaning by Abel in response to his critics see Abel, 1996, pp. 277–282. For the criticisms see Graeser, 1996 and Löhrer, 1996. See also Abel, 2004, p. 242. Lenk finds this too radical a position to take (cf. Lenk, 1993b, p. 53f). He characterizes his own position as an interpretationism with an element of residual realism that is something like a modernized methodological Kantianism, except that it is only a “hypothetical transcendental idealism” (Lenk, 1995, p. 247; cf. p. 250). The option of a residual realism is necessary from a pragmatic perspective (cf. Lenk, 1995, p. 255).
62 Also
1.4
Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity
25
(3) a level of particularized and individual acts of interpretation called interpretation3 that refers to our ordinary efforts of making sense of something, such as trying to understand the motive behind a particular action, understanding the implications of a policy decision, figuring out the use of some device based on a manual, or interpreting a literary or philosophical text (i.e., what is normally called interpretation). It also includes theory building and philosophical reflection and is called “appropriating interpretation” (Abel, 1996, p. 272). This taxonomy can be enriched by distinguishing sub-levels within the three levels mentioned or by devising alternative models of the different layers and types of interpretive acts, although the methodological basis for such differentiation remains somewhat unclear.63 But it is quite unambiguous that the primordial level of intepretation1 functions as a condition of the possibility of the higher and more specialized levels of interpretation. However, while intepretation1 represents a basic a priori with respect to other levels, it is only a necessary, not a sufficient condition of experience. Because experience is concrete it cannot be reduced to the level of intepretation1 or even interpretation2 . In our experience, there is no world constituted exclusively of interpretive constructs generated at the primordial level. Thus, higher and more particularized layers of interpretation as well as theories about the world of experience always presuppose the primordial level and the latter can be isolated from the rest only in theory, not in practice. The ensemble of these various types and levels of interpretation constitutes a holistic practice of interpreting (Interpretationspraxis) that is co-primordial with being-in-the-world as a human being.64 The logical priority of primordial interpretation is emphasized as well by distinguishing between interpreting something as . . . and the interpretation of something.65 Something must already be seen or understood as something, before it can be made the object of another interpretation or a re-interpretation. For instance, a literary text must already be understood as a poem, say, before it can be the subject of a specific interpretation. Generally speaking: Talking and understanding are possible and can be successful only within the horizon of a prior practice of interpretation as well as within an understanding of the world that derives from this practice (Abel, 1995, p. 266).
Thus, within the holistic practice of interpreting there exists a logical dependence of higher on lower levels of interpretation. Now, if higher levels of interpretation logically presuppose and are conditioned by the primordial level of intepretation1 , the question concerning the genesis or 63 Reasonable
as these distinctions may be, they appear in general to have the character of ad hoc classifications. See also the differentiation of levels of interpretation in Lenk, 1988 and Lenk, 1993b, p. 56. 64 Cf. Abel, 1995, p. 269. 65 Cf. ibid.
26
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
constitution of the primordial level naturally poses itself. We will not be surprised to learn that this question can have no real answer. The constitution of the primordial level of interpretation must remain largely inscrutable, because the world of experience is always already an interpreted world. The processes of intepretation1 interpretively construct the object-world as such in its basic ontology, and our reflection on these constructs cannot yield anything more abstract.66 The interpretive processes at the primordial level cannot be objectified in their totality, they cannot be consciously produced and made completely transparent.67 This seems to be a result that is both welcome and unwelcome at the same time. On the one hand, it is consistent with a strictly immanentist approach that must repudiate any attempt to transcend the sphere of an already interpreted experience. To somehow go behind or outside of this immanence would mean to engage in an examination of processes that are by definition not part of the experienced phenomena themselves. Furthermore, it is impossible to tease apart the formation and the material of formation at the primordial level, for this would be equivalent to identifying an as yet uninterpreted X that cannot exist in a theory for which to be is to be interpreted. The Kantian problem of an as yet uninterpreted empirical manifold is thus avoided. Therefore, while the status of the claim regarding the primordial nature of intepretation1 is transcendental in spirit, there is no transcendental deduction à la Kant of the interpretive processes and the rules they obey. Or, in short, there is a transcendental claim, but no transcendental theory to back it up.68 On the contrary, the philosophy of interpretation must claim that (a) interpretation contains an element of indeterminacy, (b) understanding signs is subject to an intrinsic alterity residing in the objects to be interpreted,69 (c) reference is inscrutable, and (d) there cannot be a definitive correlation between sign and meaning or sign and object.70 For these reasons, alternative ontologies are always possible.71 Because interpretationism must reject any essentialist conception of meaning it must also reject any essentialist ontology, i.e. an ontology that could claim to determine the objective meaning of the fundamental concepts involved in the interpretive construction of the world of inner and outer experience. Interestingly, what appeared at first to be a close-knit identity of sign and object is now mutating into a relation of two relata that allow for variability. Due to its intrinsic alterity, the object pole is potentially open to re-interpretation even at the primordial level, bringing with it a variability
66 Sign and object are indissolubly linked together, i.e. they are one. We do not think “by means of”
[vermittels] signs as if using them as tools but “in virtue of” [kraft] signs (cf. Abel, 2004, p. 160). Abel, 1995, p. 282. 68 For the general transcendental claim see Abel, 1996, pp. 277, 281. Abel, 1993, p. 455 prefers not to favor a so-called transcendental interpretationism à la Kant, because it would mean to inherit the problems connected with this type of analysis. 69 Appealing to Kant (CPR B 3) and Wittgenstein (Tractatus 5.634) Abel explains alterity as the possibility that “everything that is thus and so could equally be otherwise” (Abel, 1996, p. 283). 70 Cf. Abel, 1995, pp. 272–274. 71 Cf. Abel, 1995, p. 274. 67 Cf.
1.4
Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity
27
on the side of signitive expression. The ghost of the thing-in-itself does not seem to have been completely disposed of after all. Taken together, all of this amounts to the conclusion that a Kantian transcendental approach or a Husserlian investigation of the noetic and noematic acts by means of which the world of intentionality is constituted are no longer viable alternatives. Nor does a Heideggerian explication of the fundamental structures of Dasein or a phenomenological ontology à la Sartre seem to be admissible anymore. Now it seems easy to say that these would be alternative interpretations of how experience in general is possible. However, if interpretation theory claims to be the preferred theory of the possibility of experience, it simply cannot allow other theories to rank as alternatives. Nor can it simply declare them to be less fundamental than primordial interpretation. Instead, it must refute these alternatives and show why it is the foundational theory. In other words, alternative theories cannot be judged to be mere interpretations, while interpretationism is the only true theory of interpretation1 , unless it has been demonstrated that interpretationism is true. This by definition cannot be achieved due to the principle of alterity or indeterminacy just mentioned. Consequently, theories that do attempt an explanation of the constitutive principles or the possibility of intepretation1 must be acknowledged to be rival theories of the possibility of primordial intepretation1 . They can be dismissed only on grounds of inadequacy or inconsistency. That rival theories (such as transcendental theories, broadly conceived) are still competitors of interpretationism is therefore a distinct possibility, one, in fact, that we will explore below. This raises the question how the philosophy of interpretation can defend its foundational status, if it starts from the relatively weak position that the a priori nature of intepretation1 is simply to be taken as a “given”, whose origins are inscrutable and whose justification is a moot issue. Should we not be entitled to ask why just these basic ontological determinations and no others inform our outlook on the world? Can we really be satisfied with a hermeneutic approach to questions of our fundamental epistemological access to the world of experience and the basic ontology involved in it? Is there no explanatory desideratum that needs to be addressed? Indeed, it seems that a hermeneutic approach that simply declares intepretation1 to be the only defensible alternative must lead to a purely descriptive account of how our experience is constituted instead of explaining why it is so constituted and not otherwise. As Abel himself points out, all claims regarding the truth of our interpretations3 remain parasitic upon the processes of intepretation1 without, however, our being able to tie the former unambiguously to the latter (which function as their “conditions of fulfillment”).72 In other words, not only are higher order interpretive constructs variable and corrigible, their explanatory scope is also limited to interpretive constructs and theories at the level above primordial interpretation. As will be apparent from this last observation, this shift towards hermeneutic descriptivism may not even represent the most troubling aspect of the philosophy of interpretation. For, if I understand it correctly, the inscrutability does not only
72 Cf.
Abel, 1995, p. 283.
28
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
extend to the reasons why primordial interpretation is the way it is, it includes primordial interpretation itself. That is to say, on the assumption that the processes of primordial intepretation1 (unlike those of interpretation2 and interpretation3 ) are themselves largely preconscious we cannot be sure that we can identify and describe them correctly or as they truly are. In fact, we know about these processes only by way of the higher order interpretations2 and interpretations3 .73 In other words, from the way we interpret consciously we may infer the underlying conditions of the possibility of our higher order interpretations, but since the relationship between primordial and higher order interpretations is itself subject to the fundamental openness and variability of all higher order interpretations the results are always uncertain. Claims concerning the underlying primordial interpretive constructs thus have the nature of rationalizations of our actual interpretive practice. This means that primordial interpretation cannot fulfill any critical or normative function with respect to our conscious interpretive practices. As with a priori conditions generally, the practice of primordial interpretation is incorrigible. This is certainly as it should be. But to make it practically inscrutable as well means to deprive it of its explanatory and normative value vis-à-vis higher order interpretation practices. Ultimately, the processes of primordial interpretation must thus be stipulated and posited on an insecure inferential basis. What is thus stipulated can be supported at best by arguments of greater or less plausibility. Abel sees it as an advantage of interpretation philosophy that it avoids both essentialism and relativism.74 Essentialism is ruled out in part by the openness and variability of our interpretive practice and in part by the inscrutability of intepretation1 . Hence, there is no possibility of returning to the “things themselves” and their essential natures. Interpretations remain subject to change, even at the level of primordial interpretation. Relativism, he argues, is ruled out by the requirement that our interpretive practice as a whole must satisfy the principle of “valid coherence.”75 It is, however, difficult to see who would be in a position to survey and appraise the web of vast and multifarious interpretive practices in order to see whether they comply with the requirement of valid coherence. Not to mention the fact that, as we will see shortly, interpretation philosophy allows for a multiplicity of interpretive universes, so to speak, that are not required to obey the principle of coherence among each other. The nature of primordial interpretation also has consequences for the role the concept of objectivity can play within the framework of the philosophy of interpretation. Abel assigns this concept a systematic place within his theory, even though he points out that strict standards of objectivity and truth have yet to be worked
73 As Abel explains (Abel, 1996, p. 274) the processes of primordial interpretation (as well as those
of interpretation2 ) are disclosed through a reflective and recursive questioning that starts at the level of interpretation3 . 74 Cf. ibid. 75 Ibid.
1.4
Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity
29
out.76 In the philosophy of interpretation, objectivity is a function of the forms of thought.77 By forms of thought Abel means structures of thinking identical or analogous to those identified by Kant in his table of judgments and table of categories.78 This, however, does not make the forms of thought foundational in a strong sense. In other words, these forms are dependent on the forms of life in which we conduct our interpretive practices. As there is a pluralism of forms of life, so there is also a pluralism of categorial frameworks and consequently the possibility of alternative ontologies.79 The forms of thought thus lose the universalist status they had in Kant. They are valid relative to a specific form of life and a specific world-view. When Abel speaks of forms of life, the implicit reference to Wittgenstein is intentional.80 But forms of life are concrete historical phenomena that change over time and that can be empirically researched.81 Nevertheless, they are said to be the conditions of the possibility of semantic logic and, by implication, of value judgments and, it seems, of our ontology as well. (I take it that what conditions semantic logic in them is primordial interpretation, not higher order interpretation.) While this need not imply relativism – a charge Abel has been at pains to reject82 – it does lead to a factual pluralism of interpretive worlds (both historically and synchronically, one would assume).83 Whether and to what extent communication among such worlds is possible remains an open question, especially if interpretive worlds themselves should be individuated through differences in primordial interpretation. It could well be that interpretationism leads to a radically monadic conception (more radical than the one described by Leibniz) in which no two interpretive worlds are able to communicate with each other because their interpretive practices individuate separate universes of discourse. This might easily be the case, if there is no cross-world identity of interpretative practices at least at the primordial level. And there is reason to suspect that interpretationism would reject the idea of a common universal interpretive framework on which all interpretive worlds are dependent, since this would no doubt be regarded as a step backwards to an essentialism that is supposed to have been discredited.
76 Cf.
Abel, 2004, p. 169. Lenk maintains that objectivity is a legitimate concept, but that it is dependent on our interpretive framework (cf. Lenk, 1995, p. 246f). 78 Cf. Abel, 2004, pp. 150, 168. 79 Cf. Abel, 1995, p. 274. As he puts it elsewhere, “What ontology one has is a matter of the system of language, thought and, generally, of the system of signs and the system of interpretation that is being used as well as the ontological commitments that are bound up with them” (Abel, 2004, p. 242). 80 Cf. Abel, 2004, pp. 152–153. 81 Cf. Abel, 2004, p. 169. 82 See, for instance, Abel, 1993, pp. 495–507; 1995, p. 283; 2004, pp. 155–156. 83 Cf. Abel, 1993, p. 505. Each determinate, individuated, and specific world [of experience] can be regarded as an interpretive world (“kann man . . . als eine Interpretationswelt ansehen,” Abel, 1995, p. 266). 77 Similarly,
30
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
So the conclusion seems to be that according to interpretationism objectivity is possible within a given interpretive framework (including all the interpretive practices constitutive of a form of life or a world of experience).84 But since there does not seem to be a cross-world identity at the level of primordial interpretation, there cannot be a universal framework underlying all forms of life or all other frameworks.85 This ensures successful communication within frameworks but seems to undermine successful communication between frameworks. Cross-world identity of intepretation1 should be excluded simply because the differences in forms of life that express themselves most conspicuously at the levels of interpretation2 and interpretation3 must have their roots in differences at the level of intepretation1 . That objectivity becomes relative to a given system of language and interpretive practices does not by itself lead to relativism, as Abel has rightly pointed out.86 However, the point is not so much the relativity of standards of objectivity as their factual nature. By this I mean that interpretationism does not seem to possess the methodological basis to show that the interpretive practices within (let alone between) given frameworks are either right or wrong or even better or less good than alternative practices. Abel does make the claim that interpretationism is able to distinguish between better and less good interpretive constructs within a given framework.87 But he ignores that this can work only, if we can answer the question: “Better with respect to what?”. And the answer cannot be “Better with respect to the one we already have”, since, as I will argue below, improvement (or its opposite) can only be measured against a universal standard that is valid for all interpretations within a given life form of interpretive practices. Without such a universal standard there would be no basis for adjudicating the relative merits of one interpretive practice over another. It is, however, difficult to see how interpretationism would go about establishing such universal standards, i.e. standards that would allow us to evaluate either individual practices within a given form of life or this form of life as a whole. First, entire forms of life are not supposed to be evaluated, since there is no standpoint outside or “above” a form of life from which such an evaluation could be undertaken. This would be repeating the mistake of believing in the availability of a god’s eye point of view.88 Generally speaking, reflection on and critique of a form of life can take place only from within that form of life or interpretive practice and is always an expression of level 3 interpretation. This means, second, that any theory 84 „Within
a given system of language and interpretation, the use of predicates is no longer free in an unrestricted way (Abel, 1993, p. 453). 85 See Abel’s endorsement of a plurality of worlds as opposed to a plurality of interpretations of one world (Abel, 1993, p. 505). 86 See footnote 34 above. There is also a diachronic aspect to objectivity such that it varies with time. Abel speaks of an objectivity pro tempore (“Objektivität-auf-Zeit,” Abel, 1993, p. 183). 87 Abel, 1993, pp. 495–496 (endorsing Putnam’s “what we have are better and worse versions, and that is objectivity,” ibid.). 88 Abel insists frequently that such a position is untenable since it denies our fundamental human finitude (see, e.g., Abel, 2004, pp. 25, 57, 324; 1993, p. 497ff).
1.4
Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity
31
about objects and events within a framework of interpretation, whether scientific or philosophical, is likewise an instance of interpretation3 . Thus, all ontologies are interpretive constructs.89 Even the universal claim that all forms of human beingin-the-world are interpretive belongs to level 3 interpretation.90 But instances of interpretation3 are all on a par with respect to their claim to truth (or, for that matter, their claim to plausibility). They can be argued over, they can be said to be better or less good than some other theory, but in accordance with the principle of interpretationism (viz. that everything is interpretation) the question what “better than” means has only a relative, not an absolute answer, because there cannot be a universal standard of adjudication outside or above a given interpretive practice. It thus depends on individual or collective preferences which interpretation is deemed to be better or less good. An interpretation of this kind counts as better for me, better for you, better for us, better for them – but not better tout court. Abel argues, correctly, I think, that interpretationism is not vulnerable to the maxim “anything goes”, because any interpretive system qua system puts constraints on what fits with a given interpretive practice. Violating certain requirements of coherence and compliance with an established practice will result in failed communication. If communication is to be successful (as it generally seems to be), it must adhere to certain rules (rules of formal as well as semantic logic, I assume, grammaticality and the like). As a result, interpretations are not arbitrary. Now, it is indeed reasonable to agree that interpretive practices are generally structured by rules that ensure consistency and thus ultimately mutual understanding in communication. But one can easily see that the criterion of success is a purely formal criterion that cannot prejudge what is materially true or false. Criminal gangs communicate as successfully as members of a religious community. Totalitarian regimes are very successful in communicating their oppressive ideology to potential dissidents. Deceptive behavior would not be successful so often, if the deceived parties did not understand precisely what the deceiver wants them to understand. In other words, the fact that one can make a case for the non-arbitrariness of interpretive practices does not yet allow one to evaluate such practices as better or worse than others. For that we would need material standards with which to assess the rules and consistency constraints under which a given interpretive practice operates. Such standards are by definition universal, i.e. they cut across individual and group practices in order to determine whether what is better from A’s point of view is also better overall, all things considered, or generally. This consideration brings out the circumstance that individual practices are indeed governed not only by formal but also by material standards. What is better for me is better with respect to some purpose, interest, preference, or end. It is just that unless we possess a universal standard, position A need not accept the argument of position B and vice
89 Cf.
Abel, 1993, p. 193. Abel’s comments on the status of the “principle of interpretation” in Abel, 1996, pp. 277– 282, in particular p. 279: “It goes without saying that the principle is formulated at the level of interpretation3 .”
90 See
32
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
versa. It seems that interpretationism has no place for the impartial spectator or the neutral judge. To put it differently, it is unclear how the critical self-evaluation of a given interpretive practice might be possible. Such a self-evaluation would mean to be able in some sense to step outside that practice and to question its truth or validity.91 Clearly, this is not a trivial matter. It ought to be possible critically to evaluate forms of life as a whole as well as the individual interpretive practices that constitute them. If the lifestyle in Western societies is a form of life, we should be able to come to a conclusion as to which practices are compatible with such ultimate norms as human dignity, social justice and/or political freedom and self-determination. It should be possible to make the case that a wasteful economy is objectively worse than sustainable development or that so-called casino capitalism is objectively a perversion of the true function of an economy within society. These are normative issues whose adjudication requires a point of view beyond and above the perspectival standpoint that we normally occupy as “functioning” members of a form of life or as “functioning” participants in interpretive practices. Not only that, but we should also be in a position to ask whether only empirical truth claims are legitimate or whether our current standards of scientific rationality are adequate to deal with the nature of self-referential and self-determining systems, and so on. Such reflective practices are by their nature self-critical and self-evaluative. They presuppose the possibility of universal objective standards of evaluation and thus fundamental conceptual frameworks that cut across interpretive practices or systems. Those frameworks fix our normative commitments in the areas of theory and practice alike. The question remains for now how such a position of objectivity and normativity is supposed to be established without giving up the insight of interpretationism that all truth claims can be adjudicated only from within the immanence of experience. As I indicated earlier, my argument will be that such a position can only be supported by a transcendental strategy broadly conceived. Before I turn to an examination of such a strategy, I suggest that we briefly look at another defense of objectivity and normative standards that embraces a more pragmatist outlook. In 1997, Nicholas Rescher published a book entitled Objectivity: The Obligations of Impersonal Reason, in which he presented a defense of the universality and normative nature of the standards of rational argumentation that underwrite our concept of (cognitive or epistemic) objectivity.92 Rationality is an expression of impartial reason, Rescher claims, and as such it is “inherently ‘objective’.”93 Different cultures have “different objectives,” “different problem-solving techniques” and perhaps “a different thought-style and intellectual ethos, but not a different rationality” (Rescher, 1997, p. 29). The standards of rationality and thus the standards of
91 Abel
claims that forms of life are neither true nor false. I am not so sure. It depends to some extent what exactly a form of life is meant to include or exclude. Is a civilization that causes global warming a form of life? 92 Rescher, 1997, p. 9: “Objectivity . . . pivots on rationality.” 93 Cf. Rescher, 1997, p. 3.
1.4
Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity
33
objectivity are valid across cultures and, I might add, across life-worlds and interpretive practices. Nor are these standards relative to gender or social class, just as they are not dependent on the consensus of a group or community. On the contrary, consensus depends on rationality such that rationality determines what constitutes a meaningful consensus.94 In short, there exists a close conceptual nexus between the objectivity of claims to knowledge and the universal and normative standards of rationality that underwrite them. Claims are objective because they are based on principles of argumentation, justification, and evidentiation that are governed by the “demands of reason”. What those demands are can be circumscribed in a general way by referring to our best practices of cogent reasoning and argumentation or to principles of reasonableness that would be recognized by “sensible people at large . . . as being appropriate in the circumstances” (Rescher, 1997, p. 45). Rescher makes the interesting point that these practices and standards are always embedded in the “thought-framework” that “we actually accept” (Rescher, 1997, p. 59). We have no other way of assessing competing truth claims than “to do so from the perspective of our own cognitive posture – our own cognitive position and point of view” (Rescher, 1997, p. 60). To embrace this “perspectival stance” (Rescher, 1997, p. 58) does not prevent us from affirming the universality and normative character of our standards of objectivity or their superiority over other standards. The rationale behind this assertion is that the adequacy of the standards we embrace will have to be assessed “with reference to [other] standards of some sort.” However, “in this world we are never totally bereft of such a basis.”95 In other words, Rescher’s cognitive particularism, as we might call it, is designed to eschew the charge of advocating an absolutist God’s-eye point of view. Our evaluative frameworks are concretely situated without thereby becoming merely subjective or parochial. His defense of cognitive objectivity accommodates our perspectival stance without ceding ground to some strong form of relativism. In his insistence on the universality of reason as well as human finitude his position seems close to Kant’s. It allows him to question the validity of statements like the following that argue for the impossibility of an impartial universal rationality and in favor of relativism: [All] those cognitive concepts that philosophers have taken to be the most fundamental – whether it be the concept of rationality, truth, reality, right, the good, or norms – all such concepts must be understood as relative to a specific conceptual scheme, theoretical framework, paradigm, form of life, society, or culture, [since] there is no one single framework or single metalanguage by which we can rationally adjudicate or universally evaluate the competing claims of alternative paradigms.96
This sounds very much like the position defended by Abel even though Abel, as we saw, rejects the charge of relativism. Rescher’s claim that we do possess
94 Cf.
Rescher, 1997, p. 39, pp. 45–48. Rescher, 1997, p. 59f. 96 Quoted in Rescher, 1997, 59 from Bernstein, 1983, p. 8. Bernstein offers this as a description of relativism, but does not embrace relativism himself. 95 Cf.
34
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
such a single framework in the evaluative standards we actually accept seems to me successfully to undercut this cognitive monadicism even while allowing for the situatedness of our cognitive stance. Cognitive (or epistemic) objectivity is a crucial element in all interpersonal communicative settings, because it ensures that we communicate in and about a common shared world.97 This would obviously be acceptable from an interpretationist point of view as well, except that any common shared world would then have to be limited to a specific form of life or shared interpretive practice. For Rescher, the shared world potentially stretches across all particular interpretive schemes.98 Human cognition and interpersonal communication inevitably and spontaneously aim at establishing “an objective order of reality” (Rescher, 1997, p. 82). However, in what perhaps constitutes the pivotal juncture of his overall argument, Rescher makes the point that there is a “significant and substantial difference between a true or correct statement or contention on the one hand, and a true or correct conception on the other” (Rescher, 1997, p. 89). The reason is that for a statement or truth claim to be correct, we “merely need to get one particular fact about it right.” But to have a true conception of something, we must “get all of the important facts about it right.”99 But to get all of the important or essential facts about something (let alone the world as a whole) right, is impossible given the limitations of human knowledge. Our knowledge remains forever corrigible and incomplete. In other words, there is a gap between the validly derived and substantiated claims to objective truth and the conceptions of the nature of reality based on them on the one hand, and the real or objective order of things on the other. Employing a version of the argument from finitude, Rescher insists on the “cognitive opacity of real things,” (Rescher, 1997, p. 101) such that reality always outruns our capacity to exhaust all its aspects or its essential nature. Consequently, our conception of the objective order of things systematically falls short of that objective order itself, a feature of our knowledge that calls for “epistemic modesty” (Rescher, 1997, p. 90)100 Much like Sartre in the Introduction to Being and Nothingness, Rescher interprets the inexhaustibility of the determinations of the real as a sign of the mind-independent existence of reality. The latter is not inferred from observation or experience but instead serves as a necessary presupposition of empirical inquiry, like a postulate of reason:
97 Cf.
Rescher, 1997, p. 86. ibid. 99 Ibid. Rescher illustrates this distinction with reference to the fact that, for instance, Anaximander made a number of individual statements about the sun that were correct (such as that the sun’s light is brighter than the moon’s, or that its circumference is much larger than that of the earth, etc.), but that his conception of the sun (“as the flaming spoke of a great wheel of fire encircling the earth”) was “totally wrong” (ibid.). One could say that Anaximander was in error about the true nature of the sun, but that that did not prevent him from getting some of its phenomenal features right. 100 Cf. Rescher, 1997, p. 118: “In this world of imperfect inquirers reality is not always and inevitably on the side of the strongest arguments. Heeding the call of reason, constructive though it is, affords no categorical guarantees of success, only the reassurance of having made the best rational bet . . ..” 98 Cf.
1.4
Some Contemporary Defenses of Objectivity
35
. . . the usually accepted view . . . holds that the success of epistemic objectivity grounds the acceptance of ontological objectivity by way of an inductive inference to the best explanation. . . . By contrast, the present position takes the line that the success of the inquiry processes that we base on the supposition of epistemic objectivity retro-validates this initial postulation (presumption) of ontological objectivity by way of a pragmatic justification. On this basis, ontological objectivity has the status of a postulate validated by its functional efficacy (Rescher, 1997, p. 110).
As a postulate, however, ontological objectivity prevents us from conflating our conception of the real order of things with the real order of things. It thus keeps the space of inquiry open. The fact that we seem to make progress in our scientific investigations without ever reaching the point of saturation attests to the inexhaustibility of the real (and hence its independent existence) as well as the fundamental limitations of human knowledge. As will be apparent from this sketch of his argument, Rescher’s defense of ontological objectivity represents an endorsement of realism within the overall immanence of experience. As with Descartes, however, this kind of realism is limited to the stipulation of a mind-independent reality in general. (To be sure, unlike Descartes Rescher does not need a proof of the existence of God to support the stipulation.) And because of its status as a functional postulate, the endorsement of a mind-independent reality is not an argument in favor of direct realism. We subscribe to it on the grounds that it makes inquiry possible.101 Its justification is not based on evidence but instead on pragmatist grounds: Given that the existence of such a domain [of mind-independent reality] is not a product of empirical inquiry but a precondition for it, its acceptance has to be validated in the manner appropriate for postulates and prejudgments of any sort, namely in terms of its prospective utility (Rescher, 1997, p. 111).102
In sum, universal and normative standards of rationality ensure cognitive or epistemic objectivity, i.e. the objectivity of claims to truth based on which we develop conceptions of the objective order of things that remain fallible and corrigible and that are predicated on the distinction between how things really are and how we think or believe they really are (= ontological objectivity). Our conceptions, while subjective, are so only in the sense of being human and therefore subject to the limitations of human cognition. They are not subjective in the idiosyncratic sense. Because they are supposed to be based on standards of rational justification they are objective and normative despite being corrigible. Under ideal circumstances, epistemic objectivity would ensure the (definitive) truth of our claims to knowledge and thus at the same time generate a comprehensive understanding of how things really are. That is to say, under ideal circumstances, the difference between epistemic and ontological truth would fall away. Rescher believes that to postulate this
101 Hence
Rescher also refers to it as “a transcendental argument of sorts” (Rescher, 1997, p. 109; cf. p. 115). 102 Cf. Rescher, 1997, p. 114.
36
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
idealization is not only possible, but “inescapable,” since the possibility of making true statements, i.e. statements that agree with what is the case, depends on it: . . . the concept of truth is inseparably bound to the ideal of adaequatio ad rem. . . . This postulation . . . is an indispensable requisite for our standard conceptual scheme with respect to inquiry, cognition, and discourse. In the end, our commitment to ontological objectivity rests on the idealistic foundation of a mind-projected postulation whose validation is . . . functional and pragmatic (Rescher, 1997, p. 115).
The idealization Rescher speaks of means that “in ideal cognitive circumstances ideally rational people will (ex hypothesi) arrive at the truth” (ibid.). Under these circumstances, cognitive or epistemic objectivity would coincide with ontological objectivity. But note that for Rescher this is a postulate, hence his position is not one of metaphysical realism or absolute objectivism. One might instead call it a “fallibilistic objectivism”103 supported by a pragmatist outlook. Rescher’s defense of cognitive and ontological objectivity is interesting and instructive, because it defends the universality of rationality while rejecting metaphysical realism and adopting the position of the immanence of experience. It is therefore in no danger of being accused of advocating a God’s-eye point of view despite its insistence on universal and normative standards. The problem of making empirical truth claims possible within the context of the immanence of experience, where there is no way of simply comparing bare, uninterpreted facts with statements about them, is solved in an interesting way. The indispensable distinction – and thus also the possible agreement – between facts and truth claims is maintained by employing both a coherence and a correspondence model of truth. While cognitive objectivity operates under the coherence model, ontological objectivity introduces a gap between our conception of the objective order of things and that objective order itself. But unlike positions in the tradition of metaphysical realism Rescher does not view the objective order as an actual order existing independently of the sphere of the immanence of experience, but rather as a regulative idea projecting the ideal of the sum total of all true facts. Despite its interesting features, Rescher’s position has its weaknesses. First among them is the fact that the postulated ontological objectivity must remain entirely indeterminate, since all ontologically determinate structures are by definition part of our conceptions of the objective order (and hence fallible and corrigible). The concept of ontological objectivity cannot therefore have any real corrective function, and correspondence itself remains an unfulfilled postulate. There is thus no point at which we could say that “we got it right”. This leads to the other serious challenge this position faces, namely the impossibility of validating pragmatically either our standards of rationality or our conceptions of the objective order of things. As I argued earlier, a framework or conceptual scheme cannot be validated by adding more evidence in its support, since the evidence itself must be selected on the basis of that very scheme. In other words, ontological conceptions or conceptual frameworks remain hypothetical throughout and truth becomes elusive. 103 I
borrow this expression from Bernstein, 1983, p. 12f.
1.5
Conclusions
37
Abel, in defending interpretationism against the realist objection that not everything can be interpretation, points out that “the objectivity of empirical experience cannot be based (begründet) on empirical experience,” and that having recourse to empirical experience “does not furnish an argument in favor of non-interpretive realism” (Abel, 1996, p. 283). In this Abel is undoubtedly right, even if I do not see how he himself escapes the consequences of this argument. As we saw, interpretationism grounds objectivity in forms of thought that are embedded in forms of life, which in turn are incapable of validation in a strongly objective or normative sense. Accordingly, rather than searching for a method with which to try to justify the objectivity of empirical experience, Abel ends up referring to the “alterity” of experience in which “everything that is this and so could also be otherwise” (ibid.). Quoting Wittgenstein, he agrees that “no part of our experience is also a priori” (ibid.).104 And yet it is quite obvious what kind of method would be required to validate the objectivity of empirical experience, namely, a transcendental method of some sort such as the one developed by Kant that is based on the idea that there are a priori, i.e. not empirically derived or derivable, structures of subjectivity that determine the scope and basic elements of our experience universally and necessarily. So unless we undertake, once again, a critical review of Kant’s procedure, the question of whether or not objectivity can be grounded in something other than empirical experience has not received a satisfactory answer.
1.5 Conclusions The Cartesian turn towards subjectivity was neither merely the result of autobiographical circumstances nor merely the outcome of the attempt to solve a particular problem. As Descartes puts it at the beginning of the First Meditation, he felt the need, “some years ago,” . . . once in the course of my life to demolish everything completely and start again right from the foundations if I wanted to establish anything at all in the sciences that was stable and likely to last (CSM II 12/AT VII 17).
The challenge of “starting right from the foundations” could have been met in a number of ways. That Descartes chose certainty or indubitability as his standard of truth reveals the “personal” nature of his project. Truth claims need to be certified and endorsed by the individual in order to be recognized as truths. A truth or truth claim that has not been certified and endorsed in an act of critical reflection is just a thought, a proposition, a statement to which I am not (yet) committed. However, to commit to a truth claim means to hold it to be true, there being no such thing as to believe something to be true and not recognize its truth as having normative force for me. But an endorsement also means that to believe that something is true is 104 The quote is from Wittgenstein, Tractatus 5.634. For reasons I am not aware of, Abel claims that it is also Kantian in spirit (im Sinne Kants).
38
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
equivalent to assuming responsibility for its truth. And to assume responsibility for it is to put the stamp of “certified truth” on it. This is much like signing a document and thereby entering into an obligation. My obligation is to fulfill the responsibilities specified in the document. I vouchsafe for their fulfillment. Analogously, in endorsing a truth claim as true, I vouchsafe for the truth of a proposition and this is different from merely understanding it. The difference consists in the element of taking responsibility for the truth of the proposition, something I could not do without having first reassured myself that it is valid. But Descartes’ turn to subjectivity was also necessary for systematic reasons. It acknowledged the fact that the Aristotelian continuity between perception and natural belief formation on the one hand and knowledge of the first causes on the other had become problematic.105 For one thing, inference to the underlying causes of phenomena relied on the bona fide assumption of an isomorphism between epistemic forms in the soul and ontic forms as they exist in things.106 This assumption could no longer be upheld once the relationship between perception and its objects turned out to be anything but straightforward.107 As Descartes and others put it, ideas in the mind do not resemble, they represent objects. In other words, ideas in some way symbolize objects instead of mirroring them, and the information contained in them must therefore be assumed to be encoded, without our being sure that we possess the correct key for the decoding process. Furthermore, the Aristotelian (partial) identification of human and divine nous108 could no longer be maintained after human reason had been subordinated to divine revelation. As a consequence, belief in the possibility of metaphysical realism had to be relinquished and thinking found itself thrown back to the individual’s cognitive perspective that was now understood to be fallible and finite. The important point resulting from this turn is the insight that the cognitive subject participates in the generation of truth and assumes responsibility for it. We can see why this becomes problematic given the new paradigm of the fallibility and finitude of human cognition. For there is obviously another side to truth – subjectivity cannot make true what is not true in and of itself. What is true must be so independently of my or anybody else’s endorsement or say-so. Consequently, a position restricting truth-making to the individual or even to a collective of individuals cannot do justice to the concept of truth. In particular, a position of mental immanence is unsuitable for validating truth claims that are supposed to hold universally. So how do we reconcile these two seemingly contradictory requirements? On the one hand, subjectivity participates in making truth claims true (or false, as the case may be) and assumes responsibility for the truth through the act of endorsement, but on 105 Cf. Aristotle, An. post. I 2, 71b 33–72a 5 on the inductive path from “what is more knowable to
us” to “what is more knowable by nature”. this isomorphism see Aristotle, De an. III 8. 107 As noted earlier, Francis Bacon even suspected a systematic distortion of our view of the world caused by the mind. Also note that the modern distinction between primary and secondary qualities in perception goes back at least to Galileo. 108 For this identification see Aristotle, Metaph. XII 7, 1072b 13–15. 106 For
1.5
Conclusions
39
the other hand its participation is not sufficient to generate the objective validity that is the hallmark of truth. Earlier, we looked at Descartes’ strategy to account for objective validity from within the position of mental immanence. We have now examined some contemporary attempts at resolving this issue. They work within the broader sphere of the immanence of experience such that the issue of the existence of a mind-independent reality is no longer relevant for them. But here, too, we have run into difficulties securing non-relative objectivity and normativity across different forms of life and interpretive practices. So, on the one hand, we cannot give up the position of the immanence of experience, but on the other this immanence seems to cut us off from the possibility of securing non-relative objectivity for our interpretive framework(s). The solution to this dilemma – and hence to the crisis of subjectivity – seems obvious. Transcendental philosophy as originally developed by Kant is the attempt to ratify the Cartesian turn towards subjectivity while at the same time preserving the possibility of universal and necessary, i.e., objective truth at the level of our conceptual framework. Subjectivity becomes the source of objectivity within the immanence of experience, because it provides a universal and normative interpretive framework from within itself.109 But it does so in such a way that this fundamental framework of objectivity does not need certification by any one particular subject or community of subjects. Instead, objectivity derives from the subject’s universal aspect as a thinking and sensing self. The subject possesses two different roles, as it were. It is a universal transcendental subject and at the same time a particular empirical subject. The latter, while remaining prone to error (and guilt), cannot but move within and understand the world through the a priori forms of sensibility that are valid for all human beings and the a priori forms of the understanding that are valid for all rational beings. The result is that objectivity is possible, at least in principle, despite the limitations of fallibility and finitude. As we shall see, there remains a serious concern with Kant’s immanentism. I am not referring to the thing-in-itself that is often regarded as the worst problem of Kant’s position. The thing-in-itself, under the name of “noumenon”, rather serves to demarcate the sphere of immanence within which all experience unfolds.110 As Kant himself put it, “in experience no question is ever asked in regard to it” (Kant, CPR A 30/B45).111 The problem is not the thing-in-itself per se. The problem is that due to the restriction thesis Kant accepts an a priori framework that covers merely part of our experience, viz. the framework of a causally ordered spatio-temporal
109 Cf. Kant, CPR A 237/B 296: The “rules of [the] understanding are not only true a priori, but are indeed the source of all truth (that is, of the agreement of our knowledge with objects) . . .” 110 Cf. Kant, CPR A 255/B310f: “The concept of a noumenon is thus a merely limiting concept, the function of which is to curb the pretensions of sensibility; and it is therefore only of negative employment.” 111 The problematic aspect of the thing-in-itself becomes manifest in my opinion in Kant’s practical philosophy where it serves as the intelligible character that is the “cause” of the actions of the empirical character, even though it “does not itself stand under any conditions of sensibility” and is to be regarded “as thing in itself” (Kant, CPR A539/B 567).
40
1 The Problem of Objectivity as a Problem of Modernity
world. What concerns me here, quite independently of the thing-in-itself, is that Kant’s immanence of consciousness is (a) too limited and (b) not radical enough. As regards the latter point, the possibility of knowledge requires not only the a priori structures of subjectivity (viz., the pure forms of intuition and the pure concepts of the understanding), but also a material (viz., the empirical manifold). This material is not originally part of the transcendental unity of self-consciousness. Moreover, it lacks all determination. The problem that arises and that, as I believe, represents a fatal flaw in the argument of the Transcendental Deduction, is that this material that is necessary for knowledge can be neither determinate nor indeterminate. If so, the Transcendental Deduction ultimately fails to bring matter and form of knowledge together. As I will argue, Hegel’s strategy in the Phenomenology of Spirit, itself an expression of the position of radical immanence of experience, tries to remedy exactly this weakness in Kant’s argument while continuing to pursue Kant’s project of accounting for the possibility of objective knowledge. It also extends the scope of experience beyond Kant’s restricted spatio-temporal world and thus addresses both of the above concerns.
Chapter 2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
2.1 Kant’s Transcendental Idealism Kant conceived of the task of securing the objectivity of knowledge as the challenge to establish the possibility of a priori knowledge. Not indeed of a priori knowledge tout court, but of a priori knowledge of objects, i.e. so-called synthetic a priori knowledge.1 If there is to be room for philosophical knowledge of the real beyond empirical science, then such knowledge must be possible independently of experience. In Kant’s formulation of the problem in the Preface to the second edition of the Critique: Hitherto it has been assumed that all our knowledge must conform to objects. But all attempts to extend our knowledge of objects by establishing something in regard to them a priori, by means of concepts, have, on this assumption, ended in failure. We must therefore make trial whether we may not have more success in the tasks of metaphysics, if we suppose that objects must conform to our knowledge. This would agree better with what is desired, namely, that it should be possible to have knowledge of objects a priori, determining something in regard to them prior to their being given (B XVI).2
This “Copernican” project – the project of putting metaphysics on a new foundation – revolutionized philosophy by introducing a new kind of philosophy, one that Kant calls “transcendental” (B 73; cf. A 56-7/B 80-1). It is a position that posits the identity of the a priori structures of cognition on the one hand and the a priori features of the objects of cognition on the other. If objects of knowledge must necessarily reflect cognitive structures of the epistemic subject, then an investigation into those cognitive structures will likewise yield the basic a priori features of the object-world. Herein lies the single most important systematic advance beyond the representational turn modern philosophy took with Descartes. As I argued above, 1 For the explication of the concept of synthetic a priori judgments see the Critique’s Introduction.
also B XVII: “. . . either I must assume that the concepts, by means of which I obtain this determination [of objects through representations], conform to the object, or else I assume that the objects, or what is the same thing, that the experience in which alone, as given objects, they can be known, conform to the concepts.” Only the latter alternative can yield knowledge of objects that is a priori. See also Kant’s famous February 21, 1772 letter to Marcus Herz (AA X 129–135, especially 129–131). 2 See
41 K. Brinkmann, Idealism Without Limits, Philosophical Studies in Contemporary C Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Culture 18, DOI 10.1007/978-90-481-3622-3_2,
42
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
the representational turn towards subjectivity had made it impossible to maintain the viability of Aristotelian bona fide isomorphism, which assumed the identity between the cognitive content of forms in the soul and those same forms as they exist in things.3 For Kant, the result was the recognition that neither experience nor logic by themselves could make out anything about the necessary structure of reality.4 Barring the possibility of an intuitive grasp of essences, what was needed instead was a transcendental argument contending that unless certain a priori epistemic conditions are satisfied, there could be no well-ordered world of objects and events for us at all. One may wonder whether it would be correct to say that Kant attempted to demonstrate the a priori agreement of thought and a reality that exists independently of it. Does not his doctrine of the thing-in-itself famously deny the possibility of any such agreement? To this one would have to respond that while Kant’s restriction of knowledge to appearances evidently undercuts the possibility of knowledge of objects beyond any possible experience (as defined by Kant), the foundations of empirical knowledge Kant puts in place in the Analytic of the Critique do indeed respond to the seemingly paradoxical task of securing the identity of thought and reality while simultaneously insisting on their complete heterogeneity. Kant’s general idea is that in all knowledge of objects, be it a priori or a posteriori, there must be present an element of something irreducibly given and given independently of any intellectual or thinking activity. He calls this given element the (empirical) manifold of intuition. It is unintelligible in and of itself, and that is Kant’s point. Without the synthesis of the imagination and the unifying activity of the understanding and its (schematized) categories this manifold could never become intelligible at all, i.e. never mean anything. Although already structured by the forms of intuition independently of any conceptualization, it entirely lacks unity and specific organization. One might say that contrary to a conceptualized representation the manifold of intuition is infinitely diverse in the manner in which space and time are infinitely divisible. Because they do not contain ultimate units out of which a given volume or duration might be composed, they are incapable of being unified on their own.5 In this sense, they are unintelligible givens, pre-representational intuitions, not objects. However, if it were possible to argue that this manifold is in need of being structured in necessary ways by the forms of thought, then a case can be made for maintaining that, as Kant famously put it, the conditions of the possibility of experience in general are likewise conditions of the possibility of the objects of experience (A 158/B 197).
This speculative claim about the fundamental identity of the a priori conditions of knowledge and its possible objects does not mention the empirical intuitional 3 See 1.5 above. For a critical assessment of Aristotle’s bona fide isomorphism see Brinkmann, 2003a. 4 Nor, one might add, does the Principle of Sufficient Reason by itself impose any restrictions on our ontology, not even when it is interpreted as the Principle of the Best: cf. Leibniz, Monadology §§ 53–54. 5 Obviously, Kant must resist Leibniz’ argument in favor of monads as the “simple substances” that give unity to infinitely divisible compounds (see p. 15, footnote 38 above).
2.1
Kant’s Transcendental Idealism
43
manifold, the material for all knowledge which is merely synthesized, unified, and ordered by, but cannot in any way be derived from, the a priori forms of intuition and thought. (Nor does it mention the pure sensible manifold that Kant needs to introduce in order to explain the a priori validity of mathematics.) Nonetheless, it is only by positing the existence of a pre-representational sensible material existing independently of understanding and sensibility that Kant is able to bring off the otherwise impossible feat of determining objects of cognition prior to their being given in and through experience. To see this we only need to consider what would happen, if the forms of intuition and the categories were all that the mind contributed to knowledge. In that case, the a priori forms of cognition would have to be applied directly to representations. Now it may actually be the case that Kant was occasionally tempted to view the matter in this way.6 But it must also have occurred to him that his transcendental approach implies that there can hardly be objects (Gegenstände) existing prior to, i.e. independently of, the objectivity structures put in place by the various acts of synthesis and schematization. Indeed, for there to be an empirical sensible manifold it seems that there would need to be empirical objects first. The very distinction between empirical object and a sensation or empirical representation of it can arise only on the basis of, not prior to, a transcendentally constituted world or nature. Consequently, a direct application of the a priori forms of cognition to an empirical sensible manifold would fatally undermine the transcendental project itself. Before we proceed any further, it is necessary to draw a consequence from what has just been said. This will be crucial for our subsequent assessment of the success of Kant’s Transcendental Deduction (I will limit myself to a discussion of its B edition version7 ). As we have just seen, there are actually four factors that determine the basic structure of the Transcendental Deduction, viz. (1) the two forms of sensibility, (2) the pure manifold of space and time,8 (3) the pure concepts of the understanding or the categories, and (4) the empirical manifold of intuition. This is important, because it reflects the fact that there are two dualisms at work in Kant’s
6 See the peculiar distinction in Prolegomena § 29 between judgments of perception and judgments
of experience according to which perceptions of empirical objects (“The sun is shining, and the stone is getting warm”) may precede categorially based judgments such as “Through its light the sun is the cause of the heat in the stone.” See the discussion of this curiosity in Prauss, 1971, Longuenesse, 1998 and Henry Allison’s critical comment that “the denial of any role for the categories in judgments of perception is . . . problematic”: Allison, 1983, p. 151. I would add that just as the “subjective unity of consciousness,” judgments of perception would clearly have to be parasitic upon all three syntheses of the B deduction, not to mention the transcendental unity of apperception (for the three syntheses see below). For a more recent discussion of this issue see also Allison, 2004, pp. 197–201. 7 It will not be possible to discuss the vast literature on the Transcendental Deduction here. For a good overview of the nature of the problems Kant faces in the Transcendental Deduction and a selection of the more important secondary literature on this part of the Critique see Guyer, 1992 and footnote 2 in Guyer’s article. A lucid and at the same time critical expositions of the argument of the B deduction is to be found in Allison, 2004, 159–201. See also Part One of Förster, 1989; 2000 and in particular Carl, 1998. 8 Also called “formal intuition” at B 160–161, footnote a (see below p. 51).
44
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
argument, not just one. There is the well-known and much discussed dualism of intuition and concept, and then there is the dualism of the form of appearances and their matter.9 I will call these two dual-source models of cognition the intuitionconcept model and the matter-form model. The matter of appearances is the only element that does not possess a priori status and is not already an element contributed by the epistemic subject. Discussions of the Transcendental Deduction tend to overlook this fact, with the result that Kant scholars are often puzzled by the question what the second step of Kant’s Deduction (§§ 20–26) is supposed to achieve.10 The reason for this puzzlement is that the Deduction is often supposed to advance an argument for the necessary interplay of only one pair of dualistically opposed “sources” of knowledge, viz. that of sensibility and understanding, or intuition and concept.11 Sensibility and understanding furnish the pure, a priori forms of intuition as well as a pure intuitional manifold and the categories. That is to say, unlike the categories, the forms of intuition possess, in addition, a pure, a priori content of their own, viz. the pure manifold of space and time. Together, these elements constitute the well-known dualism of intuition and concept. It is generally (and in my view, correctly) believed that the first stage of the Deduction is meant to show the necessary interdependence of these two factors. Another way of putting this would be to say that the first stage of the Deduction tries to establish the objective validity of the categories for all possible objects of knowledge. And indeed, if there were nothing else for the Deduction to prove, the rationale for its second step would remain a mystery. There is, however, a second dualism, that of matter and form, announced at the beginning of the Transcendental Aesthetic.12 It is likewise operative in the Deduction and comes into play during its second step. The second step, therefore, deals with the question of why and how the matter, i.e. the empirical manifold, must be subsumed under the forms of intuition as well as the categories.13 Only with this second step is the Deduction complete, because only then can it be said that any possible empirical object of perception must likewise conform to the categories and the forms of intuition. Without such an argument, the objective reality of the categories would not have been established, and we would be left only with the a priori forms of intuition and concept and the pure manifold of intuition (which latter merely gives us empty space and time). Kant presents the core components of transcendental idealism in the Transcendental Aesthetic and the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique. He locates both the pure and the sensible manifold in a faculty called sensibility, which exhibits characteristics contrary to those of the understanding. While the 9 Cf.
A 20/B 34.
10 For more on this see below. The distinction between the two steps or stages in the Transcendental
Deduction was originally proposed by Dieter Henrich in 1969: see Henrich, 1969. See also Henrich, 1989 and footnote 4, p. 252. Carl, 1998 offers a critical review of Henrich’s interpretation, together with an analysis of the Transcendental Deduction. 11 Allison is an exception: see footnote 41 below. 12 See footnote 142 above. 13 Cf. Carl, 1998, pp. 210–211.
2.1
Kant’s Transcendental Idealism
45
understanding acts spontaneously, sensibility can only react. It must be affected by something existing independently of itself as well as of the understanding.14 Sensibility is receptive, not spontaneously active, its content must be intuited and cannot be replaced by a concept. Its formal structure is spatial and/or temporal, not conceptual.15 In short, both the pre-representational empirical manifold whose source is undetermined and the pure spatio-temporal manifold supplied a priori by sensibility are irreducibly different from thought. While the empirical sensible manifold – whose presence is indicated by sensation – is a heterogeneous element received from nowhere in particular, the pure manifold of intuition – which serves as the a priori intuitional content of the pure forms of intuition – must be supplied by sensibility a priori and independently of experience. We can see here already one of the problems that will plague Kant’s transcendental project. Ignoring the mildly paradoxical requirement that the pure manifold must be passively received and yet cannot be derived from any object, there is the more severe paradox that the pre-representational empirical manifold of intuition can originate neither from the subject nor from an object, and yet it, too, must be “given”. If we simply posit its existence, as Kant did once he had eliminated the “transcendental object”16 and thus the ambiguity that the thing-in-itself might be its potential source, we will have to posit it as something given empirically and yet a priori.17 The existence of the pure sensible manifold is necessary, if only because without it thought – or, rather, the imagination – would lack a content on which to perform a synthesis, and the transcendental unity of apperception would thus be quite empty and idling. The independent givenness of the pre-representational empirical manifold is equally necessary, if Kant is to secure not only the objective validity but also the objective reality of knowledge and avoid empirical idealism, i.e. the reduction of objects of experience to mere mental representations.18
14 So
when the thing-in-itself drops out as a source of the “affection” with the empirical manifold and the pure manifold is contributed by the subject itself, problems with self-affection are bound to arise. 15 By conceptual structure I here understand not only the unity of representations but also their relationship of sub- and superordination (cf. Kant’s distinction between intuitional and conceptual content in the 4th argument concerning space in the Transcendental Aesthetic, B 39–40). 16 Not entirely, though: see B 585 where the transcendental object is said to “give” us the intuition of space. 17 It is understandable, then, why Fichte would draw the logical conclusion and incorporate the prerepresentational manifold as such directly into the unity of consciousness. In Science of Knowledge (the Grundlage) we read: “The intuited, as such, is produced [sc. by the self]” (205) and “. . . all reality . . . is brought forth solely by the imagination” (202); see also Science of Knowledge 201–202. 18 At B 150 Kant claims that the figurative synthesis that operates on the pure sensible manifold or “formal intuition” (B 160, footnote a) produces “objective reality.” If this were so in an unqualified sense, it is difficult to see why a third synthesis (the synthesis of apprehension, B 160) is needed to ensure the objective reality of the categories and to “make nature possible.” My suggestion is to restrict the objective reality mentioned at B 150 to the objects of mathematics (cf. B 147).
46
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
Interestingly, at the beginning of the Transcendental Analytic Kant argues as follows: Transcendental logic . . . has lying before it a manifold of a priori sensibility, presented by transcendental aesthetic, as material for the concepts of pure understanding. In the absence of this material those concepts would be without any content, therefore entirely empty. Space and time contain a manifold of pure a priori intuition . . . But if this manifold is to be known, the spontaneity of our thought requires that it be gone through in a certain way, taken up, and connected. This act I name synthesis (A 76-7/B 102).
Two things we should note here. First, the empirical manifold of intuition is not mentioned in this passage at all. Second, the pure manifold of intuition, as distinct from the empirical manifold, makes its explicit appearance only here, at the beginning of the Analytic of Concepts. It is not discussed as such in the Transcendental Aesthetic.19 The Transcendental Aesthetic sometimes reads as if its only a priori elements were the pure forms of intuition while the content of intuition, as distinct from its form, is there being identified with the empirical manifold or the “matter” of appearances.20 As I have just argued, however, Kant must posit a pure synthesis as a condition of all subsequent empirical synthesis of representations, if there is to be an a priori determination of objects by concepts, and this pure synthesis requires the existence of a “manifold of a priori sensibility” independently of the empirical manifold and the act of synthesizing.21 19 The
pure manifold is first introduced at A 76–77/B 102. It is, however, present as a matter of fact in the proofs of the Transcendental Aesthetic. See also A 77/ B 103: “By synthesis, in its most general sense, I understand the act of putting different representations together, and of grasping what is manifold in them in one [act of] knowledge. Such a synthesis is pure, if the manifold is not empirical but is given a priori, as is the manifold in space and time. . . . Synthesis of a manifold (be it given empirically or a priori) is what first gives rise to knowledge.” 20 Cf. A 20/ B 34. Indeed, in the Transcendental Aesthetic the pure forms of intuition themselves seem to double as pure manifold: “The pure form of sensible intuitions in general, in which all the manifold of intuition is intuited in certain relations, must be found in the mind a priori. This pure form of sensibility may also itself be called pure intuition” (A 20/B 34–35). Later on, Kant suggests that when “you give yourself an object a priori in intuition” (A 48/ B 65) all that exists in addition to the forms of intuition is a sensible manifold. Because, as he explains in a paragraph added to the B edition, the a priori features of an object can all be explained through the relations its parts have to one another. These relations are part of the intuition, which is “antecedent to any and every act of thinking,” and an intuition that “contains nothing but relations” is “the form of intuition” (B 67). The pure manifold here seems to be absorbed into the forms of intuition themselves under the title of “relations”. Also note that what the epistemic subject famously affects itself with is not the pure manifold, but the forms of intuition (cf. B 67–68). 21 I take it that this “manifold of a priori sensibility” is the same as the “manifold of a priori sensible intuition” at B 150, which is there said to be the object of the figurative synthesis. This manifold is to be distinguished from the manifold in “objects of intuition in general” which is the “material” for the intellectual synthesis associated with the “unity of apperception” (ibid.). This is in keeping with Kant’s distinction between thinking and knowing – there is a unity of thinking that is more fundamental than the unity of knowledge, but which does not by itself produce knowledge. It is this unity of thinking, i.e. the transcendental unity of apperception, which grounds the “possibility of the understanding, even as regards its logical employment” (B 131). It is the “supreme principle of all employment of the understanding” of § 17 (my emphasis).
2.1
Kant’s Transcendental Idealism
47
Kant thus affirms both the identity of the epistemic conditions of knowledge and its objects as well as their fundamental independence and heterogeneity on the other, and this is precisely what is required if there is to be a solution to the problem of metaphysics as described in the second edition Preface. It is only through the idea of an a priori determination of the pure manifold of intuition that objects of experience could be determined prior to, i.e. independently of experience, at all. By making the inscription of a priori features of cognition on a manifold given independently of thought and prior to the sensible manifold a necessary condition for there to be any objects of experience Kant can speak of an a priori determination of objects without at the same time turning those objects into mere posits of our cognitive faculties. Objects are, after all, empirically real and only transcendentally ideal. We shall see later, however, that there is no empirical reality of objects without there being an empirical manifold as well. In this respect, Kant’s transcendental argument so far lacks its most crucial element. In order to acknowledge the fact that intuition and thought impose their own structures on the manifold, Kant calls the resulting reality “appearance” (in the transcendental sense22 ) and therefore needs to posit another aspect of reality whose existence is never in doubt, but whose knowability is by definition out of bounds.23 Still, the independent thing-in-itself must obviously be kept distinct from the equally independent pure manifold of intuition, since there could not be a determination of the thing-in-itself by the a priori features of cognition. Viewed in this light, the thing-in-itself is a consequence, rather than a condition, of transcendental idealism. With the idea of an independently given manifold of a priori sensibility in place, Kant proceeds to put together the basic framework of the Analytic of the Critique. Its fundamental tenets can be derived from an analysis of what is implied by the notion of a pure sensible manifold. To begin with, the a priori givenness of this manifold has a dual meaning. It is given a priori in the sense of “prior to or independently of experience”, and it is given a priori in the sense of “independently of thought” and its spontaneous synthesizing and unifying activities. The first sense of “given a priori” is crucial for the logical possibility of an a priori determination of objects while the second marks the pure manifold’s heterogeneous origin from that of the synthetic functions of the understanding. The fact that the origin of the manifold differs from that of the categorial functions also implies that the manifold per se is bare of any and all conceptual – and hence intelligible – features. Its origin in 22 See
A 45–46 on the “transcendental distinction” between appearance in the sense of empirical object and appearance in the sense of appearance (or aspect) of an empirical object. 23 If one ignores his moral philosophy, then Kant’s only real reason for introducing the thing-initself, if I see it correctly, is the logico-semantic one that one cannot talk about appearances, if they are not supposed to be supported by anything other than themselves – for then appearances would simply be illusory or systematically deceptive (like Cartesian adventitious ideas without a God) or simply non-existent: “. . . it does indeed follow that all speculative knowledge of reason is limited to mere objects of experience. But our further contention must also be duly borne in mind, namely, that though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves, we must yet be in a position to think them as things in themselves; otherwise we would be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearances without anything that appears” (B XXVI-XXVII.)
48
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
sensibility confers on it a heterogeneous, i.e. non-conceptual nature. Independence of experience and non-conceptual nature are thus the hallmarks of the pure manifold. The first is supposed to ensure that knowledge a priori is indeed knowledge of something “objective” rather than merely knowledge of the structures of the mind alone.24 The second means that the presence of the manifold by itself does not yet amount to knowledge. Instead, the original act of the synthesis of the imagination and the unifying function of the categories must supervene in order to produce specific a priori structures that necessarily inform any empirical manifold that may be part of the unity of consciousness: What must first be given – with a view to the a priori knowledge of all objects – is the manifold of pure intuition; the second factor is the synthesis of this manifold by means of the imagination. But even this does not yet yield knowledge. The concepts which give unity to this pure synthesis, and which consist solely in the representation of this necessary synthetic unity, furnish the third requisite for the [sc. a priori] knowledge of an object (A 78/B104).
The fact that the syntheses of the understanding must be performed on a heterogeneous content commits Kant to one of the above mentioned dual-source models of cognition, the dualism of (pure) intuition and concept. It also naturally leads to three further theses that are central to the Kantian project, viz. the so-called complementarity thesis, the intuitability thesis (also known as Kant’s principle of significance25 ), and the restriction thesis concerning the restriction of (empirical and mathematical) knowledge to intuitables. The fact that knowledge of objects must involve an intuitional component blocks the rationalist procedure of deriving the structure of the real from logical principles alone such as the principle of sufficient reason or the axiom that all true statements, including contingent truths, are ultimately analytic. Entities that cannot be exhibited in intuition and thus are not spatio-temporal particulars, such as for example monads, cannot be genuine objects of knowledge. They are products of speculation and more or less gratuitous constructs. Hence, all knowledge of objects must “relate ultimately to intuitions” (A 19/B 33). Consequently, Intuition and concepts constitute . . . the elements of all our knowledge, so that neither concepts without an intuition in some way corresponding to them, nor intuition without concepts, can yield knowledge (A 50/B 74).
Or again: Without sensibility no object would be given to us, without understanding no object would be thought. Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind . . . These two powers or capacities cannot exchange their functions. The understanding can intuit nothing, the senses can think nothing. Only through their union can knowledge arise (A 51/B 75).
24 I
say “supposed to ensure,” because in truth it is in the end the pre-representational empirical manifold that alone can assure the objective reality, as distinct from the objective validity, of empirical knowledge. More on this below. 25 See Strawson, 1989, p. 16.
2.1
Kant’s Transcendental Idealism
49
Because Kant’s complementarity thesis includes his intuitability thesis, he redefines knowledge of objects in such a way as to distinguish it from mere thinking: To know an object I must be able to prove its possibility, either from its actuality as attested by experience, or a priori by means of reason. But I can think whatever I please, provided only that I do not contradict myself, that is, provided my concept is a possible thought . . . But something more is required before I can ascribe to such a concept objective validity, that is, real possibility; the former possibility is merely logical (B XXVI, footnote b).
Since knowledge of objects is thus tied to intuitability, the scope of such knowledge must be restricted to intuitables or, to use Kant’s term, appearances: [The fact] that . . . we have no concepts of understanding, and consequently no elements for the knowledge of things, save in so far as intuition can be given corresponding to these concepts; and that we can therefore have no knowledge of any object as thing in itself, but only in so far as it is an object of sensible intuition, that is, an appearance – all this is proved in the analytical part of the Critique. Thus it does indeed follow that all possible speculative knowledge of reason is limited to mere objects of experience (B XXV-XXVI).
It is the task of the Transcendental Deduction, the Schematism and the Analytic of Principles to demonstrate the possibility as well as the necessity of the cooperation between sensibility and understanding. Once this task has been accomplished, Kant is in a position to claim that the subjective a priori conditions of cognition necessarily predetermine the basic structure of the world of empirical objects or that, in the formulation quoted earlier, “the conditions of the possibility of experience in general are likewise conditions of the possibility of the objects of experience.” How, then, does Kant’s transcendental idealism resolve the objectivity problem? It seems that in a fundamental respect Kant’s Copernican turn offers the ultimate response to that problem. Assuming for the moment that the argument in the Analytic of the Critique is successful, Kant has managed to secure both the independence and the basic intelligibility of the world of experience and has done so without relying on observation or induction which could never yield the universality and necessity that the claim to objective validity of knowledge requires. To be sure, Kant pays a price for this solution, viz. the restriction of knowledge to objects that can be sensibly intuited and the redefinition of theoretical or “transcendental” philosophy as a meta-philosophy that is essentially limited to the examination of the conditions under which knowledge a priori of our space-time world is possible. Theoretical philosophy seems henceforth confined to investigating the possibility and scope of empirical knowledge and thus becomes primarily a transcendental philosophy of science rather than a metaphysics. But within these self-imposed limits the solution seems perfect. It significantly goes beyond any bona fide position concerning the agreement between thought and reality. Looking back on the objectivity requirements mentioned earlier we can say that Kant has been able to ground the ontological structure of the world of experience in epistemic conditions that are universally valid and that derive from a combination of factual givens as well as stipulations about the nature of human cognition. He restricts objectivity to the immanence of experience and is able to derive the structure of objective reality from the subjective conditions under which alone knowledge of this reality is
50
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
possible. While human knowledge is discursive and conceptual, the objects of such knowledge must be available in intuition. Intuitional objects can become intelligible only under the condition that the sensible manifold through which they are given be unified, i.e. conceptualized. If we can show what these a priori epistemic conditions and principles are without which intelligibility of intuitional objects would be impossible, we will have demonstrated that and how a priori determination of reality is possible. With this “transcendental deduction” the ancient problem of the objectivity of knowledge seems to have been put to rest. While Kant’s revolutionary proposal clearly marks an unparalleled achievement, some of his fundamental assumptions are unfortunately not unassailable. I will not here reiterate the frequently voiced criticism of Kant’s thing-in-itself doctrine. The unknowability thesis connected with that doctrine seems to me to be a plausible result of Kant’s approach. If knowledge of objects must be both knowledge as well as of objects, and if objects cannot be determined a priori by concepts unless something of what makes them objects already belongs to the epistemic subject, then, naturally, the idealistic approach suggests itself, and it recommends that we start with the immanence of the subject and its a priori cognitive structures in order to learn from them what objects of experience would have to be like. As already indicated, in my view the problems of the thing-in-itself doctrine lie elsewhere, viz. in the difficulties it creates for Kant’s practical philosophy, which clearly cannot take the pure practical will to be a noumenon in the negative sense only but must grant it actual existence, not to mention the problematic status of an a-temporal noumenal will whose spontaneity is nonetheless supposed to be effective in the world of sense. Be that as it may, my next concern here will be the tenability of the doctrine of the pure sensible manifold and in particular the thesis concerning its independent source and status.26 It is here that I see the first of two serious challenges to Kant’s solution to the objectivity problem. Closer reflection reveals that the independent status of the a priori manifold of sensibility cannot indeed be maintained. If true, this fact must have significant consequences and, together with a re-evaluation of the concept of the empirical manifold, will lead to a reintegration and re-homogenization of the intuitional and conceptual content of consciousness, as can be seen in Fichte and Hegel.27 As we have seen, in order to establish the objective validity of knowledge claims about the
26 The independence thesis is clearly expressed at B 145: “. . . in the above proof [presented in § 20] there is one feature, from which I could not abstract, the feature, namely, that the manifold to be intuited must be given prior to the synthesis of understanding, and independently of it.” Kant also admits that he has no justification for it here: “How this takes place, remains here undetermined” (ibid.). 27 The chapter on Sense-Certainty in the Phenomenology of Spirit contains Hegel’s argument in favor of the homogeneity of sensation and concept: see Section 3.2 below. Pippin, 1989, pp. 27–32 recognized the centrality of this issue for Fichte and Hegel who both thought that the second part of the Transcendental Deduction begins to “undercut his [i.e. Kant’s] own separation between intuition and concept” (p. 28). Kant scholars since have acknowledged the need to mount a strong defense of the heterogeneity of intuition and concept, if the Kantian project is to escape Hegel’s criticism: see Guyer, 2000. My sense is that although there are certainly good reasons in favor of the heterogeneity of intuition and thought, this will not much help Kant’s transcendental project.
2.1
Kant’s Transcendental Idealism
51
world Kant initially stipulates the givenness of a pure manifold, a pure synthesis of the imagination which weaves this manifold together in intuition, and another synthesis or combination (“conjunctio”) (B 129) which unifies the manifold conceptually and which is entirely the work of the understanding and its pure concepts or categories. This analysis of the foundations of knowledge contains a fundamental insight, viz. that intelligibility arises solely out of the unification of representations. If there is to be meaning, understanding, and knowledge, there must be unity of representation, and the production of this unity is the prerogative of the understanding or thought. Intelligibility equals unity of representations, and unity of representations presupposes a unifying synthesis or combination of the manifold. As Kant pointed out, the mere presence of a manifold or material for knowledge does not by itself constitute anything intelligible.28 Hence his insistence that synthesis must be complemented by an act of unification which “bring[s] this synthesis to concepts” and which is “a function which belongs to the understanding” (A 78/B 103). Synthesis by itself is “the mere result of the power of imagination” which is “a blind but indispensable function of the soul” (ibid.). In other words, the function of the imagination referred to at this juncture in the Critique merely generates a continuum of intuition, but it does not unify.29 Through the synthesis of the imagination alone the manifold is not yet brought under concepts but is merely “given”. Only through the unifying combination of the manifold, or through synthesizing the manifold in accordance with a rule does the a prior intuitional content acquire objective significance. It soon becomes apparent, however, that the requirements for the objective validity of knowledge, which Kant develops in the sections preceding the Transcendental Deduction in the B edition, are incomplete. As Kant admits in the famous footnote in § 26, the manifold of intuition could not even be “given” in any meaningful sense, if in addition to having been synthesized by the imagination it had not also already been unified: Space represented as object . . . contains combination of the manifold . . . so that [sc. while] the form of intuition gives only a manifold, the formal intuition gives unity of representation. In the Aesthetic I have treated this unity as belonging to sensibility, simply in order to emphasize that it precedes any concept, although as a matter of fact, it presupposes a synthesis which does not belong to the senses but through which all concepts of space and time first become possible. For since by its means (in that the understanding determines the sensibility) space and time are first given as intuitions, the unity of this a priori intuition belongs to space and time, and not to the concept of the understanding (B 160-1, footnote a).
28 A
90–91/B 123: “Appearances might very well be so constituted that the understanding should not find them to be in accordance with the conditions of its unity. Everything might be in such confusion that . . . in the series of appearances nothing presented itself which might yield a rule of synthesis . . .” 29 Note that this synthesis is introduced prior to both the A and B edition versions of the Transcendental Deduction, a passage Kant apparently thought he needed not revise when he prepared the B edition. Allison, 2004, p. 188 calls the synthesis of the imagination “proto-conceptual,” but also “interpretive” (p. 189). The latter in my view goes too far.
52
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
It is important to realize what the correction amounts to that Kant here makes to the earlier account of the Transcendental Aesthetic and sections 10–14 of the Transcendental Deduction. It is clear that without the pure manifold the synthesis which in § 24 Kant calls “intellectual” and which in turn rests on the original synthetic unity of self-consciousness (or transcendental unity of apperception) could have no “transcendental content”, i.e. no a priori reference to objects. But what Kant now points out is that mere synthesis of the manifold without some unification of it would not be enough to constitute givenness of the pure manifold of space and time. Givenness of this manifold requires not only the weaving together of the intuitional spatio-temporal continuum, it also requires unity or combination into one whole.30 If you will, givenness requires more than mere givenness. Kant does not elaborate here on why the manifold must be unified into a “formal intuition”. He does, however, give us a hint. Unity of the manifold, he says, is necessary for space and time to be “given as intuitions”. What Kant has in mind becomes clear, if one remembers the argument in the Transcendental Aesthetic in favor of the intuitional, i.e. nonconceptual and non-discursive character of space and time considered as objects of intuition. Kant there argued that an object of intuition differs from a concept in that it is given as a whole, or as a single object.31 This is precisely what distinguishes an intellectual from an intuitional object or representation. A concept or universal is essentially incomplete or abstract, i.e. a representation applicable to objects rather than the object itself. Only the object of intuition is self-given or given in toto, and only as given in intuition is something an object as distinct from the representation of one. Kant therefore considers concepts to be mediate representations that are never in direct relationship to objects.32 In view of the dualistic intuition-concept model of cognition to which Kant subscribes we may say that intuition establishes the possibility of referentiality to objects as distinct from mere conceptual representations of them, whereas combination of the manifold in accordance with the categories establishes referentiality to objects in general as distinct from the mere intuitional givenness of appearances. The reason why a pre-categorial, non-intellectual unification of the manifold is necessary beyond its pre-categorial, non-unifying synthesis, therefore, is that without such unification in intuition no intuitable object would be “given”. That is, it would not be “present” in intuition, because an intuitional object, even if this object 30 For
a similar view see Altman, 2008, p. 140. 24/B 39: “Space is not a discursive or, as we say, general concept of relations of things in general, but a pure intuition. For, in the first place, we can represent to ourselves only one space; and if we speak of diverse spaces, we mean thereby only parts of one and the same unique space. Secondly, these parts cannot precede the one all-embracing space, as being, as it were, constituents out of which it can be composed; on the contrary they can be thought only as in it. Space is essentially one; the manifold in it, and therefore the general concept of spaces, depends solely on [the introduction of] limitations.” 32 See A 19/B 33: “In whatever manner and by whatever means a mode of knowledge may relate to objects, intuition is that through which it is in immediate relation to them, and to which all thought as a means is directed.” See also A 68/B 93: “Since no representation, save when it is an intuition, is in immediate relation to an object, no concept is ever related to an object immediately . . .” 31 A
2.1
Kant’s Transcendental Idealism
53
is merely empty space and empty time, must be individuated and hence must be a single, unified continuum, even before any matter it may contain is further synthesized and ordered in accordance with the categories. Kant acknowledges the force of this argument in the passage quoted above. It commits him, however, to stipulating the existence not only of a “pure synthesis” of imagination33 – an intuitional synthesis minus the combination part – but also a synthetic unification of the manifold through the imagination, an activity called “figurative synthesis” and “transcendental synthesis of imagination” in § 24. Furthermore, since all synthetic activity, combination included, is an expression of spontaneity, and since spontaneous activity is the prerogative of the understanding, not the sensibility, the unity brought to the pure manifold through the synthesis of imagination must be the result of “an action of the understanding on the sensibility”,34 although qua synthesis of intuitions it is productive of the intuitional content only, not of its intelligibility.35 This situation clearly constitutes a dilemma for Kant. He obviously needs a faculty distinct from the understanding to introduce unity into the pure sensible manifold independently of the intellectual synthesis of the understanding. On the other hand, all unification is the work of the understanding. Consequently, either we consider the imagination to be a hybrid of an intellectual and a non-intellectual faculty or, preferably, we take the pre-categorial (or “figurative”) synthesis of the imagination and the intellectual synthesis of the understanding to be two manifestations of one and the same fundamental faculty. The former possibility seems incoherent, the latter, however, undermines the dual-source model of knowledge based on the duality of intuition and concept.36 This, in my view, is one of the reasons why Kant will supplement this dualsource model – which, it should be noted, is concerned exclusively with the a priori elements of cognition, including the pure manifold of intuition – with the one of (pure) form and (empirical) matter in § 26 of the Transcendental Deduction. Indeed,
33 A 79/B 104. The entire passage at A 78–79/B104 suggests that this pure synthesis occurs in two
forms, as a synthesis of the imagination as well as a synthesis of the understanding. 152. 35 That is to say, “the unity of this a priori intuition belongs to space and time, and not to the concept of the understanding (cf. § 24)” (B 161, footnote a). Note that here in § 26 Kant himself establishes the connection between the pre-categorial unity of space and time and the figurative synthesis of § 24 by referring the reader back to that section. 36 My reading of the transcendental imagination is not as charitable as Allison’s (or, for that matter, Hegel’s, as we shall see) who finds “much of this [wavering on Kant’s part] . . . perfectly understandable in light of Kant’s concern to avoid the criticisms that were raised against the First Edition version of the Deduction because of its apparently psychological and psychologistic thrust”: see Allison, 1983, 163. The point, it seems to me, is that for reasons of consistency Kant is committed to assigning any synthesis or combination to the understanding while he also needs to maintain the heterogeneity of formal intuition as something given or “givable” independently of the understanding. For a similar view see Reid, 2003. He concludes that once we get to the Schematism “the distinction between intuition and concept begins to appear somewhat problematic” (253). I would only add that the erosion of the dualism between the two is quite obvious already in the Transcendental Deduction. 34 B
54
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
if we think through the consequences of the extension that Kant’s initial picture receives in §§ 24 and 26, it will become clear that the first dual-source model and with it the independent givenness of the pure manifold is not really tenable. For Kant has now explicitly conceded that for pure intuitions such as (empty) space and time to be given as objects they need to be unified at a pre-conceptual level by a faculty which is called imagination but which is clearly a function of thought. To put it differently, imagination and understanding, sensibility and thought, synthesis and combination are inseparable already at the level of intuition. I believe that this result is inevitable, if one follows Kant’s fundamental assumptions and his own argument. And it is a result hinted at by Kant himself.37 To summarize, the pure manifold, while deriving from a source independent of the understanding or any activity of thought,38 (a) does not exist independently of the epistemic subject and (b) is not given as an object of intuition independently of the synthetic function of the understanding. For any manifold to be “given” in a meaningful sense, it must already be unified or combined at a pre-categorial level as well as, according to § 24, independently of the intellectual synthesis of the understanding – and unification or combination are acts of thought, not of sensibility. If, then, there is no pure manifold that could even be given as an object of intuition independently of the function of thought, there is so far no truly heterogeneous element of cognition that might be given independently of thought either. Consequently, the basis for the objective reality of claims about the a prior structure of reality has not yet been established. If the pure manifold were the only material that cognition has to go on in its a priori determinations, all determination would be a self-determination of the epistemic subject, and the required element of empirical realism would be absent. And if a priori referentiality of thought to a subject-independent reality could not be established, the result would be that the project of demonstrating the possibility of a priori knowledge of objects would have failed. This is precisely why a pre-representational empirical manifold becomes necessary. In addition to the pure manifold, the empirical manifold represents the truly independent and heterogeneous element of empirical realism, the truly nonsubjective component in the knowledge of objects. To determine anything as an object of cognition (as opposed to an object of intuition) there needs to be not only a heterogeneous element in cognition, but also an element that is derived from a subject-independent source. Otherwise, the epistemic subject would be tautologically self-determining.39 Without such an element, the position is in danger of
37 A 15/B 29: “. . . there are two stems of human knowledge, namely, sensibility and understanding, which perhaps spring from a common, but to us unknown, root.” 38 Kant is very clear that the manifold should be given independently of the unity of apperception: “. . . the manifold to be intuited must be given prior to the synthesis of understanding, and independently of it. How this takes place, remains here undetermined [!]” (B 145). Or: The power of the understanding consists “in the act whereby it brings the synthesis of a manifold, given to it from elsewhere in intuition, to the unity of apperception” (ibid., my italics). 39 Hence the line of thought pursued by Heinrich Rickert (Rickert, 1924), who advanced the so-called heterothetic argument, cannot really succeed. Similar to Fichte’s theory of the Anstoß
2.1
Kant’s Transcendental Idealism
55
reducing to pure transcendental idealism without empirical realism. In sum, for Kant at least heterogeneity is not enough. To secure true independence of the manifold from the understanding, we need externality or subject-independence as well.40 And indeed, while Kant apparently entertained the possibility of an original unity of understanding and sensibility, he did not actually rely exclusively on the pure sensible manifold alone to make possible the reference to objects of experience. Instead, in § 26 of the Transcendental Deduction he introduces an empirical manifold, “the manifold in an empirical intuition, whereby perception, that is, empirical consciousness of the intuition (as appearance) is possible” (B 160).41 This manifold is unified by the “synthesis of apprehension” (which resurfaces here from the A edition). In other words, if the pure manifold of sensibility cannot by itself serve as a subject-independent source of the heterogeneous material, perhaps the empirical manifold can. This manifold, I suggest, is made up of those “undetermined objects of an empirical intuition” called appearances that Kant refers to at the very start of the Critique proper.42 Together with the pure sensible manifold or formal intuition this as yet undetermined empirical manifold forms the content of inner sense. It is (check), he integrated the heterogeneous element into the unity of self-consciousness. But, as we now see, heterogeneity is not enough to avoid an idealism without empirical realism, externality must also be a mark of the heterogeneous material. The heterothetic argument was taken up again by Flach, 1959 and Wagner, 1959. For a critical assessment of the heterothetic argument see Hartmann, 1999, pp. 66–69. 40 The externality requirement is what seems to have been overlooked by those who are puzzled by the question as to why the second step of the Transcendental Deduction is necessary or what exactly it is supposed to achieve over and above the first step that ends with § 20: see the discussion in Carl, 1998, pp. 208–211. Only the externality of the matter of experience can ensure the objective reality of the categories, since without this matter we are dealing merely with the pure forms of intuition and understanding and the formal intuition (i.e., empty space and time), all of which derive from the epistemic subject alone. Fichte’s alternative of positing an internal Anstoß has to struggle with the problem of losing the element of empirical realism altogether. 41 This third synthesis should not be conflated with the figurative synthesis. Hence § 26 does not find its completion with the unification of space and time referred to in the B 160–161 footnote, as Guyer, 1992, p. 153 seems to suggest, but only with this third empirical synthesis. Similarly, Longueness, 1998, 211 overlooks the critical role of the synthesis of apprehension when she claims that the Transcendental Deduction is completed with the reintroduction of the figurative synthesis in § 26. She is thus misled into concluding that “the real weight of the argument in section 26 lies in the reexamination of the two questions: what is space, and what is time?” (214). In support of the view defended here see the discussion in Reid, 2003, pp. 250–252. I also agree with Allison, 2004, who correctly, it seems to me, states: “Although the connection of the categories with the forms of sensibility through the transcendental synthesis of the imagination is undoubtedly the pivotal step of the argument, it does not of itself suffice to secure the goal of the Deduction. This requires demonstrating that the categories stand in a necessary connection with empirical intuition. Kant attempts to achieve this goal in § 26 by linking the categories to the synthesis of apprehension . . .” (p. 193) Where I differ from Allison is in regarding the necessity of the synthesis of apprehension as a breach in the transcendental argument (see below). For another detailed discussion of the structure of the Transcendental Deduction and the role of the figurative synthesis in particular see also Senderowicz, 2004. 42 “That intuition which is in relation to the object through sensation, is entitled empirical. The undetermined object of an empirical intuition is entitled appearance” (A 20/B 34).
56
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
through the synthesis of this manifold in accordance with the categories that Kant hopes definitively to secure the objective reality of the categories.43 As we shall see in what follows, it is the introduction of this manifold that will cause the most serious problem for Kant’s transcendental project. In Hegel’s view it constitutes the fatal flaw in the argument of the Transcendental Deduction.
2.2 Hegel’s Critique of Kant: The Transcendental Deduction Let me suggest that for a moment we ignore Kant’s attempt in § 26 of the Transcendental Deduction to build referentiality to a subject-independent epistemic component into the unity of consciousness by appealing to an empirical manifold of sensation. Since this move will exacerbate Kant’s dilemma, as will become clear later, any corrective measure should, if possible, be taken prior to and independently of the introduction of this manifold. Given the fact that up to this point the independence of a dimension of referentiality for as yet to be determined objects within the immanence of the transcendental unity of apperception has not yet been established, what should or could be done? Should we recommend that the idea of a manifold be given up entirely? This will not work, if we want to preserve the transcendental approach of determining objects independently of experience. The manifold is the element that represents the dimension of externality or subject-independence within the unity of self-consciousness. As such it is precisely what Kant calls the “transcendental content” without which thought would lack the object-dimension that is supposed to be organized and unified by the categories. Hence the concept of the manifold cannot be dismissed without losing the dimension of objectivity itself. It is after all the idea that objects must conform a priori to concepts that separates the Copernican project in philosophy from all others. No manifold, no transcendental argument.44 However, if it is true that the manifold cannot retain its independence of thought and at the same time be part of the transcendental unity of apperception, it follows that while it must be an original part of this immanence, it will be neither absolutely independent nor absolutely heterogeneous. Looking ahead, we can say that the manifold will need to be unified by thought a limine and as a consequence it will already contain the a priori conceptual structures. In other words, the manifold will represent the contents of experience, in so far as the latter is already permeated by the categorial determinations. It will be objective reality as it exists within the unity of self-consciousness or the immanence of experience. This is the situation as we will find it in the Sense-Certainty chapter of Hegel’s Phenomenology. 43 B
144–145 (§ 21): “In what follows (cf. § 26) it will be shown, from the mode in which the empirical intuition is given in sensibility, that its unity is no other than that which the category (according to § 20) prescribes to a given intuition in general. Only thus, by demonstration of the a priori validity of the categories in respect of all objects of our senses, will the purpose of the deduction be fully attained.” 44 Accordingly, Fichte made the manifold a fundamental principle under the title of a not-I posited by the original ego: see Fichte, Science of Knowledge, § 2, pp. 102–105.
2.2
Hegel’s Critique of Kant: The Transcendental Deduction
57
As we shall see shortly, it could thus be said that at least in Hegel’s case the development of post-Kantian German idealism takes its point of departure from a critical assessment of the consequences of Kant’s introduction of a figurative synthesis in § 24 and the acknowledgement of the need for a formal intuition in the B 160-1 footnote. The introduction of the empirical manifold in § 26, on the other hand, represents the fault line at which in Hegel’s view the Kantian strategy falls apart. As we shall see, in Hegel’s eyes § 26 with its empirical manifold marks the abandonment of the transcendental project, while the preceding part of the Transcendental Deduction can be so modified and reconstituted that transcendental idealism may be transformed into speculative idealism, which, Hegel believes, is the only consistent form of transcendental idealism. These are issues to be taken up later. It is now time to ask, whether the critique of Kant offered in the previous section is in fact shared by Hegel. Hegel’s occupation with Kant’s philosophy goes back to his student days at the Tübinger Stift. We know from Hegel’s Berne correspondence with Schelling and other sources that Hegel and his friends revered Kant as a bringer of hope who ushered in the dawn of a new era in philosophy by destroying the traditional orthodoxy and dogmatism. Although Hegel lost his initial enthusiasm for Kant’s thought, he remains appreciative of Kant’s contribution until the very end as is apparent from a footnote in the latest revision of the Science of Logic: I would mention that in this work I frequently refer to the Kantian philosophy . . . because whatever may be said, both in this work and elsewhere, about the precise character of this philosophy and about particular parts of its exposition, it constitutes the base and the starting-point of recent German philosophy and this its merit remains unaffected by whatever faults may be found in it (SL 61, n. 1/WdL I 44, footnote).
Hegel published three major critical expositions of Kant’s philosophy, the first of which is contained in the Differenzschrift of 1801. There followed the essay Glauben und Wissen (Faith and Knowledge) in 1802, a critique of Kant, Jacobi, and Fichte. A condensed presentation of Kant’s philosophy from Hegel’s mature period is to be found in the Introduction to the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences.45 In addition, there are two extended passages in the Science of Logic that merit special attention, because they allow us to reconstruct the path leading from Kant’s transcendental idealism to Hegel’s own position. Briefer references to Kant or the “critical philosophy” abound in Hegel’s writings, but we may ignore them for our purposes. Hegel’s critique of Kant is remarkably consistent over the years. His most detailed discussion of the Transcendental Deduction, however, comes in the 1802 Faith and Knowledge essay. The main point is that in the original synthetic unity of self-consciousness Kant had discovered the true principle of all philosophical 45 I
am referring to the 1830 edition of the Encyclopedia. A rudimentary presentation of Kant’s philosophy is already contained in the Heidelberg version of 1817. In the 1830 Berlin version the overview over the Kantian system occupies §§ 40–60. I am setting aside here the Kant critique to be found in Hegel’s Lectures on the History of Philosophy which were never published during Hegel’s life time.
58
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
knowledge, but that he compromised this discovery by interpreting the specific form of synthesizing which underlies the intellectual and the figurative syntheses as a mere combination of a manifold with empty concepts where both the manifold and the concepts are supposed to exist independently of or prior to the original synthesis. Instead, Kant should have realized that, in the words of Faith and Knowledge, the forms of intuition and the forms of thought, i.e. the categories, “have no isolated existence” and that together they form an “original identity of opposites” such that their unity, qua original, must be prior to their distinction while in Kant’s presentation their unity is produced out of their pre-existing separation.46 In other words, Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception is not itself the principle from which the specific forms of unity of intuition and concept are then being derived. The unity of the latter does not emerge as a self-differentiation of the original unity and is therefore “not originally synthetic” (FK 73/GW IV 330). Qua original, the synthesis would have to precede the differentiation of the elements synthesized by it: This original synthetic unity must be conceived, not as produced out of opposites, but as a truly necessary, absolute, original identity of opposites (FK 70/GW IV 327).
The idea of an original synthesis therefore does not carry over to the categorial or the figurative syntheses. In fact, this means that from Hegel’s point of view Kant’s transcendental deduction is a misunderstanding – it attempts to synthesize what from a transcendental point of view must have existed in synthetic unity from the start. In Faith and Knowledge, Hegel views the transcendental synthesis of the imagination as the key to Kant’s speculative insight. In the Logic and the Encyclopedia versions of Hegel’s critique, the imagination loses its central role in favor of the reinterpretation of the transcendental unity of apperception as a precursor of Hegel’s own Notion. The productive imagination in Faith and Knowledge is responsible for the figurative as distinct from the intellectual synthesis,47 but at one point it is also identified with the transcendental unity of apperception in that it is both subject and object in undivided identity and thus “nothing but reason itself,” because reason is just this, “the identity of unequals.”48 It is interesting to note that already in this context Hegel suggests that the subject-predicate form of the judgment represents a differentiation of the original synthetic unity into a universal (predicate) and a particular (subject) whose original unity can be reconstructed discursively only in the 46 Cf.
FK 69–70/GW IV 327. FK 69/GW IV 327. 48 Cf. FK 73/GW IV 329. Again, the productive imagination “must . . . be recognized as what is primary and original, as that out of which subjective Ego and objective world first sunder themselves into the necessarily bipartite appearance and product . . . This power of imagination is the original two-sided identity. The identity becomes subject in general on one side, and object on the other; but originally it is both (ibid.). The intellectual synthesis, on the other hand, is the categorial synthesis which produces determinate representations distinct from the original identity of intuition and understanding: see FK 70/GW IV 327). Figurative and intellectual synthesis thus both presuppose the transcendental synthesis of imagination that for Hegel is equivalent to the transcendental apperception. 47 Cf.
2.2
Hegel’s Critique of Kant: The Transcendental Deduction
59
form of a syllogism.49 Hegel thus views productive imagination, predicative judgment and syllogistic reasoning as three aspects of reason itself. Replacing productive imagination with reason, we may recognize in this appropriation of Kant an anticipation of what in the Logic Hegel calls the “subjective Notion” or “subjectivity”, which is subdivided into the Notion “as such”, the Judgment, and the Syllogism.50 Faith and Knowledge thus essentially regards Kant’s original synthetic unity of self-consciousness as a fundamental, un-derivable, if not un-analyzable, identity of “heterogeneous elements” and hence as an articulation of the idea of reason itself. Hegel even concurs with the analysis of the pure sensible manifold we developed in the previous section: One can glimpse this Idea [of reason as the identity of heterogeneous elements in Kant] . . ., but not where it should be, in the transcendental exposition of these forms [of intuition and thought], but later on, in the deduction of the categories, where the original synthetic unity of apperception finally comes to the fore. Here, the original synthetic unity of apperception is recognized also as the principle of figurative synthesis, i.e., of the forms of intuition; space and time are themselves conceived as synthetic unities, and spontaneity, the absolute synthetic activity of the productive imagination, is conceived as the principle of the very sensibility which was previously characterized only as receptivity (FK 69-70/GW IV 327, my italics).
This can be taken as a direct reference to § 24 of the Transcendental Deduction, B edition, perhaps even extending to and including the famous B 160-1 footnote in § 26. Hegel’s observation means that if space and time are now considered synthetic unities the productive imagination must be the origin not only of their unity, but of space and time themselves as objects or synthetic wholes. Indeed, the transcendental synthesis of imagination, Hegel argues, is now recognized as the most fundamental principle. It therefore overrules the initial independence of sensibility and effectively negates its merely receptive nature. Thus, productive imagination is not to be regarded as an intermediate factor only that is interpolated between “an existing absolute subject and an absolutely existing world”.51 The transcendental standpoint, Hegel seems to be saying, requires that intuition and concept be united ab ovo, as it were, instead of being brought together after the fact by a transcendental act. The difference between Hegel’s analysis here and my earlier critique is that Hegel is quite appreciative of the function of the transcendental imagination. Instead
49 Cf.
FK 72/GW IV 328–329. SL 600/WdL II 239, while commenting on the distinction between understanding and judgment in the Kantian sense, Hegel explicitly confirms this by observing that “the understanding is to be distinguished from reason only in the sense that the former is merely the faculty of the notion in general.” See also FK 79–80/GW IV 334–335): We must place Kant’s merit “in his having put the Idea of authentic a priority in the form of transcendental imagination; and also in having put the beginning of the Idea of Reason in the intellect itself. For he regarded thinking, or the form, not as something subjective, but as something in itself; not as something formless, not as empty apperception, but as intellect, as true form, namely as triplicity.” For Hegel’s integration of logic and metaphysics during the Jena period see Düsing’s excellent 1976 study, pp.150–189. 51 FK 73/GW IV 329. 50 At
60
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
of viewing it as a dubious hybrid, he re-interprets it speculatively and welcomes it as a precursor of Hegelian reason. The section on “The Notion in General”52 in the Science of Logic retains the same fundamental analysis of Kant’s transcendental position, but it also adds a new angle to Hegel’s critique. In this passage of the Science of Logic, Hegel interprets the “I” as the original synthetic unity of its internal diversity such that this inner manifold must be regarded as a “positedness” (ibid.) of the “I” itself. We easily detect in this Hegel’s re-interpretation of Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception as the source and single origin of the internal manifold. As I argued above, Hegel, unlike Kant, will be ready to admit that the empirical manifold introduced into the unity of the “I” already contains all a priori structures within itself – the I extracts them from, but does not impose them upon the manifold of experience. So Hegel not only transfers his interpretation of the Notion onto the “pure I”, but further identifies this Hegelian “I” with Kant’s original synthetic unity of self-consciousness. With the idea of an original synthetic unity of self-consciousness, he claims, Kant went beyond the ordinary conception of the “I” as an entity that possesses faculties as a thing possesses properties. While this latter view may in fact have influenced Kant’s theory of faculties in part, the idea of an original synthetic unity opens up an entirely new dimension. Says Hegel: It is one of the profoundest and truest insights to be found in the Critique of Pure Reason that the unity which constitutes the nature of the Notion is recognized as the original synthetic unity of apperception, as unity of the I think, or of self-consciousness (SL 584/WdL II 221).
Hegel apparently takes the very idea of an original synthetic unity of selfconsciousness to be the crucial point. It indicates the combination of two heterogeneous elements out of which there arises something qualitatively different from either element contained in it – if, and this is admittedly a controversial “if ”, with Hegel we understand the point of § 24 of the Transcendental Deduction and the B 160-1 footnote to be that without the activity of the understanding there could not even be a figurative synthesis. In this sense, the figurative synthesis is embedded in the intellectual synthesis and would be impossible without it. It is with some reason, then, that Hegel should regard Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception as the precursor to his concept of the Notion as far as the absolute priority of the Notion is concerned. The important point for Hegel here is the fact that the original synthetic unity of self-consciousness prefigures the original synthetic unity that is the Concept. Consequently, objectivity must be thought of as being dependent on the synthesizing activity of the understanding and is itself possible only on the basis of an original synthetic unity.53 In this way, the transcendental unity of apperception
52 The reader should note that I prefer the translation “Concept” for Hegel’s Begriff. But since I am using Miller’s translation of the Science of Logic, I will stick with “Notion” when quoting Miller’s translation. 53 SL 584/WdL II 221: “An object, says Kant, is that in the notion of which the manifold of a given intuition is unified. But all unifying of representations demands a unity of consciousness in the synthesis of them. Consequently, it is this unity of consciousness which alone constitutes
2.2
Hegel’s Critique of Kant: The Transcendental Deduction
61
becomes the foundation of the objective validity of a priori claims to knowledge. In a remarkable statement, Hegel even appeals to Kant’s authority for a confirmation of the correctness of his own thought concerning the role of the Concept in knowledge. “Thus,” he says, “we are justified by a cardinal principle of the Kantian philosophy in referring to the nature of the I in order to learn what the Notion is” (SL 585/WdL 222). A statement such as this, coming as it does at a crucial juncture in Hegel’s argument in the Logic, can leave us in no doubt about the fundamental impact of Kant’s thought on Hegel and the fact that Kant’s First Critique served both as a genuine starting point and as a benchmark for Hegel’s own attempt at solving the objectivity problem. Hegel takes himself to be preserving and developing what he believes to be the core of the genuine Kantian insight while rejecting what he takes to be heterogeneous elements incompatible with it. In addition to its absolute priority Hegel also credits the original synthetic unity of self-consciousness with the character of concrete universality. Seeing himself as drawing out what he believes to be the logical conclusion of Kant’s thought he offers the following: Through the categories . . . the manifold of given representations is so determined as to be brought into the unity of consciousness. According to this exposition [of Kant’s], the unity of the notion is that whereby something is not a mere mode of feeling, an intuition, or even a mere representation, but is an object, and this objective unity is the unity of the ego with itself. In point of fact, the comprehension of an object consists in nothing else than that the ego makes it its own, pervades it and brings it into its own form, that is, into the universality that is immediately a determinateness, or a determinateness that is immediately universality (SL 584-5/WdL II 222).
At this point Hegel clearly begins to go beyond the letter of Kant’s text.54 On the other hand, it is less obvious that Hegel is thereby necessarily doing violence to Kant’s spirit. His reasoning may be reconstructed in the following way. If the synthetic unity of self-consciousness is truly original, i.e. if it truly is the most fundamental epistemic condition, Kant’s analytic approach which first isolates two separate sources of knowledge in order afterwards to unify them again is either misleading or an artificial ladder that must be discarded once we have reached the “highest point” on which everything else, even the functioning of the understanding and thought itself, depends. If the synthetic unity is truly original, the question whether thought and intuition are really two separate sources of knowledge must become unanswerable. If anything, this indicates that to try to isolate the two sources as elements independent of one another is to start on the wrong foot. To the contrary, it is only through an analysis of the original unity that the two elements can be separated, because qua originally unified, they must be considered heterogeneous within a prior homogeneous unity. The homogeneity of the unity itself is necessary,
the connection of the representations with the object and therewith their objective validity and on which rests even the possibility of the understanding.” 54 Hegel apparently favors the two-stage (as distinct from the dual-source) model of cognition Kant employed in the Prolegomena by distinguishing judgments of perception from judgments of experience.
62
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
if there is to be genuine unity rather than merely an aggregate of diverse elements. From this it would follow that the synthetic unity constitutes an absolute starting point that cannot be derived or deduced from anything preceding it. Quite naturally, then, the content of this synthetic unity cannot be derived from anything else than the synthetic unity itself. To say that the content is “posited” by the spontaneity of the synthesizing “I” is merely to acknowledge this fact. Furthermore, one who has accepted the argument thus far would also have to admit that since the unity is transcendental, all forms of cognition, including “mere” sensation, perception, and even “pure” thinking itself, contain an element of original synthesis, beginning with sensation and intuition and continuing on through representation, empirical judgments, and the thinking of “pure” concepts. Hegel’s critique of Kant’s Copernican revolution could be summarized in a nutshell by saying that Hegel credits Kant with the discovery of this new paradigm of thought as originally synthetic, but that he equally continues to adhere to a dual-source model of knowledge nonetheless. As Hegel sees it, Kant’s transcendental idealism thus becomes a philosophy of divided loyalties.55 Why, then, did Hegel think it legitimate to claim concrete universality for the transcendental unity of apperception? I suggest the following reading of Hegel’s argument. On account of its implicit heterogeneous content the transcendental unity of apperception is determinate, not empty; as a unity of itself and its content it is homogeneous with itself, i.e. it possesses universality; and as a homogeneous unity that includes a heterogeneous element (viz. negation) it is a determinate universality. To support his interpretation of Kant Hegel focuses in particular on Kant’s complementarity thesis: . . . it is an essential proposition of the Kantian transcendental philosophy that without intuitions notions [Begriffe] are empty and are valid solely as relations of the manifold given by intuition (SL 585/WdL II 223).
Concepts can generate objectively valid cognition only insofar as they combine intuitions in an intelligible unity. There is a critique implied here as well. Concepts without such a content are not really concepts, i.e. there are, strictly speaking, no pure concepts of the understanding lying ready a priori in the mind. The latter, we are led to conclude, are abstractions, concepts that have no work to do. Concepts, categories included, always come with a determinate content. In a similar vein, Hegel acknowledges Kant’s innovation of proposing the idea of a synthetic a priori judgment. Here, too, the fundamental insight consists in that two heterogeneous elements are combined a priori in such a way that the resulting unity, while containing heterogeneity, is nonetheless a unity, i.e. homogenous.56 As a caveat, however, 55 SL
594/WdL II 233: “In the a priori synthesis of the Notion [des Begriffs], Kant possessed a higher principle [than that of an “empty, blank form”] in which a duality in a unity could be cognized, a cognition, therefore, of what is required for truth; but the material of sense, the manifold of intuition, was too strong for him and he was unable to get away from it to a consideration of the Notion and the categories in and for themselves and to a speculative method of philosophizing.” 56 SL 589/WdL II 227: “. . . differentiation must be regarded as an equally essential moment of the Notion [as unity]. Kant has introduced this consideration by the extremely important thought that there are synthetic judgments a priori. This original synthesis of apperception is one of the most
2.2
Hegel’s Critique of Kant: The Transcendental Deduction
63
we should remember that for Hegel the empirical manifold, insofar as it is saturated with a priori elements, is supposed to be originally inherent in the transcendental unity of apperception itself. Accordingly, what may on the face of it look like a Hegelian endorsement of the complementarity thesis is in reality an affirmation of Hegel’s own re-interpretation of this Kantian principle. The interpretation of the transcendental unity of apperception as absolutely original and as concrete universality also marks the turning point in Hegel’s exposition of Kant in The Notion in General. Having paid his debt to Kant, Hegel now mounts his critique. It is easy to read Hegel’s objections to what he calls Kant’s formalism and psychological idealism57 as polemical, but such a reading would likely overlook the original aspect of Hegel’s critique. For Hegel detects, or at least claims to have detected, a fault line in Kant’s position caused by an inner tension and even a contradiction between two paradigmatic but opposed conceptions of knowledge. Commenting on the relation between the Concept (i.e. the synthesis in accordance with the concepts of the understanding) and other forms of cognition such as intuition and representation Hegel remarks: The conception of this relation both in ordinary psychology and in the Kantian transcendental philosophy is that the empirical material, the manifold of intuition and representation, first exists on its own account, and then the understanding approaches it, brings unity into it and by abstraction raises it to the form of universality. The understanding is in this way an intrinsically empty form which, on the one hand, obtains a reality through the said given content and, on the other hand, abstracts from that content, that is to say, lets it drop as something useless, but useless only for the Notion. In both these actions the Notion is not the independent factor, not the essential and true element of the prior given material; on the contrary, it is the material that is regarded as the absolute reality, which cannot be extracted from the Notion (SL 587/WdL II 224-5).
Thus according to Hegel, there results the contradictory situation in which the Notion (i.e. the original unity of thought and manifold) “. . . without the manifold of intuition is again declared to be empty and devoid of content despite the fact that it is a synthesis a priori” (SL 589/WdL II 227). In the final analysis, therefore, the Concept remains “permanently conditioned by a manifold of intuition” (ibid.). The original transcendental unity reveals itself to be only an “external unity and a mere combination of entities that are intrinsically separate” (ibid.). This is the familiar Hegelian critique of the formal nature of the understanding and the categories in Kant. It is important to note, however, that this means more
profound principles for speculative development; it contains the beginning of a true apprehension of the nature of the Notion and is completely opposed to that empty identity or abstract universality which is not within itself a synthesis.” Düsing, 1976, p. 113 has pointed out that Hegel conflates two different meanings of “synthetic” in Kant, since the synthesis referred to in the transcendental apperception is valid for all judgements, whether analytic or synthetic, and only the synthesis in a synthetic judgement is one of intuition and concept. This is astute and technically correct, but neglects the point of the B 160–161 footnote and § 24 of the Transcendental Deduction that indicate an embedding of the figurative in the intellectual synthesis. Since Hegel’s argument is explicitly based on § 24, I cannot agree with Düsing’s conclusion that Hegel’s critique of Kant is “not immanent” (p. 119). 57 Cf. SL 589/WdL II 227. For the characterization of Kant’s position as one of “formal identity” and “formal idealism” see also FK 73–81/GW IV 330–335.
64
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
than merely a rejection of an aspect of Kant’s thought with which Hegel happens to disagree. Instead, Hegel means to point out a real tension in Kant’s argument in the Transcendental Deduction between the idea of an original synthesis on one hand and the formal character of the understanding and its categories on the other. Hegel clearly sees an internal contradiction at work here. It is because of the immanent character of the contradiction that Hegel can then make the argument that Kant’s thought in and of itself is in need of a transformation that will resolve the contradiction and thus complete the Copernican revolution. If the conflict were not inherent in Kant’s position itself, Hegel’s critique of Kant could perhaps be dismissed as foreign and hence irrelevant to Kant’s thought. As we shall see, however, such judgment would be premature. But what exactly is at issue in this alleged contradiction, and where in Kant’s argument does the conflict make its appearance? We are already familiar with the fact that Hegel rejects the first of Kant’s dual-source models, viz. that of intuition and concept, and its corollary, i.e., the complete independence of sensibility and understanding. So far, Hegel’s point was that the very notion of a transcendental unity of apperception or an original synthetic unity is incompatible with this dualsource model. The latter is a combination model rather than a synthesis model. For Hegel, the combination model presupposes the separate existence and independence of category and manifold prior to their synthesis, whereas the synthesis model suggests their intrinsic unity and original identity. As we saw, even in Kant’s text there are indications that he himself found the strict independence of an original unity of self-consciousness and an independently existing manifold of intuition untenable. In other words, the idea of an original unity of understanding and manifold actually overrides and even negates the first dual-source model. As was apparent from Faith and Knowledge, Hegel is prepared to read most of the Transcendental Deduction as an attempt to work out the idea of an original synthesis. His is not primarily a critique of that part of the Deduction that deals with the transcendental syntheses (roughly, the original synthetic unity, the intellectual, and the figurative synthesis).58 There must then be some other aspect in Kant’s argument that from Hegel’s point of view re-invalidates the transcendental part of the argument of the Transcendental Deduction and therefore also seriously compromises Kant’s Copernican turn. But which aspect would this be? Let us briefly review again the formulations Hegel uses to signal what he takes to be the fundamental contradiction in Kant’s position. He claims that on one hand it is “an essential proposition of the Kantian transcendental philosophy that without intuitions notions are empty” (SL 585/WdL II 223) – in other words, the manifold of intuition is crucial for the non-emptiness of the categories. On the other, he accuses Kant of unifying understanding and sensibility only in an “external” manner. Having made a point of saying that concepts and intuitions must be originally unified, he argues, Kant then takes the sensible material to be “the absolute reality” (SL 587/WdL II 224-5), lets the “given content” drop from the Notion (i.e.
58 Both the intellectual and
the figurative synthesis are “transcendental, not merely as taking place a priori, but also as conditioning the possibility of other a priori knowledge” (B 151).
2.2
Hegel’s Critique of Kant: The Transcendental Deduction
65
the objective unity of apperception), and declares the Notion to be again empty and devoid of content (SL 589/WdL II 227). This procedure ultimately results in the Notion being “permanently conditioned by a manifold of intuition” (ibid.), although the original synthesis was supposed to be the highest principle. As a consequence, the Transcendental Deduction, which was meant to prove the unity of understanding and sensibility, of concept and intuition, of category and manifold, ends in a mere external combination of two elements that remain “intrinsically separate” (ibid.). Now nowhere, it seems, does Kant declare the original unity of selfconsciousness or the transcendental unity of apperception to be “empty and devoid of content”, nor does he pronounce the sensory material to be the “absolute reality”. Quite to the contrary, he seems to affirm the opposite by insisting that empirical things are indeed only appearances (in the transcendental sense), not things-inthemselves. We may wonder, therefore, what factual basis there can be for Hegel’s critique. One thing is clear – Hegel believes that a breach of an initial promise occurs somewhere in the Transcendental Deduction: The further development [sc. of the Transcendental Deduction] . . . does not fulfill the promise of the beginning. The very expression synthesis easily recalls the conception of an external unity and a mere combination of entities that are intrinsically separate (SL 589/WdL II 227).
I suggest that what Hegel has in mind when referring to this breach of a promise is the fact that according to Kant the original synthetic unity of self-consciousness and the intellectual and figurative syntheses together are as yet insufficient by themselves to determine objects of experience. In addition, there is required an input from sensation and a synthesis of apprehension, i.e. an “empirical synthesis”,59 without which categories can have no application to objects of experience. In other words, the transcendental part of the Transcendental Deduction (i.e. the part dealing with the three transcendental syntheses) is incomplete, a necessary, but not a sufficient condition for the a priori determination of “real” objects. The intellectual synthesis unifies the pure manifold of intuition in general, the figurative synthesis unifies the manifold of formal intuition, and therefore determines inner sense only with respect to its form, not its content. But as Kant had already argued in § 22 of the Transcendental Deduction, the thought of an object in general, by means of a pure concept of the understanding, can become knowledge for us only in so far as the concept is related to objects of the senses . . . Through the determination of pure intuition we can acquire a priori knowledge of objects [my italics], as in mathematics, but only in regard to their form, as appearances; whether there can be things [my italics] which must be intuited in this form, is still left undecided . . . Now things in space and time are given only in so far as they are perceptions (that is, representations accompanied by sensation) – therefore only through empirical representation . . . Even, therefore, with the aid of [pure] intuition, the categories do not afford us any knowledge of things; they do so only through their possible application to empirical intuition (B 146-7).
146: “All possible perception is . . . dependent upon synthesis of apprehension, and this empirical synthesis in turn upon transcendental synthesis . . .”
59 B
66
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
In other words, only if it can be shown that categories “apply” to perceptions (or their sensory element) can we say that the understanding is capable of an a priori determination of things rather than objects in general. Consequently, even the objective reference that categories acquire through the determination of the form of inner sense on account of the figurative synthesis does not yet yield a priori knowledge of things, i.e. of objects of experience. As Kant explains in § 26, in addition there is needed a synthesis of apprehension by which he understands that combination of the manifold in an empirical intuition, whereby perception, that is, empirical consciousness of the intuition . . . is possible (B 160).
According to this argument, the Transcendental Deduction is systematically incomplete without the integration of the “manifold in an empirical intuition”.60 For Hegel, this means that the preceding transcendental syntheses are retroactively declared to be only formal and in this sense “empty and devoid of content”. Although they must be syntheses of some manifold, this manifold represents only the form and not yet the matter of appearances, not yet the realitas phenomenon.61 Hegel’s point, then, is that the transcendental syntheses are “empty” insofar as they lack a material that would give them “real” content. The transcendental content provided by the pure manifold of intuition and the “formal” content of the forms of intuition do not specify real objects. A passage from the Discipline of Pure Reason illustrates the point: . . . the matter of appearances, by which things are given us in space and time, can only be represented in perception, and therefore a posteriori. The only concept which represents a priori this empirical content of appearances is the concept of a thing in general, and the a priori synthetic knowledge of this thing in general can give us nothing more than the mere rule of the synthesis of that which perception may give us a posteriori. It can never yield an a priori intuition of the real object, since this must necessarily be empirical (A 720/ B 748).
If the content of the transcendental syntheses is only formal, then the truly heterogeneous element in the Transcendental Deduction is the manifold in an empirical intuition. This manifold, however, is not part of any original synthetic or transcendental unity. In this sense, it drops out of what Hegel calls the Concept. The 60 As
noted earlier, the manifold of inner sense seems to me to be what Kant elsewhere refers to as “the undetermined object of an empirical intuition”: “That intuition which is in relation to the object through sensation, is entitled empirical. The undetermined object of an empirical intuition is entitled appearance” (A 19–20/ B 34). See also the reference to “the raw material of the sensible impressions” that has to be “worked up” into “that knowledge of objects which is entitled experience” at A 1/B 1. The fatal problem for the Transcendental Deduction will be that the manifold of inner sense cannot be derived from experience, since this would be a violation of the transcendental standpoint. It would thus have to be a proto-empirical manifold which due to the synthesis of apprehension in accordance with the categories bifurcates into the subjective and objective representation of objects of experience. Obviously, some such proto-empirical material is needed, if the determination of objects is to be a priori. Husserl’s hyle represents a comparable theoretical posit (see Husserl, Ideen I, §§ 85, 97). 61 For realitas phenomenon cf. A 166: “In all appearances sensation, and the real which corresponds to it in the object (realitas phenomenon), has an intensive magnitude, that is, a degree.”
2.2
Hegel’s Critique of Kant: The Transcendental Deduction
67
heterogeneous element within the immanence of thought or apperception is not in fact a genuine “other”. We now have an objective unity of apperception standing over against an as yet undetermined, pre-conceptual, sensory manifold to which the categories must be applied in order to yield knowledge of things. This manifold is required to complete the Transcendental Deduction, which would remain a torso without it. It is therefore correct to say (as Kant does) that the manifold in empirical intuition functions as the key element without which the purpose of the Deduction could not be achieved. Moreover, the application model now re-introduced is again based on the idea of a combination of two elements existing independently of one another. Empirical manifold and unity of apperception cannot be originally unified, their synthesis is a “mere combination of entities that are intrinsically separate”, to use Hegel’s expression. The sensory element of cognition is not itself part of the objective unity of apperception, the latter only provides a rule in accordance with which the former is synthesized. From Hegel’s point of view, the situation reached at the end of the Transcendental Deduction looks as follows. At the end of the Transcendental Deduction, the matterform model re-emerges as the authoritative model of cognition. With the idea of a transcendental unity of apperception and a transcendental synthesis of concept and intuition Kant had already appealed to a “higher principle in which a duality in a unity could be cognized” (SL 594/WdL II 233). Compared to the idea of an original synthesis, the matter-form model is derivative, for if the synthesis is truly original, the dual source model has effectively been overcome. Now, however, it turns out that the matter-form distinction provides the fundamental framework within which the transcendental syntheses are located. We therefore face the curious situation that the model of cognition that is subordinate to the idea of an original synthesis nonetheless dominates the architectonic of the argument of the Transcendental Deduction. To put it somewhat provocatively, a synthesis a posteriori functions as the capstone of an argument built around the idea of a synthesis a priori. Hegel’s criticism thus consists in the objection that the conclusion of the Deduction re-invalidates its transcendental beginning. Or, despite the Copernican turn Kant fails to break free entirely of the empiricist model of cognition and its matter-form dichotomy. The matter-form model is committed to an understanding of knowledge as a relating of concepts to a content given independently of them. In the matter-form model, the spheres of thought and of the real are supposed to have an “intrinsically separate” existence. However, the transcendental paradigm with its incorporation of the domain of referentiality into the immanence of thought was meant to explain the possibility of such a matter-form relationship in the first place. Consequently, the matter-form approach cannot itself be used to ground referentiality, if a petitio is to be avoided. The Copernican turn requires that the notion of an independent “given” be dismissed.62 62 The
so-called “myth of the given” has recently become the primary focus of a rethinking of Kant’s dualism of intuition and concept towards a unified position that takes some of its inspiration from Hegel’s argument in the Phenomenology: see McDowell, 1994, 1998 and Brandom, 1994, 2000. But note that we are dealing with two dualisms, the intuition-concept and the matter-form
68
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
It seems to me that Hegel’s diagnosis of a conflict within the Transcendental Deduction between two models of cognition is essentially correct. Based on his reading of § 24 of the Transcendental Deduction, Hegel is apparently willing to grant that Kant has managed to overcome the initial concept-intuition dualism and to replace it with a genuine synthetic unity of intuition and concept. (Here he is more charitable to Kant than I was prepared to be in my earlier analysis of § 24 and the B 160-1 footnote.) However, the fact that Kant then admits that the transcendental syntheses achieve only part of the task of the deduction means that the unity of apperception produced through these syntheses is as yet empty, i.e. without the required a priori referentiality to (sensible) objects of experience.63 No reference to objects “in the weighty sense”, i.e. things, has yet been established. The first step of the deduction thus produces a merely formal unity of apperception that (apart from the formal intuition) still lacks content. This admission re-introduces what Hegel elsewhere calls the “opposition of consciousness” into the Transcendental Deduction and thus invalidates the transcendental strategy. In this sense, the empiricist matter-form model trumps the transcendental synthesis model of cognition. The question is whether Hegel’s formalism critique is convincing and whether it pinpoints the real problem with the introduction of an empirical manifold. I will explain why I hesitate to answer the first part of the question in the affirmative and why I am skeptical that Hegel’s critique succeeds in identifying the real problem with the empirical manifold. First, then, Hegel is certainly right that the empirical manifold is “intrinsically separate” from the a priori forms of cognition. Unlike the pure manifold or formal intuition it is not only a heterogeneous element but also extraneous to the transcendental unity of apperception, notwithstanding the fact that Kant thinks he can show how this material can be integrated into the synthetic unity of (pure) intuition and concepts. The givenness of this manifold “from elsewhere” means, however, that Kant has indeed relapsed into an empiricist model of cognition in which a given material is supposed to be appropriated by forms of cognition existing in the mind a priori. The crucial point here is that this second step in the Transcendental Deduction is supposed to function as the completion of a transcendental argument that aims at bringing empirical content under the rules of the transcendental syntheses. But how could an empiricist model of cognition ever complete a transcendental argument, since it itself presupposes the completion of the transcendental argument? Only on the basis of a successful transcendental argument can the possibility of the empiricist model of cognition be explained. It is because thought and intuition determine objects a priori that empirical knowledge is in principle possible. Seen in this way, Kant’s actual procedure constitutes a petitio. dualism. Overcoming the former is not yet overcoming the latter as well. To properly address these anti-dualist approaches – now often referred to as Sellarsian – from a Hegelian perspective would require a separate discussion. The Kantian dualism of concept and intuition has strong defenders as well: see again Guyer, 2000. 63 In Kant’s words: No “possible employment in experience [my italics] of the pure concepts of the understanding” has yet been deduced (see title of § 26).
2.2
Hegel’s Critique of Kant: The Transcendental Deduction
69
However, if we look at the fine print of § 26, so to speak, we see that Kant is careful to avoid the empiricist model of feeding sensory content directly into the unity of apperception. The argument is not about the empirical manifold per se but about its synthesis called synthesis of apprehension. And of this synthesis Kant claims that it “must always conform” (B 160) to the transcendental “synthesis of apperception” (B 161, footnote b). He also makes an effort to establish an intimate connection between the empirical synthesis of apprehension and the transcendental synthesis of apperception in so far as both are said to derive from “one and the same spontaneity” (B 161, footnote b). Consequently, the empirical manifold is appropriated and integrated into the unity of consciousness by a function that obeys the rules of the transcendental syntheses. There is no object or thing for consciousness to perceive independently of the synthesis of apprehension. Hence Kant tells us that this synthesis makes the empirical consciousness of an intuition (called perception) possible in the first place.64 In other words, the synthesis of apprehension cannot take place without being also subject to the transcendental syntheses, and in this sense there is no petitio. Specifically, the model is not empiricist in any straightforward sense, since the empirical manifold appropriated in this way is not a ready-made, already empirically determined content (as, for instance in the case of Lockean simple ideas). The problem that remains for Kant (and which we will ignore here) is to explain the origin of this manifold, since it cannot very well be generated by the epistemic subject itself. This brings me to what I believe is the real issue with Kant’s empirical manifold, which is that the matter for cognition, i.e. the empirical manifold of inner sense, cannot be either determined or undetermined. It cannot possess any specifiable or descriptive features because those can arise only after or on the basis of the synthesis of apprehension. Only by virtue of this synthesis do we have a consciousness of perceiving something determinate. But to argue that the manifold must therefore be undetermined leads to equally unacceptable results. To assume that this manifold is already empirically determined or can be derived directly from experience and fed into the pre-existing framework of the empirical and transcendental syntheses would be a violation of the transcendental standpoint. To accept the existence of an already empirically determined sensible manifold would simply beg the transcendental question. Determinate empirical objects (“things”) are after all supposed to arise on the basis of, not to precede transcendental determination. Consequently, in order to be imported into the transcendental framework of the Transcendental Deduction, the manifold must be without an intrinsic determination of its own. However, in that case the empirical and the transcendental syntheses must be understood to be operating on an empirically undetermined manifold (viz. the “undetermined object of an empirical intuition” of A 20/B 34, or the “the raw material of sensible impressions” of B 1), a mere sensory hyle.65 In that case, the a priori
64 Cf.
B 160. find support for this claim in Hofmann, 2002, p. 39: “Kant denkt sich . . . (empirisches) Bewußtsein, wie es bei Wahrnehmungen vorliegt, als das ‘Auffassen’ oder ‘Aufgreifen’ und
65 I
70
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
determination of appearances is under no constraint from a heterogeneous material at all. The distinction between a Kantian “given” and a Fichtean Anstoß seems to become elusive. So whether one does or does not believe that with the synthesis of apprehension the Transcendental Deduction is in violation of the Copernican principle of the a priori determination of objects, the situation seems equally problematic. As a result, the objective unity of self-consciousness remains empty and the basic structures of the various categorial syntheses have no sensible matter of cognition to which they could be “applied”. In light of our initial problem of preserving the possibility of normative standards of objective knowledge from within the immanence of experience the result we have reached suggests that we need to abandon the Kantian version of the transcendental argument. This conclusion entails, at least on one reading of it, the consequence that I briefly indicated at the beginning of this section. If the empirical manifold must become part of the objective unity of consciousness since without it this unity would remain empty, but cannot also remain undetermined, then the point of departure of our argument must change radically. Instead of having the forms of sensibility and understanding determine objects a priori we start with the premise that these objects, i.e. the contents of experience, already contains all a priori determinations. This will no doubt look like a massive petitio at first, but we are going to see that the argument actually consists in a critical evaluation of the presumptive a priori character of the structures that give meaning and coherence to our experience such that our premise is not an unquestionable presupposition but indeed only a presumption. In other words, the new starting point assumes that our experience is already saturated with a priori structures and normative standards, but that these structures and standards will be subject to a critical review of their validity.66 During the course of this critique, it will become clear that there are different levels of objectivity that successively fall short of the standard they themselves claim to embody. They will therefore be replaced by another standard that is presumptively more adequate, until a level of objectivity is reached that no longer falls short of its own standard. In this way, we perform a critical review of all levels of objectivity from within the immanence of experience itself, a strategy of critiquing the standards of objectivity undertaken by the subject that discerns those standards as being inherent in its experience. The reader will have guessed correctly that the procedure just sketched is the one developed by Hegel in the Phenomenology of Spirit, to which we now turn. The analysis of the role of the empirical manifold in Kant’s Transcendental Deduction has thus lead us quite naturally to Hegel’s attempt to overcome the shortcomings of Kant’s strategy as he sees them.
Verknüpfen oder Synthetisieren von prä-repräsentationalem Empfindungs-Mannigfaltigem [a combination or synthesizing of a pre-representational manifold of sensory data]” (my italics). Whether perceptual consciousness involves a categorial synthesis or not, remains, however, unclear: “Ob diese Art von Bewußtsein – das Wahrnehmungsbewußtsein – nach Kant begrifflich oder nichtbegrifflich verfaßt ist, ist schwer zu entscheiden.” 66 This will be the real critique of the categories and their ability to grasp the truth that Hegel missed in Kant.
2.3
Beyond the Matter-Form Distinction: Hegel as a Philosopher of Radical Immanence
71
2.3 Beyond the Matter-Form Distinction: Hegel as a Philosopher of Radical Immanence Hegel’s Introduction to the Science of Logic is one of the key texts not only for understanding his critique of Kant but also of the Hegelian project as a whole. The reader of the Introduction cannot fail to notice the ambitiousness of the project Hegel presents there. It is no less ambitious than the project formulated by Kant in the Prefaces to the Critique of Pure Reason. Not only does Hegel introduce a new type of logic, he also proposes to replace an entire paradigm of cognition and the concept of truth that it implies with something new. The old paradigm is described as follows: Hitherto, the concept of logic has rested on the separation . . . of the content of cognition and its form, or of truth and certainty. First, it is assumed that the material of knowledge is present on its own account as a ready-made world apart from thought, that thinking on its own is empty and comes as an external form to the said material, fills itself with it and only thus acquires a content and so becomes real knowing (SL 44/WdL I 24).67
The separation of content and form of cognition is also described as a separation of matter and form, object and consciousness, object and subject, and object and thought. All these oppositions are meant to refer to the same phenomenon, i.e. the so-called “opposition of consciousness” (SL 49/WdL I 30), because Hegel believes that these oppositions have their root in the basic structure of “our ordinary, phenomenal consciousness” (SL 45/WdL I 25). However, without the rise to dominance of so-called “reflective understanding” (ibid.) at the beginning of modern philosophy – i.e., with Descartes – this cognitive structure of ordinary consciousness would not have become the reigning paradigm in philosophy. For Hegel, the issue of the opposition of consciousness is so central to philosophy that the meaning of the history of modern philosophy can be derived from it. Modern philosophy is essentially the process of the emergence and the subsequent overcoming of this opposition and the paradigm of representational knowledge and truth that is bound up with it. The separation of mind and world constitutes a “prejudice” of ordinary consciousness. If such prejudices are carried out into the sphere of reason as if the same relation [of subject and object] obtained there, as if this relation were something true in its own self, then they are errors the refutation of which throughout every part of the spiritual and natural universe is philosophy, or rather, as they bar the entrance to philosophy, must be discarded at its portals (SL 45/WdL I 25).
Strong words indeed, but they give us a good idea of what Hegel considered his real task to be – to overcome this opposition of consciousness and the theories of
67 One cannot but notice the parallel here with Kant’s famous Copernican line “Hitherto it has been
assumed that all our knowledge must conform to objects” from the Preface to the B edition of the Critique (B xvi).
72
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
cognition and truth connected with it. For with the introduction of the separation between object and thought the notion of [objective] truth is lost; it is limited to knowing only subjective truth, only phenomena, appearances, only something to which the nature of the object itself does not correspond: knowing has lapsed into opinion (SL 45/WdL I 26).
In Hegel’s eyes, Kant’s contribution marks the first step in the task of overcoming this opposition and of retrieving the idea of objective truth. It is also the decisive step. Even Fichte’s work (and Schelling’s as well) is of less importance in comparison. Although Fichte took his point of departure from Kant’s revolutionary insight, he later “abandoned” the attempt to “develop the content of pure science” (SL 47/WdL I 28). It was Kant who with the idea of an original synthetic unity proposed the new paradigm of cognition and truth that would replace the old. But, as we already saw in the preceding sections, Hegel believes that Kant was not able to free himself completely from the influence of the old paradigm. Accordingly, critical philosophy was “overawed by the object” (SL 51/WdL I 32), overawed, that is, by the externality requirement of the content of knowledge. Kant’s Copernican turn remained burdened with a commitment to the older paradigm based on the opposition of consciousness, and it is this older paradigm that in the end emerged as the authoritative one for Kant. Kant had initiated the paradigm shift, but he did not complete it. Hegel’s task as he himself understood it is therefore to overcome the remnants of the old paradigm, to hold on to Kant’s transcendental insight and to bring it to fruition. With the benefit of hindsight, the emergence of the opposition of consciousness, which at first looked like “a loss and a retrograde step” (SL 46/WdL I 26) in comparison with the Ancients, was in truth a necessary stage in the development of reason. It forces thinking to examine the naïve belief in cognition’s capacity for truth in a critical light. Although this examination may at first lead to skepticism, it will eventually prepare the ground “on which rests the elevation of reason into the loftier spirit of modern philosophy” (ibid.). Indeed, as Hegel remarks in the General Division with reference to Kant . . . if philosophy was to make any real progress, it was necessary [my italics] that the interest of thought should be drawn to a consideration . . . of the ego, consciousness as such, i.e. of the abstract relation of a subjective knowing to an object, so that in this way the cognition of the infinite form, that is, of the Notion, would be introduced (SL 63/WdL I 46).
Hegel’s phrase “infinite form” refers to the original synthetic unity of selfconsciousness, which is “infinite” precisely because it no longer stands in opposition to an external world or a reality opposed to thought, but instead conceives of mind and world as one original unity of subject and object. According to Hegel, this is the Kantian nucleus that is to be preserved. However, there is yet another opposition of consciousness that affects Kant’s argument apart from the matter-form distinction operative in the Transcendental Deduction, and this is the distinction between appearances (in the transcendental sense) and things as they are in themselves. In Hegel’s later exposition of Kant’s theory as we find it in the Introduction to the 1830 Encyclopedia, Hegel’s assessment focuses more
2.3
Beyond the Matter-Form Distinction: Hegel as a Philosopher of Radical Immanence
73
on the distinction between the immanence and transcendence of consciousness than that between the matter and the form of cognition. Now Hegel seems to think that the opposition between matter and form, or subjective representation and objective truth, has indeed been resolved in Kant’s transcendental stance. Note that this is something Hegel wasn’t quite willing to concede in Faith and Knowledge. It would in fact mean that he is now prepared to recognize the success of the Transcendental Deduction per se and that he objects only to the restriction thesis that Kant imposes on knowledge. In any case, rather than focusing on the internal structure of the Deduction, Hegel now claims that in overcoming one opposition Kant has simultaneously created another. Commenting on the treatment of the categories, he remarks that Kant’s investigation of them concerns only their formal characteristic according to which these concepts of the understanding qua subjective nonetheless are constitutive of objectivity. But Kant does not examine the content of these concepts and ask whether that content is itself a true content.68 While the “antithesis” between the subjective and the objective is thus overcome within experience, the Critical Philosophy nonetheless extends the antithesis in such a way that experience in its entirety falls within subjectivity; i.e., both of these elements [i.e., the subjective and the objective] together are subjective, and nothing remains in contrast with subjectivity except the thing in itself (E § 41).
Now it is no longer the empirical manifold that makes the unity of apperception a finite whole but the opposition between appearances and things in themselves. By qualifying the realm of empirical objects as appearances, Kant has redefined the objective dimension of experience as again only subjective, which entails a new opposition between the subjective and the objective, but an objectivity that now transcends experience entirely and is therefore by definition unknowable. Now, if we set aside the thing in itself and concentrate on the Kantian version of the immanence of experience as a domain of objectivity that is grounded in subjective acts of synthesis, Kant’s position does not seem to be that far apart anymore from the contemporary positions we discussed in the previous chapter, in particular those of Abel and Lenk. On closer inspection, however, we notice that Kant’s universalist position rejects an ingredient that is essential to interpretationism, viz. the pluralism of what counts as objective in accordance with different interpretive practices and forms of life. Conversely, interpretationism lacks an account of the necessity of universally normative standards of cognition. On the other hand, it need not subscribe to Kant’s restriction thesis such that the scope of experience extends beyond the world of the senses and the natural sciences.
68 Cf.
E § 41. If Kant had examined the content of the categories, he would have realized that these concepts generate objects that are not the true objects of knowledge but finite entities that are appearances not only for us but in themselves, i.e. objectively. Consequently, they should not be considered to constitute the norm of objectivity. By contrast, the true objects of knowledge, viz. the ideas of reason, are considered to be subjective epistemic principles. For Hegel, this is a case of standing things on their head.
74
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
Whether the unity of apperception is limited by a heterogeneous empirical manifold or whether the domain of possible experience of objects is limited by the concept of things as they are in themselves (Kant’s noumenon in the negative sense), the dual source model of cognition and thus the opposition of consciousness prevails in either case and with it an essentially empiricist model of cognition containing a speculative nucleus. The consequence Hegel draws from his diagnosis of this situation is to advocate the enlargement, so to speak, of this nucleus, i.e. the extension of the sphere of experience such that it incorporates the empirical manifold (qua already determined manifold) together with the realm that transcends consciousness into the immanence of consciousness. We thus achieve a position of radical immanence, an immanence without transcendence, or an immanence in which all transcendence is transcendence within immanence. As we shall see shortly, this position marks the point of departure and the trajectory of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Beginning with a manifold that is poor in determinations, we progressively integrate a richer transcendence that is a transcendence only for an as yet finite consciousness, but is already part of the immanence of experience. In the process, consciousness learns to integrate this transcendence. At the same time, it thereby transforms itself, steadily extending the nucleus of rationality until that nucleus is transformed into the totality of experience. To be sure, Hegel’s argument does not end there, i.e., with the chapter called Absolute Knowing in the Phenomenology of Spirit. Indeed, this part of Hegel’s project serves only as the necessary preparation and groundwork for the subsequent task of reconstructing the normative standards of objectivity that are valid for and within this radical immanence of experience, a task undertaken in the Logic and the system as presented in the Encyclopedia. But more on this later. For now, I would like to point out that Hegel re-traces the trajectory of his argument very deliberately and very clearly in the Introduction to the Science of Logic. Taking his point of departure from Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception he comments that this unity had to be liberated from its finitude so that the “infinite form”, “untainted by the finitude of consciousness” (SL 63/WdL I 46), could then freely determine itself: . . . in order that this cognition [sc. of the infinite form, i.e. the Concept] could be reached, that form has still to be relieved of the finite determinateness in which it is ego, or consciousness. The form, when thus thought out into its purity [in ihre Reinheit herausgedacht], will have within itself the capacity to determine itself, that is, to give itself a content, and that a necessarily explicated content – in the form of a system of determinations of thought (SL 63/WdL I 46).
Here, in a few lines, we see Hegel describing the program of the completion of Kant’s Copernican revolution. First, Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception, still burdened by an opposition to the empirical manifold or, alternatively, the limiting concept of the thing in itself, will have to be thought out into its purity until radical immanence is reached (= the project of the Phenomenology of Spirit) in order then to let thinking determine its own categorial structure and its standards of objectivity (= the project of the Science of Logic).
2.3
Beyond the Matter-Form Distinction: Hegel as a Philosopher of Radical Immanence
75
Hegel’s philosophy, in particular the Logic and the Encyclopedia, are often said to be a metaphysics, occasionally even a metaphysics of the hubristic kind.69 I would like to emphasize that Hegel is a philosopher of the immanence of experience and, in the Logic, of the immanence of thought. That means that metaphysics with its stipulation of supersensible entities and causes that are located outside the immanence of experience in a transcendent realm has no proper place in Hegel’s thought. No other philosopher (with the exception perhaps of Spinoza) has repudiated and systematically dissolved the separation of the mundane and the supersensible as thoroughly as Hegel, and in such a way that both spheres are unified into one homogeneous sphere of experience.70 We should not be misled by Hegel’s frequent reference to the Absolute or God. These are technically speaking expressions for the immanence of experience and thought, or the closed totality that, like the Parmenidean One, has nothing outside itself, not even nothingness. It is true that in the Encyclopedia, Hegel goes so far as to characterize his Logic as a theory of the “definitions of the Absolute, as the metaphysical definitions of God” (E § 85). But again, this needs to be understood properly in its context. First, the fact that the Encyclopedia, especially with its posthumous Additions to Hegel’s published text, belongs to what one might call Hegel’s exoteric writings71 should be an indicator that this language includes a dose of pedagogic popularization and/or a deliberate attempt on Hegel’s part to intervene in public controversies about the nature of his philosophy.72 And second, what is meant by “metaphysical” should be seen in the light of Hegel’s definition of metaphysics in the Logic, viz. as the “scientific construction of the world in thought alone” (SL 63/WdL I 46). This definition excludes any connotation of metaphysical realism, representationalism, or reference to supersensible entities. Moreover, the Science of Logic, which I would call an esoteric work by comparison, avoids almost all references to God, and its technical definition of the Absolute makes this category an abstract precursor of the Spinozistic substance, the identity of the inner and outer aspects of essence. In other words, the Absolute is here strictly speaking one moment of the totality of the “system of concepts” [System der Begriffe] (SL 54/WdL I 36) or the “system of the determinations of thought” [System der Denkbestimmungen] (SL 63/WdL I 46). I suggest, therefore, that Hegel is primarily the philosopher of the immanence of experience and of thought and, in this respect, much closer to contemporary interpretationist theories than any traditional classical philosopher. But in addition he 69 Frederick
Beiser has been a proponent of the interpretation of Hegel as a metaphysician against those who see in Hegel a philosopher of a broadly transcendental orientation or one who advances an ontology or a non-metaphysical theory of categories. A good overview of the arguments pro and con can be found in Wartenberg (1993), Beiser (1993, 1995), Pinkard (1990), and Pippin (1990). I will address these interpretations in greater detail again below (see Section 4.3). 70 Cf. Brinkmann, 2006. 71 See below, Section 4.3. 72 These intellectual, religious and political controversies have been retraced in Toews, 1993, Jaeschke, 1986, and Dickey, 1993, among others.
76
2
Kant and the Problem of Objectivity
also offers the possibility of studying a conception of philosophy that allows for the defense of the objectivity of knowledge. Indeed, in this combination, I submit, consists in large part his contemporary relevance. He has room for many forms of life and interpretive practices and therefore avoids reductionisms of any kind, although he insists on a critical evaluation of the standards of objectivity and truth built into different interpretive practices. According to the view presented here, the theory that comes out of the self-critical, self-corrective review of the shapes of consciousness in the Phenomenology of Spirit is not a metaphysics but a critical ontology, a grammar of thought, i.e. a reconstruction of the fundamental conceptual framework that conditions and makes possible the adjudication of truth claims at all levels of experience. The method of this critical self-evaluation of thought is not a Kantian-type transcendental argument but the dialectic that relies on the autonomous conceptual logic inherent in the categories, a logic that defines the space or latitude of our interpretations but is not itself an interpretation. In my view, then, Hegel should be taken at his word when he says that his “objective logic . . . takes the place . . . of the former metaphysics . . .” (SL 63/WdL I 46). And while elsewhere he admits that his philosophy discusses (in part) the same fundamental concepts as the former metaphysics, his emphasis on their development and transformation should be taken seriously as well.73 There are two passages in particular that show Hegel’s commitment to a reconstruction of the framework of the fundamental categories of thought from within the immanence of experience. One is the discussion of the methodological procedure followed in the Phenomenology of Spirit presented towards the end of the Introduction to this work. This I will examine in greater detail in the opening section of the following chapter. The other such passage comes from § 6 of the Introduction to the Encyclopedia Logic and is worth quoting at length: . . . philosophy should be quite clear about the fact that its content (Inhalt) is nothing other than the basic content (Gehalt) that is originally produced and produces itself in the domain of the living spirit, the content that is made into the world, the outer and inner world of consciousness; in other words, the content (Inhalt) of philosophy is actuality. The first consciousness of this content is called experience . . . Since philosophy is distinguished only in form from other ways of becoming conscious of this same identical basic content (Gehalt), its accord with actuality and experience is necessary.
Hegel here makes a distinction between the content of philosophy generally and the way or form in which one becomes conscious of or analyzes and appropriates this content. The content of philosophy according to this explanation is none other than the world of experience, such that experience and philosophy have one and the same content, also called “actuality” (Wirklichkeit).74 This “outer and inner world of consciousness” encompasses all of human experience and includes the domains 73 Cf.
E § 9R: “Speculative Logic contains the older logic and metaphysics; it preserves the same forms of thought, laws, and objects, but it develops and transforms them with further categories.” See also SL 31, 52–53/WdL I 9, 34. 74 Which is why the “accord” of philosophy with actuality and experience is “necessary” and “an outward touchstone, at least, for the truth of a philosophy” (E § 6).
2.3
Beyond the Matter-Form Distinction: Hegel as a Philosopher of Radical Immanence
77
of “freedom, spirit, and God” (E § 8). For although the latter “are not experienced by the senses,” still “everything that is in consciousness at all is experienced” – this, Hegel adds, is even “a tautological proposition” (ibid.). The form in which this content exists or is immediately present to consciousness is likewise that of experience, whereas philosophy’s purpose is to “translate” the “genuine content of our consciousness,” i.e., “our feelings, and representations (Vorstellungen)” into thoughts (E § 5, cf. § E 3R), and furthermore these thoughts into the concept (cf. § E 20R). Philosophy is a thinking over of the content of experience in order to comprehend it and to determine “what is true in things and occurrences, as well as in feelings, intuitions, opinions, representations, etc.” (E § 5). To sum up, Hegel makes it very clear that the content of philosophy is the same as the content of human experience, that this experience is all-inclusive in the sense that whatever is in consciousness is part of our experience, and that philosophy consists essentially in translating the content of immediate experience into the form of thought.75 This translation occurs in a two-step conceptualization such that the representational, emotional, practical, religious, etc. content of experience is transformed into concepts (= the business of philosophy and the sciences generally throughout history and, more specifically, the business of the Phenomenology of Spirit) in order then to be further re-connected and reconstructed in a “system of concepts” in the Logic. It now remains to be seen how Hegel, taking the immanence of experience as his starting-point, manages to establish a normative standard of truth and objectivity while at the same time accepting the proposition that the content of experience is already saturated with a priori structures or principles. It seems that the only way to avoid an obvious petitio here is to critique each proposed a priori structure or principle in such a way that it reveals itself as preliminary. How this can be done without presupposing other, as yet unexamined a priori structures or principles as a normative standard of critique will require a satisfactory explanation, if Hegel’s project is not to disqualify itself from the start. This is why I suggest that we start the next chapter with an examination of the methodological presuppositions of Hegel’s argument in the Phenomenology.
75 See
also E §§ 1–3.
Chapter 3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
3.1 Methodological Presuppositions As we saw earlier, to overcome the opposition of consciousness and to establish complete immanence of consciousness means to transcend the limitations of finite consciousness as a principle of a priori determination of objectivity and to transform the finite unity of intuition and concept into the infinite “form” of the Concept. This means that the Phenomenology must begin with a finite consciousness, and then show why and how this finite principle develops into the radical immanence of the Concept or of Absolute Knowing. Hegel’s candidate for the initial form in which finite consciousness comes on the scene is sense-certainty. But the conditions under which the Phenomenology unfolds its argument are complex. To understand this complexity, I will first look at the larger picture, i.e. the location of the Phenomenology within Hegel’s system. As is well known, Hegel integrated a truncated version of the Phenomenology into the Encyclopedia system where it occupies the second stage in the Philosophy of Subjective Spirit, preceded by the Anthropology (Hegel’s theory of the human soul) and followed by the Psychology (Hegel’s theory of subjective reason in its cognitive and practical aspects). Next, I will discuss the methodological strategy Hegel develops in the Introduction to the Phenomenology with which he hopes to demonstrate how the self-transformation of finite consciousness into infinite self-consciousness or pure thought is possible and how it can be seen to be a necessary one.1 At both the macro-level of the system and at the level of the Phenomenology’s internal methodology there exists an issue with the circularity of Hegel’s argument that we will need to address. Consciousness is characterized by the opposition between itself and an other – the world, or what it takes to be the real. It understands itself as confronting something “immediately given” and external (cf. E § 415A), a world of particulars existing independently of it to which it relates as “something essentially other than it” (E § 416A). Thus consciousness is from the start in relation to an other by which it knows itself to be limited – hence the opposition between a “mental” sphere that is 1 In
the Preface to the Phenomenology, Hegel uses “pure I”, “pure self-consciousness”, “pure thought”, “pure Concept”, “pure spirituality” more or less synonymously.
79 K. Brinkmann, Idealism Without Limits, Philosophical Studies in Contemporary C Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Culture 18, DOI 10.1007/978-90-481-3622-3_3,
80
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
believed to be “subjective” in nature and an extra-mental, “objective” world that represents “true” reality on the other, a distinction typical of “our ordinary, phenomenal consciousness” (SL 45/WdL I 25). Due to this opposition between a “subjective” mind and an “objective” world, consciousness understands itself as finite, limited by an independent object that is more or less opaque to it. Sense-Certainty, however, with which the Phenomenology’s argument begins, is only implicitly in opposition to its object. While the distinction between self and world is already present, sensecertainty represents the immediate relation of self and object. Hegel must therefore show how and why the opposition of consciousness emerges out of sense-certainty. In the chapter on Perception, this opposition becomes explicit and fully manifest. It is there, too, that a first attempt will be made to overcome it. We will take up this part of Hegel’s argument below. Now the description of consciousness as relating to something other than itself only partially captures the conditions already in place at the start of the argument of the Phenomenology. For how could consciousness overcome the opposition between itself and the object, let alone develop into the infinite unity of the Concept, if in truth it represented only one element within this unity, viz. the form of knowledge in separation from its object? There would then be no epistemic continuity between consciousness and Concept. Consciousness could not become identical with the Concept, nor the Concept emerge from consciousness. They could not be said to be at bottom identical. As a result, nor could there be an overcoming of the opposition of consciousness either, and consciousness could not develop into pure self-consciousness or pure thought. Clearly, then, consciousness can embark on its educational journey only, if it is already implicitly reason, pure thought or the Concept. The 1807 Phenomenology is relatively silent on this important fact, at least in the discussion of its own methodology in the Introduction. There, Hegel creates the impression that we could start with the standpoint of consciousness itself. Only at the very end of the Phenomenology does he comment on the fact that the content of consciousness, i.e. the various stages of its experience from sense-certainty to religion, “is Spirit that traverses its own self” (PS § 799/3, 583). In other words, from the very start consciousness is already in some sense the totality that is to emerge from it – except that it is not conscious of this fact. That consciousness “produces” reason, spirit or the Concept from out of itself is therefore an oblique way of saying that pure thought or the Concept come to manifest themselves in and through consciousness as their medium. To understand this unspoken assumption underlying the Phenomenology’s project, we turn to the opening sections of the Encyclopedia Phenomenology (E §§ 413–417). There we can see that consciousness already has a history or a conceptual genealogy. It is preceded by the soul as the immediate identity of self and world, which Hegel describes in the Anthropology in its various stages of oneness with nature, internal differentiation, and of the emerging integration of soul and nature in the form of a soul-body unity.2 In developing a “feeling” for itself the soul
2 The
soul assimilates the otherness of nature by making the body a sign and tool of the soul: see Dodd, 1995.
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
81
gradually overcomes its immersion in and its symbiosis with nature and as “actual soul” acquires a sense of its own identity (cf. E § 411). The soul’s emerging sense of selfhood marks the point at which it becomes conscious of itself as distinct from its natural immersion in nature. Herein lies the origin of consciousness as a self and the opposition it posits between itself and an other, an opposition paradigmatic of this form of cognition. Consciousness is relational and representational precisely because it is soul become conscious of having emerged from its immersion in nature. In other words, consciousness is relational and representational because in grasping itself as an “I” or subject the soul ipso facto begins to differentiate between its selfhood or its being-for-self and its relatedness to something other than itself – a world existing independently of it to which it relates as an external object but which also exists for it qua represented in consciousness (cf. E § 413). Hegel thus captures the dual nature of consciousness that cannot be conscious of an object without also being conscious of itself and vice versa. Consciousness understands itself as related to an independent other because it is implicitly already self-consciousness. Interestingly, Hegel portrays consciousness as objectifying what for the soul still existed in undifferentiated unity with itself, viz. the inner world of the unconscious. The world confronting consciousness is its own pre-conscious life made external and objective. It is nature with which the soul previously existed in immediate symbiosis and which as consciousness it now differentiates from and opposes to itself.3 Already at this point it is apparent that for Hegel there is no real division between nature as “physical” and nature as merely “mental” content of experience. Such a division would make world and self into two things inhabiting the same spatiotemporal world and relating one knows not how (causally?) to one another.4 Soul, consciousness, self-consciousness, reason, spirit, Concept – these are not “things” (or properties of things such as persons) relating to other things in the world. Rather, soul, consciousness, reason, etc. are cognitive forms or modes that contain within themselves a relation of self and other. Thus consciousness is a form of cognition in which the self relates to the world insofar as the latter is for it an external datum, something given and existing independently of itself. At the same time, however, this world which is experienced by consciousness as external to itself is also the content of the form of cognition called consciousness. This content, however, is not merely a mental content opposed to an extra-mental world. Instead, this content is the world itself, albeit the world as experienced in the form of an external, independent, spatio-temporal reality. In other words, for Hegel the world as experienced by consciousness is not a mental phenomenon but reality in the form of an external
3 For
a more detailed analysis of the soul’s relation to nature see Brinkmann, 1998.
4 Cf. the slightly ironic description of the usual understanding of the relationship between judgment
and object (here called “the subject”): “When considering the judgment, one usually thinks first of the independence of the extremes (the subject and the predicate): that the first is a thing or determination [that stands] on its own, and that the predicate likewise is a universal determination outside that subject (for instance, in my head), which is then brought together with the subject by me, and is thus ‘judged’ ” (E § 166R).
82
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
world.5 Hegel’s point is simply that this form is not the only form in which reality can be known. Already the understanding in the Phenomenology relates to the world as essentially characterized by a distinction between (sometimes deceptive) surface phenomena and the causes underlying them. What kind of world we experience or know depends on the form of cognition we adopt as our framework. The different forms of cognition, however, while presenting us with different realities, always present us with the same world and in this sense with the same content in different forms. These forms, then, are merely different ways of objectifying the same content. Hegel expresses the fundamental methodological situation as follows: The ‘I’ . . . is in-itself the identity with itself in the otherness; ‘I’ is itself and it overarches the object as something that is in-itself sublated, it is one side of the relationship and also the relationship as a whole, – the light that manifests itself as well as something else (E § 413, my translation).
This, in a nutshell, is the fundamental idea of Hegel’s philosophy. The self or subject, whether it is consciousness in the form of sense-certainty, perception, or understanding, or whether it is I, intuition, reason, thought, or spirit, is viewed from the start as a sphere of immanence. As such this self represents (a) a form of selfrelatedness that correlates a mode of cognition with its proper type of object and (b) one pole within this form. However, because the way in which the object pole displays itself to the cognitive self is determined by the form that the self takes with a given mode of cognition, we can say that the object pole, while representing the object of this cognitive self, is likewise and simultaneously the content of this form of cognition. In this sense, then, i.e., as a unity of content and form, the subject is both itself and the totality encompassing its object. These comments should help us understand why at the beginning of the Encyclopedia Phenomenology Hegel can define consciousness as a reflection of spirit into itself. Obviously, this also means that at the beginning of the Phenomenology of Spirit we find ourselves already within the immanence of consciousness. In other words, we do not start with an original division between mind and world that then needs somehow to be bridged. The totality called spirit represents the original starting-point and divides itself into two poles or sides, consciousness and external reality, or mind and world. Both, however, are at bottom two manifestations of the same totality called spirit, pure thought, or the Concept. That is to say, they are fundamentally one. It is only from the point of view of consciousness that the reality it experiences as other than itself cannot (yet) be understood as spirit. Nonetheless, both sides, although different in appearance, are the same 5 At E § 3 Hegel puts the matter in this way: “In any one of these forms [sc. of being conscious of an
object] . . ., the content is the object of our consciousness. But in this objectivity the determinacies of these forms supervene on the content; with the result that each of these forms [sc. of cognition] seems to give rise to a particular object [e.g. an object of perception, memory, desire, definition etc.], and that what is in-itself the same can look like a different content” (GHS modified). In other words, the forms of cognition are forms of objectification. Klaus Hartmann has pointed out the affinity between Hegel and Husserl in this respect (cf. Hartmann, 1999, p. 15).
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
83
in substance. The process of overcoming the opposition of consciousness consists in the gradual realization of this identity by consciousness. As a consequence, the development of consciousness must be seen to occur within the already unified totality of spirit. From the larger perspective of the Hegelian system this means that the Phenomenology of Spirit operates under systemic conditions that cannot be articulated prior to the completion of its own argument, conditions that can become clear only once we have come “full circle”. The circularity of the Phenomenology’s argument should thus be evident. The full text of Hegel’s definition of consciousness at the beginning of the Encyclopedia Phenomenology gives us insight into the multiple mediations that are presupposed at the beginning of the Phenomenology of Spirit: Consciousness constitutes the stage of the reflexion or of the relatedness of Spirit, Spirit as appearance. ‘I’ is the infinite relation of Spirit to itself, but as subjective, as the certainty of itself; the immediate identity of the natural soul has [here] been elevated to this purely ideal (ideell) identity with itself, and the content of the former is [now] the object of this reflection which is for-itself (E § 413, my translation).
What was content of the natural soul is now the “idealized” object of a self, i.e. something whose externality and independence is negated even as it is being affirmed, so that the object is likewise the content, albeit a content not experienced as such. However, consciousness is not only the reflection of spirit into itself – and in this sense its internal self-differentiation into two relata –, it is also spirit’s “appearance”. To whom or what, then, does spirit appear? Obviously, since spirit is reflected into itself, it can only appear to itself. That is to say, spirit as object of consciousness appears to itself in the form of consciousness. Consequently, the external world that constitutes the object of consciousness’ experience is already spirit extended in space and time, known by consciousness only as an external sensible reality. The fact that spirit appears to itself is equivalent to saying that it does not yet know itself as spirit. Rather, it appears to itself in the guise of an external reality just because it is conscious of itself only as consciousness and not yet, say, as reason or spirit. What spirit knows itself as determines the form in which it becomes objective to itself. Mode of cognition and mode of objectification go together.6 Viewed in this way, the 1807 Phenomenology begins in the middle of an ongoing development of spirit. Let us also note explicitly that Hegel identifies spirit with the “I” or selfconsciousness, while consciousness, as we have already seen, is only implicitly self-consciousness. Spirit and the I are structurally the same “infinite relation to self,” and so, therefore, is consciousness. That is to say, both spirit and the I as self-consciousness relate to an other that they know to be an other in appearance
. . . appears variously determined in accordance with the variety of the given object, and its further development appears as an alteration in the determinacy of its object. . . . [T]he logical determination of the object is what is identical in the subject and in the object, it is their absolute connectedness” (E § 415, my translation). See also E § 3.
6 “Consciousness
84
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
only (while consciousness does not yet know this). The other is therefore not a limiting factor, some permanent beyond, but distinct only through an internal, “ideal” (ideell) difference in virtue of which self-consciousness represents a specific form of self-relatedness. The internal difference does not separate or disrupt the two poles. But unlike self-consciousness, the I of consciousness is reflected into itself merely immediately – this being the result of the soul’s emergence from its unity with nature. Its reflectedness out of the object and into itself is the mere tautology of the thought that I am I, and hence unlike self-consciousness or spirit the I in consciousness does not yet possess a content of its own. Instead, it excludes that content from itself as an “independently existing opposite” (E § 413A). The I as such thus has a conflicting determination. In truth, it is infinite self-relation, but as the self of consciousness that emerges from the “unconscious unity of spirit and nature” (ibid.) it is at first an empty, tautological identity. For this very reason, the object, i.e. its own content, initially appears to it as something external to itself: The pure abstract freedom [of the ‘I’ that relates immediately to itself] releases its determinateness, i.e. the natural life of the soul, from itself as something equally free, as independent object; and ‘I’ knows this object initially as something external, and it is in this way that it is consciousness (E § 413, my translation).
To be sure, qua sensible reality the independent object remains external to consciousness even beyond the further development of the latter. What happens is that through referring this externality to some essence, cause, or ground consciousness begins to “internalize” this other. The sensible form of the object-world obviously is never overcome or dissolved, but its meaning is altered from being an ultimate reality in its own right to being understood as “the sight of the unseen,” to use Anaxagoras’s incomparable aphorism.7 Now due to its lack of inner content, the I must view its object rather than itself as the source and foundation of all determination, reality, and truth, while it itself is certain only of its empty identity. Its certainty is thus merely “subjective”. This is just to say, however, that the I is initially consciousness, i.e. a self relating to an object that to it appears as an alien, external other, as a given, independent, “objective” world, a world that really is alien and opaque for consciousness in its merely sensible, external appearance. And so, granted that consciousness is in truth that which the I is in truth, viz. infinite self-relation, a dialectic must ensue: Just as [the category of] relatedness in general, . . . so consciousness represents the contradiction of the independence of both its sides as well as their identity in which they are sublated (E § 414, my translation).
In this dialectic, the alien other, the world existing independently of the mind, comes to be re-appropriated and re-possessed by consciousness as something intelligible and transparent to it, something to which it can again relate freely (for instance, insofar as it has understood the laws this world must obey and thus is able to “master
7 According to Anaxagoras, appearances (ta phainomena) are the sight or look (opsis) of the unseen
or the concealed (ton adelon): DK 59B 21a.
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
85
nature”). Consequently, it must be the goal of the development of spirit in the form of consciousness to make its appearance [as a relationship of two independent relata] identical with its essence [as infinite self-relation], and [thus] to elevate its [mere] self-certainty to the level of truth (E § 416).
In the process, consciousness is thereby transformed into a self relating freely to the world as something it now knows to be fundamentally intelligible and therefore as its “possession”. Its relation to the other will again be an infinite self-relation, and its finitude or limitedness by a brute “given” will have been overcome. At that point, consciousness itself will have changed. It will then have been transformed into reason (cf. E § 417).8 We can see very clearly, then, that while consciousness is a form of cognition for which initially two mutually opposed poles, viz. mind and an extra-mental reality, seem to be related to one another, this picture does not correspond to what consciousness is at bottom. In truth, consciousness’ relation to the world is not this fractured relationship of mind separated by a gulf from the world, as Descartes came to view it. On the contrary, its fractured relationship with reality is essentially an appearance only, one that is made necessary by the nature of consciousness itself, to be sure, but that does not represent the final word about the bond between mind and world and is not even accepted by ordinary consciousness itself as the definitive truth. Consciousness would never be able to feel at home in the world and to engage actively with it were it not for the fact that it already understands the world as something that is open to its investigation and intervention, something with which it may develop a free relationship. We who have now witnessed the emergence of consciousness from the immediate unity of soul and nature know that the opposition of consciousness marks only a transitional phase within the development of spirit, a truth consciousness will come to understand more explicitly in due course: To consciousness, the object does not appear as something posited by the ‘I’, but rather as something immediate, existent, given; for it does not yet know that the object is in-itself identical with Spirit and that it has been released into a seemingly complete independence only through a self-separation of Spirit. That this is so, only we who have advanced to the Idea of Spirit know, only we who have thus raised ourselves above that abstract, merely formal identity of the ‘I’ [with itself] (E § 414A, my translation).
So while in the Encyclopedia Phenomenology Hegel treats consciousness as the result of a preceding development that explains how the opposition of consciousness arises in the first place, in the 1807 Phenomenology the opposition of consciousness at first seems to be the starting-point. Consciousness and object seem initially to be separate from one another, the object being experienced as an extra-mental reality
8 What
we have retraced here so far relying on the text of the Encylopedia is the basic structure of the argument of the Phenomenology of Spirit in its transition from consciousness to selfconsciousness to reason, an argument that we will examine in greater detail in the subsequent sections.
86
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
beyond consciousness. It must be said, however, that in his discussion of the methodological presuppositions in the Phenomenology’s Introduction Hegel is careful to point out that this divorce of consciousness from its object is an appearance only, as we shall see shortly. Still, Hegel essentially takes up the finite perspective of consciousness itself and then tries to show how from the inside of consciousness, so to speak, its opposition to the object world that it confronts is at bottom not an opposition and can therefore gradually be transformed into a unity of self and world on the basis of consciousness’ own reflection on and its rethinking of its own experience. We will discuss in a minute how Hegel believes this self-transformation of consciousness can be made to work. But before we return to the 1807 Phenomenology, a word on Hegel’s characterization of the philosophies of Kant and Fichte at E §§ 415 and 420 may be helpful. After our earlier discussion of Kant and the references to Fichte, it will not come as a surprise that both Kant and Fichte are treated by Hegel as philosophers of consciousness. Their approach, Hegel claims, views spirit not as spirit but instead limits spirit to consciousness: The Kantian philosophy can most appropriately be regarded as having viewed Spirit in terms of consciousness; it contains exclusively the determinations of the phenomenology, not of the philosophy of Spirit. . . . The Fichtean philosophy shares the same standpoint . . . (E § 415R).
In Kant’s and Fichte’s philosophy the truth is determined from the perspective and through the lens of consciousness, so to speak. This sounds as if Hegel completely ignores the transcendental approach these philosophers take. After all, for them our ordinary phenomenal consciousness is not a starting-point and a principle, but is itself the result of various transcendental conditions. There are two comments that Hegel would likely make in response. First, from his point of view the transcendental foundation of empirical consciousness and of its world of experience means the elevation of mere appearances to the status of genuine truth, a position he argued is self-contradictory.9 Consequently, Kant’s and Fichte’s ingenuity and sophistication are lost on Hegel because all their transcendental efforts achieve, Hegel believes, is the constitution of the world of empirical consciousness. Kant in particular is viewed as having limited the perspective of consciousness to the cognitive mode of perception which, Hegel claims, represents the standpoint of our ordinary consciousness that is also “more or less” that of the empirical sciences.10 Kant essentially introduces necessity and universality into the observations of ordinary, sensory certainties and thus transforms them into truths of experience. This echoes Hegel’s remark at E § 42 that Kant basically shares the same approach with the empiricists, the difference being only that Kant tries to give a “different explanation” for the presence of the structures of necessity and universality in
9 Cf.
SL 46/WdL I 27; see also E § 60 R. E § 420 R.
10 Cf.
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
87
our experience.11 Second, Kant contrasts these necessary components of knowledge with an unknowable beyond and thus turns objective knowledge of objects of experience into subjective knowledge, knowledge that is possible for a finite consciousness. In the Science of Logic, Hegel advances a similar critique of Fichte’s so-called Anstoß: It may well be that the infinite obstacle [Anstoß] of Fichte’s idealism has no underlying thing-in-itself, so that it becomes purely a determination in the ego; but for the ego, this determinateness . . . is at the same time immediate, a limitation of the ego . . ., so that although the limitation is in the ego, it contains an immediate non-being of the ego (SL 397/WdL II 10).
In other words, both philosophers espouse a finite consciousness to serve as the foundation of knowledge and determine the concept of truth accordingly as limited to what can be given or constructed in sense-experience. In this sense, they are both philosophers of consciousness, notwithstanding their transcendental approach. Apart from the characterization of Kant as a philosopher ultimately beholden to the referential paradigm of knowledge, these comments are valuable in that they support the claim that the Phenomenology does indeed constitute an argument in favor of overcoming the Kantian restrictions on knowledge, even if only implicitly. With the exception of a few obvious allusions, Hegel’s references in the Phenomenology to other philosophers are notoriously vague. Hence it is important to be able to claim that despite the fact that Kant’s Analytic does not seem to be discussed in any specificity anywhere in the Phenomenology, the book’s argument is nonetheless meant to provide, among other things, a critique of Kant’s transcendental philosophy insofar as it remains dependent upon and limited by the opposition of consciousness. Looking now more closely at the extended and – at least at first sight – labyrinthine argument that is the Phenomenology, we find that the third stage is disproportionately long compared to the first two. The first two are contained in the two chapters Hegel calls “Consciousness” and “Self-Consciousness” while the third is titled “Reason.” Reason is in fact the third and final stage of the development. The chapters we customarily think of as following Reason – viz. Spirit, Religion, and Absolute Knowing – are in truth subdivisions of Reason itself, as a look at the original table of contents makes clear (cf. PS XXXIII-XXXV/3, 5–8). The irregularity here consists in the fact that Reason is also the first subdivision in Reason, but the latter could easily be distinguished from the former by calling it “Abstract Reason.” Reason serves the purpose of functioning as the concluding stage well, given the fact that already in Faith and Knowledge Hegel had used the concept of reason to refer to the ultimate unity beyond all opposition.12 In the
11 One
that is not based on empirical psychology as in Hume’s case, it might be added. FK 69–70/GuW 326–327. Hegel continues to refer to reason as a principle of unity in the Encyclopedia, except that there he distinguishes between a “pure” reason, which is equivalent to the logical Idea, and embodied reason or reason in actuality: see, e.g., E § 6. Their consummate union would be absolute spirit.
12 Cf.
88
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
Phenomenology, the entire third stage culminates in the concluding chapter entitled “Absolute Knowledge.” The fact that Reason, Sprit, and Religion are synthetic unities of self-consciousness, but fall short of the ultimate unity called Absolute Knowledge indicates that even at this level we are to expect some form of the opposition of consciousness, although now within an immanence of reason where this immanence is no longer opposed to anything outside itself, not opposed, that is, to an object in the way in which consciousness posits an object-pole over against itself in the form of an object-world. This particular organization of the work, the fact that the book seems to grow out of proportion once Hegel reaches the third stage of the overall argument, has made scholars wonder whether he changed his mind about the structure and content of the Phenomenology.13 Thus, having arrived at reason as the first totality that integrates all oppositions within itself such that for reason the world is no longer an opposite, Hegel may have realized that plenty of internal oppositions still remained and that reason is the ultimate ground of unity only in principle or abstractly, not yet explicitly. That reason does mark a closure is clear from Hegel’s description of it at the beginning of the Reason chapter: Now that self-consciousness is Reason, its hitherto negative relation to otherness turns round into a positive relation. Up till now it has been concerned only with its independence and freedom . . . at the expense of the world, or of its own actuality. But as Reason . . . it is at peace with them . . .; for it is certain that it is itself reality, or that everything actual [wirklich] is none other than itself, its thinking is itself directly actuality . . . (PS § 232/3, 178–179).
Quite obviously, then, with reason we have arrived at a unity of thought and reality that is comprehensive and no longer finite or “merely” subjective – “everything actual” is supposed to be none other than self-consciousness in the form of reason. The otherness of “the world” vis-à-vis self-consciousness has been negated – Hegel’s double negation. Consequently, the relationship between thought and reality has now become “positive”. If we remember that the proposed task is to show that subjectivity functions as the ground of objectivity, then this task has in principle been achieved at this point. As we shall see shortly, while finite self-consciousness emerges as the ground of an equally finite objectivity at the end of Consciousness, the end of Self-Consciousness and the beginning of Reason argue that the ground of objectivity has now become infinite self-consciousness – and so has objectivity. With this, the original task of overcoming the opposition of consciousness has in principle been resolved. What has not yet been accomplished at this point is the demonstration that (a) individual self-consciousness is identical with infinite subjectivity and that (b) infinite subjectivity or the Concept is not only the ground of the totality of objectivity but is in fact identical with the latter. Hegel’s demonstration in 13 I
cannot enter into an examination of these issues here, nor are they crucial for our current concerns. For an excellent discussion of the complexity of the problem and the scholarly debate around it see Aschenberg, 1976. For a more recent review of the issue, see Harris, 1997, I pp. 193– 195. Harris’s division of the Phenomenology into two halves (I 195) makes sense. Nonetheless, based on the systematic issue involved (viz. the overcoming of the opposition of consciousness) I will be suggesting a slightly different organization of the argument.
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
89
support of (a) is contained in the long series of shapes of consciousness from Reason through Religion – with Forgiveness and Revealed Religion as crucial moments in the process – while Absolute Knowledge responds to (b). The question we need to ask now is: What are the methodological assumptions Hegel must make in order to justify the move from the opposition of consciousness to the immanence of reason, and how might he justify those assumptions? Evidently, the transformation of the finite ground of objectivity – in Hegel’s interpretation, Kant’s original unity of self-consciousness – must begin with the finite principle of knowledge itself. A mere juxtaposition of an infinite ground and the claim that it is in fact superior to the finite principle would not constitute an argument but only an assertion. Consequently, the infinite ground must emerge from the finite ground, or the finite ground must transform itself into the infinite ground. Against this strategic plan it might be objected that finite and infinite ground are absolutely distinct and that there is no continuity between them. In this case, there seems to be no telling how the first could ever develop into the second. Hegel must therefore first convince us that the assumption of a continuity between the finite and the infinite ground is warranted – in other words, that the unity between the two is already present, at least for us, if not for consciousness. Indeed, if we interpret the nature of consciousness as inevitably representing a merely subjective or relative perspective on the world or on whatever comes before it as its object, it would seem that the entire argument of the Phenomenology is doomed from the start. In order to reject the interpretation of consciousness as merely subjective and relative, Hegel, in §§ 81–89/3, 75–81 of the Introduction, offers his own analysis of the nature of consciousness and of the kind of knowledge available to it. This knowledge, it turns out, is by its very nature always more than merely phenomenal or relative, i.e. more than knowledge of appearances. In fact, consciousness knows to distinguish, from the start, between its own “subjective” perspective on things on the one hand and the way things are “objectively” on the other, a distinction widely held to be impossible from within the immanence of consciousness, except in so far as we can form hypotheses about the way things are in themselves. So we will now turn to an examination of Hegel’s analysis of the structure of consciousness, and we shall see that it furnishes the foundation without which the argument of the Phenomenology would in fact be impossible. After suggesting that something needs to be said about the “method of carrying out the inquiry” ahead of us (PS § 81/3, 75), Hegel himself brings up a potential aporia. If we cast the project of transforming the finite synthetic unity of consciousness into an infinite unity in terms of a comparison between the standpoint of consciousness and its phenomenal knowledge on one hand and the allegedly superior standpoint of the Science and its presumed absolute knowledge on the other, we would need to appeal to the “scientific” concept of what constitutes true cognition as the standard or criterion against which to measure the limitations of phenomenal knowledge. However, the scientific standpoint – i.e. the standpoint of pure thought – is not yet available because the philosophical “science” itself has not yet been developed. Indeed, since it is supposed to emerge from the examination of phenomenal consciousness itself, it cannot be appealed to in advance. But in the absence of a
90
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
“scientific” criterion of truth, it seems, the examination of the capability of phenomenal knowledge for truth cannot even begin – the proverbial catch twenty-two situation. This aporia seems to become even more exacerbated, when we analyze the structure of the phenomenon we are to investigate, viz. the structure of consciousness and its typical understanding of what it means to relate to an object and to know the object as it exists in-itself, i.e. in truth. As Hegel points out, succinctly summarizing the cognitive model upon which epistemology since the “reflective turn” had been based, phenomenal knowledge characteristically exhibits two structural features. Consciousness both relates to and distinguishes itself from its object. Or, in Hegel’s terminology, in that consciousness relates to something as an object, the latter is or exists for consciousness, a structural feature that may be called the beingfor-consciousness or, for short, the “being for-itself”, of the object – the “look” the object presents to consciousness, as it were. For this “look” consciousness takes responsibility as the subjective perspective or the appearance of the object which is at least in part dependent on consciousness itself, but without which no relation to an object would be possible either. Without something being or existing for consciousness, it is even unclear whether there would be consciousness in the first place – all consciousness being object-consciousness, even consciousness of ourselves. Apparently, Hegel anticipates and acknowledges one aspect of what following Brentano and later Husserl came to be called the intentionality structure of consciousness, or the fact that consciousness is always consciousness of something, i.e. it is always objectifying. But just as much as consciousness must be related or have access to an object in some way in order to be conscious of it, so it also distinguishes itself, including the way in which the object presents itself to consciousness, from that object and thereby simultaneously posits the object as it is in-itself, its existence independently of consciousness, or its essence or nature as it exists objectively or “untainted” by subjective admixtures or distortions. The object’s in-itself may therefore be contrasted with its appearance for consciousness, or its being-for-another. Indeed, to relate to an object already presupposes a distinction between that which relates and that to which one relates. So while relating to the object, consciousness simultaneously knows that the way it perceives the object must not be identified with the object itself and that while its immediate acquaintance with the object may in many circumstances be a reliable indicator of its nature the two must nonetheless be kept distinct. To put it differently, except in cases of deception or illusion, consciousness usually will not confuse its immediate acquaintance with or view of the object, which it knows to be partial only, with the object’s nature or its true concept. The distinction between the being-for-itself, i.e. the being of the object for consciousness or its “being-for-another” [sc. for consciousness] and its being in-itself, or again, the distinction between the side it presents to consciousness and its independent being, is built into the very structure of consciousness itself. This distinction is a determination of consciousness as a form of cognition. Its importance may be seen in the fact that the being-in-itself can be understood as the objective nature of the object and its being-for-consciousness as its subjective aspect. The latter may again be understood
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
91
as either belonging or not belonging to the object itself, whereas the object’s “objective” being may be thought to be either a mere construct or independently real, and if independently real then either accessible or inaccessible. But whether the appearance of the object for consciousness is believed to be part of the object itself or not, or in part the one and in part the other, consciousness does not normally take the object to be a mere fiction of the mind, but to have an independent existence of its own. That is to say, consciousness posits the object as one transcending the immanence of consciousness itself. It posits a world, an independent reality, or an other – this being perhaps its most fundamental act of all.14 By its very nature, consciousness is “beyond itself”, i.e. it is anything but solipsistic. Hegel characterizes the situation as follows: . . . whatever is related to knowledge or knowing is also distinguished from it, and posited as existing outside of this relationship [my italics]; this being-in-itself is called truth (PS § 82/3, 76).
We can now see how this structural feature of consciousness, which requires the positing of the object as a transcendent entity, might make the task of establishing an objective concept of truth impossible. If the being-in-itself of the object is its truth (or is what the object is “truly” or “objectively”), and if at the same time this truth by definition transcends consciousness and is believed to be distinct from the object in so far as it exists for consciousness, it may be concluded that what the object is in truth can never be established. For it seems natural to assume that since only that of the object which exists for consciousness can be known about it, the object’s in-itself can never be known, if its transcendence were to be synonymous with its inaccessibility to consciousness. Consciousness, while never solipsistic, may nonetheless be irremediably perspectival and subjective or, in Hegel’s terminology, finite. Now the “reflective turn” at the beginning of modern philosophy had precisely the effect of driving a wedge between the being of the object for consciousness (its representation or idea in the mind) and its existence independently of this relation. That is to say, in retreating into the immanence of the mental, modern philosophy radically opposed this immanence to the transcendent sphere of independent reality and completely segregated the two – the most famous example being Descartes’ elimination, discussed above, of all transcendence from the immanence of consciousness in Meditations I and II, such that only an empty reference remained.15 We should now be in a better position to understand why Hegel thinks he is committed to the strategy of having finite consciousness overcome its limitations on its own and of letting the “scientific” standpoint emerge from that process of self-sublation. Because consciousness believes that the truth exists “outside of the relationship” between itself and the object, it may conclude that the truth (about the 14 Husserl
called it the Generalthesis: see Husserl, Ideen I, § 30. should be mentioned, however, that Hegel did not view Descartes’ contribution exclusively as one initiating the reflective turn. Rather, he believes that Descartes relapsed into the opposition of consciousness only after having successfully overcome it with the cogito, understood by Hegel as the speculative unity of thinking and being: see Brinkmann, 1996.
15 It
92
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
object, nature, the world in general, etc.) is in fact unknowable. What has apparently happened in this case may be described in two ways. Either consciousness has identified the truth with the object’s in-itself and posited both as existing outside of its relationship to the object (of which it now retains only the for-itself aspect or its appearance – the skeptical position), or consciousness – influenced by the first alternative – has separated the truth from the object’s in-itself and has posited this truth as existing beyond the relation between itself and the object in both its beingfor-it and its “objective” being (the Kantian position). That for Hegel the Kantian situation is best captured by the second scenario was apparent in the passage quoted earlier from the Encyclopedia, a passage whose precise meaning may now be even more transparent. There Hegel said of the Kantian approach: . . . the Critical Philosophy extends the antithesis [of subjectivity and objectivity] in such a way that experience in its entirety falls within subjectivity, i.e. both of these elements together are subjective, and nothing remains in contrast with subjectivity except the thingin-itself (E § 41).
In the light of our present analysis this means that Kant draws the line distinguishing consciousness and truth between the for-itself and the in-itself on the one hand and the true, but inaccessible and unknowable, in-itself on the other. He thus ends up with two concepts of the in-itself, viz. the empirical and the noumenal thing-in-itself. He can therefore call the empirical thing-in-itself an appearance and insist that the distinction between this kind of being-for-itself and in-itself is merely empirical. The basic structure of consciousness is nonetheless preserved. All that has happened is a duplication of the meaning of the in-itself and, concomitantly, a duplication of the meaning of the for-itself. In this situation, Hegel now argues, it would be futile to claim to be in possession of a better, higher, “truer” standard of knowledge, since from the vantage point of a theory of truth that is predicated on this particular understanding of the structure of consciousness any such “scientific” standard would by definition transcend the truth deemed to be accessible by consciousness. Objective objectivity is beyond the reach of the subjective objectivity which alone is accessible to consciousness. Hence consciousness “would not necessarily have to recognize the validity of such a standard” (PS § 83/3, 76). With this, we have arrived at a second impasse that seems to make the Phenomenology an impossible project. The problem is, in short, that (a) at the beginning, a scientific standard of truth is not available and (b), even if such a standard were available in advance, it would not be recognized by finite consciousness, because the latter is already convinced of the radical transcendence of such a standard and hence of the impossibility for it to be accessible by consciousness. According to (a), the examination of the capacity of consciousness for truth cannot rely on an independent standard of truth, according to (b), finite consciousness does not seem to be a suitable basis on which an independent standard of truth could emerge, because it seems to deny the possibility that such a standard could even exist. In this situation, the idea of letting the scientific concept of truth emerge from consciousness seems unworkable. How, then, is the investigation of the Phenomenology to be made possible at all? What, if any, methodological basis
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
93
can be found for it, given the conditions now in place, i.e. the fact that the scientific standard of truth does not yet exist and that finite consciousness must develop this standard out of itself? Hegel’s proposal is as follows. We need to make consciousness question its own assumptions about what it believes the true nature of the object to be. To do this, consciousness needs to see for itself that its experience of the object contradicts its own a priori beliefs about the object. If consciousness could be made to face such an internal contradiction, it would be forced to rethink either the nature of its experience or its a priori beliefs about the object, or both. Consciousness would then be in a position to correct its a priori assumptions about the object in the light of its experience – and likewise to re-interpret the meaning of its experience in the light of its revised beliefs about the true nature of the object. With such a dialectic in place, consciousness might be able to work its way up from a less adequate to a more adequate conception of the truth and thus gradually transform its initial beliefs about the truth into “scientific” form. Consciousness would then engage in a process of successively replacing one framework of objectivity with another, more adequate framework. To anticipate one of several potential objections. What I have sketched here sounds as if a priori beliefs about the true nature of objects were to be tested against experience. But no such test, it seems, could have any real force, since, according to Kant, a priori beliefs rest on synthetic a priori judgments which are universal and necessary truths that can only be confirmed but never be contradicted by experience. If so, it is impossible to see how a Kantian position in particular could be vulnerable to a dialectic that relies on experience as the foundation of truth. This concern can, however, be dispelled. We only need to remember what we already concluded as a result of our earlier analysis of Hegel’s critique of Kant. There we saw that if the unity of self-consciousness is truly original, experience must always already be informed by a priori beliefs. In other words, the experience against which consciousness’ beliefs about the true nature of things is to be tested, will itself be shot through with a priori structures and will certainly never be a “pure”, completely uninterpreted experience. Such an experience that involves “bare, naked perceptions” of objects or a “pure” manifold of intuition will have to be rejected as a myth. In case experience contradicts a given a priori belief about the nature of its object, the assumptions built into this experience will differ from the assumptions underlying consciousness’ initial beliefs. Hegel relies on this presupposition to make the case that the experience against which a given a priori belief is tested is itself informed by and progressively reveals a richer, more comprehensive, and more adequate a priori framework in the light of which consciousness likewise makes sense of a progressively richer, more comprehensive, and “truer” experience. In effect, therefore, one a priori framework comes to be tested against another a priori framework. To be sure, the a priori frameworks that are systematically elicited by the confrontation between consciousness’ initial a priori beliefs and an experience that is at variance with them because it is itself informed by different a priori beliefs will then no longer be a priori frameworks in the Kantian sense, i.e. universal, necessary, and incorrigible. As soon as a framework undergoes the test of experience, it will take on the meaning of
94
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
a preliminary, limited, and corrigible framework, i.e. it will have the significance of a putative a priori. The notion of a putative a priori will replace the Kantian notion of the incorrigible a priori.16 This obviously marks a major paradigm shift in the history of post-Kantian epistemology, one that seems to have spread beyond Hegel and Hegelianism. However, it bears pointing out that, contrary to the way he is sometimes perceived, Hegel is not prepared to relinquish the belief in an ultimate a priori framework. Since an ultimate framework would by definition have to be incorrigible, the characterization of Hegel’s approach as corrigibilist should be taken with a grain of salt.17 Assuming that the transcendental significance of the dialectical procedure can be preserved in the way just described, we would now need at least a preliminary demonstration that such a comparison between the experience of consciousness on the one hand and a putative a priori belief about the true nature of the object on the other is in fact possible. After what has been said, we may have serious doubts about this – unless we question the assumption that the transcendent nature of the truth is synonymous with its unavailability for consciousness. This is precisely what Hegel proceeds to do in § 84/3, 76–77. The in-itself or objective nature of the object to which consciousness relates, while transcending consciousness’ immediate acquaintance with the object, is nonetheless immanent to and thus knowable by consciousness – it is, in short, a transcendence within the immanence of consciousness, a characterization we used earlier when referring to contemporary interpretationism. Hegel’s argument is as follows. Because the distinction between the for-itself and the in-itself is itself a distinction within the immanence of consciousness . . . the investigation becomes a comparison of consciousness with itself [my italics] . . . In consciousness, one thing exists for another, i.e. consciousness regularly contains the determinateness of the moment of knowledge; at the same time, this other is to consciousness not merely for it, but is also outside of this relationship, or exists in itself: the moment of truth. Thus, in what consciousness affirms from within itself [my italics] as being-in-itself or the True we have the standard which consciousness itself sets up by which to measure what it knows. . . . [T]he essential point to bear in mind throughout the whole investigation is that these two moments . . . both fall within that knowledge which we are investigating (PS § 84/3, 76–77).
Both the a priori beliefs about the object as well as the actual experience of the object which reveals the in-itself, fall within consciousness. In other words, the comparison does not (and never could) occur between an idea or representation of the object and the object as an entity not mediated by any representation at all, but 16 For
the claim that the argument of the Phenomenology has transcendental significance see Charles Taylor 1972. Recently, Terry Pinkard has criticized, rightly, it seems to me, the particular form Taylor’s argument takes: see Pinkard, 1996, pp. 350–351. In my view, Hegel’s procedure is perhaps best described as a critique of the idea of putatively incorrigible a priori frameworks of cognition. The opening argument in Sense-Certainty makes yet an additional point, however, as we shall see in the next section. 17 Pinkard’s reading of Hegel in Pinkard 1988 and 1996 might be called corrigibilist. The term has recently been used with great heuristic benefit by Allen Speight with respect to Hegel’s philosophy of agency: see Speight, 2001, pp. 3–6.
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
95
rather between the object’s putative nature and consciousness’ actual experience of it. Or again, the comparison occurs in the immanence of consciousness between its preconceived concept of the object on one hand and its actual concept as revealed through experience. An appeal to some “pure” object beyond consciousness that could somehow be known independently of any representation of it, is both impossible and unnecessary. Only if we let ourselves be guided by the mistaken idea that the required comparison would have to be made between an object available to consciousness and the same object as an absolute transcendence will we be caught in the impasse Hegel initially described. Hegel thus anticipates the conclusions drawn by the interpretationists. Looking at the structure of phenomenal consciousness, we find that it is in the very nature of cognition to compare its prior assumptions about an object with its actual experience of it and to correct the former in the light of the latter. Acquisition of knowledge always operates on the basis of an internal standard of truth which consciousness tests against appearances. Appearances in turn may suggest a different standard which then leads to the re-definition of the original standard. Short of appealing to superhuman intuition there does not seem to be another possibility of explaining the process of acquiring objective knowledge. Hegel’s argument for the internalization of the in-itself is as follows. The object is synonymous with its conceptualization, since its concept represents the (putative) objective nature of the object. If so, consciousness’ direct experience of the object is nothing but the experience of its own concept of the object, or of the objective nature of the object “as it exists for an other” (PS § 84/3, 77). Consequently, to compare our experience of the object with our “idea” of it comes to the same thing as comparing the object with its own concept: If we designate knowledge as the Notion, but the essence or the True as what exists, or the object, then the examination consists in seeing whether the Notion corresponds to the object. But if we call the essence or in-itself of the object the Notion, and on the other hand understand by the object the Notion itself as object, viz. as it exists for an other, then the examination consists in seeing whether the object corresponds to its Notion. It is evident, of course, that the two procedures are the same (PS § 84/3, 77).
In other words, to compare my (putative) concept of the object (i.e., the Notion) with my experience of it (i.e., the object itself) is the same as comparing the appearance of the object (i.e., its being for an other) with the object’s essence (i.e., its Notion). My experience of the object is therefore not merely “subjective”, rather, it reveals the nature of the object. In short, experience reveals the adequacy or inadequacy of my own conception of the object, and this in the immanence of consciousness itself, since what is being compared is my direct experience of the object with my putative knowledge of it. Obviously, for this identification of experience, appearance, and essence to work we must already be convinced that the way in which the object displays itself for consciousness (its subjective appearance) is a manifestation of its objective nature, and that its objective nature is identical with the object’s conceptualization by consciousness. The being-for-consciousness of the object is just as much the subject’s experience of the object as it is the beingfor-another of the object, and the object’s in-itself is just as much consciousness’ concept of the object as it is the object’s objective nature. What Hegel specifies here
96
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
in § 84/3, 76–77 of the Introduction is his transcendental condition for the possibility of knowledge. The Phenomenology’s argument rests on the viability of this internality assumption, i.e. the assumption that not only the experience of the object but also its objective nature are internal to consciousness. What we have just witnessed, then, is nothing other than Hegel’s claim that the opposition of consciousness must be discarded before we reach the starting-point of philosophy. Hegel defends this assumption in §§ 85 and 86 (3, 77–79) and in the process clarifies the testing procedure. One might object, he suggests, that when comparing the experience of the object with the putative concept of it consciousness is merely comparing one subjective idea with another: The object, it is true, seems only to be for consciousness in the way that consciousness knows it; it seems that consciousness cannot, as it were, get behind the object as it exists for consciousness so as to examine what the object is in itself, and hence, too, cannot test its own knowledge by that standard (PS § 85/3, 78).
This mentalistic objection, however, rests on a fallacy. It assumes that the “objective” object or the in-itself must exist in a sphere of reality that is not accessible to consciousness just because anything that is accessible also exists for consciousness. Such an object, however, would not exist for consciousness at all. Consequently, . . . the distinction between the in-itself and the knowledge is already present in the very fact that consciousness knows an object at all. Something is for it the in-itself; and knowledge, or the being of the object for consciousness, is, for it, another moment (ibid.).
The distinction between the for-itself and the in-itself is built into the intentionality structure of consciousness, and hence is internal to it. However, Hegel makes a crucial assumption at this point that he does not explicitly argue for, but that we need to understand before we can proceed. For he posits without much explanation that the comparison between the for-itself and the in-itself will yield a contradiction between the two.18 Why this should be so may not be immediately obvious. For example, if we look at Husserl’s analysis of perception in Ideas I, we can see that no contradiction arises at all between the appearance of something and its presumed essence. While the two are clearly distinguished by Husserl, he generally finds that they match one another. The perspectival appearances of the table or of a sound, for instance, are held together by consciousness’ knowledge of the typical ways in which spatial objects display themselves in perception.19 The essence or noema is a valid rule for the synthesis of the appearances, the one confirms the other, and the case of disillusionment is not a contradiction between the correct correlation of appearance and essence, but an indication of a mismatch between a for-itself and an in-itself which are correlated with one another only by mistake. Interestingly, Hegel’s scenario is very different. His for-itself is already a synthesis of appearance and essence because for him the separation of the two would
PS § 85/3, 78: “. . . consciousness thus finds that its knowledge does not correspond to its object . . ..” 19 Husserl, Ideas I § 95. 18 Cf.
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
97
yield an artificial phenomenon, one that is not part of our actual experience. Isolated aspects of appearances such as impressions or sense-data are not objects of experience, only creations of philosophical reflection. Experience therefore always presupposes an interpreted object or something seen and understood as something. Hence nothing could be truer than that while all our knowledge begins with experience not all of it is derived from experience – because part of our knowledge must always precede experience. The question is only whether our preconceived, a priori interpretation is adequate or not. Now at first, consciousness simply believes that its interpretation of the object is in fact adequate. What this interpretation entails can be spelled out because it is precisely what consciousness knows the object to be. In a second step, however, this belief is subjected to actual experience, i.e. to an observation of the actual behavior of the object as compared to what consciousness believes it to be. As was mentioned above, the object’s actual behavior must be regarded as the manifestation of the object’s own independent nature, and hence as the object’s true in-itself. Here, then, we have a second for-itself/in-itself, viz., the true nature of the object as it displays itself for consciousness. Consequently, we now have two concepts of the object, one a naïve, untested concept, the other a more refined concept of a consciousness wizened by experience. It is only when viewing the matter in this way that we can discern Hegel’s rationale. Hegel’s point is simply that two different a priori conceptions of the same object cannot both be true. The contradiction arises because one and the same object is here supposedly explained by recourse to two different essences or conceptual frameworks. For Hegel, then, both the for-itself and the in-itself are two different conceptions of the in-itself, the one known and explicit, the other not yet known and implicit, but explicit after consciousness’ experience of the object’s actual behavior. In this sense, the “for-itself” now stands for the preconceived a priori, the “in-itself” for the a priori disclosed by experience. The conflict between the two per se conceptions of the same object is the source of the “dialectical movement” that drives the learning process called experience (cf. PS § 86/ 3, 78–79). We start with a for-itself that is for consciousness the object’s in-itself or true nature (consciousness’ knowledge) and that when compared to the in-itself revealed in actual experience (the object) is no longer the true in-itself: Hence it comes to pass for consciousness that what it previously took to be the in-itself is not an in-itself, or that it was only an in-itself for consciousness (ibid.).
With this reversal two things have changed. The old standard (in-itself) is replaced by a new standard, but the previous object is likewise replaced by a new object or reality because . . . the knowledge that was present was essentially a knowledge of the object: as the knowledge changes, so too does the object, for it essentially belonged to this knowledge (ibid.).
In a sense, Hegel acknowledges the interpretationist (but also Kantian) point that an object is an object in virtue of being “interpreted” by consciousness. But unlike interpretationism he also argues that there cannot be two true concepts of the same
98
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
object. Hence, when the concept changes, so does the object change as well. It takes on a new meaning because experience has shed a new light on it. To use an example from the Phenomenology itself, what was previously thought to be “in reality” an individual thing with a unique essence through experience comes to be viewed as the manifestation of some underlying force or the result of causal processes and hence changeable. Causal processes in turn imply the presence of laws, and thus a new sphere of objectivity and a new sphere of experience is opened up. We still perceive individual things, but instead of taking them only to be individual substances that are supposed to be ontologically independent (first per se conception), we now also view them as in truth dependent on mechanical laws and physical or chemical processes (second, revised per se conception). From having been primary constituents in our ontology they have become derivative. The dependent object is now a different object for consciousness. The new object is what the previous object was in truth and its revised concept also contains a new putative in-itself, viz. the idea of the ground on which the object depends for its existence or nature. In this way, what was previously thought to be the objective nature of something comes to be understood by consciousness as the appearance of another objective nature, or as a for-itself that was an in-itself only for a less experienced consciousness, so to speak. To revise the projections of our a priori conceptualizations of reality in this way and replace them by new interpretations of changed aspects of what at bottom is one and the same reality is what we call experience (cf. PS § 86/3, 78–79). Hegel’s claim is that for every new putative per se conception of reality experience will disclose another per se conception that underlies it and that is more comprehensive and pro tanto more objective than its predecessor. In this way, experience generates a series of correlations of appearance and underlying reality or ground where every ground is subsequently reinterpreted as one more appearance of yet another underlying in-itself. The most pressing objection a potential critic might raise against this interpretation is probably this. If Hegel takes the view that the truth must be determined from within consciousness, how can he possibly maintain the objectivity of such a determination? If, as Hegel claims, the in-itself exists for consciousness just like the for-itself, the radical distinction between the subjective and the objective collapses, and the in-itself becomes no less subjective than the for-itself. Are we not, then, in the very same situation Hegel attributes to Kant? Does not Hegel also propose a mere subjective objectivity when he argues that every in-itself reveals itself as an “in-itself only for consciousness” (PS § 85/3, 77–78; § 86/3, 78–79)? This is indeed a serious objection. For it would seem that if every in-itself turns out to be only a subjective objectivity, objective objectivity will forever elude consciousness. Alternatively, it could be argued that the opposition between for-itself and in-itself is constantly recreated. Apparently, that opposition will be overcome only if and when the in-itself and the for-itself become identical – which, it seems, they never will as long as our cognitive standpoint is that of consciousness itself! The difference between the for-itself and the in-itself is a structural feature of consciousness and is precisely what makes consciousness finite. Without it consciousness would no longer be consciousness. Consequently, if Hegel is to deal with this objection successfully, his project in the Phenomenology must include a demonstration of
3.1
Methodological Presuppositions
99
how the standpoint of consciousness itself is eventually overcome, for to overcome the opposition of consciousness is synonymous with overcoming the structure of consciousness as the basis for cognition.20 The consequence of this is that to make the in-itself internal to consciousness by showing that it is really an in-itself for consciousness is merely the first methodological step and does not yet accomplish the goal of the Phenomenology which consists in the explicit transcendence of the opposition of consciousness – explicit, because, as we saw above, implicitly it has been overcome already. The opposition exists only for the standpoint of consciousness or “for it”, not for the standpoint of “the Science”, or “in itself”. The standpoint of consciousness is not itself the standpoint of objective thought. It must be left behind because this standpoint implies the subjectivity of every in-itself or, if you will, the merely relative nature of all truths. While consciousness is able progressively to correct its conception of the initself, what it really needs to “correct” is its standpoint as consciousness. Objective objectivity can arise only when the in-itself can no longer be re-interpreted as merely an in-itself for consciousness. Apparently, this can never happen as long as we view matters exclusively from the point of view of consciousness. In other words, consciousness itself must become objective thought in the process. It is strange that in his methodological comments in the Introduction Hegel comments on the all-important transition from the standpoint of consciousness to that of objective thought or reason almost as an afterthought. After all, the whole point of the Phenomenology is to make this transition happen. But all Hegel has to say on this crucial point is that [i]n pressing forward to its true existence, consciousness will arrive at a point at which it gets rid of its semblance of being burdened with something alien, with what is only for it, and some sort of ‘other’, at a point where appearance becomes identical with essence, so that its exposition will coincide at just this point with the authentic Science of Spirit. And finally, when consciousness itself grasps this its own essence, it will signify the nature of absolute knowledge itself (PS § 89/3, 80–81).
Clearly, for consciousness to become identical with absolute knowledge means for it to transcend itself, to become something other than consciousness. This final step, therefore, falls outside the methodological framework Hegel has set up in the Introduction and one would wish that Hegel had to say something more about this transition. Indeed, from an interpretationist viewpoint, this situation could be used to argue that the horizon of consciousness can never be transcended in the way Hegel claims – and therefore interpretationism must be right. The task Hegel has set himself looks like a typical case of lifting oneself up from the ground by one’s own bootstraps.21 Consciousness, it seems, must somehow be able to transform itself into something larger than itself, or to overcome its own limitation from within itself. It must come to view itself as the appearance of 20 The
opposition of consciousness is ostensibly overcome in the transition from Consciousness to Self-Consciousness. However, the opposition is thereby only internalized. It persists up until the transition from Religion to Absolute Knowing. 21 Reinhold Aschenberg has pointed out that the apparent paradox is in fact three-fold (the so-called Münchhausen-Trilemma): cf. Aschenberg, 1976.
100
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
objective thought, and its object as the objective truth insofar as it exists for another. But in order to do this, it must apparently also possess knowledge of the objective truth itself – the truth as it exists independently of its being-for-consciousness. This seems impossible – unless, as we already concluded, consciousness from the start is nothing but absolute knowledge in disguise. The progression towards the standpoint of objective thought will then have the meaning of re-establishing an original totality of knowledge which through the introduction of the standpoint of consciousness had been temporarily obscured. It will then not be the standpoint of consciousness that is the true source of knowledge: the latter is, rather, a deficient mode of objective thought. Nor is it really finite consciousness that does the heavy lifting. Instead, science or objective thought provides the “ladder” with the help of which consciousness is able to climb to the top: Science . . . requires that self-consciousness should have raised itself into this Aether [sc. of objective thought] in order to be able to live . . . with Science and in Science. Conversely, the individual has the right to demand that Science should at least provide him with the ladder to this standpoint, should show him this standpoint within himself [my italics] (PS § 26/3, 29).
We may wonder, then, how the petitio Hegel himself warns us of in § 83/3, 76 will really be avoided. If science must hand consciousness the ladder, science must precede the ascent of consciousness to the position of science. This consideration will be crucial for assessing the so-called introductory function of the Phenomenology within the Hegelian system as a whole. It seems to confirm what we indicated earlier, viz. that the Phenomenology cannot make a beginning from scratch or even with the standpoint of the opposition of consciousness as its true standpoint. To put it differently, the ladder cannot, as might have been thought, be constructed as we go along, it must be offered to consciousness, while consciousness must learn to negotiate, but cannot itself generate, its rungs. But if the project of the Phenomenology presupposes the solution to the problem it is supposed to solve, its introductory function needs to be reconsidered. We will eventually address this problem at the beginning of the next chapter.22 For now, we turn to the argument of the Phenomenology itself in order to see how the opposition of consciousness that is already overcome for us is also overcome for consciousness.
3.2 Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal We now turn to the examination of the Phenomenology of Spirit as the key work in which Hegel attempts the completion of the Copernican revolution in its methodological aspect. The Phenomenology, it should be pointed out, does not yet develop Hegel’s actual account of objectivity, a task which is left to the Logic and the Encyclopedia. It only prepares the methodological basis for such an account. It functions as the ladder that is supposed to demonstrate the epistemic continuity between 22 See
Section 4.1 below.
3.2
Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal
101
immediate experience and explanatory ground. The constant re-interpretation or revision of the ontological ground-grounded relationship is in fact what constitutes epistemological progress and secures the epistemic continuity between the successive stages of reinterpretation. To establish this epistemic continuity between the initial position of Sense-Certainty and the concluding stage of Absolute Knowing is what it means, and what it takes, to overcome the opposition of consciousness for consciousness. In the following sections, our aim will be to retrace Hegel’s argument in the Phenomenology, to determine the different forms the opposition of consciousness takes, and to see how this opposition is in fact overcome. The intention is to highlight the major stages and turning points of the argument of the Phenomenology. The reader should not expect a commentary or a detailed analysis of the entire work, only a précis of Hegel’s argumentative strategy.23 We begin with the Phenomenology’s first chapter. As we saw, this beginning already operates under certain preconditions. Most important among them is the fact that the Phenomenology must assume the position of the immanence of thought from the start. The implication of this is that Hegel cannot but view the process of overcoming the opposition of consciousness as one of the self-transformation of consciousness into reason (and ultimately into absolute knowing). This in turn seems possible only, if consciousness is viewed from the beginning as a limited form of reason, reason as it exists in a finite form – hence the remark in the Introduction to the Science of Logic quoted earlier that Kant’s finite unity of consciousness needed to be “thought out into its purity” and developed into a non-finite principle. Conversely, therefore, the successive transformation of consciousness into reason is synonymous with the unfolding of reason itself from finite reason (i.e., consciousness) to infinite reason (i.e., absolute knowing). Moreover, to the extent that consciousness becomes identical with reason, reason becomes more and more conscious of itself – and in this sense becomes infinite self-consciousness. The initial appearance of reason as opposed to consciousness and of a world existing independently of consciousness gradually vanishes. As this appearance vanishes, consciousness’ transformation into reason is at the same time the “appearance of absolute knowledge,” i.e. its emergence in consciousness. This means quite literally that the “thing” or the “forces” and “laws” of nature that successively become the object of consciousness are objective forms of reason. For consciousness, however, these configurations of reality have the meaning of a facticity and of something given. Consciousness’ transformation into the comprehensive identity of thought and reality called reason is therefore a two-fold process. Insofar as consciousness is already reason, albeit in a finite form, it is made to shed its own limitations until it becomes reason itself (and ultimately absolute knowing). On the other hand, insofar as consciousness is individual consciousness, it is transformed into a moment of and 23 For
this reason I will be able to include only a limited number of secondary references into the discussion. For a detailed commentary on the Phenomenology the reader should consult the standard works such as Hyppolite, 1974, Heinrichs, 1974, Taylor, 1975, Lauer, 1976, revised 1993, Flay, 1984, Pinkard, 1996, Siep, 2000, Vieweg/Welsch, 2008, and Harris’s invaluable two volume study of 1997 titled Hegel’s Ladder.
102
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
within the comprehensive sphere of immanence called the Notion. In this way, finite consciousness is grounded in infinite reason, but insofar as finite consciousness is a form of reason, reason actually grounds itself in itself. In the Phenomenology, “Notion” or “Concept” is Hegel’s technical term for the ultimate unity of consciousness and its object. The Notion “is the Self that is for itself” (PS § 795/3, 580). With the Notion, then, we arrive at that point at which both ground and grounded, or consciousness and its object, have assumed the structure of infinity. What appeared initially to be an independent world over against finite consciousness has become a duplicate self. Immanence will have turned into a comprehensive totality in which the distinction between self and other is itself only an appearance. At the same time, we will witness a reversal of the relationship between ground and grounded. Whereas consciousness first develops into the ground of the world (roughly, up until the end of Reason), it turns into the moment of a larger structure in Spirit. Turning now to the opening chapter on Sense-Certainty, we will keep in mind that the fundamental unity of self and other which Hegel variously refers to as self-consciousness, reason, the Notion/Concept, or spirit, is tacitly presupposed. The opposition of consciousness emerges against the background and within the immanence of this subject-object unity. It constitutes an internal division within the immanence of experience. Arguably, this is Hegel’s smartest methodological move. It allows him to combine the idea of a fundamental unity of consciousness and object with consciousness’ referential nature. It could be said with some justification that this principle of the cognitive immanence of all objects of knowledge, or the principle of cognitive immanence for short, represents the major methodological correction, if correction it is to be called, vis-à-vis Kant. For according to this principle, both the appearance and the thing-in-itself are available to consciousness. The independent object-world, or what consciousness takes to be the true, transcends consciousness as subjective mind, but this transcendence is a transcendence within the overall cognitive immanence. This is why in the Science of Logic Hegel criticized Kant for having been interested “only” in “the so-called transcendental aspect of the categories” (SL 63). Kant, so Hegel had argued, had failed to extend the principle of cognitive immanence beyond appearances to include things-in-themselves. The transcendental logic could for this reason not be a logic of truth as that which is both for consciousness and in-itself, but only a logic of truth-for-consciousness. Consequently, at the very start of Sense-Certainty we find that Hegel does not begin with a clearly marked opposition of consciousness and object, but with a consciousness that is in direct, immediate contact with its object. The reason for this is methodological. Every beginning for Hegel must be a beginning with an immediate, i.e. a “zero”, relationship or a coincidence of two relata because all oppositions must be derived from an original unity. No opposition is original or irreducible for Hegel, so all oppositions must be shown to emerge from a unity in order for us to understand why they arise in the first place. At the beginning of Sense Certainty, then, the opposition between consciousness and object cannot yet have emerged, although it is already implicit in the fact that consciousness is supposed to be in touch with something external to and other than itself. That this opposition is as yet implicit
3.2
Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal
103
also means that the difference between appearance and essence, between what is for it and what is in-itself, has not yet become explicit for consciousness – everything seems to be up front, so to speak. Consciousness will articulate and reflect on the opposition between what is for it and what it takes the object to be in-itself in Perception, and it will begin to overcome it in Force and Understanding. By the time we reach Self-Consciousness, this opposition will have become internal to consciousness while another seemingly external opposition will arise until we reach Reason, at which point all oppositions have been internalized (but not yet overcome). Here at the very beginning, however, the opposition between the in-itself and the for-itself has yet to arise. Sense-certainty is still unaware of it. For it, there is no difference between what is for it and what is in-itself – what you see is what you get is its initial presumption. The aim of Hegel’s argument in Sense-Certainty is therefore to show how through its own experience consciousness is led to confront the fact that there is a difference between appearance and in-itself, surface and depth. It is that difference with which it will try to come to terms in Perception. It is likely that Hegel also has a more specific reason for beginning with a type of cognition so simple that the subject-object divide is not yet clearly manifest. Sense-certainty is the first form of cognition of consciousness, i.e. it is the first and most basic form of knowledge. The soul does not yet “know” an object. It lives in symbiosis with nature, it “feels” its body, it is unconsciously active in the routines that the body executes, but it does not objectify or reflect on the difference between itself and its body. What Hegel aims to show in Sense-Certainty is that even the most basic and minimal type of knowledge involves an experience of the objectworld that is typically due to the presence of conceptual structures that “synthesize” and thus transform the sensory data or, rather, the content of the “actual soul” (cf. E § 411). There is no absolutely unmediated “intake” of “simple ideas” at the level of consciousness. Nor is there a separate intuitional material that could be identified and characterized prior to and independently of our form of awareness of it. In other words, the Kantian separation of matter and form of cognition resulting in two independent “sources” of knowledge is ontologically spurious as is the idea of a pristine sensible “given” unaffected by the form in and through which it is presented. Even space and time, Hegel will argue, are already conceptually permeated, are more than formal intuitions.24 How does Hegel go about demonstrating these points? As we would expect from our discussion of the Phenomenology’s argumentative strategy in the preceding section, he essentially plays off consciousness’ putative a priori against its actual experience of the object. The conflict between the two leads to a corrected a priori which then forms the presumptive a priori of the next experiential cycle beginning with Perception. The putative a priori of sense-certainty is described by Hegel as follows:
24 If
there is any non-subjective, natural given at all, it would have to be sought at the prerepresentational level which Hegel discusses under the title of the “natural” and the “feeling” soul (cf. E §§ 391–410).
104
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
Because of its concrete content, sense-certainty immediately appears as the richest kind of knowledge, indeed a knowledge of infinite wealth for which no bounds can be found, either when we reach out into space and time in which it is dispersed, or when we take a bit of this wealth, and by division enter into it (PS § 91/3, 82).
Later in Sense-Certainty and with apparent reference to a philosophical position, he says that those who believe in this kind of reality describe it as an infinite wealth of singular external sensible particulars, all of them real, unique, i.e. unlike every other, even “wholly personal” (cf. PS § 110/3, 91).25 The objects of sense-certainty are concrete individual things in space and time whose existence is in no doubt by virtue of the immediate contact sense-certainty entertains with them. In parenthesis, it should be noted that in the later Encyclopedia version Hegel corrects the Phenomenology’s subsumption of spatio-temporal particulars under Sense-Certainty. Instead, he argues, spatio-temporal particulars are properly discussed only in connection with the cognitive form of Anschauung, or intuiting, which in Hegel’s system marks a much higher cognitive level, one even that follows the Phenomenology and forms the first stage of the Psychology (cf. E § 445A).26 The reason Hegel gives for this reassignment of the subject matter of the Phenomenology’s Sense-Certainty to the Encyclopedia’s Psychology is that spatio-temporal particulars are thought to be independent individuals that are not only external to consciousness, but external to, and therefore distinguished and separate from, one another (cf. E § 418R). In other words, spatio-temporal particulars are regarded as having an intrinsic identity of their own by distinguishing themselves from one another in terms of spatial and temporal location as well as a host of properties attaching to them.27 By contrast, in the form of cognition called sensecertainty these particulars are supposed to be experienced not as spatio-temporal objects with an identity of their own and with rule-governed connections among themselves, but merely as the singular ad hoc objects of our sensory awareness (cf. E § 418). While external particulars, they are distinct entities only on account of the immediate characteristics they exhibit for consciousness, not as particulars with a nature and a contextual setting of their own. Sense-certainty, Hegel implies in
25 The
position implicitly referred to is in all likelihood that of Jacobi: see Falke, 1996, p. 71 ff., Harris, 1997, I 214, Siep, 2000, p. 84. Graeser, 1998, pp. 40–41 plausibly establishes a connection with Epicurus. 26 See E § 418R: “The spatial and temporal singleness, Here and Now, as which I determined the object of sensory consciousness in the Phenomenology of Spirit . . . properly belongs only to intuition.” See also E § 449A, where Hegel suggests that the mere sensory awareness of objects in sense-certainty might already be called intuition, but it would be more like a “mindless intuiting” (geistloses Anschauen) than intuiting proper. 27 Intuition proper, Hegel argues, grasps the external object in its totality, as a wealth of determinations held together by a concept rather than treating it, as sensory consciousness does, as a singular particular that immediately falls apart into many different aspects (cf. E § 449A). Intuition is also the gift of the poet who is able to give exemplary expression to a strong emotional experience and thus to objectify and “domesticate” it, so to speak: see Hegel’s reference to Goethe’s Werther at E § 448A.
3.2
Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal
105
the Encyclopedia, is impressionistic. Rather than gathering the multifaceted appearances into ordered complexes of objects and objective relationships, as intuition will do, it fractures them into a myriad of sense-impressions. For sense-certainty, reality is one big unorganized mosaic, similar to the routed soldiers in Aristotle’s famous battle metaphor before they have started to regroup.28 For the sensory consciousness we are dealing with here, then, these external objects are concrete sensible particulars such as a house or a tree (cf. PS § 98/3, 85). Furthermore, due to the immediate contact sense-certainty entertains with them, these particulars are supposed to be the rock bottom of reality, undeniably given and objectively real. Sense-certainty will undergo three major cycles of testing during which it is successively disabused of its putative a priori. Consciousness is asked to reflect upon and summarize its experience of the object, of itself, and of the relationship it entertains with the object. How does what consciousness believes to know about its object, itself, and its relationship to the sensible particular translate into knowledge, i.e. into informative cognitive content? The result of the test is the opening up of a contrast – in fact, a contradiction – between consciousness’ doxa and its actual knowledge. It believes the object to be a unique singular thing with an inexhaustible wealth of features and to be the true reality in its experience, but what it knows about this object is something quite different: All that it says about what it knows is just that it [sc. the object] is; and its truth contains nothing but the sheer being of the thing. Consciousness, for its part, is in this certainty only as a pure ‘I’; or I am in it only as a pure ‘This’, and the object similarly only as a pure ‘This’. I, this particular I, am certain of this particular thing . . . It is; this is the essential point for sense-knowledge, and this pure being, or this simple immediacy, constitutes its truth (PS § 91/3, 82–83).
The knowledge sense-certainty has of its object is limited to knowledge of its bare existence, Hegel claims. This is a puzzling diagnosis. Why, it may be asked, does Hegel characterize the sensible particular as a This of whose existence consciousness is certain, but which has no further determinations than being present? Is the object of sense-certainty not a thing with many, indeed infinitely many, features? A thing of “infinite wealth for which no bounds can be found, either when we reach out into space and time in which it is dispersed, or when we take a bit of this wealth, and by division enter into it,” as Hegel described it earlier (PS § 91/3, 82)? Why, then, can sense-certainty know this particular only in the form of a featureless This? As a preliminary explanation one might offer the following. Sense-certainty has reasons to restrict itself to a deictic language that can pinpoint objects only by referring to them as “this here now”, “or that there now”, etc. To be sure, the sensible particulars could be described in greater detail, but such description would properly belong to the cognitive level of perception which possesses a richer language. Hence, the point is not that the sensible object could not be described in more informative ways. Rather, sense-certainty denies itself any such richer description because it believes
28 Cf.
Aristotle, An post. II 19, 100a 12–13.
106
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
that anything beyond pointing out the “this something” would either reduce the infinite wealth of this reality to an abstraction or import concepts that over-interpret what is actually “given” in sensation. What sense-certainty attempts to do on this assumption, then, is to refuse to conceptualize its experience in the belief that any such conceptualization might either falsify or distort the immediacy and purity of its sensations or become vulnerable to the skeptic who might call into question the objective reference of any ascriptions of objective features to the content of sense-experience. There is some evidence that Hegel here attacks a position that tries to disarm skepticism by assuming nothing but the possibility of an immediate sensory contact with what is real that is as yet untainted by any mental intervention.29 This position limits itself to a purely deictic language because a richer language might already contain the danger of unwarranted subjective additions or conceptual abstraction. Sensory consciousness believes, Hegel says, that “it has not as yet omitted anything from the object, but has the object before it in its perfect entirety” (PS § 91/3, 82). He might have added that consciousness also believes it has not as yet added anything to what is purely given. In other words, the position perhaps targeted here by Hegel is a misguided attempt to defeat skepticism by refusing to conceptualize one’s experience. But, as Hegel will point out, the “sin” of conceptualization is an original sin which has in any case already been committed. Still, sense-certainty is curiously Janus-faced. On the one hand, it knows its object merely as a This that seems to be a wholesale abstraction from the actual content of its experience, on the other it believes to be in possession of the object “in its entirety,” i.e. as yet untouched by any abstraction. To be a This means to be an indeterminate something, a something or other or a something that is nothing in particular. How can such a This also be the object in its entirety, i.e., a unified object? How is this duality of being both infinitely determined and at the same time indeterminate to be explained? Unless Hegel is confusing the issue, it must be sense-certainty itself that is confused about what its experience consists of. And so it is, nor does this come as a surprise. Sense-certainty, we have seen, represents an immediate relation between consciousness and object, one in which there is as yet no distinction between appearance and essence or between belief and knowledge. These distinctions are yet to emerge in order to become distinct opposites for it. Consequently, the object of sense-certainty is necessarily Janus-faced. It is simultaneously an infinitely rich reality in virtue of its being “dispersed” in space and time, and an indeterminate something in virtue of the immediacy with which it is being experienced. Necessarily, qua this singular thing the object is infinitely individuated
29 Cf. PS § 109/3, 90: “It is therefore astonishing when . . . it is asserted as universal experience and put forward, too, as a philosophical proposition, even as the outcome of [sc. an attempt to defeat] Scepticism, that the reality or being of external things taken as Thises or sense-objects has absolute truth for consciousness.” For the influence of ancient skepticism on Hegel’s argument here see Düsing, 1973.
3.2
Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal
107
and is therefore dispersed, at least potentially, into infinitely many “Thises”.30 What is being objectified is merely the having of an experience now, while the content of that experience is still a matter of feeling (Empfindung).31 As a result, the unity remains blank. Conceptual unity and sensory quality are not yet united into one object. Whether this is a plausible scenario is debatable. It is difficult to decide, if what Hegel is describing here is a genuine form of cognition at all or whether he is reconstructing what he thinks to be the conceptual underpinnings of some theory such as Jacobi’s. Since he retains sense-certainty in the Encyclopedia (where its importance as a form of cognition seems minimal, however32 ), and since he does refer to an anti-skeptical position at PS § 109/3, 90, it is possible that he believes to be doing both.33 We can leave aside the question which anti-skeptical position is supposed to be in the background. As far as the cognitive form of sense-certainty itself is concerned, whether genuine or not, there is a strong systemic reason for describing it the way Hegel does. As indicated above, sense-certainty represents an immediate relation of consciousness and object such that in it consciousness is as yet unaware of the distinction between in-itself and for-itself, essence and instance (or type and token), conceptual unity and sensory diversity. This difference must become evident for consciousness, but it must also already be implicit in the way in which it understands its object. Hence the difference must be present in an unmediated form. As a result, sense-certainty is by nature ambiguous about whether its object is a unique singular This or a myriad of “Thises”. It is necessarily both at the same time without experiencing a contradiction between the two. If one were to ask what a given This is, the answer would be that nothing else could be said about it other than that it is a This. And if one were to insist on some distinguishing mark of the This, one would have to say that this This is different from another This by not being the other This. Sense-certainty possesses only one tool, viz. the indexical “this” and its deictic cognates “that”, “now”, “here”, “there”, “I”, to pick out and identify its object
30 Here
Hegel’s comment at E § 419A is helpful: “The content of sensuous consciousness is in itself dialectical. It is supposed to be the single, isolated individual; but it is just this that makes it not a single individual but all individuals . . . ” 31 See E § 418: “That rich contents is constituted by the determinations of feeling; they are the matter of consciousness (§ 414), the substantial and qualitative in which the soul consists. . . and which it finds in itself. ” And: “The specific contents of the sensible, such as smell, taste, color, etc., belongs to feeling (Empfindung), as we saw in § 401.” 32 Note again that the content of the experience belongs to feeling, not to consciousness per se. The object of sensuous consciousness possesses as yet no other thought-determination than that of existing and of being some singular external thing which is other than consciousness (E § 418A). This sounds very much like bumping into some unidentified object in the dark. 33 For the likelihood that Jacobi is the target see footnote 3 above. That Hegel’s account here is puzzling, perhaps even problematic, has not escaped the attention of scholars: see Stederoth, 2001, pp. 283–285 and Westphal, 1973, p. 89. Westphal has suggested, quite persuasively in view of E § 418 it seems to me, that Hegel’s sense-certainty very much looks like an artificial abstraction, not a genuine form of cognition.
108
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
or to refer to itself.34 Hence Hegel’s use of “house”, “tree”, “day”, “night”, etc. is strictly illustrative, borne of the need to give the reader an idea of what kinds of particulars sense-certainty would be referring to, if it were not just sense-certainty. In no way do universals such as “house” and “day” as such belong to the descriptive level of sense-certainty. The descriptive language of sense-certainty consists entirely of deictic expressions. This is perhaps useful to underline, since it highlights the fact that Hegel is not analyzing the use of indexicals here, which as such, are not descriptive.35 The error from which sense-certainty suffers is that “this” picks out a unique individual with a wealth of features, something both indubitably real and knowable in all its richness. As consciousness will learn, this is not the case. Sense-certainty is not really engaged in the language game of picking out things with the help of indexicals to which it can, in the manner of ostensive definitions, give a name and to which it then attributes qualities. To be sure, the aspect of referring to sensible particulars is part of the scenario of sense-certainty. Thus consciousness is asked to report which sensible particular it has picked out, and one of the answers is that “Here is a tree” (PS § 98/3, 85). But again, the point is that for sense-certainty the tree is a This and not yet a tree. As the discussion in the text shows, by playing off the This as tree against the This as house Hegel wants to challenge sense-certainty to see whether it can still come up with a definite description of the object when it is denied the use of the object’s name.36 It cannot. All it can do, if use of this richer, already representational language is ruled out, is the empty description offered by deictic expressions. Hegel, it seems, understands the deictic expressions in the subject position as empty descriptions, not as indexicals. Interestingly, by locating the vocabulary of sense-certainty at the pre-representational level, he seems to be suggesting that we regress to Kant’s “undetermined object of an empirical intuition” called “appearance” (A 20/B 34), only to find that even at this reduced level we are already using universals such as “This”, “Here”, “I”, etc., i.e. concepts. This brings us to the crucial point of Hegel’s argument.37 When used in deictic reference, indexicals do indeed pick out individual sensible particulars. Hegel’s analysis, however, is not concerned with deictic reference, ostensive definitions, and the question of how definite descriptions can be used unambiguously to pick out individual things. Generally speaking, Hegel does not intend to deal with the use of words in referential contexts but with the question how words conceptualize the
34 It should be noted right away that Hegel uses these indexicals not just as deictic expressions, but
also as predicates, i.e. concepts (see below). is apparently the reason why Terry Pinkard expresses misgivings about Charles Taylor’s treatment of the deictic expressions as indexicals: see Pinkard, 1996, pp. 350–351, footnote 11. 36 I am therefore skeptical of Harris’s insistence that Sense-Certainty is about a common sense position and that those who argue that the position is at least somewhat artificial must be mistaken: see Harris, 1997, I 230–231, footnote 12. In everyday life we are not denied the association between the perceived This and its name. Hence Harris’s reference (I 211) to G.E. Moore’s “This is a hand” obscures the strategy and aim of Hegel’s argument. 37 Incidentally, a point that I have not seen articulated all that well in the literature. 35 This
3.2
Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal
109
objects they stand for. The referential link between word and object is not at issue, because due to the position of immanence Hegel adopts the word is the object. His scenario in Sense-Certainty assumes that while picking out a familiar object, “this” thereby primarily and directly picks out a This, and only secondarily and indirectly (i.e. for a more advanced form of cognition) a house or a tree. The object of sensecertainty is a “this something” (or a “something here” or “something now”), an “x”.38 Analysis shows, however, that the conceptual information contained in the concept of This (or of Here, or Now) is close to zero. “This” as an deictic pronoun refers to a particular, but to be a This means nothing other than to be a particular something or other with which I am currently in sensory contact. Everything is some particular thing, and hence while “this” picks out a This, the This picked out could be anything whatsoever – there vanishes the uniqueness of the This. The belief that the concept of the This predicated of “this here now” means something unique and absolutely singular or that it conveys a wealth of information must be revised. In other words, Hegel asks us to consider that in the type of cognition called sense-certainty the deictic expression is also used as a predicate and functions as the concept of the object that it also picks out (“This is a this”). Sense-certainty is in touch with something which may be called either a tree or a house or anything else, but which is ontologically speaking a This. House, tree, etc. are the names of different “Thises”, but they do not express what kind of object houses, trees, or rivers are when they are objects of sensory contact. If asked that question, sense-certainty can only answer: a this something (a tode ti, to use the Aristotelian expression). Ontologically speaking, therefore, the object of sense-certainty is nothing but a bare particular. But a bare particular is not something that is immediately experienced. Here again we can see that the position Hegel analyzes under the title of sensecertainty is artificial insofar as it assumes contact with objects at a level “below” ordinary perceptual relationships.39 The rationale for this artificiality, as I see it, is Hegel’s intention to experiment with the idea of a pre-representational language and to show that even this reduced language cannot but operate with universals and that therefore to posit Kantian pre-conceptual “undetermined objects of empirical intuition” or “singular representations” is an impossibility. Conceptualization of experience is logically prior to sense-experience itself. To be a This is the most minimal characterization of objects that can qualify as knowledge, and it already presupposes conceptualization. Consequently, consciousness can have access to the sensible particulars only through the mediation of a concept, not in perfect immediacy. Hegel’s examination of sense-certainty is designed in part to disabuse sense-certainty of its belief in the possibility of an access to sensible objects that would be completely unmediated by concepts.
38 One may be reminded here of the deictic expressions in so-called protocol sentences. But again,
the idea is not to pick out some spatio-temporal object by “this” for the purpose of further description, but to ask what conceptual information the expression “this” conveys about the object thus picked out. 39 See again the reference to M. Westphal in footnote 11 above.
110
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
The first question with which Hegel challenges the putative a priori of sensecertainty is therefore: “What is the This?” (PS § 95/3, 84). Is it really the kind of rock solid reality consciousness believes it to be? Can consciousness really know the unique singular item it believes to possess in the This? If not, what is it that consciousness can really know about the This? And finally, can the This really be accessed by bypassing any conceptual mediation or presupposed framework of reference? The answer to all these questions is negative. The This can be anything since any sensible particular is a This. Everything is a This, but the This is nothing in particular. Hence it is not very helpful to insist that what I really mean is this This, not that This. A This is what it is by both excluding and including any specific sensible particular. It is all of them, but none of them specifically, and yet, the This is also meant to pick out unambiguously one thing and not another. As a deictic expression it can do so, as a concept it cannot. As such, it is not a particular at all, but a universal: A simple thing of this kind which is through negation, which is neither this not that, a notThis, and is with equal indifference This as well as That – such a thing we call a universal. So it is in fact the universal that is the true [content] of sense-certainty (PS § 96/3, 85).
The This, then, while being represented as a unique singular particular such as “this house here now”, can at the level of sense-certainty be characterized only by means of universals, viz. as “This x here now is a This here now,” and it can therefore be known only as or in terms of an (empty) universal. If the universal is a name such as “house”, the particular could be known at least minimally. But as we have seen, such general names are denied sense-certainty. If, however, the universal is “x”, the particular referred to cannot strictly speaking be known at all. The sensory content that falls outside the deictic universals is variable and perishable, its reality is as abstract as that of the This. In fact, the sensible particular taken as a This possesses no intrinsic being (cf. PS § 109/3, 91).40 The This may now be day and later night, as in “Now it [i.e., this This] is night,” but a little later “this This” is day, i.e. it is that This, not this This – a futile attempt to distinguish one particular from another conceptually by their common characteristic and the only characteristic they each possess at the level of sense-certainty.41 The sensible reality is such that it changes on its own accord. One reality is replaced by another, one sensible particular by the next. The individual sensible object vanishes. It is there now, and gone the next moment. Its reality is fleeting and unstable. The This is like a window through which one observes the passage of the clouds in the sky – an ever changing scenario, but nothing stable except the window itself. Hegel claims that die Tiere . . . bleiben nicht vor den sinnlichen Dingen als an sich seienden stehen . . . ” the point is not that we can distinguish two Thises by pointing. The point is that both are conceptually speaking a This, hence indistinguishable with respect to their conceptual determination. – It is tempting to suspect that in using day and night as examples Hegel may have a reference to Heraclitus in mind (see fr. 67). A reference to Pyrrhonian skepticism has also been suggested (which by no means excludes a further “background” reference to Heraclitus): see Köhler/Pöggeler, 1998, p. 9. Hegel’s point in any case is the same as Heraclitus’, viz. that the logos is that which unifies things by affirming and negating their difference at the same time.
40 “Auch
41 Again,
3.2
Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal
111
the content left in the universal is the notion of “pure being”, or mere existence (cf. PS § 99/3, 85). This does not seem to be quite accurate. To be a This apparently connotes being a determinate particular, an individual. But it is also not more than that, it has no description whatsoever. Looked at in this way, the sensible particular is hollow at its core, it is a “nothingness” [Nichtigkeit] (PS § 109/3, 91). Are we supposed to associate a Platonic reference here in the sense that if knowledge is what we are after we should leave the Thises behind and turn to the more substantial universals? What, then, does consciousness really know when it knows this universal? Essentially, it knows a bare particular, a “mediated simplicity, or a universality” (PS § 98/3, 85). As a concept or category of what is being picked out in sense-certainty, This (or Here, Now, I) rejects all further determination. It is “indifferent to what happens in it,” but is “permanent and self-preserving . . . through the fact that something else, viz. Day and Night, is not” (PS § 96/3, 84). But now we need to ask, Where is the variable content of the This to be found? Is this content not also part of the experience of sense-certainty? Hegel responds that the (variable) content of the This is to be found in consciousness’ putative knowledge (Meinen).42 Consciousness’ putative knowing (Meinen) stands against its actual knowledge, what it merely believes or purports to know against what it can actually put into words. What consciousness merely means – in the sense of gropes towards, but cannot articulate – turns out to be strictly ineffable. The variable content of the This can be known only if it is likewise
42 In this particular usage, meinen is difficult to capture in translation. It can be used in German the
same way it is used in English, for instance when we ask “What do you mean?” – Was meinst Du? Meinen may also mean “to believe” or “to think” as in “If I am not mistaken, I believe (meine or, alternatively, glaube) that Michelangelo painted the Sistine Chapel.” But Hegel’s use of Meinen here is special. It is closer to having something in mind, but not being able to articulate exactly what that is. The phrase “If you see what I mean” perhaps uses “mean” in a way closest to Hegel’s here. For often we fail to see what somebody means when they are struggling to put it into words. In those cases we may divine or speculate what the other person means, but sometimes we simply remain clueless – and so may the speaker himself. He purports to communicate something but does not arrive at expressing it. This is the situation Hegel envisions in Sense-Certainty. Hegel elsewhere (E § 20R) draws on the etymological connection between meinen in the sense of “believe” and the possessive pronoun mein (“my”). What I mean is strictly what I mean, what belongs to me as my opinion or putative knowledge and what may therefore also be subjective to the point of being incommunicable. The connection with a Wittgensteinian argument against the possibility of a private language suggests itself. Hegel would agree that language is not such that it could express something supposedly exclusively mine. The reader should be cautioned against drawing parallels too quickly between Hegel’s point and Wittgenstein’s private language argument. The question of what affinity exists here, if any, should be examined in the light of Hintikka and Hintikka, 1986, pp. 241–271. As far as Hegel is concerned, language subverts the attempt to establish any kind of “private” meaning, i.e. a meaning that could not possibly be shared with others but that I could nonetheless “share” with myself. Hegel’s way of putting this is that “What I only mean is mine; it belongs to me as this particular individual. But if language expresses only what is universal, then I cannot say what I only mean” (E § 20R). However, neither Hegel nor, following Hintikka & Hintikka, Wittgenstein deny that there exist private experiences that can be meaningfully talked about in the context of a publicly available language-game. In a sense, the issue in both Hegel and Wittgenstein comes down to exposing a simple fallacy, viz. the idea of a language of the ineffable.
112
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
translated into a This or, rather, infinitely many Thises. But it is immediately clear that since the variable content of the This is supposed to be infinite this translation could never actually be accomplished – the sensible particular would “crumble away” (PS § 110/3, 92) long before the list of its features could be completed. If, as sense-certainty seems to believe, the unique singular particular of sense is unique on account of being infinitely individuated, then what I mean when I say “This unique individual sensible particular” can never be expressed or “cashed in”. As Hegel puts it: . . . the sensuous This that is meant cannot be reached by language, which belongs to consciousness, i.e. to that which is inherently universal (PS § 110/3, 91–92).
Language, Hegel asserts, is more truthful than sense-certainty’s mistaken belief in the truth of the sensible particular. In language, he says, We ourselves directly refute what we mean to say, and since the universal is the true [content] of sense-certainty and language expresses this true [content] alone, it is just not possible for us ever to say, or express in words, a sensuous being that we mean (PS § 97/3, 85).
Nor, and this is typical of Hegel, would it be worth the effort. From the point of view of knowledge and intelligibility the sensuous content of the sensible particular is of no particular interest, because all that could be said about it is that it is a This here now. What is ineffable is not for this reason precious but, to the contrary, not worth expressing.43 We might try to enumerate the features of sensible particulars or make a list of their names. But for one thing, this would have to be done in a language that employs a richer vocabulary than sense-certainty is allowed to utilize and for another it would be rather pointless. The result of Hegel’s argument thus far is that the This represents the most minimal conceptualization of the content of consciousness’ experience. It expresses what consciousness knows about the object of sense-certainty which is, as we have seen, nearly nothing. But even the most minimal form of conceptualization already contains mediation or synthesis, i.e. negation of internal difference. The matter of pure intuition is left behind as either ineffable at the level of sense-certainty itself or irrelevant in a context of acquiring knowledge about objects. Modifying Aristotle’s wistful phrase concerning the relationship of particular and universal in perception, Hegel might have said that while we “mean” the particular, we nevertheless express the universal.44 For this reason, meaning, in the sense of semantic information or conceptual content, does not depend on what we “mean” in the sense of “purport 43 Cf. Hegel’s similar comments on the supposedly inexpressible meaning of thoughts at E § 462A.
actual phrase is “. . . for though one perceives the particular, perception is of the universal – e.g. of man but not of Callias the man” (An. post. II 19, 100a 17- b 2). The wistfulness lies in the fact that the Greek uses the same word for “perceiving” and “perception” (α´ισθησις), so that the sentence “means” to express the difference between sensing the particular and recognizing the universal in it, but does not actually express it, except through the morphological variation of verb as opposed to noun. And for good reason, since in the act of perception the two are immediately one. This means that while the proper name “Callias” is not a universal it could not be understood
44 Aristotle’s
3.2
Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal
113
to know but cannot say”. Generally speaking, the meaning of what we say does not depend on what you or I subjectively associate with it. Semantic meaning is universally available through language. At the level of consciousness, all intuited matter has been translated into conceptual determinations. The This in its own right already contains the element of differentiation – every This is both a simple one and a multitude of Thises: . . . by pointing out this bit of paper, experience teaches me what the truth of sense-certainty in fact is: I point it out as a ‘Here’, which is a Here of other Heres, or is in its own self a ‘simple togetherness of many Heres’; i.e. it is a universal (PS § 110/3, 92).
This also means that the heterogeneous element of Kantian intuition is replaced by conceptual heterogeneity expressed through negation. As our quote indicates, not only is the concept of the This a “mediated universality”, a spatio-temporal framework, too, must already be presupposed for any deictic reference to be successful. A This can be picked out deictically only if it is understood that “here” presupposes an understanding of “not there” – i.e., of negation – and “now” an understanding of “not yesterday”, etc. An entire framework of reference must be in place for even the most “immediate” act of pointing to indicate more than an empty directionality.45 It is not the case, then, that there is such a thing as pointing out something in pure immediacy. All reference, even deictic reference, is context dependent. But furthermore, even these Kantian forms of intuition, space and time, already contain universality and negation. A Here is a plurality of many Heres, a Now a plurality of many Nows (cf. PS § 107–8/3, 89–90). This proof constitutes the third cycle of the experience of sense-certainty (cf. PS §§ 105–8/3, 88–90). Previously, consciousness had made the experience that just as “this” picks out a This, so does “I”. For the purposes of knowledge, the I referred to in sense-certainty is likewise a simple universality. When speaking of myself as “I”, I do indeed mean a single ‘I’, but I can no more say what I mean in the case of ‘I’ than I can in the case of ‘Now’ and ‘Here’. . . . when I say ‘I’, this singular ‘I’, I say in general all ‘I’s; everyone is what I say, everyone is ‘I’, this singular ‘I’ (PS § 102/3, 86–87).
Again, it should be understood that “I” here functions as the concept of the self, not as an indexical – for obviously, the indexical does not pick out the same “I” when used by different speakers. As a concept, “I” does not and cannot pick out any particular I. It picks out all of them and none. What, then, is the end result of the argument in Sense-Certainty? Knowledge is knowledge of the universal from the start, i.e. it is conceptual. The most primitive form of conceptualization presupposes mediation, i.e. negation of negation. The This maintains itself as a unit of meaning by excluding all other meaning from if it were not taken to name a particular that falls under a universal. Without the implicit relation to a universal such as “man” or some other kind of thing, “Callias” would be a word without meaning. 45 This point was made in a different way brilliantly by Strawson in Individuals. The argument is that deictic expressions would be unable to fulfill their referential function without relying on a spatio-temporal framework that constitutes their a priori semantic condition (cf. Strawson, 1990, p. 31 ff.).
114
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
itself and by subsuming all other particulars under itself qua Thises – it is “permanent and self-preserving . . . through the fact that something else . . . is not” (PS § 96/3, 84). It expresses the thought of “this particular item and no other”, but then all particulars are conceptually just that. In other words, the most primitive universal is already a synthesis, one that does not include an intuitional element that is radically different from thought. Now this result, it should be pointed out, in a way does not contradict Kant’s complementarity thesis. Indeed, it might even seem to confirm it – no knowledge without a synthesis of intuition and concept.46 Hegel’s critique of sense-certainty’s claims to knowledge does not deny the existence of a manifold. However, a fine line needs to be observed here. The pure heterogeneous manifold Kant talks about is not the manifold that is part of the universal called “This”. Rather, in Hegel’s scenario the intuitional element is represented in the concept by a potential conceptual diversity, i.e. an internal conceptual differentiation waiting to be explicated. The intuitional manifold is thus in principle homogeneous with the concept, not heterogeneous, or heterogeneous only in degree and not in kind. Depending, then, on how one reads the complementarity thesis, Hegel’s proposal in Sense-Certainty in one sense does and in another does not conflict with Kant’s approach. If the heterogeneity of sensibility and understanding is thought to be a matter of degree, Hegel’s position might be compatible with Kant’s. There can, however, be little doubt that for Kant the complementarity thesis implies the radical heterogeneity of sensibility and understanding. If that is so, Hegel does not so much overcome as reject Kant’s complementarity thesis. For his argument in SenseCertainty has the effect of “purifying” the transcendental unity of apperception by leaving aside the heterogeneous manifold of intuition as an ineffable content. In other words, the pure manifold is excluded from, not taken up into, the unity of the concept. It is excluded partly because it is ineffable and partly because to the extent that it can be made intelligible the information it contributes about the object is entirely vacuous from the point of view of knowledge. The information may indeed not be trivial for purposes of identifying an object unambiguously in a perceptual context. But as we have seen, the study of how linguistic expressions are used to perform certain referential functions is not Hegel’s concern. There is yet another reason why the idea of a pure sensible manifold or an undetermined empirical manifold may lead us in the wrong direction. When we ask what in our experience is really unique or private in an exclusive sense such that it cannot be shared or experienced by anyone else, the only aspect that remains after all that is effable has been said is the fact that it is my experience, i.e. something that by definition cannot have been experienced by anyone else. But what is that exclusively private aspect? It is obviously not what we experience, since that is sharable and can be experienced by others as well, nor is it so much how we experience, since even that is communicable and sharable. It is merely the fact that it is I rather than someone else who has or undergoes or makes the experience. The 46 This
is what Hegel has in mind when, in the Science of Logic he approvingly refers to Kant’s complementarity thesis by saying that “it is an essential proposition of the Kantian transcendental philosophy that without intuitions concepts are empty and are valid solely as relations of the manifold given by intuition” (SL 585).
3.2
Sense-Certainty: The Particular and the Universal
115
exclusive privacy of the experience consists in its noetic aspect, not in its noematic content, so to speak. Both are effable, but it is the noetic performance or the mental event that is strictly private, not what they are of or about. It is private in the sense that only I can know incorrigibly whether or not I had the experience, whereas others are left to speculate. It is private in the sense that nobody else can strictly speaking make this experience on my behalf. It is unique in its aspect of being a token, not in its aspect of being of a certain type. The stipulation of a pure or undetermined manifold wrongly suggests that there is some matter in our experience that we somehow experience but that remains ineffable unless and until it is being conceptualized. What in fact happens, however, is that there is an aspect of experience that in one respect (and only in one respect) remains strictly private while still being effable (we can report our experiencing pain). But this has nothing to do with content, only with performance. Hence, paraphrasing Gorgias we might say, a pure or undetermined manifold as part of the content of experience does not exist. Even if it existed, we could not know it. Even if we could know it, we could not communicate it. In conclusion, we may summarize the issue as follows. The question of a pure or undetermined (pre-conceptual) sensible manifold in sense-certainty concerns the issue whether or not there is an ineffable intuitional element involved in sensecertainty or not. To this Hegel answers that the ineffable is something we mean but cannot express. This, however, should not be taken as an endorsement on Hegel’s part of a deep problem of ineffability (at most, what Hegel might endorse, if he were to care enough about it, is the privacy of mental experience). That we cannot say what we merely mean is not an endorsement of “strong” ineffability, because it simply makes no sense just to mean something without being able to express what we mean. Merely to mean without somehow giving to understand that we mean something and yet to convey something intelligible by doing so is an impossibility. If sense-certainty were like that, it could not even be treated as a form of knowing and hence could not have a place in the Phenomenology. Merely to mean while giving to understand that something is being meant is a case of weak or circumstantial ineffability. It is like a gagged person trying to say something but managing to utter only unintelligible noises. We clearly understand that something is being conveyed, but not what that might be.47 Some interpreters of Hegel’s argument in Sense-Certainty may have been confused by taking Hegel to argue in favor of strong ineffability while what he likely has in mind is a critique of weak or circumstantial ineffability. Granted, then, that there exists no strictly ineffable content and that ineffability only results from a factual, artificial, or forced limitation on the means of expression, i.e. accidentally, there are still three possible interpretations of how Hegel’s argument in Sense-Certainty could be construed. What may also have contributed 47 There
are of course many ways to illustrate weak ineffability. Imagine yourself at a dinner table with guests while you are trying to communicate to your husband some embarrassing little fact that you could not possibly convey openly under the circumstances etc. Here, ineffability is simply a consequence of a restriction on your means of expression required by etiquette, i.e., it is weak, not strong ineffability.
116
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
to confuse some interpreters of this section of the Phenomenology is the fact that the text can seem to support all three interpretations. The first would be to say that to spell out the determinacy of the content of sense-certainty in full with the severely limited semantic means of deictic expressions alone would be tedious and totally uninformative. It would indeed be very much like trying to say something with a band aid taped over one’s mouth. A slightly modified version of the same interpretation could go as follows. Assuming that consciousness for the most part is in contact with full-fledged sensible objects in perception, this richer representational content would certainly be effable, but since sense-certainty is artificially restricted to deictic expressions (i.e. in this sense “gagged”), this content cannot be expressed. Second, assuming that Hegel meant to allow for a minimally richer vocabulary with which to convey the contents of sense-certainty, such as “This is white” or “This is a white piece of paper” (which strictly speaking belong to the level of perception or even intuition, not to sense-certainty proper), it would still be utterly futile, even if not completely uninformative, to try to spell out the determinacy of the content of sense-certainty. It would be like trying to describe a blank piece of paper by superimposing a pixel grid upon it and then start to describe each pixel by saying “The paper is white here” etc. After having finished the process we would be able to conclude that indeed the entire piece of paper was white, but depending on how small we chose to make the pixels (and we may make them as small as we like) we more likely would “not be able to complete the description, but would be compelled to leave it to others” (PS § 110/3, 92), until in the end the paper would “crumble away” (ibid.), before anyone had finally determined that it was white all over. According to this interpretation, Hegel’s aim would have been to show that sense-certainty is incapable of conveying the simple truth that a perceptual judgment would be able to express based on just one quick glance, viz. that the entire piece of paper is white. Or, since an exhaustive description of any object insofar as it is an infinite aggregate of Thises or Heres in an infinite number of Nows is impossible, the intended result, i.e. the judgment that the whole piece of paper is white, could never be established. In this sense, not to be able to express everything would be equivalent to expressing nothing – one would “finally have to admit to speaking about something which is not” (ibid.), i.e. is not anything whole and substantial. Finally, the third interpretation takes the argument of Sense-Certainty to be that the language of sense-certainty is “This is a This” or “Here is a Here” or “Here is a This,” etc. The argument then proceeds to show not only that “This is a This” is entirely uninformative, but also and above all that the concept of the This connotes determinacy, while saying something about the This which is true of everything and anything. The concept of a This or Here would be the most minimal conceptual determinacy, but as such it would already imply a conceptualization. A concept or universal would be understood as a determinate content that by definition is true of or applies to more than one thing, i.e. that has the refusal to be true of only one particular built into its very structure. The Now is now night, but a little later the Now is day, i.e. night and day are both a Now. As such, a concept is a negation of a negation. In rejecting identification of its meaning with only one thing, it nonetheless determines whatever it is true of or applies to as something
3.3
Perception and Understanding
117
definite.48 Except that in the case of the This the determinacy of the concept converges on zero. All it says about a thing is that it is something or other, an “x”. This is certainly not nothing. But it is something only minimally determinate, i.e. an indeterminate something. This is what it means to be a This. In principle, though, the entire content of sense-certainty could be dissolved into an aggregate of infinite Thises, Heres, Nows, and I’s. One would then still not have reached a purely intuitional, pre- or non-conceptual, ineffable content of experience which Kant claims is an indispensable condition of something being given in experience, but only an infinite aggregate of minimal determination. The most basic element of cognition is not a pure or an undetermined sensible manifold, but the empty universal designating a non-descript particular. The “hard work” of conceptualization starts with the effable, not the ineffable.
3.3 Perception and Understanding: The Immanence of Thinking and the Meaning of Aufhebung Earlier we indicated the complex structure of the Phenomenology’s argument on its two levels, viz. the dialectic between the in-itself and the for-itself that reoccurs with every cycle of consciousness’ experience, and the successive transformation of the relationship between grounding principle and grounded experience that works itself out over the course of the entire Phenomenology. After our discussion of Hegel’s argument in Sense-Certainty, it may be useful to introduce in a more formal way the three aspects we will be paying specific attention to for the remainder of our analysis of the Phenomenology. This will help us to stay focused on the major steps that are supposed to demonstrate how and why consciousness progresses on its path from knowledge of the sensible world via knowledge of the “supersensible” world to knowledge of the unconditioned. To capture the essential aspects of Hegel’s argumentative plot, we may distinguish between a thematic and a methodological level. At the thematic level, we see Hegel introducing new object domains of consciousness as well as new forms of experience that are directly dependent on the mode of cognition consciousness has reached. At the methodological level, we follow the gradual transformation of the ground-grounded relationship from a “realistic” model in which the ground is both an other over against consciousness as well as the touchstone of truth (Consciousness and Self-Consciousness) into a speculative model. In the latter, consciousness first recognizes itself in the ground in Reason. While reason is universal, however, consciousness is individual. Consequently, the two do not completely coincide. The ground first needs to assume the nature of 48 Thus
I cannot quite agree with Matthias Kettner that the argument in Sense-Certainty is primarily a critique of ontological atomism which in my view is the target rather of the third cycle of Perception: see Kettner 1990, 9. The reader may want to turn to Kettner for an excellent discussion not only of Sense-Certainty, but also of all the relevant literature on this chapter since Feuerbach and Purpus up to and including W. Becker, K. Düsing, J. Simon, E. Tugendhat, M. Westphal as well as analytic approaches from Frege, Quine and Searle to Putnam.
118
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
subjectivity or self-consciousness in Spirit for individual consciousness to be able to identify with it completely. It then remains for consciousness to realize that this self-conscious ground recognizes itself in consciousness (in Religion, particularly in revealed religion). On this basis, consciousness can proceed to the final identification of itself with the self-conscious ground, i.e. it can itself become self-conscious spirit in Absolute Knowing.49 Third, in addition to following these two aspects we may on occasion also want to comment briefly on Hegel’s implicit critique directed at other philosophical positions that are successively rejected or overcome as a result of the advance of consciousness. To take these aspects in reverse order and putting to one side for the moment the question of Hegel’s implicit historical references, we may say that, among other things, Sense-Certainty can be read as Hegel’s rejection of the dual source model of cognition as well as the ‘myth’ of immediacy. That model gives way to a single source model in which the manifold of purely sensible intuition is replaced by conceptualizable diversity. The argument is that a purely sensible element would be strictly unintelligible. From the point of view of knowledge and of what can be said it would become the ineffable. Nor is our understanding in any way the poorer for it, because contrary to a widespread belief the ineffable is not the most precious truth. What really remains unsaid at the level of sense-certainty is not the ineffable but the determinable. That which is implicitly determinate but which has not yet been explicitly determined replaces the irreducibly sensible and non-conceptual and becomes the conceptually determinable matter of knowledge. To be sure, it can be and has been argued that elimination of the non-conceptual element in knowledge is impossible because without it we lose the reference to spatio-temporal reality and the possibility to refer to things or states of affairs in the world.50 Independently of difficulties inherent in the dual source model itself,51 it may be said in response that if referentiality presupposes intelligibility of the referent, intelligibility cannot itself be derived from the referent. For that reason, a purely sensible, entirely nonconceptualized referent could not even become an object of consciousness. It does not make sense to divide the object into a purely sensible aspect (its matter) and a purely intelligible aspect (its form) because such matter would remain ineffable. 49 Hegel
details these developments at the beginning of Absolute Knowing, PS §§ 788–799/3, 575–583. 50 For a persuasive (although in my view not entirely successful) argument in defense of Kantian dualism see Guyer, 2000, pp. 37–56. 51 I argued earlier that the most serious difficulty for the empirical manifold, i.e. the matter of cognition (“the raw material offered by sensibility,” as Kant called it at A 1), is probably to be either determinate or indeterminate. To recapitulate briefly, if the manifold is pure, it is indeterminate and hence cannot generate determinacy. Since the categories do not themselves contain determinate content, determinacy of the structures of objectivity remains unaccounted for. If the manifold is empirical, i.e. determinate, it cannot account for determinacy either, because an empirical manifold must already be the product of some synthesis. We cannot, therefore, avoid the conclusion that the manifold is always already determinate. If so, the task becomes one of reconstruction of determinacy, not the construction and then superimposition of determinacy where allegedly there was none in the first place.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
119
Consequently, the intelligibility of our experience, including our sensory experience, must be presupposed. The question is only how important the truths are that the various forms of cognition are able to deliver. Hegel’s answer is that all these forms of knowledge are possible, but not all are equally valuable from a philosophical point of view. His interest lies in the value of the truths expressed in sentences, not in the truth value of sentences. A radically non-conceptual element, whatever its function in human experience, by definition is not part of what is knowable. Nor does its ineffability detract from what is knowable because it could not contribute to it anyway. So it seems that a fairly good case can be made against the dual source model of knowledge, if one is willing to let the problem of reference take care of itself. We perceive (sense) the particular, but perception (knowledge) is of the universal. The purely sensory in the end reduces to the performance aspect of cognition, the fact that I am aware of something. But this performative aspect does not contribute to what it is that is being experienced. To turn next to the methodological aspect, what has emerged through the experience of Sense-Certainty is the opposition between particular and universal and the assumption that the sensible object is the essential truth-validating element in knowledge. This opinion will in fact be re-enforced through consciousness’ experience in Perception before it is replaced by the realization, at the end of Perception, that reality is best understood as a self-differentiating process which exhibits a ground-grounded relationship within itself. This result will serve as the basis for the transformation of the ground as object into the ground as self or subjectivity. Since self-referentiality is characteristic of life generally as that which renews itself by turning what is other into a part of itself, life as the most immediate embodiment of self-referentiality is the phenomenon with which the chapter on Self-Consciousness begins. Perception starts with a realistic position which assumes that the object is immediately accessible to consciousness as a unified whole and that its unity is unproblematic. As it turns out, this belief is mistaken. A straightforward realistic interpretation of the object founders on its contradictory nature. It is simultaneously one and many things such that its oneness and its multiplicity need to be mediated with one another. Consciousness again takes this result at its face value and concludes that since its realist interpretation of objects of sense has come to grief it should now try a non-realist, constructionist reading of the object. This second cycle of consciousness’ experience in Perception can be read as Hegel’s implicit critique and rejection of empiricism insofar as the latter attempts to construct the object of sense out of sensory data. A reference to Plato’s Theaetetus is likewise possible.52
52 In one of the analyses of the Theaetetus the sensible thing is indeed resolved into its sensory data which are then unified by the soul (see Theaet. 184D). There is an interesting parallel here between the Theaetetus and the Phenomenology’s Perception in that the soul as unifier is introduced after the sensible object has for all intents and purposes been “dissolved” in a Heraclitean flux (cf. Theaet. 182C – 183C), just as at the end of the first cycle of the experience in Perception consciousness learns that “the truth of perception is its dissolution” (PS § 118/3, 98), i.e. the dissolution of the realist conception of the object.
120
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
Hegel’s analysis here has also been read as a comment on a transcendental approach which imposes objectivity structures on a manifold of sense.53 However that may be, the solution to the failure of the constructionist approach to come up with a coherent model of what kind of thing a thing is Hegel, in the third cycle of the experience of perceptual consciousness, interestingly proposes a form of essentialism which might be called atomic essentialism and which one could identify with certain aspects of Aristotle’s theory of substance in Metaphysics Zeta and Eta. At the thematic level, the three positions indicated just now, viz. perceptual realism, empiricism or constructionism, and atomic essentialism, follow the usual three-stage dialectic of immediacy, opposition or contradiction, and resolution. The object has now revealed itself as a mediated but simple universal (cf. PS § 112/3, 94), or as a more determinate This of many Thises, or Here of many Heres, in short, as a thing with many properties (ibid.). Compared to the Thises of Sense-Certainty, the object now displays the dialectic of a polarized structure such that one pole is more “substantial” than the other and vice versa. However, just as the This, which is now conceptualized as a thing, is a universal, so are the many Thises or properties. The thing is therefore at first the togetherness of universals in a dominant universal. Perception perceives the thing as something, i.e. as the instantiation of a type. And similarly it perceives the properties as features of a certain kind (such as kinds of colors and of shapes). The problem to be resolved in Perception is to bring together in one coherent conception the two aspects of the thing, viz. its unity and its determinacy as a particular. At the most basic conceptual level, any particular thing is both one and also many. It is one because it is a singular thing, and it is many because it must have characteristics in virtue of which it differs from other singular things. The dialectic that ensues is already contained in these simple determinations. That the thing is singular is a character it shares with all other particulars. If to be this singular thing were its only characteristic, it could not be conceptually distinct from any other thing. It must therefore be its properties that mark it off as this particular thing. This is a first contradiction, since to be singular already means to be unmistakably this specific thing and no other. Purported meaning and conceptual analysis point in opposite directions. Furthermore, the individuating properties themselves are universals that are shared by other things as well and so cannot account for the singularity of the thing – a second contradiction. Perceptual consciousness will discover these difficulties for itself during its first cycle of experience. The next two cycles, i.e. the constructionist and the essentialist phase, are an attempt to respond to the initial contradictions and to find a conception of thinghood that would combine the singularity and the universality aspects of the thing in a manner free from contradiction. In keeping with the realist orientation of perception and to maintain the sense of the objectivity of the object, the thing should in the end emerge as a particular that while intrinsically determined in and of itself coexists alongside all other intrinsically determined things.
53 For a possible Kantian background to the second cycle in Perception see Hyppolite, 1974, p. 113.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
121
Without going into the detail of the dialectical development, the first cycle of consciousness’ experience can be sketched as follows.54 Perception starts with the putative a priori that the unity of thing and properties is an unproblematic concept. But it soon finds out upon further analysis that the unity aspect by itself does not characterize the thing as a determinate or specific thing. The oneness of the thing is an empty determination without specificity. Nor do the properties belong exclusively to any one particular thing since they are universal and therefore “transcend” the singularity of any given object. Consciousness therefore reinterprets the thing as a “medium” or “community” of properties. It is obvious, however, that the thing, if conceived of as a mere medium or community is not intrinsically unified. Rather, it is a mere aggregate of properties. How the thing can be something intrinsically unified or something substantial and self-standing, so to speak, cannot be understood in this way. Indeed, it could be said that under these circumstances a real conception of thinghood has not yet arisen. (Instead, we might be closer to a Protagorean or Anaxagorean conception of sensible particulars.) The problem, then, consists in incorporating specificity or determinacy into the oneness of the thing, i.e. to make determinacy an intrinsic feature of the particular. Looking more closely now at the properties as that which gives the thing its specificity, consciousness realizes that they are themselves determinate and hence differ from each other. Their difference indicates an opposition between any two given properties – blue is not yellow, and yellow is not round, etc. – and hence an exclusionary relationship between them. As a result, if attention is paid to the specific character of these universals, the continuity of the thing as medium is broken up and its two aspects, i.e. the simple oneness and the diversity, again fall apart. A property, however, that does not intrinsically determine the thing of which it is a property, is not really a property but an isolated characteristic just like the This of Sense-Certainty, a “pure relating of itself to itself” (PS § 117/3, 98). So the unity of the thing continues to be empty while its diversity is scattered into a mere multiplicity of accidents that do not belong to anything in particular. Hegel comments that with this outcome consciousness “has ceased altogether to perceive and has withdrawn into itself” (ibid.). Consciousness must make a fresh attempt to bring together the oneness or singularity of the thing with its diversity or determinacy such as to be able to understand the thing as intrinsically determined by its properties. Because consciousness, during its first learning experience, has been forced to re-think and re-interpret its perception several times it has also drawn attention to itself as the subject that undertook the re-interpretation. This is an important moment, for consciousness has now become aware of itself and of the fact that the object is not a mere “given”, but something to whose givenness it must itself make a contribution so that the object may be perceived by it as this or that thing in the first place. Its experience therefore becomes reflective and self-critical.
54 Hegel
97–98.
summarizes the first cycle of the experience of perceptual consciousness in PS § 117/3,
122
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
Consciousness will now take responsibility for whatever appears to be incoherent in its perception of the object.55 At first, then, the particular’s many features fall into the perceiver, not the object – the thing “is white only to our eyes, also tart to our tongue, also cubical to our touch” (PS § 119/3, 99). The perceiver thus lets his mind be furnished with simple ideas and regards himself as “the universal medium in which such moments are kept apart and exist each on its own” (ibid.). But the thing’s properties must soon be re-ascribed to the object itself, if the latter is to be more than a something we know not what, while the unity of the object’s two aspects of singularity and diversity will now be contributed by consciousness.56 The thing thus becomes a “genuine Also” and its properties assume the character of “stuffs” – they are the reality that remains after the thing with properties has turned into a “collection of ‘matters’” and its oneness now is no more than “an enclosing surface” (cf. PS § 121/3, 101).57 With this, what was initially a self-standing, self-supporting thing (an individual substance) has become an epiphenomenon while its material constituents are now the primary reality. From “substance” in the sense of bearer of properties we have moved to “substance” in the sense of stuff. Hegel summarizes the experience of perceptual consciousness thus far by explaining that the object has now revealed itself to consciousness in a twofold way, viz. as something that is both a one and a diversity not only for consciousness but also in and of itself. That is to say, because even in its constructionist attitude consciousness found it necessary to view both aspects of the thing not only as subjective but also as objective, the concept of the thing as a unity of oneness and diversity is by no means a mere mental construct but has objective reality, so to speak: Our experience, then, is this, that the Thing exhibits itself for the consciousness apprehending it, in a specific manner, but is at the same time reflected out of the way in which it presents itself to consciousness and back into itself; in other words, it contains in its own self an opposite truth (PS § 122/3, 101).
Consciousness has now caught up with the situation described in the Introduction. Not only does the way in which the thing displays itself outwardly exist for consciousness, the in-itself or essence does so, too. The object’s in-itself appears in and through the requirements it imposes on consciousness’ constructionist efforts such that consciousness knows what the in-itself would have to be like.
55 The
second cycle of the experience of perceptual consciousness is detailed at PS §§ 119–121/3, 99–101. 56 Interestingly, Hegel locates the emergence of the Principle of Non-Contradiction at this juncture in the construction of thinghood. The PNC lets us avoid having to say that something is simultaneously F,G, and H “all over” by offering the escape hatch of the “insofar” (cf. PS § 121/3, 100–101). Insofar as x is F it is not G etc., notwithstanding the fact that in the thing all these properties interpenetrate – the grain of salt is not white on one side and tart or soluble on the other or now one thing and then the other, rather in perception it is all these things at once and everywhere. 57 We are all familiar with this way of looking at things as collections of matters. When we pick up a box of margarine in the supermarket, for instance, the nutrition information tells us that we hold in our hands a composite of various “matters” combining x percent of fat, y percent of cholesterol, z percent of carbohydrates etc. From the chemist’s point of view, our piece of margarine is just that.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
123
The anti-realist, constructionist phase concludes on a contradictory note, however. Either the unity marks the in-itself aspect and the diversity falls into consciousness, or the unity falls into consciousness and the diversity into the object. Both seem to be true, but cannot be true with equal right. Consciousness now returns to a position of realism and tries to reconcile both aspects on the side of the object. This construal of the intrinsic determinacy of the thing takes the form of metaphysical or essence realism58 : [t]he object is now for consciousness this whole movement which was previously shared between the object and consciousness (PS § 123/3, 101).
In other words, the elements of oneness and determinacy that had emerged as a form requirement contributed by consciousness must now be united on the side of the thing itself. The candidate for this position is, I suggest, atomic essentialism which distinguishes between an in-itself that determines a thing intrinsically and which is called its essence, and the thing’s relatedness to other things, its being-for-others on account of which the thing is connected with other things.59 A thing’s relatedness to other things makes possible a comparison between itself and other things which reveals both differences and commonalities. However, perceptual consciousness already knows through its experience during the first cycle that the common properties cannot individuate the thing since they are universal and are also found in other things. Accordingly, they cannot constitute the thing’s essential identity or nature and are therefore separated from its intrinsic determination as that which is inessential.60 It must therefore be the in-itself which constitutes the thing’s essence. The essence is here conceived of as negative self-relatedness or an as yet incomplete being-for-self. That is to say, it is self-related in opposition to its other-relatedness. The thing’s self-relatedness is therefore no longer an immediate relation. Rather, the thing’s in-itself is a result of its being “reflected into itself” (ibid.) out of its being-for-another. It is not difficult to see that the thing’s self-relatedness or being-for-self is logically possible only in contrast to its other-relatedness. Hegel’s point is thus that the thing’s essence cannot be viewed as something existing in splendid isolation from its being related to other things. On the contrary, the thing’s inessential being-for-another is a necessary presupposition of its self-relatedness because self-relation here is a negation, not an immediacy. On the basis of these assumptions, atomistic essentialism turns out to be a total
58 Cf. Pinkard, 1996, p. 32. Pinkard does not explicitly suggest any particular metaphysical position
that might be associated with this cycle of consciousness’ experience. 59 It is probably not a coincidence that this terminology is reminiscent of Aristotle’s similar expres-
sions kath’ hauto and kat’ allou. For Aristotle’s atomic essentialism cf. Metaph. VII 13, 1038b 9–11: “. . . primary substance is that kind of substance which is peculiar to an individual, which does not belong to anything else.” 60 In an Aristotelian context the unessential aspect of the thing is similar to both the accidental properties (symbebekota) and the matter which, according to Aristotelian doctrine, is not part of the essence of something (cf. Metaph. VII 10, 1035a 26–32).
124
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
fiasco. For not only is it contradictory to say that that which is inessential is nonetheless a necessary condition, it is also paradoxical to believe that something like the in-itself which exists as the negation of an opposite determination could enjoy complete autarky. To be itself, the thing must negate its relation to other things, but this negation, if true, undermines its self-relatedness. As Hegel puts it: . . . the Thing is demolished by the very determinateness that constitutes its essence and its being-for-self . . . (PS § 126/3, 103).
The claim that to be a thing is to be an independent, intrinsically determined bearer of properties cannot be sustained. The allegedly self-subsistent nature of substances – so strongly advocated by Aristotle – cannot be upheld. The other-relatedness of the particular is the negation of its self-subsistence, and it is really the essential property of the Thing that is its undoing (PS § 125/3, 103).
Hegel’s general point in all this, it seems to me, is that particulars are not the kind of thing that can be self-subsistent or independent. Self-subsistence and independence can be achieved only if the relation to the other is internalized and has thus effectively become a self-relation via an immanent other. From being “an other” of something the other must be transformed into “its other”.61 The relation to an external other which is necessary for the thing’s self-relation makes the thing dependent on that other and thus compromises its isolation from others. The being-for-another, instead of being excluded from the in-itself needs to be included in it, if the beingin-itself is to be a genuine being-for-self. As long as this has not happened, the thing remains “afflicted with an [external] opposition” (PS § 129/3, 104) and “burdened with a being-for-another” (PS § 130/3, 105). A contradiction persists between the thing’s self-relatedness, its self-subsistence, and its dependence on external conditions. The allegedly “substantial” being is a “conditioned being-for-self alongside which appears another being-for-self” (ibid.). This other being-for-self, however, does not merely exist alongside the thing, it is the thing’s own diversity or beingfor-another which is, after all, only the reflection of the fact that a particular is necessarily one among many. Other-relatedness is built into the very concept of the supposedly serenely self-related particular. The phenomenon that expresses this situation is force, and the appropriate form of cognition of consciousness is called the understanding. Hence, “Force and Understanding” is the title of the chapter following Perception. A note on the concept of the understanding. For Hegel, the understanding is the intellectual activity that intelligently observes, makes inventories of, categorizes, analyzes, scientifically explains and tries to form an accurate theory of reality. In Force and Understanding the understanding’s activities are associated with the great scientific discoveries since the Copernican revolution and the philosophical response to them from Galileo through Kant, Fichte and Schelling. The understanding is the great bookkeeper of reality and its scientific investigator. It embodies the 61 See
SL 118/WdL I 105 (something is “das Andere seiner selbst,” “the other in its own self”).
3.3
Perception and Understanding
125
analytic skill of thought. Its guiding principles in the ordering and explanation of data are discrimination, accuracy of distinctions, inductive and deductive reasoning, and that combination of comprehensiveness and simplicity which makes for the elegance of theories. It strives for unity of knowledge while strictly adhering to the principles of non-contradiction and excluded middle. Hegel is known for holding the understanding in relatively low esteem, in contrast to reason which is the unifier of opposites and thus the real synthesizer whereas the understanding brings uniformity rather than unity to diversity. He refers to the philosophies of Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz and the British Empiricists as a metaphysics of the understanding and criticizes Kant for having made the understanding, rather than reason, the primary source of knowledge.62 Indeed, for him the understanding is intelligent consciousness, but as such also affected with the opposition of consciousness. And yet, Hegel does not think badly of the understanding. It is true that he chides Kant for having treated reason as if it were even less capable of knowledge than the understanding. But then he also believed that Kant’s original synthetic unity of self-consciousness represented the genuinely speculative principle of philosophy anticipating his own concept of the Notion, even if described in accordance with the terms of the understanding.63 It is the understanding that resists reason which is really the target of Hegel’s critique. As long as the understanding prepares the ground for the work of reason, it fulfills a valuable, even indispensable role: . . . the thinking of the understanding must unquestionably be conceded its right and merit, which generally consists in the fact that without the understanding there is no fixity or determinacy in the domains either of theory or of practice. First, with regard to cognition, it begins by apprehending given objects in their determinate distinctions. Thus, in the consideration of nature, . . . distinctions are drawn between matters, forces, kinds, etc. and they are marked off, each on its own account, in isolation one from another. . . . Understanding is just as indispensable in the practical sphere . . . Character is an essential factor in conduct, and a man of character is a man of understanding who (for that reason) has definite purposes in mind and pursues them with firm intent. . . . Furthermore, the understanding is an essential moment in culture generally. A cultivated person is not satisfied with what is cloudy and indeterminate; indeed, he grasps subject matters in their fixed determinacy . . . (Enc. § 80A).
The weakness of the understanding consist chiefly in its incapacity to establish an intrinsic connection among its various partial insights. Its modus operandi is the “either/or and not both” (cf. E § 80A). Its primary form of expression is the judgment or proposition, and its idea of truth is that no true proposition should ever contradict another – an idea that is analyzed further in the Logic under the title of “formal identity or identity-of-the-understanding.”64 Left to its own devices, the understanding gets caught between, and is paralyzed by, the Scylla of tautology and the Charybdis 62 See
WW 19, 328–331.
63 The categories of the understanding have, after all, objective reality, whereas the ideas of reason
are merely regulative. Cf. Hegel’s comment in Differenzschrift (IV 6) that Kant’s theory of the understanding in the Transcendental Deduction had been held over the baptismal by reason (and thus was graced with a genuinely speculative spirit), but that afterwards – i.e. in the Dialectic of the Critique – reason was treated as if it was even more obtuse than the understanding. 64 See E § 115 and SL 411–4116/WdL II 26–32.
126
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
of contradiction. However, Hegel also believes that the understanding is in essence a form of reason, reason in its immediacy. Consequently, when the understanding is made to reflect on itself, its true nature should emerge in due course. This is what Force and Understanding will try to show. The analysis of atomic essentialism corresponds to the dialectic of something and its other in the Logic.65 This lets us suspect that the third cycle of Perception marks the transition to what in the Logic is called the genuine infinite.66 However, while in Force and Understanding Hegel does indeed discuss structures that implement infinitude and exhibit being-for-self or self-referentiality, these structures, such as the laws of physics, are at first still merely objective in the realist sense of existing independently of consciousness.67 Methodologically speaking, being-in-itself and being-for-another are at first united on the side of the object, but the object itself is not yet united with consciousness in an immanent subject-object relationship. Unity of being-in-itself and being-for-another on the side of the object as well as the subject is the pattern that underlies the subsequent confrontation of two selfconsciousnesses. The chapter on Force and Understanding is meant to achieve the incorporation of the objective into the subjective and thus to prepare the way for the emergence of the concept of genuine reason. Hence the content-form opposition characteristic of consciousness is still operative in Force and Understanding and is overcome only at its very end. Prior to that conclusion, consciousness does not yet understand its object as its own other. Instead, it sees the structure of infinity emerge on the object side first so that it may eventually recognize its own self-referential nature in its object as if in a mirror, a moment that will have arrived towards the conclusion of Force and Understanding. Talking about the infinite, it should be recalled that infinity for Hegel is not a problematic notion. Genuine infinity for him is nothing but “affirmative” selfrelation, i.e. relation to self via an other whose otherness has been negated or internalized (hence the characterization of this structure as a negation of negation68 ): As the “consummated return into self,” the genuine infinite is The relation of itself to itself, is being – but not indeterminate, abstract being, for it is posited as negating the negation; it is, therefore, also determinate being for it contains negation in general and hence determinateness. It is and is there, present before us. It is only the spurious infinite which is the beyond, because it is only the negation of the finite posited as real . . . (SL 148–149/WdL I 138).
65 For
the detailed analysis of being-in-itself and being-for-another see SL 122–129/WdL I 110– 116. 66 Hegel confirms this at PS § 163/3, 133: “Infinity . . . has been from the start the soul of all that has gone before . . ..” 67 Hence Hegel comments that the object of the understanding “which is now the true object of consciousness is still just an object for it” (PS § 132/3, 107–108), that the object has “become Notion in principle; but consciousness is not yet for-itself the Notion” (ibid.), or that consciousness “converts” its insight “into an objective inner [i.e. an inner being of the object], and distinguishes this reflection of Things from its own reflection into itself. . . . This inner is, therefore, for consciousness an extreme over against it . . .” (PS § 143/3, 116). 68 Cf. SL 137/WdL I 126: “The infinite is the negation of negation, affirmation, being which has restored itself out of limitedness.”
3.3
Perception and Understanding
127
Nor should it be forgotten that such affirmative self-relation and inclusion of the other in the self also transforms the self, broadens and enlarges it in such a way that the initial self in turn becomes a moment within the new inclusive structure. To indicate the main methodological task of Force and Understanding, Hegel’s purpose will be to show that epistemological dualism, including its Kantian version, must be replaced by a thoroughgoing idealism which incorporates the objects and their ground completely into the immanence of thought. Force and Understanding thus goes beyond the otherwise necessary “reflective turn” in philosophy about which we heard earlier in the Introduction to the Science of Logic and which Hegel recapitulated very briefly in the second cycle of Perception. At the end of Force and Understanding, “the true”, which had so far been thought to exist independently of consciousness and to be opposed to it, will then be included in it, albeit “in theory” or “subjectively” only and not yet objectively or in actuality. With this move, however, consciousness is no longer just consciousness.69 Since consciousness is defined by the so-called opposition of consciousness, once the first, immediate form of that opposition is overcome consciousness itself is transformed into a moment of the new, more comprehensive structure called self-consciousness. Insofar as inclusion of the other is a characteristic of reason it is also correct to say that Force and Understanding effectively anticipates the concept of reason, just as the chapter on Self-Consciousness will anticipate the concept of spirit.70 Force and Understanding is as much about the concept of truth and the nature of theorizing as it is about the concept of force and the explanation of the sensible world. Looking at the methodological aspect of Force and Understanding in more detail, it appears that there are three major oppositions of consciousness that the understanding must work through in order to penetrate to the nature of truth. The first is the opposition between the concept or Notion of force and its reality. This opposition is transformed into the unity of Notion and reality of force which Hegel calls the “inner being of Things” (PS § 136/3, 111; § 142/3, 115–116). The second opposition expresses at first a quasi-Platonic distinction between “a vanishing present world” of sensuous reality over against a “supersensible world” which forms a “permanent beyond” (PS § 144/3, 117). This opposition is then further developed into the notorious Kantian distinction of appearance and thing-in-itself, or phenomena and noumena. The realm of noumena is also characterized as a “supersensible world” (PS § 144/3, 117) and a “tranquil kingdom of laws” (PS § 157/3, 127). Finally, the third opposition is in a sense a variation on the second. In it the first supersensible world is transformed into a second, so-called “inverted” world that is now the inverted opposite of the first supersensible world (ibid.). This development is prompted by the attempt to incorporate the phenomenon of polarity in nature and human life into the supersensible realm. It also addresses the Schellingian divide between the principle of indifference and the subject-object duality. Interestingly, 69 In
fact, as we saw above in Section 3.1 consciousness was never merely consciousness. explicitly confirms this. The concept of reason appears first, if only in an “imperfect” form, at PS § 144/3, 117 during the introduction of the so-called supersensible world. In SelfConsciousness, the mutual relation of one self-consciousness to another marks the presence of spirit, if only at first the “Notion”, not yet the actuality, of spirit (cf. PS § 177/3, 144–145).
70 Hegel
128
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
this final opposition within understanding finds its resolution in Fichte’s intellectual intuition which serves as the radicalized version of Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception. We will briefly summarize these oppositions and their resolution in what follows. Thematically, Hegel starts with force. By force we should not understand this or that specific physical force but rather the ground of nature as well as nature itself as it appears. It is perhaps not too far off the mark to see in the concept of force an equivalent of what in Spinoza is called natura naturans and natura naturata. In other words, Hegel’s notion of force here is very broad – we are asked to look at the world as a manifestation of force. The result of Perception was that reality is best understood as a self-differentiating and self-determining process existing independently of consciousness. Accordingly, reality now appears in the form of a “play of forces” that is intrinsically determined by the unchangeable laws of physics. This captures both the “dynamic” interpretation of reality by the modern scientific mind and its objectifying attitude for which the world is essentially a manifestation of objective forces. In a philosophical context such as Descartes’ we meet with the idea that the universe is a mechanical system – particles of matter having been set in motion with a certain initial amount of motion. Whatever happens in the world is an outcome of the impact of infinitely many particles on one another. In Leibniz we witness an understanding of reality as dependent on the intrinsically determined behavior of individual monads that are moved by a force called appetition. Leibniz’ idea of an “inner reality” of things that is non-spatial and non-temporal and of which the visible world is merely a “well-founded phenomenon”, and his belief that the laws of physics have no metaphysical necessity but can be suspended by an act of God71 may serve as paradigmatic illustrations of Hegel’s argument in Force and Understanding, viz. that the world of sensible substances and physical forces is but an ideal moment within a larger “kingdom of laws”. The conceptual structure of force is that of an “unconditioned universal” (PS § 132/3, 107). This means that, unlike in the case of the atomic essence, difference is internal to it, not external. Force is therefore the first object of consciousness that is intrinsically determined.72 It is the paradigmatic phenomenon representing the unity of being-for-self and being for-another that has resulted from Perception.73 Hegel calls the moment that corresponds to the being-for-another of the thing and to the universal medium of many subsistent matters “the expression of Force” (PS § 136/3, 110) and that which corresponds to its being-in-itself or oneness “Force proper” (ibid.). Both are related as mutually dependent on one another, but dependent in such a way that unlike things with properties they no longer exist in opposition to one another but instead form two aspects of one reality. The conceptual framework of 71 Cf.
Leibniz, Discourse of Metaphysics §§ 6, 7. force, Hegel says, “the absolute antithesis [of being-for-self and being-for-another, of independent and dependent being, ground and grounded] is posited as self-identical essence” (PS § 134/3, 108). 73 As a result of the development in Perception, “the unity of ‘being-for-self’ and ‘being-foranother’ is posited” (PS § 134/3, 108). 72 In
3.3
Perception and Understanding
129
an atomism of particulars has been replaced by one of internal relations. Taking our cue from Kant’s table of categories we may say that one aspect of the relationship here discussed is that expressed by the second category of relation, viz. causality, while the other is that of Kant’s third category of relation, i.e. reciprocal action. This is confirmed by Hegel’s discussion of causality and reciprocal action in the Jena Logic which parallels that of force in Force and Understanding,74 even though the discussion of Force at PS §§ 136–142/3, 109–116 never mentions the concepts of cause and effect and only hints at that of reciprocal action when talking about “the interplay” of forces (PS § 139/3, 113).75 Hegel’s basic argument is that the duplication of what is at bottom one reality into two independent phenomena – i.e. cause and effect and two separate interacting forces, respectively – is on one hand necessary in order for force to be “real”. On the other hand, however, this independence is merely an appearance, or, rather, is characteristic of reality as appearance. The argument is designed to show that the “idealization” of sensible reality, i.e. its transformation into a dependent manifestation of the “inner being” of things is an inevitable and logically necessary development as well as an actual experience of consciousness. To begin with, then, force has two aspects, force proper or force as potentiality and force expressing itself. Both aspects are necessary. If force expresses itself, it must do so from an opposite state of being “driven back into itself” (PS § 136/3, 110). Likewise, force must manifest itself in order to be force. A force that could not possibly become actual would not be force, since force is force in virtue of having a manifestation. This is simply the logic of the concept of force and it leads us to posit an “expression” of force distinct from “force proper” – or an effect of a cause. But on the other hand, what is thus posited as an effect is in fact the same force that already exists as the cause. The force expresses itself in its effect, but to say that it causes the effect is merely to say that the same force continues to exist as a manifestation of itself. The effect just is the cause, if by effect we understand, as Hegel does, the force in the
74 The
substance-accident relationship, it might be argued, was taken up in Perception under the title of the Thing and its many properties. In the Jena Logic Hegel says of force: „Über den soeben erläuterten Kausalzusammenhang erhebt sich der Begriff der Kraft; die Kraft vereinigt in sich die beiden wesentlichen Seiten des Verhältnisses, die Identität und das Getrenntsein“ (JL 50). The basic argument in the Jena Logic is also the same as that in the Phenomenology, viz. that the distinction between cause and effect or between two mutually reacting substances is only a formal one since the content is the same on both sides. See, for instance, JL 43: “Man sieht, daß die Kraft eigentlich das ganze Kausalitätsverhältnis in sich ausdrückt oder die Ursache, wie sie mit der Wirkung eins und in Wahrheit wirkliche Substanz, aber auch das Kausalitätsverhältnis aufgehoben ist” (my emphasis). Hegel even argues that the identity of cause and effect (which he continues to defend in SL and E) is the real reason why Hume was justified to deny any necessity to the cause-effect relationship – not, as Hume thought, because it could not be observed, but because the two relata are separable only in appearance (cf. JL 48). – For the question to what extent the Jena Logic serves as the foil for the argument of the entire Phenomenology see J. Heinrichs’ still indispensable study Die Logik der, Phänomenologie des Geistes’ (Heinrichs, 1974). 75 The Miller translation interprets the text by adding “reciprocal” and “mutually” (end of PS § 138 and beginning of § 139/3, 113), expressions that have no direct counterpart in Hegel’s text.
130
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
process of expressing itself.76 If we take the single event of a billiard ball in motion, the movement of the ball is the expression of the force that moves it and hence is its effect. But while the ball keeps moving the force continues to be a cause and therefore remains “force proper” or force “driven back into itself” (PS § 136/3, 110) even while expressing itself. In other words, we distinguish force as cause from force as expression while in fact the two are indeed the same force. Hegel can therefore claim that in expressing itself force is nonetheless “remaining within itself” (ibid.), i.e. in its expression it remains force proper. This is just another way of saying that the same force is both cause and effect. The distinction between the two aspects of force is merely conceptual while the content or reality of force is identically the same. I take this to be Hegel’s conceptualization of the Newtonian concept of inertia. He concludes therefore that “the difference exists only in thought” (PS §136/3, 110). In expressing itself force has only made itself into an effect of itself, i.e. it has caused itself to appear. This effect, however, is nothing but the actuality of force, i.e. the being effective of force proper.77 The distinction between force proper and expression of force is only a formal one. This should not mislead us into thinking, however, that the distinction is only nominal or verbal. If force could not be separated into cause and effect, neither would there be a distinction between a ground and a grounded. And without the latter, force would serve no explanatory purpose. It would merely be a descriptive concept. Consequently, the distinction must be established in such a way that force proper and the expression of force differ not only in thought but also in existence. Hegel takes this to mean that the concept (or “Notion”) of force itself must become real. So if we really want to be able to distinguish cause and effect from one another we need to redefine our concept of force in such a way that the aspect of being a cause and that of being an effect can be separated in reality. However, just because the two have already been seen to be aspects of one force this “realization” of the concept of force requires that we duplicate force into two forces. The positing of two forces allows us to maintain the cause-effect distinction as a real distinction, or a distinction in content, not in form only. Hegel therefore introduces a distinction between a soliciting and a solicited force (PS § 137/3, 111–112). The soliciting or active force solicits another, passive force to manifest itself. This is actually what happens in what is normally considered a simple cause-effect connection where we think of a force being transmitted from one body to the next through contact. In truth, however, any such cause-effect relation is a case of reciprocal action in which the effect also reacts to the cause (the billiard ball that is hit makes the ball hitting it come to a stop, for instance, and the effect is thus also the actualization of a latent 76 In
order to avoid a misunderstanding we should keep at bay the Humean analysis of two events following one another. To make sense of what Hegel means here we should be thinking of one event only, where the event is itself the manifestation of force. The billiard ball rolling is already an “expression” of force, quite independently of its impinging on another ball. The conventional cause-effect sequence is discussed in what immediately follows under the title of a duplication of forces. 77 Cf. also E §§ 153–154.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
131
force in the second ball). Effects are responses by a latent force in the object affected by the cause and the cause therefore has “repercussions”. Effects are also causes, not only in the sense of propagating other effects linearly but also in the reciprocal sense of affecting their causes due to being prompted to manifest their latent forces by a cause acting on them. The usual cause-effect relationship in which a force is transmitted from one body to the next reveals itself as an abstraction of a more complicated scenario of reciprocal action. In this scenario, causes are affected by their effects and effects are causes. Although the two are distinct, they also exchange their determinations. Moreover, the force itself is again only one force – each action calls forth a counteraction in kind. A push meets with resistance, i.e. with a push in the opposite direction, a pull results in a pull in the opposite direction, a centrifugal force is opposed to a centripetal force. Indeed, without such counteraction there would not be a duplication of force but the previous indistinguishableness of cause and effect. In cause and effect, inertia collides with itself. Looked at superficially, two bodies related by reciprocal action are merely two things unaffected in their identity by what is happening between them – the two billiard balls are essentially the same balls before and after the impact. But Hegel is not concerned here with these two things but with the forces that explain their behavior. And at that level, a truly remarkable phenomenon reveals itself. First, obviously there would not be an impact or the deployment of force without resistance, i.e. without some counteraction. Hence the actualization of force necessitates the “duplication into two Forces” (PS § 141/3, 114). But secondly, these two forces do not alternate in their activity. That is to say, when force manifests itself in action and reaction it is not the case that one force is first active and then becomes passive while the other force is first passive and is then activated. Rather, the activity of both forces occurs simultaneously – or not at all. Without a centripetal pull there could not be a centrifugal pull. And yet the two are opposites. It is therefore correct to say that the actuality of force is a paradox. An action or state such as the deployment of force is realized and held together by two opposites. And looked at more closely it is not just a matter of their existing simultaneously either. If one of the opposites were suspended or eliminated, the phenomenon itself would disappear. This can only mean that the reality of the phenomenon exists by virtue of the opposites that create it through their opposition. The opposites in fact create and maintain the unity of the phenomenon. This is no doubt what Heraclitus tried to convey to “those who prove to be uncomprehending both before they have heard it and when once they have heard it” (KRS # 194, p. 187), viz. that They do not apprehend how being at variance it agrees with itself [lit. how being brought apart it is brought together with itself]: there is a back-stretched connexion, as in the bow and the lyre (KRS # 209, p. 192).
Just as Heraclitus attributes this paradoxical fact to the operation of logos, so Hegel sees in the analysis of the actuality of force the proof that the concept or Notion of force represents the true reality of force. Against this reality, the manifestation of force in the form of a duplication of two forces is an appearance only. For the conceptualization of this appearance leaves no other choice than to say that
132
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
the two opposing forces are mere “moments” of force itself. The actuality of force is characterized by the fact that two opposites form a unity in which they are both distinct and identical. They are distinct in appearance, but identical in kind, and both this identity and distinctness are reflected in the concept of actual force. Behind the appearance of two independent forces, actual force thus exhibits the structure of the Notion as a unity of opposites both of which are constitutive of the identity of the reality called force. The true reality of force consists in its concept. In other words, thinking reveals the true nature of force. Its concept, not its appearance, is what force really is: . . . the truth of Force remains only the thought of it; the moments of its actuality, their substances and their movement, collapse unresistingly into an undifferentiated unity, a unity which is . . . its Notion qua Notion (PS § 141/3, 115).
Hegel continues that the realization of force is thus “at the same time the loss of reality” (ibid.). That is to say, its conceptualization is at the same time the loss of the apparent substantiality and independence of the sensible phenomenon that ordinary consciousness takes as a given and that misleads us, for instance, into treating the behavior of the approaching billiard ball and the impacted ball as something occurring between two separate substances or independent things (such that Hume famously concluded that all events seem to be entirely separate and unconnected). The duplication of force is a matter of its appearance which, while required by the concept of force, is also superseded by it. Taking force as a paradigm of the ground of the sensible world generally we can say that this sensible world has now been made dependent on the “inner being” of appearances which is none other than “the Notion of Force qua Notion” (PS § 142/3, 115–116). It is interesting to note that Hegel singles out just this concept, i.e. the concept of force, as the dominant category of the theoretical world-view of early modernity. With this step Hegel’s argument has made a significant advance. The inner being of appearances has now become the truth of the sensible world, not in the sense of being separate from, but in that of being intrinsic to it. The sensible world is seen as dependent upon this inner being and is thus superseded in its immediacy – the idea that the world of appearances represents an independent, self-sustaining reality has been put to rest. This marks the transition to what may loosely be called the metaphysical standpoint. It has now been understood that thought, not perception, grasps the true nature of phenomena and that that nature is “noumenal”. In principle, from now on thought itself is the “inner being of things”.78 At the same time, however, the dualism of this new “supersensible world” (PS § 144/3, 117) and the world of appearances has not been left behind. For one thing, although consciousness knows the inner being of things to be the true reality, it does not identify with this inner being. In typical fashion, it “converts” the inner being again into an “objective inner,” a “permanent beyond” (PS §§ 143–4/3, 116–117). While this mundus intelligibilis is purely noumenal, i.e. an object of thought and therefore “the 78 Frank-Peter
Hansen expresses this very well: „Der Begriff der Sache ist der Begriff der Sache“ – the concept of the matter is the concept of the matter: see Hansen, 1994, p. 53.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
133
first,” if “imperfect, appearance of Reason” (§ 144/3, 117), it is also “an extreme” over against consciousness, i.e. separated from it by the immediately observed sensuous world. As understanding, consciousness does not yet recognize itself in this reason – reason is something above and beyond it, it is divine like a Cartesian or Spinozistic infinite substance, a Leibnizean monad of monads, or an impersonal Law. Because in the order of discovery consciousness has inferred the true nature of things from and on the basis of the sensible world, this sensible world continues to be for it the stepping stone or “hypothesis” to reach the supersensible world: [The] true essence of Things has now the character of not being immediately for consciousness; on the contrary, consciousness has a mediated relation to the inner being and, as the Understanding, looks through this mediating play of Forces into the true background of Things (PS § 143/3, 116).
What, then, does consciousness see behind the veil of appearances? From a philosophical point of view, the inner being may lack any determinacy whatsoever. This happens, if the inner being is understood as the mere “nothingness of appearance” (PS § 146/3, 117). In that case, the ground of appearances is effectively cut off from the appearances themselves. Appearances do not manifest the inner being of things which therefore disguises itself as an unknowable thing-in-itself. Hegel dismisses this Kantian scenario as a red herring: Certainly, we have no knowledge of this inner world as it is here in its immediacy; but not because Reason is too short-sighted or is limited . . ., but because of the simple nature of the matter in hand, that is to say, because in the void nothing is known (PS § 146/3, 117).79
Instead, he sees in the awakening of the scientific consciousness of modernity the true standard bearer of the metaphysical spirit. Modern science will fill the supersensible void with the “law of Force” which is “the stable image of unstable appearance” (PS § 149/3, 120). The “absolute flux of appearance” (ibid.) will be reduced to the identity of equations in which the values of variables change while the equation remains imperturbably and steadily selfsame. Soon, however, the dualism of the sensible world and the “realm of laws” (PS § 150/3, 120) develops into a new contradiction. The laws of nature turn out to be idealizations of the actual behavior of phenomena and thus lack accuracy. There are numerous other forces operative in the observed sensible world whose influence is ignored in the formulation of a law, so-called marginal conditions, ideal or standard assumptions, etc. The understanding must try to accommodate these impure circumstances by adding more and more specific laws. This triggers the opposite motivation to unify all laws and to discover 79 He also formulates the critique that later reappears in the Introduction to the Science of Logic, viz.
that if the supersensible realm is posited as necessary and affirmed to be unknowable nonetheless, we are left with the world of appearances as our object of knowledge, a world which, however, as something explicitly made dependent on the supersensible world is simultaneously known not to contain the truth. In other words, we then “perceive something as true which we know is not true” (PS § 146/3, 118). At SL 46/WdL I 27 Hegel calls this view “absurd” [ungereimt]. That the concept of the thing-in-itself is essentially a logical construct and a contradiction, viz. a ground whose grounding function is both affirmed and denied (and thus becomes a dysfunctional concept), is also Hegel’s view in the Logic (see, e.g., SL 489–490/WdL II 111–112; E § 124).
134
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
“the theory of everything”, for instance in the form of one fundamental force. The theory supposedly would enable us to explain all phenomena by recourse to a single law. But it is clear that the explanatory value of such a theory would be very limited. In its simplicity, such a theory would not be much more than a tautology. The actual behavior of appearances could not be explained in this way, specific explanations would again belong to the particular laws. For instance, The unification of all laws in universal attraction expresses no other content than just the mere Notion of law itself . . . Universal attraction merely asserts that everything has a constant difference in relation to other things. The Understanding imagines that in this unification it has found a universal law which expresses universal reality as such; but in fact it has only found the Notion of law itself, although in such a way that what it is saying is that all reality is in its own self, conformable to law (PS § 150/3, 121–122).80
There opens up, then, another opposition between “the inner world as a simple unity” (PS § 151/3, 122) and the specific laws “in which the differences are expressed as independent moments” (PS § 152/3, 122). The simple unity of the inner world cannot, however, comfortably be maintained, once science discovers seemingly paradoxical phenomena that suggest an irreducible dualism within reality itself. Thus magnetism and electricity exhibit a polar nature for which no unified origin seems imaginable. Typically, a plus pole cannot exist independently of a minus pole and vice versa.81 While this sounds like a repetition of the earlier unity of opposites we saw in the case of force, it is not. The two opposites are not only, Hegel wants to argue, opposites vis-à-vis each other but opposites of themselves, or each is not only the opposite of an other but also its own opposite. The earlier opposition has been sharpened to become an “antithesis within the antithesis itself” (PS § 160/3, 130). To illustrate, if it is really the case that a magnetic pole is radically inseparable from its opposite, then the idea that there could be a pole that is only positive or only negative must be rejected even though on the surface, i.e. on the basis of mere observation, any given pole is either the one or the other. Instead, following this line of reasoning we seem compelled to accept the idea that the positive pole is in itself also the negative pole and vice versa. In other words, the two must coexist not just as two different aspects of a third element that keeps them together, but each must literally be both itself and its opposite. Each opposite thus carries an “inner difference” within itself (PS § 157/3, 128; § 161/3, 131). Moreover, while each opposite has its opposite within its own self, each is also opposed to the other opposite that likewise carries its opposite within itself. Each thus possesses both an internal and an external opposite, an antithesis within the antithetical relata. Each “repels” its internal opposite in the sense that in its manifestation it can be only negative or positive but not both, and it “attracts” its external opposite. But it also 80 It
should be noted, however, that while Hegel’s tautology objection may be correct, the point is not the formula alone but its quantifiability that allows the scientist to derive non-tautological measurements and predictions. 81 It was reported not too long ago that scientists have apparently managed artificially to isolate one magnetic pole. I am not competent to judge whether this invalidates the traditional belief in the inseparability of the polar opposites or whether the isolated pole can still be called a magnetic pole.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
135
attracts its internal opposite simply because it is its own opposite, and it repels its external homologue. From this complex opposition there results the unified reality of a magnet. For the understanding, this situation is a conceptual conundrum, but for Hegel it expresses the structure of infinity or of the Notion (cf. PS § 160/3, 131). What we have here is a negation of the negative relation of two opposites resulting in a stable unity. Both opposites carry the same inner difference of a positive and a negative aspect and are in this respect identical, and both relate to each other as opposites that attract one another. The understanding thus learns, Hegel explains, that . . . it is a law of appearance itself, that differences arise which are no differences, or that what is selfsame repels itself from itself; and similarly, that the differences are only such as are in reality no differences and which cancel themselves; in other words, what is not selfsame is self-attractive” (PS § 156/3, 126–127).
It is important to understand that with this experience difference or opposition has now penetrated into the thing itself, i.e. into the inner being or inner world insofar as the latter is the true ground of appearances (cf. PS § 155/3, 126).82 The inner being of things is no longer a “tranquil kingdom of laws” (PS § 157/3, 127), but affected by “the principle of change and alteration” (PS § 157/3, 128). What is more, a contradiction has entered into the realm of laws for which there does not seem to be an immediate solution. If the identity of something consists in the fact that (a) it is simultaneously positive and negative and (b) cannot exist without uniting with an opposite that is equally both positive and negative, the understanding, which is committed to the principles of tautological identity and external difference, finds itself severely challenged. Hegel discusses three solutions to this situation. To the first he gives the name of the “inverted world” (PS §§ 157–9/3, 127–130). The second represents his own dialectical “sublation” of the contradiction (PS §§ 160–2/3, 130–133). The third proposal is not clearly identified, but the formulation of the text suggests very strongly that it is Schelling’s philosophy of indifference that Hegel has in mind (PS § 162/3, 132–134).83 Schelling’s position is criticized and unceremoniously dismissed as the result of “fretting” over a pseudo-problem. Force and Understanding ends with the argument that the position reached with Hegel’s proposed solution corresponds to the Fichtean version of Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception, i.e. the idea that the original unity of self-consciousness is an absolute I that reveals itself to itself as the ground of all reality (PS §§ 164–5/3, 134–136). At the end of Force and Understanding, then, the experience of consciousness has caught up 82 The
penetration of difference into the inner being of things occurs indirectly at first with the tautological process of explanation discussed earlier in the text, in which a difference between theory and reality is stated which “is not [yet] a difference belonging to the thing itself” (PS § 154/3, 125). Indirectly, because the self-differentiation is supposed to happen only “theoretically”, i.e. in the understanding, and does not yet affect things themselves (cf. PS § 155/3, 126). I take the discussion of explanation at PS § 155 to contain an implicit reference to Kant’s analysis of the Paralogisms and the Antinomies which so to speak explains away any possible contradiction so that from the point of view of the understanding everything is in good logical order in the noumenal realm. 83 See also Falke, 1996, pp. 125–130.
136
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
with the beginning of the Copernican revolution in philosophy, the position Hegel elsewhere calls subjective idealism.84 The inverted world is notorious among Hegel scholars for its obscurity.85 It is called a “second supersensible world” (PS § 157/3, 128) and is supposed to be the inversion not of the world of appearances but of the first supersensible world (ibid.). I suggest that the enigma of the inverted world may be resolved in the light of our earlier discussion of the dualistic nature of phenomena. But first let us look again at the genesis of the inverted world. It arises through the incorporation of duality or opposition into the first supersensible world. In other words, the inverted world is on one hand the inversion of the first supersensible world but on the other it contains latter within itself.86 As such it is at the same time the mirror image of the world of appearance that exhibits the same dualism and contradiction, albeit in an unexplained, immediate fashion. Just like the first supersensible world, however, the inverted world is supposed to be the explanatory ground of the sensible world, and because it mirrors the latter it is both its duplicate and its ground, i.e. it has completely absorbed the sensible world into itself while at the same time supplying its foundation. With this step, then, we have reached Fichte’s position of the theoretical immanence of finite self and world, I and not-I, within an absolute self that “posits” the duality of subject and object within itself. Since the inversion now exists within the immanence of the second supersensible world, everything that is like itself in the first supersensible world is in truth unlike itself in the second and everything that is unlike itself in the first is in truth like itself in the second: Expressed in determinate moments, this means that what in the law of the first [supersensible] world is sweet, in this inverted in-itself is sour, what in the former is black is, in the other, white. What in the law of the first is the north pole of the magnet is, in its other, supersensible in-itself [. . .], the south pole (PS § 158/3, 128).87
84 If
correct this interpretation strongly suggests that a possible proto-version of the Phenomenology would not have ended with Force and Understanding but with the Reason chapter at the earliest. 85 Gadamer’s account seems least persuasive: see Gadamer, 1976, pp. 35–53. For a more recent treatment and comments on other interpretations see Harris, 1997, pp. I 294–300 and footnotes 38–43. 86 Cf. PS § 160/3, 131: “. . . the supersensible world, which is the inverted world, has at the same time overarched the other [sc. supersensible] world and has it within it . . ..” Hegel rejects the view that the opposition between the first supersensible world and the inverted world is only external as if the first supersensible world were now a world of appearance and the inverted world contained the true “in-itself” of the first supersensible world: “Looked at superficially, this inverted world is the opposite of the first [sc. supersensible world] in the sense that it has the latter outside of it and repels that world from itself as an inverted actual world: that the one is appearance, but the other the in-itself . . .” (PS § 159/3, 129). If this were the case, duality and contradiction would not yet have entered into the supersensible world. We would just have produced an inverted version of the sensible world, i.e. a caricature (see below). 87 As an interpretive addendum Miller’s translation puts “viz. in the earth” in the bracketed space above. This may be misleading since the reference is not to the sensible but the first supersensible world.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
137
If we now add that both supersensible worlds are not externally opposed but opposed within the immanence of one supersensible world we can see the problem arising for the understanding. Since the first supersensible world was already the in-itself of the sensible world the very essence of things has now become contradictory. Things are now endowed with two essential determinations that are polar opposites of one another. It is no use, Hegel argues, to distribute the “repelled differences” again and have them “shared afresh between two substances such as would support them and lend them a separate existence” (PS § 159/3, 129), for this would only mean a return to the previous opposition between the sensible and the (first) supersensible world, only now with an inverted first supersensible world. In that case, what would be a punishment in this world would actually be a blessing in the supersensible world, what would be black in this world would actually be white in the other and vice versa.88 But clearly, a just punishment in this world would need to be a just punishment also in the other world. Otherwise, the supersensible world would become the caricature of the sensible world and we would be witnessing the satire of two comically inverted worlds. This, however, would no longer be the “true” inverted world that resulted from the introduction of an antithesis into the first supersensible world. The true inversion, Hegel suggests, consists in the fact that what is right in this world is the right of a wrong in both worlds, and what is wrong in that world is the wrong of a right also in this world. A crime, for instance, is the negation of itself across all possible worlds. It is not a crime in one world and an act of virtue in an other. It carries its negation within itself as something that ought not to be and that is positively negated by its appropriate punishment. In Hegel’s words, . . . the crime, as regards its content, has its reflection-into-self, or its inversion, in the actual punishment; this is the reconciliation of the law with the actuality opposed to it in the crime. [And likewise], the actual punishment has its inverted actuality present in it in such a way that the punishment is an actualization of the law, whereby the activity exercised by the law as punishment suspends itself, and, from being active, the law becomes again quiescent and is vindicated, and the conflict of individuality with it, and of it with individuality, is extinguished (ibid.).
Wrongdoing, as Socrates pointed out, is self-subverting. It does not stand in any world. By causing trouble it also “asks for trouble” in the form of a just punishment and thus it ideally undoes again what it set out to do, i.e. it negates itself. Moreover, just punishment is another subversion of the conflict between the crime and the law and the re-establishment of the just order. In this way, punishment is the negation of 88 The
play by Ludwig Tieck entitled Die verkehrte Welt (i.e., “The Inverted World”) published in 1800, which is often cited as the model for Hegel’s discussion, obviously represents an inversion of the sensible world, not of the supersensible world, and is thus merely yet another version of the caricature of Hegel’s inverted supersensible world (the play begins with a “symphony”, the prologue is spoken by the Epilogue, the actors want to be spectators, the spectators want to rewrite the play etc. etc.). The correct interpretation and resolution of the conflict within the supersensible world is laid out at PS §§ 160–2/3, 130–133. PS § 162/3, 132–133 also contains a reference to Schelling’s principle of indifference and rejects it, not because it represents a caricature à la Tieck, but because it offers a mistaken solution to the conflict within the inverted supersensible world (see below).
138
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
the opposition between the criminal deed and the law brought about by the criminal deed itself. Generally speaking, all finite things are self-subverting to the extent that they contradict their own essence, and they are self-preserving to the extent that they are in harmony with it. Hegel’s solution to the supposed dualism of the two essential but opposed characteristics within a single per se determination consists in pointing out that the inverted world implicitly contains its own inversion within itself. That is to say, “it is for itself the inverted world, i.e. the inversion of itself” (PS § 160/3, 131). The impasse for the understanding arises from the fact that it does not recognize this inversion as internal to the inverted world. Instead, driven by the principle of non-contradiction, it takes refuge in “the sensuous idea of fixing the differences in a different sustaining element” (ibid.). In other words, the understanding distributes the two opposed essences among two worlds, a first and a second supersensible world, so that the inverted world is inverted not for itself but only from the point of view of the first supersensible world (and thus remains external to it). If, however, Hegel can show that the inversion that exists for the understanding between the two opposed supersensible worlds actually already exists in the inverted world itself, the external opposition between the two supersensible worlds becomes redundant and falls away. The inverted world would then reveals itself as the true supersensible world, and, moreover, as one that contains the superseded sensible world within itself. It would then remain to be seen what happens to the contradiction within the one supersensible inverted world. In approaching this solution, the first thing to acknowledge is that an opposite that has an inner difference (like the positive pole of a magnet “hiding” a negative pole within itself) is not only the opposite of another opposite (viz. the negative pole of the magnet) but is also the opposite of itself. In a rare moment of generosity towards the struggling reader Hegel explains the logic of this otherness of the same by explicitly correcting a possible misunderstanding, something he almost never does: . . . in the difference which is an inner difference, the opposite is not merely one of two – if it were, it would simply be, without being an opposite – but it is the opposite of an opposite, or the other is itself immediately present in it. [Now the potential misunderstanding:] Certainly, I put the ‘opposite’ here, and the ‘other’ of which it is the opposite, there; the ‘opposite’, then, is on one side, is in and for itself without the other. [Correction of the potential misunderstanding:] But just because I have the ‘opposite’ here in and for itself, it is the opposite of itself, or it has, in fact, the ‘other’ immediately present in it (PS § 160/3, 130–131).
Something that is essentially opposed to an other – or is defined as an opposite, like the pole of a magnet – must for that reason contain oppositeness or the nature of being an opposite – within itself, or else it would just be something essentially unaffected by its opposition and merely accidentally opposed to something else; i.e., it would thus “simply be, without being an opposite [sc. in its very nature].” But if so, it must combine its being this thing with its being opposed to another thing. Surely, it could not just be oppositeness without being anything else since then there would not be two different opposites and without them no inversion. Consequently,
3.3
Perception and Understanding
139
what is essentially the opposite of an other must be both itself as well as its own opposite. In other words, once we realize that the external opposite is an essential and not just an accidental opposite, we have included it in the first opposite (and vice versa). With this, the externality of the relationship between the two opposites falls away, and the external opposite becomes an internal opposite. However, the difference between the two opposites does not vanish for that matter. It is just as essential because the phenomenon only exists by virtue of this difference. Without it we would be relapsing into atomic essentialism. As a result, Hegel can say that the relationship between the two opposites is such that . . . their being is . . . to posit themselves as not-being and to suspend themselves in the unity. The two distinguished moments both subsist; they are implicit and are opposites in themselves, i.e. each is the opposite of itself; each has its ‘other’ within it and they are only one unity (PS § 161/3, 131–132).
Moments that posit each other as different within a unity and mutually override their difference at the same time constitute for Hegel the nature of the Concept or Notion. The latter represents what Hegel understands by genuine reality, viz. ideality that is at the same time a reality and reality that is likewise ideality. Like the poles of the magnet, the sensible reality carries its opposite, ideality, within itself as a negation, but it is equally true that this inner ideality could not even exist without inhering in its opposite whose independence and separateness it also negates. The embodied soul goes together with an ensouled body. Neither the one nor the other can be absent without destroying the reality of the phenomenon. Outside their unity, both of them are abstractions and are no longer what they are within it. Looking in greater detail at the example of the crime and its punishment again we may be able better to understand the detail of the dialectic at work here. A crime is a wrong against a right, a violation of the proper order. On Hegel’s analysis, the crime does not have its opposite, the right, outside it. If we were to look at things in that light, punishment of the crime would not be provoked by the crime itself but by external circumstances. Punishment would then be accidental, i.e. arbitrary. But the punishment is intrinsic to the crime itself and therefore necessary and not arbitrary. In other words, the necessity of its negation is required by the crime itself as something that cannot stand. While the crime is being planned and committed it already harbors the opposite within itself which it tries to repel and evade. When the punishment comes, it comes as the inversion of the crime, not as its annihilation, since the deed that has been done cannot be undone.89 The inversion consists in negating the pretense of the crime to have created not only a new physical, material, emotional or moral fact but a new reality. To be sure, a fact was created by the crime, and the world was irrevocably changed. But because from its inception in the intention the crime already carries its negation within itself, these facts, real as they are, do not have the value of a true or genuine reality. Their factual reality, pernicious and painful as it may
89 Cf.
PR § 97: “The violation of the right qua right that has occurred exists, to be sure, positively, as an external fact which, however, is null and void in itself.”
140
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
be, is ideally negated from the start. The crime is essentially its own opposite. Its existence is denied actuality from the start. But the criminal deed is so far negated only ideally, not in reality. The crime ought not to have occurred, but it has. The ideality of this “ought” needs to be transformed into an “is”. The punishment brings about this transformation. But not in an immediate manner. For quite clearly, the punishment can never undo the crime. Even where the damage is only material and full restitution is made in terms of monetary value, for instance, the immaterial value of the object for the owner cannot thus be matched because the original is either lost or damaged and its attachment value is irreplaceable. Hence, when the ideality of the “ought” is transformed into an “is”, the resulting “is” is not just another state of affairs in the world. While the punishment certainly is a physical event just like the crime, its significance cannot be captured by its material effect. In its physical aspect, it is like the kind of counterforce we discussed earlier in connection with the duplication of force into two forces – except that it comes too late to prevent the crime. This is already an indication that its significance is not exhausted by its outer manifestation. For one thing, the necessity of the punishment is not an external, mechanical necessity but an inevitability or fate. Hegel calls it a law that has become intrinsically necessary [das Gesetz zur Notwendigkeit an ihm selbst vollendet]90 and views it as the culmination of the general idea of lawfulness (cf. PS § 161/3, 131). And for another, the punishment does not “pay back in kind”.91 It does not literally do to the criminal what the criminal did to others, it only corrects the crime. It subverts the crime’s claim to have posited a new order of legitimacy.92 It may sound surprising that a crime can even claim to institute a new legitimacy. But this is in fact its inner conviction.93 In his mind, the criminal is convinced that his crime rights a wrong. Here we can grasp with our hands the inversion that the crime represents in and of itself and that constitutes its very definition. In the mind of the criminal, the deed he contemplates or has done is the righting of an injustice that was supposedly done to him. This is obviously the first inversion (the original sin, so to speak) and at the same time a negation of the proper order (sc., of the first supersensible world). In terms of Hegel’s argument, it is this inversion that represents the introduction of 90 Miller
translates “law completes itself into an immanent necessity” (PS § 161). if it does it would be revenge, not punishment. Revenge is the futile attempt to undo a crime. See Hegel’s discussion of revenge and punishment at PR §§ 97–103. Hegel had worked out his understanding of the self-subversive nature of the crime already during his time as headmaster in Nürnberg: see Nürnberger Schriften, WW 4 §§ 19–21. 92 See E § 500: In the criminal deed “the agent . . . sets up a law – a law, however, which is nominal and recognized by him only – a universal which holds good for him, and under which he has at the same time subsumed itself by his action.” Allen Speight’s “corrigibilist” interpretation of agency in Hegel as developed in Speight 2001 nicely captures this phenomenon of an inverted inversion: the pretence to legitimacy of the criminal deed is subverted through “correctional” action, while the deed itself cannot be physically undone. Its inner meaning changes while its outer existence remains a fact. 93 Evil, this suggest, is not contingent or accidental for Hegel, it is essential. It is the eternally negated but necessary and essential opposite of the good and the right. 91 Or
3.3
Perception and Understanding
141
difference and contradiction into the first supersensible world (the tranquil reign of the law) and thus the appearance of an inverted world within the supersensible world. What is needed to right this wrong, to overcome the violation of justice, is an inversion of this first inversion.94 This is brought about by the condemnation of the crime and the vindication of justice through the punishment. The condemnation re-establishes or re-affirms the proper order, i.e. the reign of the law. But it does so not by annihilating the criminal deed nor by retaliating in kind. Instead, it invalidates the crime by negating its pretence of legitimacy. The inversion of the inversion represents the re-affirmation of the ideality of the proper order as the true reality. The criminal deed and its consequences are not undone as a result, nor is the punishment merely an act of retaliation. Instead, through the act of re-affirming the validity of the law, the condemnation and the punishment of the crime de-legitimize the crime in actuality. They thereby give reality to the ideal validity of the law (i.e., the ideal ought). It is the act of de-legitimizing the violation of the proper order that constitutes the “sublation” or “supersession” of a factual reality which nonetheless cannot be physically undone. This inversion of the inversion is for Hegel the nature of idealism broadly conceived. The evil deed that was done is invalidated through a real act with real consequences but an ideal (ideell) significance. Through the condemnation and punishment of the crime (= the inversion of the first supersensible world) ideality, or the first supersensible world, (re-) establishes itself as the in-itself of the sensible world by way of the inversion of the inverted world. The analysis of the dialectic of crime and punishment may explain why Hegel sees in life the image or, more accurately, a concrete manifestation of the inversion of the inversion and an expression of what in terms of the Logic he calls being-forself, infinity, or the (absolute) Notion.95 Generally speaking, life has the paradoxical feature of recreating the difference between (physical) reality and (organic) ideality through negating it. It feeds on the non-identity of self and other in order to convert both into their opposite and thus maintain itself as a universal that exists both as a “one apart from the many” and as well as “one and the same in all those things,” to use Aristotle’s characterization of the universal in An. Post. II 19. The difference is thus as necessary as is its supersession. But the difference must be understood, as Hegel emphasizes several times, as an “inner difference,” i.e. a difference that is non-disruptive and subservient to the unity that contains it. It is through the incorporation of difference that something is intrinsically determined. Moreover, it is important to realize that this interpretation of the concept of life only works, if the two “moments” within this self-differentiating, self-referential, self-replicating process are defined as essential opposites. Only then can the two aspects or factors be
94 Cf.
PR § 97A: “The criminal act is not a first, something positive, to which the punishment is joined as a negation; rather, it is something negative, such that the punishment is only the negation of a negation.” 95 Also note that in Hegel’s architectonic of the philosophy of nature mechanics and physics, including the laws of motion and chemistry are followed by organics and the philosophy of the life sciences.
142
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
said to be both opposed and identical, i.e. to form an intrinsically determined, internally differentiated unity or whole. With the validation of this conceptual structure as real, Force and Understanding reaches a certain climax. Hegel’s language accordingly celebrates the moment of the affirmation of the supersensible in the sensible world in a series of colorful metaphors: This simple infinity, or the absolute Notion [i.e., the right that has in principle eternally overcome its essential opposite], may be called the simple essence of life, the soul of the world, the universal blood, whose omnipresence is neither disturbed nor interrupted by any difference, but rather is itself every difference, as also their supersession; it pulsates within itself but does not move, inwardly vibrates, yet is at rest (PS § 162/3, 132).
In more formal terms, Hegel repeats that this intrinsically determined, internally differentiated structure is accordingly a “relation-to-self” that is equally a “selfsundering,” and a self-sundering that is equally “a pure, self-identical essence that has no difference in it” (ibid.). The fact that the unity is a unity of opposites accounts for the self-sundering or difference while the fact that the opposites are essential or intrinsic opposites of each other is responsible for their unity. Hegel takes this opportunity to comment on an unresolved problem that in his view beset Schelling’s philosophy generally. Schelling had proposed a similarly inverted world in his Identitätsphilosophie. Taking Spinoza’s absolute substance and its dualism of an ideal and a real series of modifications96 as a source of inspiration he had stipulated an “absolute identity,” or A = A, to function as the unitary ground of both “series”. He identified this absolute identity with absolute reason that posits itself necessarily as subject and object in order to know itself.97 Subject and object are in turn characterized each as unities of subjectivity and objectivity. In the object (i.e., nature) the element of objectivity quantitatively outweighs that of subjectivity, in the subject (i.e., spirit or intelligence) the opposite ratio obtains. In essence, then, we have a structure similar to that of the magnet with its positive and negative poles that each “hide” their opposite pole within themselves. Subject and object are both essential opposites of each other and of themselves. The problem is, what is the common root of this opposition? In Erster Entwurf eines Systems der Naturphilosophie of 1799 Schelling had in fact discussed this question with reference to the phenomenon of “universal magnetism.” Magnetism, he argued, was a special case of a “universal dualism” in nature and the latter could be reduced to a “primordial opposition”98 or “duplicity.” The problem then is, how to explain the origin of duplicity from identity and again that of identity from duplicity?99 96 Cf.
Spinoza, Ethics II P 7. Schelling, Darstellung meines Systems der Philosophie (1801) §§ 1, 9, 21, 22 (SW I 4, 114–129). 98 “Urgegensatz” (SW I 3, 250); also „ursprünligcher Gegensatz“ (SW I 3, 251 footnote). 99 Cf. SW I 3, 250: “But what, then, caused that primordial opposition to emerge from the universal identity of nature?” Hegel’s formulation at PS § 162/3, 132 directly echoes Schelling’s: “ ‘How, from this pure essence, how does difference or otherness issue forth from it?’ ” Through his use of quotation marks Hegel makes it clear that he literally mimics Schelling – only to dismiss the question as unnecessary “fretting” over a pseudo-problem. 97 Cf.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
143
Schelling believed that the two somehow needed to be derived from one another, for without such a derivation a radical dualism of duplicity and identity or of “heterogeneity” and “homogeneity”100 would remain at the foundation of the system. In a sense, Schelling’s answer to this problem would always be the same, viz. the one he also gave in Erster Entwurf of 1799 and which is that strictly speaking there was no explanation. To be sure, to assume the existence of an ultimate identity out of which duplicity arises was absolutely necessary because the opposition was one of essential opposites, i.e. an opposition within a unity in which opposites attract one another. The two co-implied each other,101 and both identity and duplicity therefore ultimately had to form a unity. In Erster Entwurf Schelling concluded that the ultimate origin of this “inner contradiction” (SW I 3, 251 footnote) could not be known, that we could only become aware of it in its most basic manifestation as magnetism. In that case, however, its origin is not so much explained as inferred post factum on the basis of an observed phenomenon. Magnetism, Schelling argued, was the primordial manifestation of the “Urgegensatz,” while the ultimate cause of this manifestation was unknowable: There is thus one cause only which introduced the primordial opposition into nature, and this cause we can indicate by reference to the (unknown) cause of original magnetism (SW I 3, 260).
In other words, while Schelling held on to the idea of an ultimate unitary cause of duplicity, he was unable to specify its nature. This pattern of explaining the inexplicable actually continues right through Schelling’s later philosophy, the so-called Spätphilosophie. The ultimate ground of reality, the absolute, while itself identified with absolute reason defies cognition by (human) reason. Reason is an enigma for reason. It can only be known that the absolute exists, not what it is – just as, according to Kant, I can know about myself as a noumenon only that I am, not what I am.102 Anything that can be conceptualized must for that reason already contain internal difference or duplicity.103 In Erster Entwurf, Schelling had already anticipated the beginnings of what in 1801 he proposed as a solution, viz. that duplicity or “heterogeneity” must emerge from “homogeneity” or “indifference,” i.e. from a state of neutrality that contains no difference. In the 1801 Darstellung, he then explicitly identified absolute reason or the totality itself with the principle of indifference.104 Consequently, this ultimate principle of everything became “pure identity,” i.e. “a complete quantitative equilibrium of subjectivity and objectivity . . . 100 Cf.
ibid. SW I 3, 251: “Both coexist necessarily; what is homogenous repels itself from itself only to the extent that the heterogeneous attracts itself, and the heterogeneous attracts itself only to the extent that the homogenous repels itself from itself.” 102 See CPR B 422, footnote 3. 103 For Schelling’s later philosophical system, the Philosophy of Revelation and the Philosophy of Mythology, see Brinkmann 1976 and Bowie 1993. 104 SW I 4, 114 (§ 1): “I call reason the absolute reason, or reason insofar as it is conceived of as the complete indifference of the subjective and the objective.” 101 Cf.
144
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
in which nothing can be distinguished” (SW I 4, 127) and which contains “neither the one [i.e., subjectivity] nor the other [i.e., objectivity]” (SW I 4, 125) – Hegel’s “night in which all cows are black,” which achieved notoriety as the abyss out of which reality emerges like “a shot from a pistol”. As Hegel correctly points out at PS § 162/3, 132, Schelling had thus isolated one of the two opposites, viz. identity, separated it from its own opposite and then turned it into the supposed overarching unity of identity and difference. Unnecessarily so, and in a logically flawed way, Hegel argued, for obviously the isolated opposite will thus have lost its internal opposite: The unity, of which it is usual to say that difference cannot issue from it, is in fact itself one of the two moments; it is the abstraction of the simplicity or unitary nature over against the difference. But in saying that the unity is an abstraction, that is, is only one of the opposed moments, it is already implied that it is the dividing of itself; for if the unity is a negative, is opposed to something, then it is eo ipso posited as that which has an opposite within it (PS § 162/3, 132–133).
The unity, therefore, is “already divided” as it also always already has “superseded itself as an otherness” (cf. ibid.). In other words, there is no need to posit an abstract totality apart from the unity of the two opposites. Each opposite is in and of itself united with its opposite both internally and externally. The unity is not something beyond the two opposites but contains them and is contained by them from the start. The unity of essential opposites is an original unity that is originally selfdifferentiating, or the original unity contains difference originally. Instead of trying to derive this unity from something simpler and less differentiated we start with it – and essentially remain with and in it throughout its unfolding and development. It is thus apparent that in Hegel’s view Schelling’s positing of an unknowable – because undifferentiated – ground of reality results from a lingering commitment to the opposition of consciousness and an unwillingness to abandon the standpoint of the understanding. The fact that (absolute) reason remains an enigma for (human) reason indicates that (human) reason continues to be identified with the understanding. For what Schelling has in effect done is to eliminate the inner opposite from one of the opposites. He did not follow the logic of the concept of an inner difference but instead let himself be guided by the concept of an external difference. Following the principle of non-contradiction as Spinoza had done he treated the opposites as “predicates, whose essence is an inert substance” (PS § 164/3, 134), i.e., as being only accidentally attached to their totality. This, however, makes the ground a mere “Verstandes-Identität,” i.e. a tautological unity (“A = A”) from which nothing can be derived.105 To try to do so is to belabor a pseudo-problem. This suggests again that Hegel saw in Schelling’s philosophy essentially an impasse. Like Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre this was not the way to complete the Copernican
105 Hegel had also criticized this “Verstandes-Identität” as tautological and as a “one-sided abstract unity” in the 1801 Differenzschrift, although there his criticism had ostensibly been directed against Fichte only: cf. GW 4, 23–25.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
145
revolution. The original synthetic unity of self-consciousness could not be transformed into an infinite principle in this way. As we saw earlier, neither Fichte’s nor Schelling’s approach went “beyond the Kantian results” (SL 62, footnote/WdL I 44 footnote). Therefore, if real progress was to be made, one had once again to “turn to that preceding [Kantian] exposition” (ibid.). Force and Understanding thus appropriately ends with the evocation of that genuine starting-point of speculative philosophy as Hegel understood it, viz. self-consciousness as the original unity of subject and object which is no longer opposed by an other outside itself. Schelling’s philosophy of identity is not a foundation on which to build. In Hegel’s view, the true foundation remains Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception, albeit in its Fichtean version of the I intuiting itself. This is the position we have reached at the end of Force and Understanding. Consciousness has all along been self-consciousness, i.e. a unity that distinguishes itself as consciousness of self from itself as consciousness of objects and at the same time knows this distinction to be only relative or internal to itself. Consciousness is itself what it now knows its object to be, viz. a self-referential, self-determined totality, i.e. an infinity. Because this is so, consciousness is consciousness of a difference that is no less immediately cancelled; consciousness is for its own self, it is a distinguishing of that which contains no difference, or selfconsciousness. I distinguish myself from myself, and in doing so I am directly aware that what is distinguished from myself is not different [from me] (PS § 164/3, 134–135).
And yet, consciousness is the unity of self-consciousness and objectconsciousness only implicitly or unconsciously at this point, or it is this unity “for us”, not yet for itself, Hegel argues. Consciousness has achieved the awareness of itself as object of itself – its object-consciousness has now been reflectively endorsed as its object-consciousness. Consciousness abstracts from the particular content of its object-consciousness and focuses on the fact that what is conscious of this content is itself – the “inner being” or I “gazes” into the inner, supersensible world and finds itself there (PS § 165/3, 135).106 In other words, consciousness has become aware of itself as the ground of the inner world – the inner is on both sides of the curtain of appearances. With his inimitable sense for the dialectical climax Hegel puts it thus: It is manifest that behind the so-called curtain which is supposed to conceal the inner world, there is nothing to be seen unless we go behind it ourselves, as much in order that we may see, as that there may be something behind there which can be seen (PS § 165/3, 135–136).
How did this moment of self-intuition in the other come about, and what does it imply? It is important to emphasize the intuitive nature of this self-awareness. As Hegel makes abundantly clear at PS § 164/3, 134–135, consciousness is as yet far from recognizing itself in its object. Their identity exists explicitly only for us, but
106 Hegel’s formulation suggests a Fichtean act of self-intuition: “Das Schauen des Inneren in das Innere [ist] vorhanden” (ibid.).
146
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
not yet for consciousness itself. Throughout Force and Understanding, while looking into the background of appearances, consciousness had been looking at its own activity. Again and again it unified phenomena by subsuming them under a law and then differentiated the law into several laws only to bring this multiplicity back into a unified conception of the lawful behavior of all appearances, with the result that it had to revise this unified conception again in the face of phenomena characterized by essential opposites etc. All along, the inner world had reflected its own movement, the movement of explaining executed by consciousness as understanding (cf. PS § 163/3, 133). The form determinations of its content were its own, but it continued to “apportion” the differences and oppositions “to two worlds, or to two substantial elements” (cf. PS § 164/3, 134). What it has not yet realized is that its form determinations are constitutive of the objectivity of the very content itself, i.e. it has not yet grasped the transcendental nature of its knowledge of the supersensible world. At the end of Force and Understanding, this insight has become the inevitable next step: The necessary advance from the previous shapes of consciousness for which their truth was a Thing, an ‘other’ than themselves, expresses just this, that not only is consciousness of a thing possible only for a self-consciousness, but that self-consciousness alone is the truth of those shapes. But it is only for us that this truth exists, not yet for consciousness (PS § 164/3, 135).
Self-consciousness is the truth of object-consciousness. In other words, objectconsciousness is dependent on self-consciousness. This means that the barrier between object and content of consciousness has been taken down. As a result, the cornerstone of representational thought has been removed and the opposition of consciousness has been overcome, in theory if not in practice. In becoming aware of itself, consciousness becomes aware of the fact that the objectivity or truth of its object comes about through thinking the content of consciousness. Consequently, the content of consciousness when so translated into thought is just as much the object of consciousness, its Gegenstand or “the true”, as its object is its content. In making itself its object, consciousness realizes that it is itself constitutive of the objectivity of its object, i.e. that objectivity is constituted by conceptualizing the content of consciousness. Because the objectivity of the content is just what it means to be an object for consciousness, this objectivity together with the object reveals itself to be a moment of consciousness’ own immanence. Thus when we say that to be the object of consciousness is equivalent to being its conceptualized content, this is merely another way of formulating the insight at the basis of the Copernican turn, viz. that the subjective conditions of the knowledge of objects are likewise the conditions of those very objects. There is no other objectivity than that of, by, and for thought. That the conceptualized content of consciousness is the same as its object was the point of the argument in the Introduction that we discussed earlier. Not only the appearance, the in-itself or essence, too, is accessible to consciousness for the simple reason that the essence is the noumenal ground of the appearance, i.e. the inner determination of the object for thought. In the introductory text to the Third
3.3
Perception and Understanding
147
Book of the Science of Logic, Hegel makes a similar point. Commenting on the significance of Kant’s Copernican revolution and on the function of the categories and the unity of consciousness in particular he says that “according to this [i.e. Kant’s] exposition, the [synthetic] unity of the concept is that whereby something is not a mere mode of feeling, an intuition, or even a mere representation, but is an object, and this objective unity is the unity of the ego with itself” (SL 584/WdL II 222). Or again in characteristically Hegelian paraphrase of Kant: Thought sublates the immediacy with which the object at first confronts us and thus converts the object into a positedness; but this its positedness is its being-in-and-for-[it]self, or its objectivity. The object therefore has its objectivity in the Notion [i.e. the concept] and this is the unity of self-consciousness into which it has been received; consequently, its objectivity, or the Notion, is itself none other than the nature of self-consciousness, has no other moments or determinations than the I itself (SL 585/WdL II 222).
Thinking converts the immediate content of consciousness into something objective – not any kind of thinking, but thinking in accordance with the categories of thought. This is what Hegel calls objective thought in the Introduction to the Encyclopedia and in the Introduction to the Science of Logic (which we will discuss in greater detail in the next chapter). Furthermore, the categories are nothing but the ways in which the content of consciousness (feelings, sensations, intuitions, representations etc.) is unified in a unity of self-consciousness. According to Hegel’s argument here this unity is, however, simply the reflection of thinking on the content of consciousness and the transformation of this content into thoughts, concepts, judgments, theories. Through this synthesis of representations in accordance with the categories, self-consciousness generates objectivity. It is therefore equivalent to Hegel’s so-called Notion. It is perhaps useful to remind ourselves that Hegel is not here embracing a form of subjective idealism, as if according to this argument reality were a construct of the mind. Consciousness reflects on its experience, not on imaginings. Its choice of categories in conceptualizing the content of experience is not arbitrary. To identify things as a This or as entities with properties or as intrinsically determined or to view them as dependent on forces or obeying laws is not arbitrary. Nor can it be said that consciousness conceptualizes things in just one way and then claims that this way is the necessary or only possible one. Hegel scrutinizes all the important ways in which reality has been construed, and all upon reflection are deficient, except the way that allows us to detect this deficiency. It could of course be objected that thinking got it wrong, that there are no things with properties, really; no essential determinations; no laws etc. Such a position has the onus of demonstrating what else there is, if anything. Worse, it can rely on no other resource than thinking in trying to prove its point. But might not thinking be in error, in oblivion of the truth? Well, if a mistake was made, if an error occurred, if oblivion of the truth has taken over, how was this detected? In the end, thinking is still the judge of all claims to objectivity and truth. The idea of a comprehensive web of delusion in which reason could be caught is as unfruitful and untenable as Descartes’ dream argument. Because it leaves experience as it is, its explanatory value is nil.
148
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
This is clearly not a sufficient answer to possible objections against Hegel’s identification of the conceptualized content of consciousness with objectivity, but it is the beginning of an argument that needs to be pursued further. For the moment I would like to emphasize that Hegel’s point is not that the content of consciousness and the objectivity of its object are immediately the same. Apart from being a fallacy, this would also undermine the distinction between what presents itself immediately to consciousness (i.e., the for-itself) and what consciousness can find out about its object only after a process of reflection (i.e. the in-itself), or the distinction between belief – which is always in danger of being mistaken – and knowledge. It is, rather, the content of consciousness translated into thought (i.e. concepts, judgments, theories) that can count as objective or as “the true” or that can at least compete with other such translated content for objectivity and truth. This statement, however, is not quite innocent either. For as minimal as the content of consciousness may be, it has always already been translated into thought in at least a rudimentary sense, as we saw in Sense-Certainty. This kind of circularity will turn out to be unavoidable and will demand a more sustained defense later. Returning now to the concluding sections of Force and Understanding it should again be noted that the moment of self-recognition in the other that initiates the overcoming of the opposition of consciousness is not yet clearly understood by consciousness. Hegel deliberately uses the Fichtean model of a self-intuition of the self in an other which is itself. But intuition is not yet recognition, “gazing” at something is not yet comprehending it. So when Hegel concludes that “self-consciousness has at first become [simply] for itself, not yet as a unity with consciousness in general” (PS § 164/3, 135), he should not be understood as saying that we have already arrived at the realization of self-consciousness. On the contrary, what has now been reached is merely the concept (or Notion) of self-consciousness. That is to say, the concept of self-consciousness will be the basic transcendental schema, so to speak, in terms of which consciousness will organize the next phases of its experience. It will come to know in experience “what consciousness knows in knowing itself” as self-consciousness (PS § 165/3, 136). In this sense, consciousness sees itself in the other, but in an unconscious or uncomprehending manner which is just what the concept of intellectual intuition symbolizes. It feels itself in the other, as it were. But such an immediate relation to self in the other, while marking the overcoming of the opposition of consciousness “in principle” or implicitly, does not yet include the comprehension of what this implies. In fact, to feel, rather than comprehend, one’s being united with one’s opposite or other is precisely what it means to live, because the elementary process of living consists in the assimilation and incorporation of the other (nature, environment, nutrition) into the self, i.e. its transformation into a part of the self. Consequently, from being unconsciously conscious of itself in the other self-consciousness will now have to learn what it means to recognize itself in an other. Just as Fichte argued that the theoretical or implicit truth of the immanence of the other in the self needed to be complemented by a practical proof, so Hegel now suggests that consciousness go through the experience of living the truth of what it is. This experience will take us from the subjective idealism of Kant and Fichte to the standpoint of absolute idealism at the beginning of the chapter on Reason and beyond.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
149
To conclude the discussion of Force and Understanding, let us reflect on the methodological result Hegel has tried to bring about up to this point. The major advance that occurs in Force and Understanding is the overcoming of the opposition of consciousness. However, this statement is in need of qualification. The opposition of consciousness obviously cannot have been overcome entirely or absolutely, or else the Phenomenology’s argument would now be complete. Consequently, it is only the external opposition between consciousness and its object that has been overcome with the standpoint called Self-Consciousness. What follows is a long series of internal oppositions that will find their ultimate resolution only in Absolute Knowing. By external opposition I mean the interpretation of the relationship between consciousness and object, mind and world, as representational and referential.107 At first, this object was the immediate object of sensuous consciousness, later it became the ground of appearances, an inner or supersensible world of laws. The crucial moment that forced the rethinking of this model came with consciousness’ attempt to deal with two contrary determinations of an object that are both equally constitutive of its essence. The solution to this paradox required the introduction of a second supersensible world, the so-called inverted world. Obviously, to the understanding these two worlds would simply be incompatible. It would find itself in the vexed situation of being unable to come to a decision as to which world was the real or true world. The notion of one reality would have to be abandoned. The inverted world scenario thus leaves the understanding paralyzed by the idea of two diametrically opposed, inverted realms of truth, an idea superbly suited for being comically exploited.108 With its concept of an antithesis within the antithesis, Force and Understanding also offers a paradigmatic example of the single most important feature of Hegel’s dialectic, i.e. the sublation or supersession (Aufhebung) of a contradiction, or the negation of negation. The solution to the inverted world paradox is the point at which this logical move becomes thematic after having been operative from the start. It is the point at which the “negative” dialectic of the understanding is abandoned in favor of the superior power of positive reason.109 It is here that the move is made from the antinomical to the speculative mode of reason. The impasse of two supersensible worlds represents the stage at which “thinking gets entangled in contradictions” and which it must overcome in order to “accomplish in thinking itself the resolution of its own contradictions” (E § 11). We can easily see why this 107 For the thesis that all consciousness is representational, i.e. that there is no non-representational mental content and that consciousness’ relationship to the object is always subjectively mediated, see Hofmann, 2002. 108 A hilarious example of such an inverted world (and perhaps a better one than the play by Tieck mentioned earlier) is Molière’s Amphytrion, a fireworks of paradoxical inversions of identity especially in the character of Sosias. Marivaux is also particularly good at this. Generally speaking, the era of the French enlightenment is full of plays of mistaken and inverted identities, often coupled with change of gender. Other examples of such duplications and inversions of reality such as Mozart’s Così fan tutte could easily be added to the list. 109 At E § 79 Hegel refers to three aspects or moments of logical thought, viz. the abstractly rational or the aspect of the understanding, the dialectical or “negatively rational” and the “positively rational” which is also the speculative moment of thought.
150
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
contradiction is so hard for thinking to overcome. Thinking seems to be asked to embrace rather than reject the contradiction, a step which would have the meaning of violating the Principle of Non-Contradiction. There should, however, be no doubt that a violation of the PNC is out of the question. It is precisely because the two supersensible worlds within one world constitute a violation of the PNC in that they postulate the existence of two diametrically opposed realities and thus of two contrary realms of truth that the inverted world must be superseded in favor of one “universe of discourse” in which only one truth is valid.110 Indeed, when Hegel seems to make fun of the understanding’s mistaken attempts to unify these realities he is making fun of the violation of the PNC.111 This contradiction can be overcome only through the unification of the two universes and thus the integration of the two opposed realities as two dependent moments of one unified whole. In other words, we must move to a higher level at which the previous external relationship between two independent realities is replaced by an internal relationship. But this is not enough. If the two moments or aspects are both of equal value, the result will be the unceasing alternation of the true and the false, such that whenever P is true Q is false and vice versa. But as we saw in Hegel’s example of the self-sublation of the criminal act, crime is never true nor is the just ever unjust. Crime only pretends to be a valid reality, but this pretense is undermined even before the crime has been committed. On the other hand, it is difficult to think of a reality in which crime would be completely absent. Hence the reality of the negation of justice cannot be ignored, it must be accepted as more than a contingent matter. As we see, then, sublation cannot mean to grant equal validity to both opposites within the unified reality. Instead, one of the opposites must be assumed to be the “normal” or dominant one while the other, while necessary and essential, is a disturbance, an interruption or a temporary disorder or violation of this normality. But even the best of all possible worlds necessarily contains evil. In the terms of our example, justice must be assumed to gain the upper hand as a rule. Hegel’s standard formula to express this insight is to say that the sublation represents the truth of the earlier contradiction. It remains nonetheless true that without this disturbance there would not be a normality, just as it remains empirically true that the disturbance may contingently become disruptive such that we relapse into earlier contradictions. The latter observation also means that Hegel’s dialectic is not downward compatible, so to speak, only upward compatible. Contradictions are not eliminated at the lower level even though by them we are logically compelled to move on to their supersession. In a context in
110 I am largely in agreement with Pippin’s construal of the dialectic in Pippin 1996 and his attempt to show that Hegel does not violate PNC (249–250). For other explanations of why Hegel employs but does not violate PNC see Hartmann 1973 and Wandschneider 1995. Hartmann’s explanation of the second negation as a limitative opposition has been neglected and should be rediscovered and discussed. I also find Robert Hanna’s interpretation of the dialectic very helpful and persuasive: see Hanna 1996. 111 To this extent the argument in the inverted world episode is indeed a reductio, as Joseph C. Flay had argued, but it is only one part of the argument, one of the two red herrings that should not be pursued, the other being Schelling’s principle of indifference: see Flay 1970. To that extent, Siep’s comment on Flay in Siep 2000, 95, footnote 16, would need to be amended.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
151
which crime is not considered inherently invalid justice becomes retributive, i.e. the criminal deed is just as valid or invalid as the retaliation against it depending on the point of view, and the latter does not have the meaning of a sublation of the former. It is true that Hegel’s language occasionally seems to suggest the equipollence of both opposites in a unity, as if identity contains difference just as much as difference contains identity: The different moments of self-sundering and of becoming self-identical are . . . only this movement of self-suppression; for since the self-identical . . . is an abstraction or is already itself a sundered moment, its self-sundering is therefore a supersession of what it is, and therefore the supersession of its dividedness. Its becoming self-identical is equally a selfsundering; what becomes identical with itself thereby opposes itself to its self-sundering, i.e. it thereby puts itself on one side, or rather it becomes a sundered moment (PS § 162/3, 133).
From this comment it would seem that to be self-identical is to be self-sundering and, “equally,” to be self-sundering is to be identical. It is clear, however, that the contradiction between identity and opposition, or same and other, can be contained only if the moment of identity is more dominant than that of opposition, for otherwise we would either remain stuck in the “dialectical see-saw” of an interminable back and forth without resolution or the unity would dissolve altogether. If, to speak metaphorically, the positive pole of the magnet is to attract its external negative pole, it must “hide” or dominate the internal negative pole it carries within itself. Nor can the internal opposite be neutralized by the dominant pole, for then the magnet would be demagnetized, i.e. no longer be a magnet. Consequently, the internal opposite is (a) attracted, (b) repelled and (c) dominated by its opposite. In short, it is subordinate. While (a) and (b) are symmetrical reciprocal relationships, (c) contains an asymmetry. The two “moments” of the dialectical unity (identity and difference, same and other, attraction and repulsion, positive and negative, etc.) are not of equal logical force. This may be the reason why in addition to magnetism Hegel introduces the example of the crime. The phenomenon of magnetism can be misleading because it suggests that the unity of the magnet comes about simply through the mutual attraction of the positive and negative poles. However, this unity of what I have called external opposites merely reflects a surface phenomenon. It plays at the level of appearance at which it seems as if both moments are of equal standing. It is precisely this assumption of an equality of the two that gets the understanding into trouble when it tries to ground the opposites in their contraries. For then the result is an inconclusive alternation between two domains of reality each of which has equal validity. By contrast, Hegel introduces the example of the crime because it more clearly reflects the intended meaning, viz. that the internal opposition of contraries supersedes or transcends the external, seeming equality between the opposites (in this case those of right and wrong). It is the internal opposition we just analyzed, the opposition within one of the contraries, that is the model for Hegel’s notorious Aufhebung. In this model, unity dominates difference, without neutralizing the difference. While the unity is internally differentiated, “its essence is unity,” as Hegel puts it at PS § 161/3, 131. Similarly, the criminal deed is the opposite within the opposite by which it is dominated, i.e. the right and the just. It is only as a brute fact that the crime is also the external opposite of the just that apparently reacts to it in kind. At the deeper level of the internal opposition, however, the validity of
152
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
appearances is questioned and overturned, and the realm of appearances as something existing independently in its own right is genuinely superseded. The crime calls forth its correction. The correction subverts the crime’s external validity and re-establishes the domination of the just order over the lawless crime. The latter is invalidated without being undone. We can now see what methodological reasons may have motivated Hegel when he chose the phenomenon of force, especially in its appearance as magnetism with its attraction of what is different and the repulsion of what is selfsame. That the selfsame should be different from itself and the different identical to itself constitutes a challenge for the understanding. It forces the understanding to go beyond the negative dialectic of an antinomical reason and to embrace contradiction rather than retreat from it.112 As we saw, the PNC remains intact in the process. The second negation is stronger than the first. It includes the first negation without neutralizing it. Unity has priority over difference even when difference is an essential component. This is the speculative insight Hegel had worked hard to win and which he believed had bypassed Schelling in his philosophy of identity. The inverted world episode thus constitutes the genuine turning point of the argument in Force and Understanding. As we shall see at the beginning of the next section, it also in a sense constitutes the turning point of the entire Phenomenology. The prototype of a “negatively rational” form of reasoning is the analysis of the concept of becoming in the Logic whose back and forth between coming-into-being and passing-away finds its resolution only in the concept of Dasein or determinate being. The state of becoming, Hegel explains, is a transition from not-being to being and equally from being to not-being.113 Here the “equally” must be accorded its full meaning. If becoming were only one of the two, it would cease to be becoming and either issue in being or in nothing. But neither is it already a stable unity of being and not-being. On the contrary, becoming is a “restless” being-in-transition, having departed from something without having arrived anywhere. Only when we reach determinate being something has come to be out of becoming.114 Consequently, in the concept of Dasein the moment of being must dominate that of not-being: From becoming there issues determinate being, which is the simple oneness of being and nothing [i.e. being with an inner difference or limitation]. . . . Its mediation, becoming, lies behind it; it has sublated itself and determinate being appears, therefore, as a first, as a starting-point for the ensuing development. It is [sc. for this reason] first of all in the one-sided determination of being (my italics) (SL 109/WdL I 96).
112 Thematically, force is obviously one of the crucial concepts in modern metaphysics since Descartes, Newton, and Leibniz. This metaphysics is a metaphysics of the understanding according to Hegel, and hence the chapter on Force and Understanding is also meant to analyze the significance of this category for the history of thought’s self-reflection. 113 Hegel’s reference to Heraclitus here is only to be expected (cf. E § 88A). It was Heraclitus who for the first time dared to face the contradiction that contraries could be essential components of the identity of something and to declare this to be the universal truth. 114 For this reason, I treat Becoming as a second stage in the dialectic, not as a regular synthesis of Being and Nothing despite some of Hegel’s own comments to the contrary.
3.3
Perception and Understanding
153
One of the loci for studying the meaning of sublation and dialectical synthesis or the inclusion of the other in the same is Hegel’s discussion of genuine infinity in the Logic as a unity of the finite and the infinite.115 Thus Hegel says that in the unity of the finite and the infinite . . . there is revealed the specific nature of speculative thought, which consists solely in grasping the opposed moments in their unity. Each moment actually shows that it contains its opposite within itself and that in this opposite it is united with itself; thus the affirmative truth is this immanently active unity . . . – a the relation to self which is not immediate but infinite (SL 152/WdL I 142).
Here, too, it might at first seem as if the finite and the infinite are two moments of equal right and force.116 It is, after all, customary to explain the third stage of Hegel’s dialectical triad of immediacy, opposition, and synthesis (negation of negation) as the combination of the two preceding opposites. However, this way of portraying what Hegel means by supersession or sublation leaves the crucial thing unsaid, as the following passage from the Encyclopedia makes clear. Having demonstrated the “nullity of the antithesis set up by the understanding between the finite and the infinite” (Enc. § 95R) Hegel continues that one might now . . . easily fall back upon the expression that the finite and the infinite are therefore One, that the True, or genuine Infinity, is determined and expressed as the unity of the infinite and the finite (Enc. § 95R).
While such an expression would no doubt “contain something correct,” it would, however, only represent one side of the truth and therefore be “misleading and false” (ibid.). Why is this so, one might wonder? The answer is that . . . in the above expression (“The Infinite is the unity of the infinite and the finite”) the finite appears to be left as it was; it is not explicitly expressed as sublated. – Or, if we were to reflect on the fact that the finite, when posited as one with the infinite, could surely not remain what it was outside of this unity . . ., then the same would happen to the infinite, which as the negative . . . would . . . also be blunted upon the other. . . . But the genuine Infinite . . . preserves itself; the negation of the negation is not a neutralization; the Infinite is the affirmative, and it is only the finite which is sublated (ibid).
Hegel’s intention here should be unmistakable. We only need to keep in mind that when he speaks of the infinite there are actually two meanings involved, viz. the socalled “spurious” and the so-called “genuine” infinite. When the finite is opposed to the infinite, the infinite in question is the spurious infinite, i.e. the endless iteration of the finite. When, however, the opposition of the finite and the infinite is said to give way to the genuine infinite, then finitude in general, including the opposition of finitude and spurious infinite, is meant to be sublated, i.e. incorporated into the 115 See SL 143–152/WdL I 132–142 and E § 95, including the Remark. The other important locus for studying Aufhebung in Hegel is the dialectic of something and an other (SL 117–129/WdL I 104–116). 116 This is suggested by the language at SL 151–152/WdL I 141–142 where Hegel seems to treat the two moments as equipollent. We will see presently that this impression is corrected by passages such as the one in the Remark to E § 95.
154
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
genuine infinite. In this sense, Hegel can say that “only the finite . . . is sublated” while the “genuine Infinite . . . preserves itself” despite the incorporation of finitude. In other words, with the sublation of one opposite its earlier opposite, viz. the spurious infinite, is likewise sublated. In this sense, both earlier opposites are superseded. They collapse into one opposite, the finite generally, which is sublated as the necessary, but dependent moment of the appearance of the infinite. In the genuine infinite, also called being-for-self, the prototype of the Hegelian Concept, the infinite is “stronger” than the finite. The second negation overrules the first, but does not eliminate it. Hegel’s Aufhebung results in an asymmetrical unity in which one moment is both the whole and a moment within the whole. The infinite is limited, and yet it is also all-inclusive.117
3.4 The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason This section will take us from the beginning of the chapter on Self-Consciousness to the end of the chapter on Spirit. This is an enormous leap in terms of thematic material, but one that can be justified by the fact that our focus is primarily on the methodological aspect of the Phenomenology, i.e. the question as to how the opposition of consciousness is in fact overcome. Moreover, as will be apparent presently, it is also justified by the methodological advance that has already taken place and that we discussed towards the end of the preceding section. That the opposition of consciousness, at least in the most obvious sense of consciousness’s realistic attitude, has indeed been overcome is confirmed by Hegel right at the start of SelfConsciousness. In the “previous modes of certainty,” Hegel says, “what is true for consciousness is something other than itself” (PS § 166/3, 137). Up till now, consciousness believed the in-itself, i.e. the essence or truth of appearances, to be an object or a reality existing independently of itself. Only if its explanatory posits have an existence independently of consciousness may its knowledge be regarded as more than just subjective. Now, however, consciousness has come to realize that the otherness of the in-itself, its independent status, is a function of its mode of cognition as finite consciousness. That the object, and hence the evidence confirming or disconfirming a truth claim, is “out there” is a structural feature of consciousness itself. Objectivity adheres to conceptual or noematic content. The in-itself or objectivity is not a “Thing out there” standing opposed to consciousness on the side of sensible phenomena. It is the conceptualized content of consciousness – and there is no other in-itself behind or beyond it. This means that the methodological program of the Introduction has now run its first full course118 and the distinction between a truth for consciousness and an objective truth has become obsolete:
117 The structure of the totality is to be both limited and all-inclusive. It is the logical structure of Parmenides’ One as well (cf. KRS 252–253). 118 § 166/3, 137–138 in fact takes up the very same wording that Hegel had already used in § 84/3, 76–77.
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
155
The Notion of the object is superseded in the actual object, or the first, immediate presentation of the object is superseded in experience: certainty gives place to truth (ibid.).
Looking back we can see that while the putative a priori of the object (the “Notion of the object”) has been replaced by the true a priori (the “actual object”) a number of times and the true a priori (the “actual object”) has become a putative a priori (the “Notion of the object”) in turn, this series of reversals has now issued in a reinterpretation of the meaning of truth. It is now true for consciousness that “the object corresponds to the Notion” and vice versa, or that the object’s in-itself and its beingfor-another “are one and the same” (ibid.). With the benefit of hindsight we now also see that what for consciousness was a thing existing independently of itself was in truth the Notion in the guise of an independent world of facts and laws. In other words, consciousness’ previous view of reality now turns out to be an abstraction. While the in-itself or essence of reality continues to differ from its appearance, consciousness now knows that this difference is not an external difference, one between mind and world, so to speak, but has become an internal difference within selfconsciousness, an ideal [ideell] difference.119 Hence from this moment on, what is true for the subject and in this sense “subjective” is also objectively true, and vice versa – at least in principle or programmatically. In actuality, however, because this self-consciousness continues to be limited by an other, even if only internally, it finds itself opposed to an “inner enemy” that it will have to conquer through its experience as an “unhappy consciousness” and as individual reason that gives and tests laws, for instance. Still, the hypothesis now to be “verified” and corroborated by consciousness is that the in-itself and the being-for-another are the same conceptual content – the in-itself is the noematic content of consciousness and this content is known by consciousness to capture the truth of the object. In this sense, “the ‘I’ is the content of the connection and the connecting itself” (ibid.).120 In short, the object or other, the “reality out there” has been integrated into the immanence of (self-)consciousness and has revealed itself as a complicated noematic structure of laws and theories. Since the divide between mind and world has become internal to self-consciousness the issue of whether anything “outside consciousness” corresponds to this structure is necessarily moot. The position of objective thought has in principle been achieved. If philosophy as science “presupposes the liberation from the opposition of consciousness” (SL 49/WdL I 30), then this liberation has now occurred. This is why at the beginning of Self-Consciousness Hegel can say that “we have . . . entered the native realm of truth” (PS § 167/3, 138). The reason why the transformation of the divide between mind and world into an inner distinction within self-consciousness does not lead to skepticism prompted
119 Cf. PS § 166/3, 137: “In this [relation of self to object] there is indeed an otherness; that is to say, consciousness makes a distinction, but one which at the same time is for consciousness not a distinction.” 120 “Opposed to an other, the ‘I’ is its own self, and at the same time it overarches this other which, for the ‘I’, is equally only the ‘I’ itself,” Hegel adds and thus anticipates the formulation he will use later at the very beginning of the Encyclopedia Phenomenology (cf. E § 413).
156
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
by questions of correspondence and reference is to be seen in the fact that Hegel’s understanding of what it means to know is not based on the model of truth as correspondence of representation and object or on the referential model of cognition. Rather, for Hegel knowledge is understood in terms of translation of representations into concepts or thoughts that offers a progressive increase in intelligibility. Still, we should not ignore that from the point of view of ordinary consciousness and empirical science Hegel is making a move of momentous significance. To ask that the representational model be no longer the only model of cognition and truth is a lot to ask of ordinary consciousness, although for the latter the idea that there may be different truths than those of empirical science – and not necessarily for that reason spurious ones – is not entirely alien.121 However, our ordinary concept of truth presupposes the verifiability and testability of propositions and theories against what can be observed and allows only the answer of “true” or “false” or, if neither can be established, the epochê of the undecided. While in a sense Hegel in fact agrees with this concept of truth as something that must be testable and verifiable,122 he nonetheless argues that there are different levels of truth and that depending on their content propositions have so to speak an intensive truth value, i.e. can be more or less true or false, or have more or less weight. That Hegel advocates a comparative notion of truth may seem less strange, if we consider that even in ordinary discourse we have no problem accepting distinctions such as those between “trivial” and “important” or “essential” truths, or between a commonplace, a cliché, a simple truth, or a complicated web of truths. The important point for Hegel is that the scope of our experience goes way beyond the domain of what can be said about individuated spatio-temporal particulars and empirical laws – indeed, it includes the entire scope of the experience of consciousness in the Phenomenology, from sensory to religious consciousness. Having arrived at the entrance of the “native land of truth” consciousness will remain in it to the end of its journey. The oppositions to be overcome will henceforth be internal oppositions within self-consciousness, reason, and spirit. Hegel even argues that as early as the beginning of Self-Consciousness we have also already made acquaintance with the concept of spirit. Since Self-Consciousness will involve the initial confrontation and then the recognition between two selves, self-consciousness will already have learned implicitly what spirit means, viz. a selfconsciousness that recognizes another self in its opposite and unites with it through an act of recognition that allows them “in their opposition [to] enjoy perfect freedom and independence” (PS § 177/3, 145). With this arises the idea of an “‘I’ that
121 Hence Hegel’s appeal to religion as a representative of another truth beyond the domain of the “verifiable” (cf., e.g., SL 587–588/WdL II 225–226, SL 50/WdL I 31, E §§ 1, 12R, to mention just a few passages). SL 587–588/WdL II 225–226 in particular contrasts the reality and truth of the “fleeting and superficial phenomena of the world of sensuous particulars” with the truth represented by religion. 122 See, for instance, his comment at E § 6 that agreement with experience is a criterion of philosophical truth: Philosophy’s “accord with actuality and experience is necessary. Indeed, this accord can be viewed as an outward touchstone, at least, for the truth of a philosophy . . ..”
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
157
is ‘We’ and [a] ‘We’ that is ‘I’” (ibid.). If we ask, however, at which point in the Phenomenology this plural I or singular We becomes a reality, we find that this quest will take us to the section on Forgiveness at the very end of the long chapter on Spirit. This part of Hegel’s argument thus spans the development from the beginning of Self-Consciousness right up to the transition to Religion. To be sure, there are major developments and reversals along the way. Consciousness will first have to work out for itself what it means to be a selfconsciousness. Next it will undergo the experience of being an exponent of reason in a world assumed to be fundamentally rational but that turns out to be rational in a way different from what individual self-consciousness presumes it to be. Finally, in the chapter on Spirit, it will come to understand what it means to be part of a context that is larger than itself. It will thus see itself transformed into a moment of a larger structure. With this, consciousness will have reached the threshold of religious experience. In this section, I will delineate this development by selectively discussing some of the strategic junctures that signal major methodological advances. To begin with, we should keep in mind that self-consciousness is a unity of self and object in such a way that the object is now synonymous with the content of consciousness or is indeed consciousness itself insofar as the latter is distinct from self-consciousness proper, i.e. the “I” that is capable of accompanying all representations of and in consciousness, so to speak. Hegel argues that the earlier “moments” or aspects of consciousness are therefore likewise present. These moments are the singleness of sense-certainty, the universality of perception, and the “empty inner being of the Understanding” (PS § 167/3, 138), i.e. the abstract thinking self that intuits itself as object – the original indeterminate self-intuiting self-consciousness. Due to the synonymy of consciousness and object these same moments immediately have objective meaning as well. However, the moment of their independent existence seems to have vanished since they “have no reality for consciousness” anymore (ibid.). Their independence is now understood to be a matter of appearance only – in truth they have no independent standing for self-consciousness. This suggests that in its object the self now immediately relates only to itself. The unity of object-consciousness and self-consciousness “is only the motionless tautology of: ‘I am I’” (ibid.). In other words, this self is so far only an empty or indeterminate self. And yet, Hegel argues, the difference between object-consciousness and selfconsciousness is still present for this self-consciousness, and the object of the objectconsciousness does indeed also have independent existence for consciousness. How is that possible? The reason is that self-consciousness at first relates unreflectively to its object, it is immersed in or completely taken up by its object-consciousness. Its object-consciousness is not really distinct from the self and thus the “I” of its self-consciousness has as yet no content of its own, as we just saw. Because the difference between self-consciousness and object-consciousness “does not have the form of being” for self-consciousness, it is unreflective self-consciousness and to that extent “not self-consciousness” (ibid.) and still consciousness, for which the object does have independent existence. Hence it is also true that the other of the self “is for it in the form of a being, or as a distinct moment” (ibid.). At
158
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
the same time, however, the moment of unreflective unity of object-consciousness and self-consciousness is likewise present – this consciousness is, after all, selfconsciousness. Consequently, the object both does and does not have the meaning of an independent being for consciousness. The opposition of consciousness continues to be present, even though it has implicitly been superseded or internalized. In sum, . . . self-consciousness is in the form of consciousness, and the whole expanse of the sensuous world is preserved for it, but at the same time only as connected with the second moment, the unity of self-consciousness with itself; and hence the sensuous world is for it an enduring existence which, however, is only appearance, or a difference which, in itself, is no difference (ibid.).
In this way, Hegel sets up a conflict that demands resolution – the object cannot with equal logical force be both independent of self-consciousness and dependent on it. In essence one must outweigh the other, as we saw at the end of the last section, without, however, eliminating it. And since the preceding development has already shown that the object does not have genuine independence, “this antithesis of its appearance and its truth” must be resolved in favor of the true relationship, viz. the “unity of self-consciousness with itself” (ibid.). The conflict between dependence and independence of consciousness’ object is, however, not only theoretical but also practical. As far as the theoretical relationship is concerned, consciousness relates cognitively to the object as a thing, although now “a living thing” (PS § 168/3, 139), since the object of consciousness is, after all, a self, albeit one in which self-consciousness cannot initially recognize itself as the self it itself is. A living thing exists as a self reflected into itself (cf. ibid.), i.e. it constitutes a center of the world in its own right. Nonetheless, this living thing has no genuine independence for self-consciousness (both as part of the general species-life and as object for another self-consciousness) and is for that reason only an appearance just as much as rocks, iron, or wood turned out to be at the end of Force and Understanding. However, to this theoretical negation Hegel adds a practical negation which he calls desire. The self’s desire is to overcome practically what it knows cognitively to be only an apparent independence. However, such a desire cannot merely be explained by the logical conflict we just analyzed according to which the object of self-consciousness both is and is not an independent existence. Desire is desire to overcome an incompleteness or lack, and so Hegel must show why selfconsciousness is incomplete without an object and therefore needs the object to complete itself. If he can say that self-consciousness needs the object as a complement without which it would somehow be unfinished or fragmentary, he will be able to argue that this need contradicts the “identity of itself with itself” [Gleichheit (equality) seiner mit sich selbst] (PS § 167/3, 139) which is its “true essence” (ibid.). And this is indeed Hegel’s argument. Self-consciousness needs the object in order to be conscious of itself as distinct from its object-consciousness, or it needs the object in order to be self-consciousness. However, just as much must it deny the need for or dependence on an object, if it is to be self-consciousness – a perfect contradiction, but now a practical contradiction affecting self-consciousness’ relation to the
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
159
object. Because self-consciousness is at this point just this unresolved contradiction between self- and object-consciousness, Hegel can say that self-consciousness is “Desire in general” (ibid.). In the most basic case, desire is a craving for the possession or appropriation of an object which is desired because its possession or appropriation alleviates a felt need or compensates for a lack. But there is a curious self-defeating dialectic at work in desire. Satisfaction of desire is equivalent to the affirmation of the undisturbed identity of the self with itself, a return to the serene relation to itself. And yet, as long as self-consciousness is in conflict with its own object-consciousness, its self-relatedness keeps being disturbed. Moreover, mere gratification does not give substantial content to the self. Consequently, self-consciousness must re-affirm its identity with itself by appropriating the object again and again. And selfconsciousness is indeed “bothered” by its object-consciousness because at this stage self-consciousness is still in conflict with itself over how to deal with its objectconsciousness, i.e. whether to ignore it, to eliminate it practically, or to identify with it. The aspects of being completely engaged in and by the world around it and that of being-for-itself have not yet been brought together in a stable unity.123 In its dependence on the object, self-consciousness therefore reacts negatively towards it: Certain of the nothingness of this other . . . it destroys the independent object and thereby gives itself the certainty of itself as a true certainty (PS § 174/3, 143)
But the satisfaction derived from the destruction of the object does not last. It is self-consciousness itself that renews the object and with it the need to negate it: Desire and the self-certainty obtained in its gratification are conditioned by the object, for self-consciousness comes from superseding this other: in order that this supersession can take place, there must be this other (PS § 175/3, 143).
The demand for satisfaction is created anew once gratification has occurred, simply because self-consciousness at this stage still derives its identity from “negating” its other, i.e. its own object-consciousness. We can see that it must indeed eliminate this other even though it is also dependent on it, because qua object-consciousness this other is also its own self. Self-consciousness is “unable to supersede” its object and instead “produces the object again” (ibid.), because it craves selfhood based on its superiority over the other – a process leading to the endless repetition typical of a “bad” infinity. There is no remedy for this tug of war as long as self-consciousness believes that satisfaction consists in the annihilation of the other and its own uncontested superiority. For with the annihilation of the object self-consciousness also annihilates the possibility of affirming itself as an independent self. Alternatively, it must seek out ever new objects for its appropriation. And yet, in this way it remains chained to its finitude and the iron fist of desire continues to wield power over it. 123 Indeed,
the self-relatedness of the self must as yet emerge from the immersion of the self in its object – this being the reason why Hegel prefaces the famous confrontation of two selfconsciousnesses in the struggle for recognition with the dialectical unfolding of the idea of life (the latter is best read in connection with Hegel’s analysis of the concept of organic life in the Organics chapter of the Philosophy of Nature).
160
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
As long as this dialectic plays itself out in the animal kingdom it does not create a problem for the self because its self-consciousness is here located in the impersonal genus which does not develop an independent self but lives vicariously in and through the individual members of its species.124 However, for the thinking individual that develops a self-consciousness for itself the self-defeating nature of the gratification of desire becomes an experience that it must confront. It learns that genuine satisfaction and thus the “true certainty” of its independence as a self would require that it become a fulfilled self-consciousness instead of withdrawing again and again into the mere “tautology of ‘I am I’” after each gratification of its desire. How is this goal to be achieved? The requirement seems at first impossible to satisfy. If the self is to overcome the sterility of its tautological self-relatedness it seems that it will have to relate positively to something other than itself. The only other available to it, however, is the sensuous living thing. If self-consciousness also wants to be able to identify with this other as it must in order to become a fulfilled self-relatedness, the other must be like itself, and hence the sensuous living thing cannot function as the desired match. Instead, the other or object must be an alter ego, i.e. another self-consciousness. This would indeed be the only object that can fill the other position in the formula “I am I” while at the same time avoiding a tautological return of the self into itself. Hegel therefore, famously, lays it down that Self-consciousness achieves its satisfaction only in another self-consciousness (PS § 175/3, 144).
Only when relating to another self-consciousness does self-consciousness in fact exist as self-consciousness, Hegel says (cf. PS § 177/3, 144–145) – and, we might add, not merely as consciousness. For in this relationship the self relates to another self whose otherness while essential is less essential than its sameness, i.e. in the alter ego it unites non-tautologically with itself and thus becomes a fulfilled self-consciousness.125 This unity, however, is possible only as an act of mutual acceptance or recognition. For a self to unite with another self as self-consciousness must mean to accept the other both as other and as equal, and such an acceptance can become real only through an act of recognition, indeed of mutual recognition since there would be no equality without reciprocity. The desire for satisfaction turns out in the end to be a desire for recognition: Self-consciousness exists in and for itself when, and by the fact that, it so exists for another; that is, it exists only in being acknowledged (PS § 178/3, 145).
Hegel thus establishes a necessary connection between a self existing in the form of self-consciousness, its being acknowledged as an equal by another selfconsciousness, and therefore its achievement of independence or freedom. Freedom
124 Cf. PS § 172/3, 143: In “the movement of Life itself” the “simple genus does not exist for itself qua this simple determination,” i.e. qua unity reflected into itself. Instead, “Life consists rather in being the self-developing whole which dissolves its development [i.e. the creation of individual members] and in this movement simply preserves itself” (PS § 171/3, 142). 125 In Hegel’s words: “. . . only in this way does the unity of itself in its otherness become explicit for it” (PS § 177/3, 144–145).
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
161
for Hegel consists in the implicit or explicit acknowledgement by others of being an end in oneself, an acknowledgement that is mutual and universal and that can ultimately exist only in institutionalized form.126 Strictly speaking, there is no genuine freedom for Hegel outside such an institutionalized mutual recognition of equals. Freedom is always the freedom of an I that is part of a mutually recognitive We.127 For this reason, freedom is intimately connected with Hegel’s idea of spirit, for spirit is the institutionalized recognition of freedom. Because the idea of such an institutionalized freedom of equals grows out of the idea of mutual recognition, the development that begins with Self-Consciousness can find its completion only in the actuality of spirit. At this point, however, the mutual acceptance of two selves as equals is as yet a promised land. We need to remember that self-consciousness is still “in the form of consciousness”. That is to say, it still behaves towards the other as something to be appropriated. Its attitude is one of abstract negation of the other, denying the object an independent being. Self-consciousness suppresses the object rather than relating to it in a positive manner. But an alter ego is not the kind of object that could be appropriated or possessed, let alone annihilated, if the self is to enrich itself through its relationship with the other self. That an alter ego cannot even really be the possession of another self is the lesson the master fails to learn in the wellknown master-slave parable about to unfold. The “process of recognition” (E § 430) through which self-consciousness is supposed to achieve freedom will therefore at first take the form of a struggle for recognition, since the initial negative relationship that escalates into a “life-and-death struggle” (PS § 187/3, 149) needs to be transformed into an affirmative relationship with the other. Desire for the other needs to be sublimated and transformed into respect for the other. We will not detail this well-known emergence of man out of the state of nature and instead reflect on its result.128 Remarkably, the struggle for mutual recognition 126 The Encyclopedia version of the Phenomenology makes this connection more explicitly than does the Phenomenology: “Universal self-consciousness is the affirmative awareness of oneself in another self; each self as a free individuality has his own absolute independence, yet in virtue of the negation of its immediacy or desire it does not distinguish itself from the other. Each is thus universal self-consciousness and objective; each has genuine universality in the shape of reciprocity, so far as each knows itself to be acknowledged by the free other and is aware of this insofar as it acknowledges the other and knows it to be free. This universal re-appearance of self-consciousness . . . is the form in which the substance of all genuine spirituality becomes conscious of itself, i.e. the spirituality that is manifest in the family, the fatherland, the state as well as in all the virtues, in love, friendship, courage, honor, and glory” (E § 436, after Miller, with modifications; see also the Addition). 127 The centrality of this connection between recognition and freedom has been underscored by Robert Williams in two excellent studies: see Williams 1992 and 1997. 128 Note that in the Encyclopedia Hegel views the life-and-death struggle and the subsequent master-slave relationship as marking the transition from a Rousseauean state of nature into a semicivil state: “. . . the fight for recognition pushed to the extreme here indicated can only occur in the natural state, where men exist only as single, separate individuals; but it is absent in civil society and the State because here the recognition for which the combatants fought already exists. For although the state may originate in violence, it does not rest on it” (E § 432A). And: “As regards the historical side of this [master-slave] relationship, it can be remarked that ancient peoples, the
162
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
issues in an unequal relationship.129 The master-slave relationship is not one of mutual recognition of equals since only one of them, the master, emerges as a free self-consciousness. And even his freedom is not genuine. For one thing, the master accepts the recognition as an independent self from someone whom he cannot respect as his equal. But the recognition offered by a “servile consciousness” is not a genuine recognition (cf. PS § 193/3, 152). Furthermore, the master is also dependent on the slave for just the reason for which he won his superiority over the bondsman, viz. the satisfaction of his desires. In the struggle he was willing to sacrifice this satisfaction unconditionally, but the slave’s submission makes it possible for him to indulge himself. This is the master’s Achilles heel in the relationship because it prevents him from advancing beyond the natural state.130 By contrast, it is the slave who achieves freedom. He emancipates himself from his natural state because in working for the master he must postpone his own gratification. In developing practical skills and abilities by creating artifacts through his labor he proves himself to be a master of himself and of nature generally. While the master achieves a dubious independence, the slave gains autonomy. Perhaps surprisingly, the outcome of the struggle for recognition at this juncture is a free self-consciousness whose freedom is not recognized by anyone. Mutual acknowledgement of two self-consciousnesses as equals will in fact be postponed until the end of the chapter on Spirit, as pointed out earlier. Nonetheless, with the emancipation of the slave through his own labor “we are in the presence of selfconsciousness in a new shape,” Hegel claims (PS § 197/3, 156). What, then, is the structure of this new shape? Hegel regards the new self as a synthesis of the two preceding types of self-consciousness. As we might expect, this synthesis is more than just a combination of the master and the slave consciousness in one new selfconsciousness. In accordance with the dialectical procedure, the combination issues in a novelty that cannot simply be resolved into the preceding shapes of consciousness.131 The self-consciousness of the emancipated slave unites within itself that of the master whose self, however, had previously been dependent on an objectconsciousness that remained foreign to him and whose desires could be satisfied only indirectly through the work of the slave, not directly by himself. The master exchanged the labor of self-discipline for the luxury of leisure. In this new configuration, the object-consciousness of the master has been internalized by the slave for whom it has, however, become a consciousness of which he is himself the master.
Greeks and Romans, had not yet risen to the Notion of absolute freedom, since they did not know that man as such, man as this universal ‘I’, as rational self-consciousness, is entitled to freedom. On the contrary, with them . . . freedom still had the character of a natural state” (E § 433A). 129 PS § 191/3, 152: “The outcome is a recognition that is one-sided and unequal.” 130 Cf. PS § 197/3, 155: “For the independent self-consciousness it is only the pure abstraction of the ‘I’ that is its essential nature, and, when it does develop its own differences, this differentiation does not become a nature that is objective and intrinsic to it. Thus this self-consciousness does not become an ‘I’ that . . . in this absolute differentiation remains identical with itself.” 131 Klaus Hartmann referred to this feature of the dialectic as issuing in a (categorial, conceptual) “novum” (novelty): see Hartmann, 1972b; 1999, pp. 58–59, 61.
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
163
The object generally has been appropriated by the emancipated slave and with it he has transformed his immediate naturalness into skills and virtues. The slave is now master of his desires as well as homo faber. But he has also internalized the master’s self-consciousness and thereby transformed it into a self that has taken possession of its object-consciousness and thus of nature generally in his own right. As a result, self-consciousness has now become a fulfilled self that in the object relates to itself. Or again, object-consciousness and self-consciousness are non-tautologically united in one self-referential self-consciousness. The previous opposition of a dependent servile self and an independent but “hollow” self of the master has been replaced by a self-consciousness that is master over itself and its object. Hegel somewhat unexpectedly claims that the new shape of self-consciousness expresses the thinking relationship between subject and object (cf. PS § 197/3, 156). This is a significant moment in the development of the Phenomenology’s argument that calls for further comment, not least because Hegel’s philosophy as a whole makes much of the contrast between thought or thinking (Denken) and representation or representing (Vorstellung or Vorstellen). Whereas representation is closely connected with the (external) opposition of consciousness, thinking in Hegel’s view marks the cognitive relationship between the object qua immanent in thought and the thinking self and must therefore be regarded as a milestone in the development of the argument. First, however, how do we explain the fact that a cognitive relationship is supposed to emerge from what seems to have been primarily a practical relationship between the slave and the object of his labor? Hegel’s text is of no great help in this respect and unfortunately the later Encyclopedia Phenomenology starts to take a different path after the master-slave dialectic, leading to a position called Universal Self-Consciousness and finally issuing in two very short sections on Reason that make the transition to the Encyclopedia Psychology.132 Moreover, in the Encyclopedia the transition from representation to thinking is given a systematic place in the Psychology chapter right at the end of theoretical spirit before the discussion moves on to practical spirit.133 Systematically speaking, therefore, there does not exist a strict parallelism between the Phenomenology’s introduction of the concept of thinking and that of the Encyclopedia, independently of the fact that what Hegel means by thought and representation, respectively, did not undergo any significant changes between the Phenomenology and the Encyclopedia. I believe the clue to understanding why Hegel feels justified in moving from the emancipated slave to the cognitive mode of thinking lies in the fact that the slave has overcome desire as a primary motivation for action. For this reason, his relation to the object is free from appetitive attachment, i.e. it is in effect a contemplative or theoretical attitude, albeit one towards life. It would therefore be correct to say that we have reached a synthesis of theory and practice beyond their mere opposition. In the light of the historical examples Hegel is about to introduce now, this interpretation seems to make eminent sense, as we shall see shortly.
132 Cf. 133 Cf.
E §§ 436–439. E §§ 464–468.
164
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
Of thinking Hegel says that it does not mean to have oneself for object as an abstract ‘I’, but as an ‘I’ which at the same time has the meaning of an in-itself; or again, to think means to relate to objective being in such a way that the latter has the significance of the being-for-self of that consciousness for which it exists (PS § 197/3, 156; my translation).
Thinking is fundamentally a relation to self, Hegel tells us, i.e. a relationship within an immanence. In all it does, thinking has essentially itself for object. However, the content of thinking is a substantial content, one that “has the meaning of an in-itself” and of “objective being” for thinking. In other words, the object of thinking is like thinking in that it claims the same independence, i.e. the same self-relatedness, that the self of thinking claims for itself – and it does so for thinking. But this is just to say that, for Hegel, thinking as such is objective, because it has translated the object into thought determinations that claim to be valid independently of the fact that they are being thought by someone. Thinking can therefore neither be “merely subjective” nor empty. It is objective in the sense of an objectladen theoria, to coin a phrase. But it is also objective in the sense that its object has been conceptualized in its independent being-for-self. If it is correct to say that thinking grasps the inner nature of things, the object’s in-itself or essence is not only an in-itself for consciousness, or relatively, but is an in-itself considered in and of itself, or absolutely. By contrast with the earlier section of Consciousness, the object’s being-for-another has now become part of its own essential determination. This was, we may remember, the point of the inverted-world argument and the transformation of difference into an inner difference. The object of thinking thus contains difference within itself as part of its concept, or it contains determination intrinsically, and this is exactly why we can now say that for thinking the object is in and of itself an objectively determined object – but only for thinking is this so, not yet for sensation, perception, or the understanding. The object’s determinateness belongs to it in virtue of itself or intrinsically (per se, kath’ hauto, an und für sich), not only to the way it presents itself to another.134 That the object present itself and be known as it is determined in and of itself or intrinsically and not only by a determination that it exhibits in relation to an other is what is generally meant by objectivity and objective knowledge. Hence when we believe we know that something is objectively the case we say “This is how things are” – not just how we believe them to be. To know something to be objectively true is to know it independently of a particular perspective or “take”. Again, Hegel’s point here is that such independent objectivity exists for consciousness qua thought. Thinking for Hegel is inherently objective. Furthermore, the thing could not be genuinely known, as opposed to known superficially or through mere familiarity or acquaintance with it, if its intrinsic determination were not known. Its intrinsic determination can, however, be known only when the object presents itself 134 It should be noted, however, that in their traditional meaning per se and kath’ hauto do not include the “inner difference”. They are supposed to be tautologically identical to themselves and hence suffer the fate of the atomic essences, as we saw in the chapter on Perception.
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
165
to thinking as it exists in itself, i.e. not only as it exists for an other. As long as the in-itself is “a mode in which the object is only for an other” (PS § 166/3, 137) as was the case throughout the chapter on Consciousness, the in-itself necessarily lacks intrinsic determination. Consequently, the object of sense-certainty, perception, and the understanding cannot be known objectively, or it cannot be known, period, if knowledge is “science” and knowledge and objective knowledge are one and the same thing. And yet, to be known also means to be known by someone. There is thus an irreducible, indeed a crucial, element of “subjectivity” involved in the concept of objectivity. Hegel’s point is that thinking is that subjectivity in relation to which the object reveals itself as it is in and of itself, because in this cognitive mode the nature of what is called reality is the same as its conceptual content. Thinking therefore is by definition categorial, i.e. it provides the categories that define the nature of things or reality in general. This is why Hegel characterizes truth not as the agreement of representation and object but as agreement of an object with its own concept. Truth is the result of an evaluative judgment.135 To the extent, however, that we are here still speaking of a relation between object and subject, the objective knowledge thus achieved continues to be marked by an opposition, albeit now an opposition internal to thinking. We have here a tangible clue as to why the argument of the Phenomenology continues even after the typical opposition of consciousness, viz. that of “ordinary consciousness”, has been overcome. The reason is that even after the immanence of the real in thought has been established an opposition continues to exist between the conceptual content of thinking and the thinking self itself. The “I” that is the object in this relation to itself called thinking, is at first a self only implicitly or in form, not in content. This is why the object pole of the self will continue to have the meaning of an objectconsciousness that remains distinguishable from the pure relation of self to self, even though this “object-I” is of the same conceptual structure as the self. It is only when the object pole itself has manifestly become a self that this internal opposition, too, will have been superseded. To achieve this goal constitutes the methodological agenda of the remainder of the Phenomenology. The same point can also be made in a different way. The fact that consciousness is distinguishable from self-consciousness can also be attributed to consciousness’ necessary particularity. Consciousness is also always a consciousness, a tode ti. As such, it represents the existential substrate of spirit’s reality, the form in which thinking and spirit exist and are active. Thought, reason, and spirit are not abstractions
135 Cf. E § 24A2: “Usually we call truth the agreement of an object with our representation of it. Thus we have an object as a presupposition, and our representation is supposed to conform to it. – In the philosophical sense, by contrast, truth means in general the agreement of a content with itself, to put it abstractly. Consequently, this is a meaning of truth entirely different from the one just mentioned. Incidentally, the deeper (i.e. philosophical) meaning of truth can already be found to some extent in the ordinary use of language. Thus, for instance, we speak of a true friend and mean by that someone whose way of acting conforms to the concept of friendship. Similarly, we speak of a true work of art. Untrue then means as much as bad, something in itself inadequate.”
166
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
for Hegel precisely because they must be embodied to be actual, and the primary locus or substratum of their embodiment is consciousness, as we shall see at the beginning of the Phenomenology’s chapter on Spirit.136 The Phenomenology reconstructs the appearance of spirit as actuality in its existential substrate called consciousness. As long, therefore, as consciousness retains an aspect of particularity that does not serve as such a substrate the process of its “purification” will continue.137 That the opposition of consciousness has now been internalized means that the new form of self-consciousness represents “an ‘I’ which has the otherness within itself” (PS § 200/3, 158). But the “I” that has otherness, or its object generally, within itself is synonymous with the activity of thinking, as we just saw. So Hegel can now also identify the communion via the object of the self with itself in thinking with the idea of freedom, since freedom is essentially a relation of self to an other insofar as the other is the same as the self or another self: In thinking, I am free, because I am not in an other, but remain simply and solely in communion with myself, and the object, which is for me the essential being, is in undivided unity my being-for-myself; and my moving among concepts is a moving within myself (PS § 197/3, 156; modified after Miller).
Here again Hegel’s specific understanding of thinking and thought comes to the fore. Thinking is not about referentiality, not about attaching a thought (such as a predicate) to a subject existing extra-linguistically, represented by my “idea” of it. Instead, thinking concerns the internal “fit” between the concept of the subject and the predicate, or the question whether the predicate adequately captures the nature of the subject and whether the subject’s nature is worth capturing. It is apparent that the significance of this new level of cognition called thinking lies in the fact that the external opposition of consciousness has been left behind in favor of the immanence of the object in thought, an immanence that constitutes the object’s objectivity. Hegel therefore takes the opportunity to contrast thinking with representing (Vorstellen) or “picture thinking”, as it is sometimes called.138 Representational thinking, as we might call it, is nothing mysterious, however. First of all, it has little to do with “thinking in pictures”. The key feature of representational thinking consists in the fact that it is representational, i.e. that it presupposes the external opposition of consciousness or the referentiality of thought: What is pictured or represented [e.g. by an ‘idea’ in the mind], what immediately is, has, as such, the form of being something other than consciousness (ibid.).
136 This seems to ignore that thought, reason, and spirit for Hegel also exist in nature as such, e.g. in the mechanics of the solar system, the chemistry of inorganic and organic compounds, the metabolism of the bioshpere, and the animal organism. These latter are, however, essentially the substrates of the living Idea rather than independent realities. 137 The Phenomenology can therefore also be read as an account of the structures that are necessary for the comprehensive embodiment of spirit: see the illuminating study by John Russon, 1997. 138 Miller also uses “to conceive figuratively” here (cf. PS § 197, p. 120).
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
167
By contrast, when focusing on the noematic content of thinking consciousness remains immediately aware of its unity with this determinate and distinct being, not, as in the case of representational thought, where consciousness still has specially to bear in mind that this is its representation [i.e. that the representation differs from what is represented]; on the contrary, the concept [sc. of the object] is for me straightaway my concept (ibid.; modified after Miller).
Representational thinking is predicated on the hiatus between mind and world, self and other, or form and content of knowledge. It is therefore “subjective” in the sense of being perspectival. It upholds a difference between what exists for consciousness or for another and what exists in-itself. Remembering Hegel’s remark that philosophy begins only after the opposition of consciousness has been overcome,139 we can see how significant the achievement of the position of thinking is. In thinking, we “connect” immediately with the object as it is in and of itself, and we can connect with it precisely because the object and the concept of the object are synonymous and as such are part of the immanence of thought. The object therefore does not need to be represented by an intermediary such as an idea, image, or other representational content at all. Instead of being an object in its own right, the representation becomes a completely transparent sign for thinking. These comments also make it clear that thinking, taken as a specific cognitive mode that is distinct from sensing, perceiving, and representing (which latter we might also describe as the attempt to “figure things out”, i.e. not yet to know or understand them), is the basis of that “pure science” which, as Hegel put it in the Introduction to the Science of Logic, contains thought in so far as this is just as much the object in its own self, or the object in its own self in so far as it is equally pure thought (SL 49/WdL I 30).
It will no longer come as a surprise when Hegel continues that “as science, truth is pure self-consciousness in its self-development and has the shape of the self” (ibid.). Taking this parallel with the Introduction to the Science of Logic to heart we should say that in the development of the Phenomenology we have now arrived at the standpoint of the Logic itself. This is a puzzling result since the Phenomenology as a whole is supposed to lead us to that standpoint. I suggest, therefore, that we distinguish between the standpoint of the Logic and the standpoint of the system as a whole. Although it is true that Hegel’s system begins with the Logic, the two starting-points have different implications and hence differ in what they presuppose. The Logic presupposes the overcoming of the opposition of consciousness, but the system as a whole presupposes the overcoming of the opposition between “the reason that is conscious of itself,” i.e. the Logic, and “the reason that exists or possesses actuality” (E § 6) as well. Insofar as the Phenomenology is supposed to lay the foundation for the system as a whole, its argument at this point is indeed far from having 139 “These [sc. representationalist or referentialist] views on the relation of subject and object to each other express the determinations which constitute the nature of our ordinary, phenomenal consciousness; . . . as they bar the entrance to philosophy, [they] must be discarded at its portals” (SL 45/WdL I 25).
168
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
reached its goal. To put it differently, while we have now achieved the immanence of theoria, the appropriation of the actuality of reason or spirit from this position of immanence poses itself as the next task. Still, must not the question be raised nonetheless how thinking could possibly determine whether its thoughts have objective validity and truth if there is no checking of truth claims against an independent standard, criterion, or state of affairs? Does not truth become a matter of stipulation, consensus, or convention and to that extent arbitrary? The answer to these serious concerns will have to come in two parts. First, as we saw earlier, the representational model of cognition either begs the question or it leads to radical skepticism, unless it is embedded in a normative framework of cognition. The role of the fundamental categories of thought in constituting the basic structure of what we even mean by reality – in all its various forms of things, properties, events, appearance and underlying essence, substance, cause, effect, sensations, emotions, persons, community, society, art, actions, good and bad, just and unjust, etc. – is indispensable, if we want to hold on to a viable concept of objectivity. If we do not want to attribute an arbitrary or contingent meaning to these terms or to qualify their validity as merely conventional, we cannot justify their correct use by the same procedure through which we establish facts without becoming involved in a vicious circle. Kant’s dictum applies that such concepts or conceptual schemes must be accounted for independently of experience (in the sense of empirical knowledge). Second, because adherence to the fundamental principles of formal logical validity such as the PNC is insufficient to justify material claims, those concepts or conceptual schemes must have an a priori content of their own that thought must be able to extract. These concepts cannot be mere forms into which a heterogeneous content is imported and then organized in accordance with the requirements of human receptivity. In an attempt to preserve both the a priori nature of the categories and yet secure objective reality for them, Kant had adopted the latter procedure. Hegel, as we saw in Chapter 2, had criticized this dual-source model of cognition because it repeated the representationalist error at a higher level. It could therefore be said that Hegel’s argument in favor of the immanence of thought so far wins by default. But he still owes us an explanation as to how the extraction of the contents of those concepts can be effected in a controlled way and why the contents of those fundamental thought determinations is not merely presupposed in all of consciousness’ experience. The answer to the first question is obviously the dialectic. The explanation concerning the ultimate origin of the content of thought is answered by Hegel by saying that thinking generates this content out of itself. How it can do so is a question for our next chapter. Let us conclude this methodological interlude by saying that the categoriality of thinking has now been established as a general principle. Again, this does not mean, however, that the identity of thought and actuality has already been established. Consciousness will learn this the hard way during the Reason chapter. The connection between emancipated slave consciousness, thinking, and freedom helps to understand Hegel’s characterization of this new stance of (self-)consciousness as that of ancient Stoicism (cf. PS § 198/3, 157). For Stoicism typically asserts that through the power of thinking alone man can achieve the
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
169
highest happiness called apathia, i.e. complete composure of one’s inner being or imperturbable equanimity attained through freedom from affects. It is as if by dint of mere reasoning the core of one’s being could be detached or decoupled from one’s emotional life, and the influence of the latter on the former neutralized or rendered ineffective by sheer rationalization – an extreme form of ethical intellectualism. This unrealistic attitude of radical detachment is also reflected in the proverbial composure with which the Stoic is supposed to endure all life’s vicissitudes as well as its moments of happiness and to withdraw completely into the identity with his thinking self such that for this consciousness “whether on the throne or in chains . . . its aim is to be free” (PS § 199/3, 157). With unmistakable critical undertones Hegel describes this attitude as one of “lifeless indifference which steadfastly withdraws from the bustle of existence, alike from being active as passive, into the simple essentiality of thought” (ibid.). Everything becomes an adiaphoron for this consciousness or, rather, the Stoic’s (object-) consciousness becomes an adiaphoron for his self-consciousness, since nothing has intrinsic value independently of its relation to this self which, at this point and indeed until the end of the chapter on Reason, retains a particularity within the unity of consciousness and self-consciousness, or “I” = “I”. Because everything lacks an intrinsic value of its own, nothing makes a difference. The only value that may attach to something is the fact that thinking has reduced it to something indifferent: Essential importance no longer attaches to the difference as a specific thing, or as consciousness of a specific natural existence, as a feeling, or as desire and its object . . . What alone has importance is the difference posited by thought . . . (PS § 199/3, 157).
To paraphrase Epictetus, the Stoic should ignore entirely what is not in his power and abstain from desiring that which is in his power.140 The Stoic, one might say, develops an aesthetic attitude towards life in the sense so felicitously characterized by Kant as one of disinterested pleasure (or displeasure, as the case may be).141 While this characterizes well the emotional attitude involved in the contemplation of a work of art, it is obviously a recipe for disaster when applied to the vicissitudes of life. Despite having emancipated himself the Stoic in a sense remains a slave. He is a master of himself and the world in thought only, but not in actuality. The inner structure of the Stoic consciousness is therefore one that has “the otherness within itself” (PS § 200/3, 158), but only as an abstraction, as an objectivity without determinacy. And yet, did we not say that the emancipated self-consciousness is a fulfilled self, one that relates to itself non-tautologically? This is indeed the case, except that the self to which the Stoic self relates is a non-descript other without specificity – it is a fulfilled self only potentially, not in actuality. As a result, the freedom of this self is a theoretical freedom only, one which “lacks the fullness of life” (PS § 200/3, 158). Freedom “in thought” is “only the Notion of freedom, not the 140 Cf.
Epictetus, Encheiridion I 1. Kant, CJ V 209–211. A judgment of taste, says Kant, is “merely contemplative” and “indifferent” towards the existence or non-existence of the object. 141 See
170
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
living reality of freedom itself” (ibid.). Methodologically speaking, in relating to an as yet indeterminate self/other self-consciousness likewise does not recognize itself in its object-consciousness. There is therefore present a “twofold reflection” (cf. ibid.). The Stoic self withdraws from the world into the pure identity with itself again and, due to this withdrawal, which in effect is equivalent to being in denial, lets the “natural existence” to which it is indifferent “equally go free” (ibid.). It thus rejects its object-consciousness instead of appropriating it. It fails to “grasp the living world as a system of thought” in its thinking (ibid., my italics). The negation of the otherness of the other is “thus only the incomplete negation of otherness” (PS § 201/3, 159). In everything this consciousness sees only a shadow – and thus reduces itself to a shadow as well. Out of this twilight of thought there emerges the “polemical” mind of the Skeptic (PS § 202/3, 159). Like Stoicism, Skepticism is not merely a theory but a philosophy that aims to be a lifestyle. Unlike Stoicism, however, it is aware of the conflict that exists between saying that nothing counts for anything until and unless it has been approved or disapproved by thought and foregoing the labor of a detailed examination of beliefs and the reasons given for them. Skepticism thus becomes “the actual experience of what the freedom of thought is” (ibid.), albeit of its abstract, merely negative freedom. Where Stoicism recommended the wholesale rejection of the influence of experience and beliefs on the mind, the Skeptic advocates “the concrete thinking which annihilates the being of the world in all its manifold determinateness” (ibid.). It is precisely by arguing against any reasons that would support a given positive belief that skeptical consciousness neutralizes the force of reasoning. It refutes all reasons in order to affirm its rationality. It thus reproduces its merely negative independence again and again as a reasoning self for which no specific reason makes a difference: Through this self-conscious negation it produces for its own self the certainty of its freedom, generates the experience of that freedom, and thereby raises it to truth (PS § 204/3, 160–161).
Hegel calls this “the dialectical movement” (PS § 203/3, 160) of Skeptical consciousness whose result is the dissolution of all specific difference on one hand and the empty satisfaction of its own negativity on the other. We know that historically Skepticism achieved this satisfaction by making inventories – so-called tropes – of reasons for and against a given belief to which it then applied the principle of equipollence that says that for any claim both reasons for and reasons against its truth can be found. This procedure, however, has a curious consequence – it carries within itself its own refutation. If it is assumed that any claim may both be affirmed and denied with equal force, then even to start formulating claims becomes a futile business. The outcome of such an endeavor is known beforehand, viz. that no claim can survive scrutiny and consequently no substantive claim can ever be justified. More importantly, however, to accept this outcome as truth would mean to admit that reasoning and arguing as such are futile undertakings because they can always be shown to lead to nothing – a direct contradiction of the essence of Skeptical selfconsciousness that needs to busy itself with refuting claims. Consequently, while
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
171
the mental limbo produced by practicing the principle of equipollence in one sense leads to the desired outcome for Skeptical consciousness, in another it is unwelcome. For on one hand the principle of equipollence has the effect of producing the attitude of withholding judgment, i.e. the epoch¯e that brings peace of mind or ataraxia; but on the other the Skeptic cannot really enjoy this fruit of his intellectual labor because it denies him the pleasure of actively rebuffing specific claims. What is worse, permanent enjoyment of the state of epoch¯e would be equivalent to Stoic apathia whose intellectual “tediousness” (PS § 200/3, 159) must annoy the Skeptic. Skeptical self-consciousness thus cannot find peace of mind in a permanent withholding of judgment nor can it cease to try to do so. Quite unavoidably therefore, it is thrown into the “dizziness” and “restless confusion” of a “perpetually selfengendered disorder” and an “unconscious, thoughtless rambling” (PS § 205/3, 161). It vacillates between two identities, one a self that withholds judgment and has lifted itself up above the hustle and bustle of the world and the wrongheaded, futile beliefs of mankind, the other a polemical self that busies itself pedantically with the refutation of those futile beliefs and thus admits that it takes them very seriously indeed: At one time it recognizes that its freedom lies in rising above all the confusion and contingency of existence, and at another time it equally admits to a relapse into occupying itself with what is unessential. It lets the unessential content in its thinking vanish; but just in doing so it is the consciousness of something unessential (ibid.).
The contradiction is intrinsic to this self-consciousness and hence it cannot be overcome by its own resources. It develops into a split consciousness that wavers between Stoic “unchangeableness” on one hand and “utter contingency and nonidentity with itself” (ibid.) on the other. Like a schizophrenic consciousness this thoughtless thinking “keeps the poles of this self-contradiction apart” and denies that there might be a problem with its logic. It behaves like “the squabbling of selfwilled children” who “by contradicting themselves buy for themselves the pleasure of continually contradicting one another” (PS § 205/3, 162–163). The rejection of reason and reasonableness by a consciousness whose essence is reasoning and argumentation can hardly be the basis for a consistent lifestyle and so we are not surprised to hear that in the wake of its Skeptical experience the Pyrrhonist would relapse into living the unexamined life again, “following natural inclinations, immediate experience, and the laws and customs of his society without ever judging or committing himself to any view about them.”142 While the Skeptic thus cures himself of his theoretical schizophrenia by entering into a state of amnesia the problem itself, as always with Hegel, is not a contingent problem. Instead, it indicates one of the fundamental experiences of human consciousness that, because it is a thinking consciousness, can neither return to the Stoic lifestyle which it has already seen to be wanting in intellectual consistency nor accept the ridiculous alternative of adopting a false identity. Consequently, Skeptical consciousness must confront the fact of its incompatible identities and respond to this experience. Acknowledging 142 See
Audi, 1995, s.v. skepticism.
172
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
its “inwardly disrupted” state (PS § 207/3, 163), Skeptical consciousness is transformed into the unhappy consciousness, a self that rather than trying to escape it is painfully aware of its inner division. Unhappy Consciousness marks one of those chapters in the Phenomenology that in addition to the breathtaking boldness of their argument show Hegel’s mastery at bringing out the drama of human existence in ways no less poignant and touching than the drama of ancient tragedies. Other such passages include the ones on the lifeand-death struggle, the clash of divine and human law exemplified in Antigone’s experience, the French Revolution and the Reign of Terror, and the chapter on Forgiveness. The chapter on the Unhappy Consciousness contains Hegel’s analysis of the human experience of participating concomitantly in the two realms of finitude and transcendence. It thus poses the question as to the true homeland of the human spirit, and since the answer to this question has traditionally been given by religion this chapter also lays the foundation for Hegel’s interpretation of the meaning of man’s religious experience. Methodologically speaking, the task consists in establishing the true ground of individual self-consciousness by trying to reconcile man’s two identities as they have emerged during consciousness’ preceding struggle for freedom and independence. The conflict between finitude and transcendence does not appear out of the blue. It has been in the making ever since the duplication of self-consciousness prior to the life-and-death struggle. At first it took the form of the individual vs. the species or genus, then that of the master’s vs. the slave’s self-consciousness, the one choosing freedom over life, the other life over freedom. Both were unified in the Stoic self-consciousness which, however, already implicitly contained the new duplication of the Skeptic’s two identities. In discussing the Skeptic, Hegel had introduced those two identities under the titles of a “consciousness of unchangeableness and sameness” and of “utter contingency and non-identity” (PS § 205/3, 162). While for the Skeptic these were two self-consciousnesses held together in a tenuous unity only by a continuous vacillation between them, for the unhappy consciousness they are now two forms of one self-consciousness, or two essential and opposed aspects of the self within a single self that Hegel names the (“simple”) “Unchangeable” and the (“protean”) “Changeable” (PS § 208/3, 164), respectively. In becoming aware of the contradictory nature of these two selves the unhappy consciousness has the structure of a self-consciousness that unlike that of the Skeptic is fully aware of two mutually exclusive identities. Methodologically speaking, the exclusionary relationship between the two selves in Skeptical self-consciousness has been sharpened into an inner contradiction between two essential determinations, similar to the earlier inverted world scenario. Not only is this situation untenable, it is also seemingly impossible to overcome. If we take this talk of identity seriously, as we must, then, since something cannot lose its identity without ceasing to be what it is, unhappy consciousness cannot simply suppress, reject, or eliminate either one of its identities. As Hegel puts it: Here . . . we have a struggle against an enemy, to vanquish whom is really to suffer defeat, where victory in one consciousness is really lost in its opposite (PS § 209/3, 164).
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
173
We know by now that the ensuing dialectic will lead to a new unifying framework in which both identities can find a place, but which will favor one identity slightly over the other and thus essentially transform the other identity as well. As usual, Hegel organizes the argument in Unhappy Consciousness in a series of three cycles each of which contains another triad within itself. Viewed in terms of its logical underpinnings, the progression of the argument can be seen to consist in giving the “I” of Skeptical self-consciousness a concrete filling. Skeptical self-consciousness was split up into two identities whose contradictory nature led to the “restless confusion” of “rising above” contingency (transcendence) and “falling back again into it” (finitude), as Hegel put it at PS § 205/3, 161–162. However, because the incompatibility of the two states of consciousness was not recognized by Skeptical self-consciousness as the “restless confusion” it in fact is, the Skeptical “I” merely provided an otherwise empty enclosure for this back and forth movement. The self of Skeptical consciousness cannot therefore mediate between the two and begin to reconcile itself to both of them. This, however, the unhappy consciousness must do because it is a self-reflective consciousness. Roughly speaking, its challenge consists in finding the proper mediator that could combine both identities in one unified self-consciousness. Or again, what consciousness will be looking for is a convincing synthesis of finitude and transcendence. As far as the logical schema of the argument is concerned, Hegel relies on the three-fold structure of the syllogism in which all three positions, i.e. terminus major, minor, and medius, are occupied once by each “moment” of the Notion or Concept, i.e. individuality (I), particularity (P), and universality (U). Schematically speaking, the three cycles therefore obey the following pattern: I–P–U, U–I–P, and P–U–I, respectively.143 In other words, the unhappy consciousness qua unity of the Unchangeable and the Changeable successively takes the positions of terminus medius, minor, and major, and so do its two identities, viz. the Unchangeable and the Changeable. Through this process, each term acquires the aspects to which it was previously opposed and so strictly speaking they all become identical. Except that the process as a whole unfolds as one that exists for consciousness and is thus experienced as a real, indeed historical, story. For this reason, even though we are clearly moving within an immanence of self-consciousness now – after all, the story is one of religious experience, and physical events have lost their immediate meaning and assumed a spiritual significance instead – there remains an internal opposition between individual consciousness and its true ground. Since for our purposes it is not necessary to follow every turn of Hegel’s argument, we will briefly recapitulate the argument of the first cycle and then go straight to the core of the chapter located in the second cycle. Nor can we detail the implied references in this text which is saturated with historical connotations. It will suffice to mention that the three cycles roughly correspond to the Jewish experience
143 For a brief account of the three moments of the Notion or Concept see E § 163 (in the GeraetsSuchting-Harris translation singularity is used instead of individuality). The permutations of the three-fold syllogistic structure are illustrated in a helpful way at E § 198 with reference to the state.
174
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
as it is narrated in the Old Testament (the chosen people and its jealous God), the New Testament story of the advent of Christ and the emergence of a trinitarian God (especially the experience of the presence of Christ followed by the shock of discovering his empty grave), and, thirdly, the contradictions of medieval religiosity with its utter devotion on one hand, its secular debauchery and concomitant selfcastigation on the other and the institutionalization of a church hierarchy as mediator between the sinful human believer and the graceful but remote divine power.144 It is worth mentioning in parenthesis that Hegel gives credit to the Jewish religion for confronting for the first time man’s spiritual struggle with his dual nature as embodied transcendence. Hegel thus acknowledges that the existential drama depicted in the Old Testament and the fervent desire for a resolution of this dualism through redemption and divine recognition marks one of the highpoints in the history of the human spirit. Unhappy consciousness, then, as “consciousness of self as a dual-natured, merely contradictory being” (PS § 206/3, 163) must mediate between finitude and transcendence, must reconcile the contradiction between its contingent and its eternal self. And yet, it cannot do so “because it is itself the consciousness of this contradiction” and therefore “identifies itself with the changeable consciousness, and takes itself to be the unessential Being” (PS § 208/3, 164). From mediating between the two, unhappy consciousness thus moves immediately to an opposition between itself qua contingent and unworthy self and an “alien Being” (ibid.) over against it, the objectification of its own transcendent self. Still, since it knows the Unchangeable to be “its own essence” it must likewise “set about freeing itself from the unessential, i.e. from itself” (ibid.). In the attempt to do so, however, it makes the “agonizing” experience that its existence and activity fill it with the “consciousness of its own nothingness” and bring home to it the fact that “its essence is only its opposite” (PS § 209/3, 164). It must thus deny an essential part of itself while it tries to find itself in the other – it cannot “come to rest in its opposite, but in it only produces itself afresh as an opposite” (PS § 208/3, 164). This antagonistic relationship is resolved only by a kind of truce. The unhappy consciousness raises itself out of its misery and “goes over into the Unchangeable” (PS § 209/3, 165) – an “elevation” (ibid.) that produces a special relationship between itself and the alien Being, which thereby becomes an individual, personal God who enters into an exclusive covenant with his chosen people and guides it into the Promised Land.145 The dialectic leading to the second cycle of the experience of the unhappy consciousness is condensed into just a few lines (cf. the beginning of PS § 212/3, 166) and would have been much more convincing, if Hegel had done his readers the favor to elaborate. Because the thought of individuality has entered into the unchangeable consciousness, there opens up an opposition between its universality and its individuality. Due to the dual nature of this consciousness, this opposition is likewise reflected in its other – the
144 For
other implicit references to Schleiermacher etc. see Falke 1996, 177–184. § 209/3, 165: “The Unchangeable that enters into consciousness is through this very fact at the same time affected by individuality . . ..” Moses’ meeting with God on Mount Sinai might be an appropriate allusion. 145 PS
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
175
idea of God the son as distinct from God the father has emerged. Hegel rationalizes the contingent fact of the appearance of Christ at a particular moment in time by viewing it as the flipside of the division within religious consciousness that is as yet unable to unify its universal, law-abiding self with its contingent, individual self. As a result, “the fact that the Unchangeable receives the form of individuality is only a contingent happening” (ibid.). The contingent historical moment of the birth of Christ has thus received its speculative blessing. It is important to realize that this event implies not just the individuality but the actual individuation of the divine power, i.e. the incarnation of God in human shape.146 Clearly, this absolute event represents the consummate synthesis of finitude and transcendence, human and divine, and as such the culmination of the argument. However, the advent of the divine in human form is also a turning point that leads to the dissolution of this synthesis. For the unhappy consciousness finds it difficult to believe that the unity of the finite and the infinite could ever exist in sensuous, bodily form in space and time. And it seems indeed a preposterous thought that the divine should become a sensible, finite reality, not only in appearance but “in the flesh”, i.e. not just symbolically but “in actuality” so that the essence of Jesus is to be divine and the essence of Christ to be human, contingent, and finite.147 That the “referent” of these two mutually exclusive and internally or intensionally contradictory descriptions should be one and the same, therein is encapsulated the paradox of faith. So while unhappy consciousness recognizes itself in the son of God, it also “confronts him as an opaque sensuous unit with all the obstinacy of what is actual” (ibid.).148 The opacity of Christ, the visible person, is no doubt the direct reflex of his unity with God, the Father, who continues to be the “alien Being” as the one who remains in the transcendent “beyond” (ibid.) and does not become incarnate. Despite the fact, then, that the unhappy consciousness does “find itself in the Unchangeable” (ibid.) through Christ, there persists an unbridgeable gap between the human and the divine, and “the hope of becoming one with it [sc. God] must remain a hope, i.e. without fulfillment and present fruition” (ibid.). The paradox of the factual unity of human and divine being, of finitude and transcendence, is the reason why the actual unio mystica is postponed until a Second Coming and the divine “remains utterly remote” (ibid.).149 Because the parousia of the divine has occurred as a fact, the relationship between consciousness and “the
146 Hegel speaks of an “immediately present One,” a One that has being (seiendes Eins, PS § 212/3,
167; modified). 147 We may again be reminded of the logical configuration underlying the inverted world here. 148 Hence the debates during the formative stages of Christian theology about the trinity and the true nature of Christ, in particular whether Christ was supposed to be essentially God himself (homoousios, same essence) or of the same nature as God but with a separate identity (homoiousios) or merely a human symbol of God (homoios, like or similar). Similarly, it needed to be determined whether the real person Jesus was entirely divine in nature (monophysitism) or of a dual essence (dyophysitism). 149 PS § 212/3, 167: “By the nature of this immediately present unit, through the actual existence in which it has clothed itself, it necessarily follows that in the world of time it has vanished, and that in space it had a remote existence and remains utterly remote.”
176
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
incarnate Unchangeable” (PS § 213/3, 167) has assumed an external quality and has become an “alien reality” (ibid.) for it which it must now try to retrieve: . . . its efforts from now on are directed . . . to setting aside its relation with the pure formless Unchangeable, and to coming into relation only with the Unchangeable in its embodied or incarnate form. For the oneness of the particular individual with the Unchangeable is henceforth the essence and the object for this consciousness . . . (PS § 213/3, 167).
As a result, the happiness of the unhappy consciousness is postponed indefinitely until the end of time, and there begins the long journey through the vale of tears under the guidance of the church.150 Nonetheless, the third cycle of consciousness’ experience does lead to a reconciliation of its two identities, even if this is only a solution ad interim. The unhappy consciousness has successively made the experience that neither itself nor the “divine Man” (PS § 784/3, 570) can effect “the reconciliation of its individuality with the universal” (PS § 210/3, 165). Indeed, as we shall see, this part of the argument of the Phenomenology will not conclude until and unless individual consciousness eventually brings about this reconciliation by itself. This moment will arrive with the resolution of the conflict between the “hard heart” and the confessing consciousness in the chapter on Forgiveness. In this sense, the outcome of the dialectic of the unhappy consciousness represents an interim solution that stretches to the end of Forgiveness and includes not only the long section on Reason but also the even longer section entitled Spirit that ends with Forgiveness. (It is only in the Revealed Religion section of the Religion chapter that the event of the Pentecost is understood to have been the definitive fulfillment of the union of human and divine.) It is therefore possible to view the reconciliation of consciousness’ individuality with the universality of spirit as the key to understanding the structure of the overall argument beginning with Self-Consciousness and ending only with the beginning of Religion. The beginning of Self-Consciousness marks the point at which the external “other” has been internalized by consciousness and the “original unity of self-consciousness” is made the sole foundation of the subsequent development. The end of Spirit, on the other hand, concludes the struggle for mutual recognition that grew out of the reinterpretation of the transcendental unity of apperception as life. The little word “henceforth” in the above quote from PS § 213/3, 167 can therefore be taken literally: From this point onward, the essence of consciousness’ struggle is to “set aside its relation with the pure formless Unchangeable, and to come into relation only with the Unchangeable in its embodied or incarnate form”. If this is a veiled reference to the act of mutual forgiveness, it remains to be seen what else needs to be revealed in the section on Religion that has not already been demonstrated at the end of Spirit and why having reached the reconciliation of individual
150 Kierkegaard may have found the paradox of faith analyzed here (and even more clearly at PS § 217/3, 168–170), but remained notoriously unhappy with Hegel’s solution (for Kierkegaard’s analysis see his Philosophical Fragments).
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
177
consciousness with spirit’s universality in Forgiveness Hegel cannot go straight to the concluding chapter on Absolute Knowing.151 What, then, does the interim reconciliation that is achieved at the end of Unhappy Consciousness look like, and where does consciousness go from there? Let us remember that the task at hand was for consciousness to reconcile and unify its two identities of finite, perishable human individual at the mercy of a contingent world over which it has no real control other than through thinking, and this same individual as endowed with a transcendent spirit in virtue of its essential nature as pure thought through which it participates in the divine. Obviously, if human consciousness did not share in the nature of the transcendent divine, its finitude and its impotence in the face of death could never become a problem for it. But neither can the finite individual as such simply become the divine, except in the shape of Christ who for that reason must also “necessarily” vanish again in the world of time and space (cf. PS § 212/3, 167) and withdraw into heaven where he takes his seat on the right hand of God from whence he shall come to judge the living and the dead.152 The remoteness of the divine therefore makes necessary a “temporary”, i.e. temporal, solution in the form of a mediator who relates both identities to one another by promising the eventual redemption of finitude in exchange for renunciation of the individual’s self-will.153 The fact that individual consciousness officially and publicly renounces its own will and thus gains the “certainty of having truly divested itself of its ‘I’” (PS § 229/3, 175–176) represents the crucial aspect of this reconciliation ad interim. In professing the unconditional surrender of its self-willed, “egoistic” life and actions to the will of the divine, individual consciousness at the same time receives its life back as a universal life with the blessings of the highest authority on earth. What the individual does will henceforth have universal significance as the expression of a universal thinking and willing. In the renunciation of its unessential being-for-self . . . there has arisen for consciousness the idea of Reason, of the certainty that, in its particular individuality, it has being absolutely in itself, or is all reality (PS § 230/3, 177).
That consciousness in its “particular individuality” should be “all reality” seems to be an extravagant, not to say preposterous claim. However, what Hegel means is that consciousness is now certain that what is real is rational and immediately intelligible by its own lights or that the world’s objective rationality is just a reflection of its own rationality and vice versa. It is in this spirit that it now approaches the world
151 Roughly, the answer to this question will be along the following lines: 1) “Consciousness” through “Spirit”: The immediate experience of consciousness of its gradual unification with spirit; 2) “Religion’: The concomitant reflective appropriation of this experience in the medium of representation; 3) “Absolute Knowing’: The resulting realization in thought of the identity of the immediate experience and its representational appropriation in religion. The result of the Phenomenology’s argument will thus be that the unification of consciousness’ finitude with spirit’s universality and infinity is first lived, then represented, and finally comprehended by thought. 152 I am paraphrasing the last lines of the Second Article of the Creed in Luther’s Small Catechism. 153 Cf. PS §§ 229–30/3, 175–177.
178
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
with renewed interest in order to appropriate and conquer it, at first theoretically, then practically: Now that self-consciousness is Reason, its hitherto negative relation to otherness turns round into a positive relation. Up till now it has been concerned only with its independence and freedom, concerned to save and maintain itself for itself at the expense of the world, or of its own actuality, both of which appeared to it as the negative of its essence. But as Reason, assured of itself, it is at peace with them, and can endure them; for it is certain that it is itself reality, or that everything actual is none other than itself . . . (PS § 232/3, 178–179).
In this combination of object-consciousness and self-consciousness, the individual self-consciousness becomes the protagonist of reason in a world which is in essence rational, both in the sense of exhibiting rational and hence intelligible structures and in the sense of offering no absolute resistance to its rational (re-)organization by the individual. What for Skeptical consciousness used to be merely contingent and unessential is here presumed to be subject to the laws and principles of reason. The “I = I” formula now stands for a subject that has achieved an affirmative instead of a merely negative relationship to the object immanent within itself. What Hegel describes here finds its historical expression in the renewed interest in the empirical world characteristic of the Renaissance and the beginning of modernity.154 Under the title of Observing Reason, consciousness will start to bring the world to concepts with the certainty that there is reason in beings, and that this reason is its own reason: [P]reviously it did not understand the world; it desired it and worked on it, withdrew from it into itself and abolished it as an existence on its own account . . . [now, however] it discovers the world is its new real world, which in its permanence holds an interest for it which previously lay only in its transiency; for the existence of the world becomes for selfconsciousness its own truth and presence; it is certain of experiencing only itself therein (PS § 232/3, 179).
Because the world is like a mirror held up to self-consciousness, it recognizes its own rationality therein (and deems irrational what it does not so recognize) and is in this sense “all reality”: Reason now has . . . a universal interest in the world, because it is certain of its presence in the world, or that the world present to it is rational. It seeks its ‘other’, knowing that therein it possesses nothing else but itself: it seeks only its own infinitude (PS § 240/3, 186).
In the following two sections on the Actualization of Self-Consciousness and the Individuality Which Takes Itself To Be Real In And For Itself, consciousness will actively appropriate this world in a practical sense, first by trying to find immediate satisfaction in the use and enjoyment of things, then by shaping the world in the image of its own rationality.155 154 I take it that Hegel attributes this stage of the unification of the transcendent and the finite to the Lutheran Reformation. If so, the birth of the scientific spirit of modernity is thus closely connected in Hegel’s mind with the this-wordly orientation of Luther’s spiritual revolution. Through faith, reason has been re-embodied in the world. 155 See sections B and C, PS §§ 347 ff./3, 263 ff. and §§ 394 ff./3, 292 ff., respectively.
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
179
Hegel calls this new attitude of self towards the world idealism.156 It is an attitude of feeling essentially at home in a world in which self-consciousness recognizes its own rationality. In more technical parlance, the world as phenomenon is now not only superseded or “idealized” (ideell gemacht) by being made dependent on some anonymous law such as gravity or eternal justice, both of which offer only partial interpretations of the behavior of things. It is viewed instead as the totality of the real that qua totality is amenable to a rational reconstruction. Idealism is therefore by definition holistic both ontologically and epistemologically. Earlier, we saw Hegel invoke idealism as a philosophical position that presupposes the overcoming of the opposition between finitude and the spurious infinite that is merely the ever receding limit of the finite. Systematically speaking, we have arrived at the same juncture in the Phenomenology, except that the opposition of finitude and infinity had already been internal to self-consciousness, and not as in Force and Understanding one between the sensible world and a transcendent inner being. The internality of the opposition explains why its unity is now called reason. Already during Hegel’s Jena period, reason was that mode of thought for which the oppositions between subject and object, appearance and thing-in-itself, finitude and infinity no longer hold good as we can see, for instance, in Faith and Knowledge.157 From the point of view of reason such oppositions arise because their original unity has been broken up by the analytical power of the understanding and contraries such as finitude and infinity have been isolated as if they could exist independently of their unifying context. As a result, solutions to antinomies of reason à la Kant are from a Hegelian perspective strictly speaking solutions to pseudo-problems. As we saw on the occasion of the inversion of the inverted world, Hegel’s fundamental methodological approach is characterized by the maxim that the original unity is primary and that oppositions are posterior, even though in the discursive progression of the dialectic the original unity seems to emerge as a solution to a contradiction. In truth, however, the original unity does not so much emerge from the preceding contradictions as it reemerges as their “teleological ground.”158 Reason, then, is that synthesis of finitude and transcendence, contingency and necessity, human and divine that the unhappy consciousness had been seeking. Individual consciousness can achieve this interim resolution of its unhappiness not by becoming this synthesis itself, but only by being commissioned to enact it as a mediator in this world, as the exponent and agent of
156 “Reason
is the certainty of consciousness that it is all reality; thus does idealism express its Notion” (PS § 233/3, 179). 157 See also SL 755/WdL II 407–408. 158 Teleological ground is Hegel’s translation of causa finalis: “ . . . by sufficient ground, Leibniz understood one that was also sufficient for this unity [of an existent being] and which therefore comprehended not merely [mechanical] causes, but final causes. . . . teleological ground is a property of the Notion and of mediation by the Notion, which is reason” (SL 446–447/WdL II 66). Hegel uses this expression to indicate the fact that what emerges at the end as the result of the dialectical process of derivation constitutes in truth the basis from which the derivation proceeds and to which it returns. Consequently, the progressive disclosure of new categories is in actuality the systematic reconstruction of their original unity.
180
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
a universal thinking and willing. In fact, when at a later stage individual consciousness will be pushed into the role of representing the immediate unity of particular individuality and the universal will (volonté générale), that experience will have disastrous consequences.159 It is only as a moment or member of the universal will – more precisely, of spirit – that individual consciousness can be said to represent it. It must be said, however, that Hegel’s comments so far on the new position of reason achieved by consciousness sound much like a perceptive description of the spirit of beginning modernity or like an apt characterization of the speculative aspects of the so-called Continental Rationalists, and much less like an argument. How is it possible, the reader may well ask, for Hegel to posit the existence of rational self-consciousness as the signature of the pre-Enlightenment period, let alone the existence of reason in the world? These look like massive stipulations for which no justification seems to be offered. The following answer may be given in response to these queries. As was said earlier, with the beginning of the chapter on SelfConsciousness the original unity of self-consciousness was made the foundation of the subsequent development. All new cognitive relationships between self and other, or subject and object, are consequently internal relationships between an object- and a self-consciousness within a self-consciousness (which subsequently develops into reason and spirit and then, finally, into absolute knowing). The new quality of the cognitive relationship called reason consists in the fact that the object-consciousness has now acquired the nature of self-consciousness not only formally but in terms of content as well. This does not mean that the internal other of self-consciousness is now itself an individual self-consciousness. For the latter constellation to occur we need again to wait until the section on Forgiveness. It does mean, however, that the object of this self-consciousness is understood as a self-contained totality with self-determining, self-organizing features. For an illustration we may think of the world systems proposed in particular by Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz.160 It is in their systems that Hegel recognizes the attempt at a rational reconstruction of reality as a whole. Their proposals to explain reality in terms of a unified mechanistic or, alternatively, a unified mechanistic and teleological system as well as a unified nature and spirit as with Spinoza or with Leibniz’ harmony between the metaphysical kingdom of nature and the moral kingdom of grace161 is testimony to the fact that thinking here rediscovers its own rationality in its object. And yet, we may still want to ask whether these systems are “true”. But true in what sense? Obviously, we cannot prove the existence of monads since they are not spatio-temporal objects. Still, one might say that Leibniz’ monadology does capture a genuine feature of reality, if we have reason to believe that among its fundamental traits are the absolute self-referentiality and the self-activation and thus the singularity and dynamic 159 See the Reign of Terror during the French Revolution (cf. PS §§ 582 ff./3, 431 ff., in particular §§ 587–92/3, 434–438). 160 Descartes’ self-contained universe of moving bodies, Spinoza’s singular substance, and Leibniz’ attempt to show the compatibility of mechanistic and teleological causality in one systematically unified universe of monads may serve as examples. 161 Cf. Leibniz, Monadology § 87.
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
181
nature of all individuated entities – nothing is really “dead” in Leibniz’ universe. To construct an entire metaphysics on this premise seems like a valuable contribution to our understanding of reality as a whole. In this sense, Leibniz’ monadology or Spinoza’s substance monism may capture something true, even though their limitations are no less apparent. The important point is that truths such as these come to light only in the holistic approach characteristic of reason rather than the piecemeal procedure of the understanding. What Hegel understands by reason here therefore answers well Kant’s description of reason as the faculty of ideas under which a body of knowledge is supposed to be systematically unified. The fact that reason here appears in the form of self-consciousness such that the object of the individual self likewise exhibits the structural features of the “I” – viz. self-referentiality and self-determination – is of significance for the methodological aspect of the argument on which we are primarily focusing. As can be seen most clearly from Hegel’s Lectures on the History of Philosophy and the Introduction to the Encyclopedia, Hegel views the self-referential Cartesian cogito, ergo sum as the foundation of the development of modern philosophy. He interprets the cogito as a speculative principle that postulates the identity of thought and being in general, not just the identity of the thinking activity with the existence of a thinking subject, although in the next step Descartes falls back into the opposition of consciousness by creating a hiatus between thinking and extended substances.162 However, for a brief moment, so to speak, the idea of an original unity of self-consciousness has been grasped, even if it is let go of almost immediately.163 Moreover, despite the subsequent oppositions between res extensa and res cogitans as well as finite and infinite substance the cogito represents the sole arbiter of truth. The system explaining the structure of the universe is constructed within the immanence of this thinking self, despite the fact that the ultimate ground of both the thinking and the extended reality that transcends it remains unintelligible to it.164 In the general introduction to the chapter on Reason in the Phenomenology, Hegel apparently sees a continuity between the Cartesian cogito and Kant’s and then Fichte’s original unity of selfconsciousness – while also criticizing Kant’s “spurious idealism” for again opposing this unity with an external in-itself.165 Descartes’ cogito, Kant’s (already purified) transcendental unity of apperception, and Fichte’s I = I are collectively referred to as 162 See
LHP XX 122–156. See also Brinkmann, 1997. to the interpretation of the cogito at Principles I 19, Hegel argues that “Descartes explains at once and explicitly that by “thinking” he understands consciousness in general and as such,” i.e. not just as this particular, individual consciousness (E § 76). 164 Descartes famously claims that although he cannot comprehend the divine substance, he can still understand it and thus have a clear and distinct idea of it (cf. Meditations, Meditation Three, CSM II 32/AT VII 46 and footnote 1). 165 “It is only the one-sided, spurious idealism that lets this unity again come on the scene as consciousness, on one side, confronted by an in-itself, on the other” (PS § 235/3, 181). E § 41, which we discussed in the previous chapter, echoes this earlier criticism. The Phenomenology likewise refers to Kant when it criticizes “empty idealism” for being in the same situation as (Humean) skepticism: It “fails equally . . . to bring together its contradictory thoughts of pure consciousness being all reality, while the extraneous impulse or sensations and ideas are equally [sc. deemed to 163 Referring
182
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
“the category” or “the simple category” (PS § 235/3, 181).166 By this Hegel means the unity of thinking and being in the form of a self-referential self. This unity is a “simple unity of self-consciousness and being” and as such “possesses difference in itself” in the form of particular categories (ibid.). The simple category is thus a category of categories, analogous to Aristotle’s nous that Aristotle calls a form of forms.167 The categories need to be derived from this “pure ‘I’” that is “the pure Understanding itself” (ibid.). We should recall, however, that Hegel believes that Fichte was the first to carry out such a derivation. By contrast, Kant’s metaphysical deduction is chided for being “an outrage on Science,” because it regards the forms of judgment as a given from which the table of categories can be derived without inquiring into the validity of the forms of judgment themselves (ibid.). There is an important methodological consequence to be drawn from this identification of reason with the original unity of self-consciousness. In the Encyclopedia Phenomenology, reason is defined as the unity of Notion or Concept and reality or objectivity (cf. E § 437). This, as Hegel points out, is just what from a purely structural point of view the Idea is in the Science of Logic. It is there defined as “the absolute unity of Concept and objectivity” (E § 213). But reason is here the “logical Idea” in the form of “universal self-consciousness” (E § 437A), and that means that it is the Idea that expresses itself in the world through the intelligent activity of individual selves. Self-consciousness is, as we said above, the agent or protagonist of reason in a world presumed to be itself fundamentally rational. Universal self-consciousness is the collective unity or community of rational selves or rational agents.168 Two comments are in order regarding this characterization of reason as universal self-consciousness. First, qua unity of (subjective) Notion and objectivity – the first two moments of the Notion in the Logic – reason is logically speaking the absolute self-referential totality and the ultimate unity of self and other in Hegel’s system – the ultimate unconditioned. Consequently, when reason is identified with the original unity of self-consciousness this unity of self and other must be equivalent to the already “purified” transcendental unity of apperception, not Kant’s “subjective” unity of self-consciousness, which (a) needs empirical input to account for the objective reality of the categories and (b) posits the existence of an ultimate ground of appearances beyond the reach of human knowledge. As we argued earlier, this “purification” or the overcoming of the external opposition of consciousness occurred with the inversion of the inverted world and the attainment of the (at first abstract) identity of the self with itself in Self-Consciousness. Secondly, however, reason is the unconditioned in the form of universal selfconsciousness, and this implies a qualification in scope and finality. Universal
be] reality. Instead of bringing them together, it shifts from one to the other, and is caught up in the spurious, i.e. the sensuous, infinite” (PS § 238/3, 184). 166 Or again as the “pure category” (PS § 236/3, 183). The expression “the unity of apperception” does in fact occur at PS § 238/3, 184. 167 Cf. De an. III 8, 432a 2 (nous eidos eid¯ on). 168 For the definition of universal self-consciousness see E § 436.
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
183
self-consciousness, while representing the identity of thought and being and hence a totality of immanence, is an abstract identity of Concept and reality only. As the Addition to E § 437 puts it by way of clarification: In this context the name ‘Reason’ has the meaning only of the initially still abstract or formal unity of self-consciousness with its object. This unity establishes what must be called, in specific contrast to the true, the merely correct. My idea is correct merely when it agrees with the object, even when the latter . . . has hardly any truth at all. Only when a true content becomes an object for me does my intelligence acquire the significance of Reason in its concrete sense.
To illustrate, reason in the form of universal self-consciousness can be understood as the intelligent activity of a community of rational agents who are participants in rational discourse, but without a shared stock of substantial beliefs – i.e. without a “true content” for all of them – beyond their universal agreement on formal principles of reasoning and procedural maxims. This fact has repercussions for the outcome of their debates and the “objectivity” of their proposals, as we shall soon see. In essence, it means that a new (internal) opposition opens up between what is formally true or “correct” in Hegel’s terminology and what is substantially true. To bring out this potential disagreement between the content and the form of truth (and the theoretical and practical disarray it may cause) is the central issue in the chapter on Reason which is thus designed to motivate the transition to the identity of content and form, or objectivity and Notion, an identity that Hegel will call “Spirit”. As a result of this internal opposition between the form and the content of truth within reason, the rationality propagated and upheld by the individual selfconsciousness must be called subjective or formal in the sense of lacking an objective or substantive content.169 Nonetheless, whichever content will be maintained as rational by the individual, it immediately inherits the claim to universal validity simply because individual self-consciousness is essentially universal selfconsciousness, i.e. one self is supposed to be just as rational as the next. Given, however, that apart from formal principles of correct reasoning there is no shared set of fundamental convictions or beliefs on the basis of which these selves could recognize each other as participating in the same form of life, this community of rational agents and discussants is faced by a plurality of rational proposals of how the world might be organized or made a better place while at the same time lacking a set of common values that would allow them to adjudicate objectively between the merits of their respective proposals. Or alternatively, if a set of values is believed to be shared by everyone, it soon turns out that this “common cause” inevitably means different things to different agents and that their agreement is in fact merely verbal. 169 That the Reason chapter in the Phenomenology is an early version of what Hegel later in the Encyclopedia system calls “subjective spirit” is born out by sections such as §§ 344/3, 260–261, 356/3, 267–268, 357/3, 268–269. At § 356/3, 267 Hegel refers to spirit (which seems to be anticipated a bit too early at § 350/3, 264–265 under the title of substance) as being so far only an “inner abstraction,” i.e. the projection of subjective reason of what an objectively rational community of agents would be like.
184
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
But to maintain the outward appearance of sharing the same beliefs with everybody else while stubbornly holding on to one’s own definition of what is best for all or, worse, preaching water in public and drinking wine privately, is a sure recipe for ruining the common cause and encouraging cynicism. What I just sketched is in outline the experience of consciousness during the third and final part of the chapter on Reason. More precisely, the first section of this part entitled “a. The spiritual animal kingdom and deceit, or the common cause [die Sache selbst]”170 analyzes the deceptive nature of theoretical agreements about what constitutes the shared substantial interest of a community of practical agents. What Hegel means by “die Sache selbst” is something like the rallying force of a common cause where the common cause is all that should matter and personal interest should be completely absent, but which eventually turns out to have the opposite effect of dividing people against each other because quite naturally each individual takes – and even must take – a personal interest in the success of the common endeavor – a universal phenomenon of human experience in private, professional, and above all political life. The cause that unites us also divides us.171 Out of this experience grows what one might call a pragmatic attempt to identify those universally valid rules that can be applied in any situation no matter what the particular circumstances or the particular interests of particular agents. In sub-section “b. Reason as lawgiver” Hegel therefore analyzes rules of conduct that place the burden of applying them correctly on the individual self-consciousness that is, after all, endowed with universal rationality. Anticipating the transition to Spirit in the next chapter, he calls the good to be enacted by following such golden rules “the ethical substance” (PS § 420/3, 311). Self-consciousness identifies with this substance and in its actions is supposed to actualize it as a matter of course. As “sound Reason,” it . . . knows immediately what is right and good. Just as it knows the law immediately, so too the law is valid for it immediately, and it says directly: ‘this is right and good’ (PS § 422/3, 312).
Self-consciousness “calls them as it sees them”, so to speak. In applying rules of conduct such as “Everyone ought to speak the truth” (PS § 424/3, 313) or “Love thy neighbor as thyself” (PS § 425/3, 314) – to which could be added the golden rule or the principle of the mean – the self acts as the protagonist or “moment” of the ethical substance, more precisely as its “being-for-self” or self-consciousness
170 “Common cause” is the translation I suggest for Hegel’s “die Sache selbst.” In German, there are standard expressions such as “es geht mir/uns um die Sache selbst” (I am/we are concerned with the matter itself, i.e. not with some peripheral side-issue” or “nur die Sache selbst im Auge haben” (to focus exclusively on the matter at hand, and not, for instance, on some personal interest that may be involved as well). 171 The reason is that the common cause is merely abstractly defined, “an abstract, universal reality lacking filling and content” (PS § 397/3, 294). The “deception” Hegel invokes at PS § 418/3, 309– 310 has less to do with ill-intentioned individuals who play intrigues against each other for petty personal reasons. Deception is, rather, systemic at this level of individuated reason, because the universal can become actual only through being particularized and by benefiting the individual agents. Their disagreement about the good is inevitable.
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
185
(PS § 422/3, 312). However, the crucial point is that this identity of the individual self-consciousness and the ethical substance is here only presumed, not real. Self-consciousness is supposed to be the individual exponent or protagonist of the ethical substance,172 but that substance itself does not yet have a fixed content. In other words, we have not yet entered the “ethical order” of the chapter on Spirit (cf. PS, p. 266: “The True Spirit: The Ethical Order”). Nothing perhaps marks the difference between reason and spirit better than the ad-hoc character of the maxims and laws proposed by formal rationality. When reason acts as lawgiver, the content of the maxim (e.g., that everyone ought to speak the truth) is universal, but its application is ad hoc or contingent. By applying the maxim, the individual thus makes the maxim into a law based on a particular case. In the subsequent sub-section “c. Reason as testing laws,” the content is ad hoc or contingent, but its application is supposed to be uniform. Differently put, in “Reason as lawgiver” the individual self-consciousness is supposed to particularize the universal whereas in “Reason as testing laws” it is meant to universalize the particular. Neither procedure, it turns out, is successful due to the lack of rules for the application of commandments in the first case and the tautological character of the testing procedure in the second. The two sub-sections can be seen as a reconstruction of a Kantian argument in the Groundwork, plus a critique of the principle of universalizability.173 Just as Kant is skeptical of the claim that an innocent heart is the best counsel in moral matters,174 so also does Hegel criticize the view that “sound reason” can determine what is right and good without further ado merely by applying ad hoc universally known commandments such as that one must always tell the truth. For one can tell the truth only when one knows what the truth is, otherwise one might easily be misled into innocently telling a falsehood based on hearsay, rumor, or slander. To know the truth is therefore not a matter of immediate intuition. As in all cases of such “celebrated commandments” (cf. PS § 425/3, 314) as telling the truth or loving your neighbor intelligence, judgment, or practical wisdom are required: Active love . . . aims at removing an evil from someone and being good to him. For this purpose I have to distinguish what is bad for him, what is the appropriate good to counter this evil, and what in general is good for him; i.e. I must love him intelligently. Unintelligent love will perhaps do him more harm than hatred (ibid.).
The idea of determining what is good or bad in a given instance by applying general maxims intuitively on an ad hoc basis turns out to be an illusion. This is why reason next proposes a principle for testing given maxims with a view to their universalizability. This would be a rational procedure to determine, not whether 172 Hence the anticipation of the ethical world of spirit already at PS § 350/3, 264–265 (see footnote 169 above). 173 I.e., the critique of Kant’s so-called formalism. It should be noted that Kant’s moral philosophy proper is critically targeted only much later in the Phenomenology, viz. in sub-sections “a. The moral view of the world” and “b. Dissemblance or duplicity.” The sub-section on reason as testing laws deals with the principle of universalizability as a criterion of the good generally. The chief example for Hegel’s critique is taken from a debate about distributive justice in the case of private property. 174 See Groundwork, AA IV 405.
186
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
a precept of reason fits a particular circumstance, but whether an “already given” content (PS § 429/3, 317) or maxim would be fit to be a universal law. The idea behind this, Hegel explains, is that . . . the essence of ethics consists just in law being identical with itself and through this self-identity, i.e. through having its ground in itself, it is unconditioned (PS § 430/3, 317).
That the ethical law consist in whatever can be shown to exhibit the form of a law is, however, the weakness of the universalizability principle, for in this case “one content is just as acceptable to it as its opposite” (ibid.), since any content, taken in isolation, is identical with itself and hence a non-contradictory simple universal. It is only when maxims are taken together to yield a whole web of rules of conduct that reasons can be given for or against particular provisions. Thus, whether there ought to be private property or not or common ownership instead cannot be determined “in the abstract”, because there is nothing self-contradictory in any of these ideas. We can well imagine scenarios with or without private property, with or without common ownership. It is when we start to bring out the particular implications these provisions might have in conjunction with further stipulations and under particular circumstances that specific reasons for or against can be given. Thus, if the question of distribution is brought to bear on the idea of common ownership the issue becomes whether “each receives as much as he needs” or whether “goods will be equally distributed” (PS § 430/3, 318). Both alternatives, Hegel claims, can be shown to contradict the idea of common ownership and thus be ruled out. Common ownership implies both the right of everyone to possess goods and thus an equal right of all to an equal share as it also implies the idea of sharing possessions on the basis of individual need, i.e. unequal shares (cf. ibid.). If common ownership thus appears contradictory, it is not because the idea of common ownership taken in isolation could not be made a universal law but “only because it has not been left as a simple determinateness” (PS § 431/3, 318). All depends, therefore, on the context into which the ideas of common ownership or private property ought to fit and on the principles on which their validity is to be based – in the above case on whether equality or individual need is supposed to take precedence. And yet, these determinations once again require a commitment to some prior principle and there is thus no end to bringing in further and further considerations, all of them rationally justifiable, it is true, but without an anchoring in a substantive conception of the good. Substantive conceptions of the good, however, cannot simply be invented by reason or thought up at the drawing board like those social and political utopias that have been produced throughout history and that have been of a purely theoretical interest without any practical use. The objective validity of substantive conceptions of the good, Hegel argues, is not dependent on receiving the seal of approval from this or that individual consciousness. Of moral injunctions Hegel says: They are. If I inquire after their origin and confine them to the point whence they arose, then I have transcended them; for now it is I who am the universal, and they are the conditioned and limited. If they are supposed to be validated by my insight, then I have already denied their unshakeable, intrinsic being, and regard them as something which, for me, is perhaps true, but also is perhaps not true (PS § 437/3, 322).
3.4
The Native Land of Truth: From Desire to Reason
187
Because testing a given maxim for its universalizability is by itself inconclusive, it invites bringing in further considerations on an ad hoc basis and thus re-introduces the element of subjectivity, contingency, and arbitrariness that was supposed to be overcome by the procedure of testing. Neither as giving nor as testing laws does rational consciousness therefore regard their ethical content as something that has “an intrinsic being” (PS § 436/3, 321). But “ethical disposition consists just in sticking steadfastly to what is right, and abstaining from all attempts to move or shake it, or derive it” (PS § 437/3, 322). Hegel thus erects an opposition between the determination by the individual of what is right and good on one hand and the “unshakeable, intrinsic being” of the ethical substance itself on the other. To return a deposit to its owner is the right thing to do, not because I have first satisfied myself that keeping the deposit would be wrong but because returning it is just the moral thing to do, whether one believes that one ought to do it or not: It is not, therefore, because I find something is not self-contradictory that it is right; on the contrary, it is right because it is right. That something is the property of another, this is fundamental; I have not to argue about it, or hunt around for or entertain thoughts, connections, aspects of various kinds; I have to think neither of making laws nor of testing them (ibid.).
The key to understanding Hegel’s critique of so-called Kantian formalism is therefore Hegel’s concern that by making the individual agent the arbiter of what is right and good the proper relationship between the moral law and the individual agent is being inverted. Something ought or ought not to be done not because I have satisfied myself of its rightness or wrongness, but because it is the ethical thing to do. As soon as I start to test a moral precept for its rightness or wrongness, I am on a slippery slope – “I have already begun to tread an unethical path” (ibid.). It can be and has been argued, of course, that this is not at all how Kant understood the testing procedure. Rather than creating an opportunity for the individual to find a loophole in a given moral injunction or prohibition through manipulating the meaning of a maxim or the circumstances of its application, Kant to the contrary insists firmly that the significance of the testing procedure consists precisely in eliminating the possibility of making an exception for oneself. The result of applying the categorical imperative to a given maxim is therefore exactly the one Hegel desires, viz. that there is no legitimate alternative whatsoever to obeying the moral law. One might contend, then, that Hegel should have said, not that testing maxims for their universalizability invites arbitrariness on the part of the individual but that the testing procedure is in fact redundant because the outcome of the testing can be no other than what the moral law demands. And what the moral law demands, Hegel should have continued, cannot be in doubt. Its injunctions are or ought to be selfevident. But here is the point at which Hegel’s real argument comes to the fore. His criticism is precisely that if the demands of the moral law were self-evident, a testing procedure would not be needed. Conversely, the fact that Kant believes a procedural rule like the categorical imperative to be necessary is testimony that in his view the injunctions of the moral law are not self-evident, that the individual agent would not know immediately what to do. And there is indeed in Kant a presumption not
188
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
to trust the individual’s ethical disposition. The human will, according to a famous passage in the Groundwork, is constitutionally at a crossroads between letting itself be determined either heteronymously by inclination or autonomously by the moral law, and it is, as experience seems to show, more likely to follow the former than the latter path.175 Because the ethical disposition of the individual is uncertain, appeal must be made to his rational capacity to see for himself that to act against the moral law is self-contradictory. As if experience did not show with equal eloquence that self-contradiction is hardly an obstacle for inconsistent behavior. Consequently, the testing procedure is not a very suitable means to strengthen or reinforce the ethical disposition of the agent. To have satisfied oneself through reasoning that a given maxim is universalizable, results in a rational belief. But rational belief falls short of the unfaltering conviction that allows me to “stick steadfastly to what is right” and easily falls prey to corrupting desires, as had long since been pointed out by Plato: Ethical self-consciousness is immediately one with essential being through the universality of its self; belief, on the other hand, starts from the individual consciousness; it is the movement of that consciousness always towards this unity [sc. with the ethical substance or the moral law], but without attaining to the presence of its essential being (PS § 436/3, 321).
Analysis reveals, then, that for Hegel the deeper issue at stake in his formalism critique is the lack of ethical disposition in the individual, something Kant seems to accept as a given, and the lack of a determinate, substantive content of the moral law.176 Others may see these as a virtue of Kant’s procedural approach to ethics in the Groundwork, because it is seemingly realistic in its suspicion of the goodness of the human heart and apt to give guidance to the members of a pluralistic society that lacks a core of shared substantive values but is willing to accept procedural rules. For Hegel, however, the fact that a testing procedure is needed at all is an indication that the will of the individual and the ethical substance are both as yet without a fixed ethical content. It is an indication of an ethical void that is supposed to be filled by reasoning and argumentation. But the universal acceptance of rational procedures is seen by Hegel as a poor substitute for ethical disposition since it only replaces, but cannot generate, the ethical substance of the community itself. Abstract rationality leaves the content of the good indeterminate. Instead, the agent falls back 175 Later in the Phenomenology, Hegel confirms this point by saying of the (Kantian) moral spirit that “it is immediate, like the ethical consciousness [sc. of the Ancients, or like Antigone’s] which knows its duty and does it . . .; but it is not character, as that ethical consciousness is . . .” (PS § 597/3, 442). 176 Otherwise, it would be near impossible to explain why Hegel believes that changing one’s mind about whether to return or keep a deposit is not inconsistent with Kant’s moral theory but merely an “alteration of the point of view” that by itself is “not contradiction” (PS § 437/3, 322). Note that Hegel’s critique here is directed primarily at the Groundwork, not the later position in the Second Critique, the Metaphysics of Morals and the Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone. For a recent succinct presentation of the fundamental ideas and principles of Kant’s practical philosophy, including his Anthropology and philosophy of history as well as the moral philosophy see Wood 2000. With this comprehensive approach, Wood sees a much better chance for Kant to escape the formalism critique.
3.5
Methodological Interlude: Overcoming the Opposition of Consciousness
189
on intuitively plausible commandments and ad hoc assumptions about the good. But such expedients, reasonable though they may be in a given case, are incapable of grounding a form of life based on a determinate, universally accepted idea of the good. For that to be possible, abstract rationality must be anchored in a universal ethical substance. By contrast, spirit for Hegel represents the entelechy of reason precisely in the sense that spirit combines individual rationality with the universal validity of a substantial ethical content, a “unity” towards which the self-consciousness in Reason is always moving “without attaining to the presence of its essential being” (PS § 436/3, 321). Hegel sees this unity emerge towards the end of the chapter on Reason: The spiritual being . . . exists first of all for self-consciousness as law which has an intrinsic being; the universality associated with testing the law, a merely formal, not an essential universality, is now behind us. The law is equally an eternal law which is grounded not in the will of a particular individual, but is valid in and for itself; it is the absolute pure will of all which has the form of immediate being. Also, it is not a commandment, which only ought to be: it is and is valid . . . (PS § 436/3, 321).
One might therefore say that with this combination of subjective rationality and objective substance called Spirit we have finally reached that objective objectivity that maintains the existence of an objective universal truth (viz., the universal ethical substance that unites a community of rational agents), but also takes into account the essential and irreducible contribution of individual self-consciousness. That this is indeed what Hegel has in mind will become apparent shortly when we turn to the analysis of Hegel’s concept of spirit in the Phenomenology. First, however, I suggest that at this juncture a brief recapitulation of the methodological moves that have brought us to this point may be useful.
3.5 Methodological Interlude: Overcoming the Opposition of Consciousness We may want to distinguish here between two ways in which to view the self-other relationship that is fundamental for consciousness, and for knowledge in general. We indicated initially that given the emphasis on the methodological aspect of the Phenomenology we would want to focus particularly on the question of how the opposition of consciousness is in fact overcome. It is equally important, however, to keep in mind how the two “poles” of the self-other relationship relate to one another and how their nature and status changes over the course of the argument. To begin with, then, I pointed out earlier that Hegel himself described his task as a “thinking out into purity” the Kantian original unity of self-consciousness since the latter for him continued to be burdened by a dual external opposition between itself and an empirical manifold on one hand and a thing-in-itself on the other. In the execution of this program Hegel first showed that objectivity is in fact the result of a process of translating experience into thoughts. With this the idea that consciousness qua thinking is permanently opposed to an other that is for it the
190
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
truth but whose in-itself or essence it can never really fathom fell away. Instead, at the end of Consciousness, self-consciousness emerged as the ground of consciousness and, since the opposition between consciousness and object had collapsed, the object of self-consciousness became synonymous with reality itself, a reality internal to self-consciousness. Note that the representational model of cognition was then explicitly rejected during Hegel’s discussion of the meaning of thinking at the beginning of the sub-section entitled Freedom of Self-Consciousness.177 For thinking there no longer exists an external opposition between itself and its object. Now selfconsciousness and consciousness by definition form a unity since there cannot be one without the other. An object-consciousness without a self-consciousness would not be the consciousness of an object, i.e. the object would not stand in a relation to the self that is, after all, supposed to know it. Again, a self-consciousness without an object-consciousness would be unable to know itself, since self-consciousness presupposes an opposition between self and other. Hegel relied on this feature of self-consciousness to argue that if the object of (self-)consciousness was an empty self, then the resulting knowledge would be the mere tautology of “I = I”, i.e. knowledge of a blank. Consequently, for the self to know itself, it must relate to itself as an other, albeit an other that is internal to the unity of self-consciousness. Only thus can its self-knowledge acquire a content. As we already know, however, this other will have to reveal itself as a self or self-consciousness, since without such recognition of self in another self the self will never be able to know itself through the other but always only an other through itself. Spirit in general represents the moment of self-recognition in other. Looking ahead, however, we can see that there are still three explicit such moments of self-recognition to come, the first at the end of Forgiveness, the second in Revealed Religion, and the third in Absolute Knowing. The question why all of them are necessary and what their function is within the overall argument will occupy us shortly. Reason represents the stage of the argument at which thinking has become “idealism”, i.e. the certainty of self-consciousness that its object is transparent and intelligible to it because it exhibits those rational structures that self-consciousness recognizes as its own, structures such as self-referentiality and self-determination.178 Interestingly, Hegel called this unity of self and other that is reason “the category.” As I argued above, “category” in this sense is nothing other than the original unity of self-consciousness, albeit now without external oppositions. I took this to be an indication that reason is here to be understood as subjective or abstract reason that takes itself to have immediate objective significance but which, as subjective, is formal and lacks a universal content. It is also pluralistic in the sense in which any rational content can be defended as being internally coherent or, more loosely, as “making sense”. As is well known, spirit for Hegel means a step beyond such pluralism 177 See again PS § 197/3, 156 and the contrast between thinking and representational thinking or “picture-thought” and our discussion above p. 163ff. 178 Hence the interpretation of reality in terms of a teleological system in Observing Reason and of self-consciousness as an end in itself in the third subsection of Reason (cf. PS §§ 254 ff./3, 196 ff. and § 394/3, 292 f., § 401/3, 239 f.), respectively.
3.5
Methodological Interlude: Overcoming the Opposition of Consciousness
191
towards one rationality with a universal substantial content with which individual self-consciousness identifies.179 As far as the opposition of consciousness is concerned we have seen that the initial external opposition between self and other had been overcome at the end of the chapter on Consciousness. (As a reminder, even that external opposition was an appearance only since from the point of view of the system the entire development already occurs within the unity of Concept and objectivity.) However, in the resulting identity of self and other in the form of I = I the opposition between self and object had to be recreated internally in order for the self of self-consciousness to become a fulfilled self. In the Unhappy Consciousness, this opposition found an interim resolution. The chapter on Reason showed that the actual appropriation of the internal other by the self did not yet lead to a fulfilled self because the individual self as subjective reason mistakenly claimed immediate universal validity for its particular rational content. Hegel was thus able to develop a contradiction between the particularity of the rational content – e.g., the various rational “schemes” of how the world ought to be – and its attached claim to universal validity. It is obvious, however, that different rational proposals do not immediately harmonize with one another, not even when they are grounded in the same fundamental principle – the abstract principle of the right of individuals freely to determine their lives can support both an abortionist as well as an anti-abortionist position. We thus have a contradiction between the particularity of the contents and its claim to be immediately universalizable due to its internal abstract rationality. Rational pluralism means that everyone’s rational proposal is formally valid and thus formally universalizable, except that its content is not immediately universalizable because it must first be reconciled with all the other rational proposals. This is the very situation that in a pluralistic society we take to be both inevitable and irresolvable. Controversies then get settled by majority vote, either at the level of legislation or at the level of the supreme courts. For Hegel the contradiction cannot be settled in this way, since that would mean the privileging of one particular scheme over another or, alternatively, a decision not to take a decision. A pluralistic “ethical substance” could not claim genuine universality. For Hegel, the contradiction can only be resolved if we posit the compatibility of subjective rationality and objective rational substance such that there is one recognized substantial ethical content for all individual rational agents within a community. What is thus posited methodologically as a solution to the contradiction between formal and substantial rationality Hegel believes has also made a historical appearance in the “ethical order” of the Ancients (and then again in the modern state). What we end up with in Spirit, then, is a unified totality with a substantial content in which the moments – viz. the ethical substance and the individual self-consciousness – mutually reinforce one another.180
179 Consequently, seeing in Hegel’s ethical life an institutional framework for a pluralistic normative discourse as does Pippin (in Pippin, 2000) while tempting is nonetheless problematic. 180 One can and even should be critical of the lack of pluralism in Hegel’s ethical substance. In a sense, Hegel’s analysis of the self-destruction of the ethical world of the Ancients centers around
192
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
If, finally, we ask ourselves how the self-other relationship has been transformed in terms of a ground-grounded relationship over the course of consciousness’ experience up to this point, we can see that a considerable metamorphosis has occurred. Initially, the other of the self appeared in the form of particulars and things (or atomic facts) that counted as “the true” while the self was supposed to be inessential. The other was a reality existing independently of consciousness for which the existence of consciousness in turn was irrelevant – much like we view our relationship to the world from the standpoint of ordinary consciousness. In the sequel, however, what used to be a mind-independent reality was transformed into an appearance whose underlying ground were at first the laws of the understanding and ultimately the thinking self itself. This thinking self, while at first master of itself and (theoretically) of the world, was confronted with two sides of itself, one contingent and particular (i.e. the human world of work and enjoyment), the other transcendent and universal (the divine). Qua I = I, self-consciousness needed to reconcile these two essences within itself and unify the worldly human reality with the transcendent beyond. Reason emerged as this unity. In Reason, the opposition between self and other no longer existed, but rational self-consciousness came into conflict with the requirement that its contingent content ought simultaneously to be universally valid. To resolve this conflict, Hegel suggested the idea of spirit as the unity of subjective rationality and universal substantial content that he calls the ethical substance. When we now look at the specific ground-grounded relationship involved in spirit we see that what formerly functioned as ground, viz. self-consciousness, has now become something that is itself grounded in the ethical substance. The ethical substance in turn is in an oblique way a self-consciousness, albeit not an individual one, in that it is conscious of itself through the individual self-consciousness that is conscious of it as its own essence. The ethical substance is thus a universal selfconsciousness that constitutes the essential identity of the self-conscious individuals who understand themselves as its exponents or protagonists. In other words, the consciousness of the individual agents is determined by their self-consciousness that consists in the identification of their essence with the ethical substance. Individual self-consciousness has become a dependent moment of the ethical substance as ground, but is similarly an independent self vis-à-vis all other individual selves. This is just what Hegel understands by spirit in its objective form. It is formally analogous to what, in the Encyclopedia, he calls “universal self-consciousness,” which is there defined as “the affirmative awareness of self in an other self” and the “root of all true spiritual life” (E § 436), except that in Spirit this affirmative awareness of self in an other self is no longer mediated merely through the mutual recognition of agents as rational but is instead based upon the presence of a shared ethical substance that is
such lack of pluralism. Still, Hegel continues to favor a monolithic and thus potentially fundamentalist or “ideological” interpretation of the unity of the modern state even later. The challenge posed by making Hegel’s political philosophy contemporary, so to speak, is obviously to try to combine his institutionally based organic model of political unity with the demands of a pluralistic society. It is a political community beyond (abstract) morality on the one hand and “Sittlichkeit” on the other.
3.5
Methodological Interlude: Overcoming the Opposition of Consciousness
193
affirmed by everyone.181 From thinghood as ground that (cognitively) grounds the self’s knowledge, and the self as ground of (theoretical and practical) objectivity we have moved, then, to the ethical substance as a ground that (absolutely) grounds individual self-consciousness and incorporates it as a moment or member. We have thus again witnessed a double inversion of ground and grounded. The ground that was initially located on the object side, so to speak, is now again located on the object side, but this object or other has mutated into a self, albeit a universal self in the form of a consciousness of shared values, convictions, customs, and laws. That the ethical substance is indeed a self-referential, self-determining structure and can therefore legitimately be called a self will become clear shortly. Earlier we said that with spirit Hegel seems to have reached that objective objectivity to which the knowledge and action of the individual self-consciousness is equally essential. If this is so, then in principle the initial problem of explaining how objectivity is possible seems to have been resolved, albeit in a special way. The problem, we may remember, consisted in the simple but seemingly paradoxical fact that objective truth must on the one hand exist independently of the individual consciousness, but must on the other also be true for an individual. The latter it cannot be, however, without the individual’s active participation since the truth is, after all, something that needs to be grasped, thought and understood in order to be the truth. The world exists independently of thought and an individual consciousness, but the truth does not. The individual is and must be involved in the very constitution of the truth. As a thinking being, then, the individual consciousness must contribute to what is for it the truth and must know this to be the truth objectively, i.e. not for it only but universally. It seems that Hegel is able to satisfy these conflicting requirements through the conception of objectivity that results from his understanding of the concept of spirit. This conception means that the true (a) in one sense is prior to the individual since qua universal substance it is independent of any particular individual and is therefore (b) re-produced by the individual that actively identifies with it, while in another sense it is also (c) pro-duced, i.e. brought to light, by the activity of the individual and in this sense transformed from something potential into something actual and real. If we wanted to go a step further, we could even say that in the process of being recreated what counts as objective truth may also be augmented, changed and thus gradually transformed by the collective activity of all, just as languages keep evolving over time through the input of individual speakers and writers. Only thus would the individual self be capable of contributing substantially and innovatively, and not only reproductively, to the truth. Whether Hegel would be willing to go that far is, however, another question.182
181 Note that in the Encyclopedia Hegel indicated that the “appearance of the underlying essence,” i.e. of the ethical substance, “may also be severed from that essence, and be maintained apart in worthless honor, idle fame etc.” (E § 436). It is this severance that is characteristic of Reason in the Phenomenology. 182 For an interpretation of Hegel’s “developmental approach” that allows the individual agent a substantive, not only an accidental, role in the realization of freedom see again Pippin, 2000.
194
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
Hegel’s text reinforces the view that a certain finality or entelechy has been achieved with Spirit. Spirit, he says is “the ethical life of a nation . . . – the individual that is a world” (PS § 441/3, 326), in other words, spirit is an individuated totality. Furthermore, all the previous shapes of consciousness are “abstract forms” of spirit, i.e. modes of cognition which are versions of spirit in which neither consciousness recognizes spirit, however, nor spirit itself. When looked at in isolation, as happened with consciousness, self-consciousness, and reason, these forms of spirit seemed to have “the appearance [Schein] of really existing as such” (PS § 440/3, 325; my italics). In truth, however, these earlier modes of cognition and action “presuppose” spirit and “exist only in Spirit” (ibid.). One might speak of a fallacy of misplaced concreteness here. Someone who believes, for instance, that the understanding and its principle of identity is the only valid form of cognition mistakes an abstract, partial interpretation of reality for the whole. In progressing from one cognitive level to the next, then, we successively re-admit a context that for purposes of discursive explanation and reconstruction had been blocked and without which these forms of knowledge cannot properly be evaluated. The move from abstraction to concreteness (where concreteness comes logically first but appears last in terms of exposition) is the methodological basis of the architectonic that underlies Hegel’s procedure of rational reconstruction.
3.6 The Internalization of Spirit: From Ethical Substance to the Spiritual Individual The complex nature of spirit in the Phenomenology can best be understood by turning to Hegel’s own structural analysis of it, which is worth quoting in full: Spirit, being the substance and the universal, self-identical, and abiding essence, is the unmoved solid ground and starting-point for the action of all, and it is their purpose and goal, the in-itself of every self-consciousness expressed in thought. This substance is equally the universal work produced by the action of all and each as their unity and identity, for it is the being-for-self, the self, action. As substance, Spirit is unshaken righteous self-identity; but as being-for-self it is a fragmented being, self-sacrificing and benevolent, in which each accomplishes his own work, rends asunder the universal being, and takes from it its own share. This resolving of the essence into individuals is precisely the moment of the action and the self of all; it is the movement and soul of substance and the resulting universal being. Just because it is a being that is resolved in the self, it is not a dead essence, but is actual and alive (PS § 439/3, 325).
We learn here that spirit is both the inner substance, so to speak, of the action of the individuals and the actually existing reality produced by their work, which as that which unites them is prior to their activity – prior in the sense in which the final cause or the whole is prior to the efficient cause or the part. Each individual self-consciousness is instrumental in translating the “abiding essence” into a living – and lived – reality. The being-for-self or self-referential subjectivity of the ethical substance consists in the fact that it re-produces and actualizes itself. It does so through the action of each individual self-consciousness. In this way it is
3.6
The Internalization of Spirit: From Ethical Substance to the Spiritual Individual
195
both its own presupposition and result. In the process, however, the “unshaken righteous self-identity” of this substance is “fragmented”, i.e. appropriated and used up by the individual who thereby achieves individual “being-for-self” or independent selfhood. The being-for-self of the abiding essence is therefore in one sense merely a transitory moment in its reproduction as is the independent selfhood of individual self-consciousness, which derives its identity only from the identical, not the fragmented substance.183 But because this process of the self-actualization of spirit represents a reproductive cycle, its moments also have the permanence of the eternal recurrence. Spiritual substance is alive, because and only because the individuals through their work and action keep it alive. If this self-reproducing collective phenomenon called spirit is such a comprehensive closed system and in a way represents the ultimate level of the experience of consciousness, why, it might be asked, is there a necessity for it to undergo further transformations and reversals? Basically, there are two reasons. The first is that the immediate form of spirit with which this section begins while at first in harmony with itself is in truth internally divided against itself, a division that is made explicit in an exemplary way by Antigone’s defiance of Creon’s orders and that in the sequel leads to the break up of the beauty of the ethical order of the Ancients and to the “ruin of the ethical Substance” (PS § 476/3, 354). The clash of Creon’s Human with Antigone’s Divine Law is far from accidental for Hegel and points to an immaturity in the immediate ethical substance, viz. its immediate identity of the natural and the rational, or nature and spirit. The ethical substance thus carries within itself an opposition of two particularized spheres or powers both of which claim to be totalities and can therefore coexist only as long as there occurs no action that is absolutely right in one sphere while being absolutely wrong in the other. At that moment, the break up of the ethical substance becomes necessary, and in its demise it destroys the individual agents that were its protagonists. This new opposition is not only internal but also logically speaking the most severe contradiction, because it opposes two totalities that are in essence one spirit. The breakup of the ethical order is followed by spirit in the form of Enlightenment culture and in the form of morality. Morality represents the re-unification of the opposition in the Enlightenment between a utilitarian, positivistic and thus sterile culture on one hand and the piety of faith that flees the world in favor of an equally sterile beyond. In morality, Hegel argues, self-consciousness grasps itself as the essentiality and essence [sc. of spirit] as the actual self; it no longer places its world and its ground outside of itself, but lets everything fade into itself, and, as conscience, is Spirit that is certain of itself (PS § 442/3, 327).
Kant’s moral metaphysics, the idea of a secret harmony between the phenomenal and the noumenal realms and the hypothetical but rationally necessary positing of 183 This point is important for Hegel’s provocative thesis that from time to time the state needs to rally its citizens around itself through war since otherwise the natural fragmentation of society that encourages acquisition of private property and pursuit of personal well-being will erode the cohesion of the political community.
196
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
a highest good, marks a crucial link in the re-appropriation of an undivided ethical substance by self-consciousness that will eventually be completed after the transition from secular to religious spirituality in the chapter on Religion. The second reason why the immediate unity of self and ethical substance cannot last is the fact that it does not honor the individuality of individual selfconsciousness. In the ethical world of the Ancients, the individual has “character,” but no real autonomy.184 It is not recognized as a self-determining self: “This particular individual counts only as a shadowy unreality” (PS § 464/3, 342). The identification of the agent with the ethical substance is absolute – hence Antigone’s and Creon’s tragic fate. Because they are, in Hegel’s interpretation, the pure, almost selfless, representatives of their respective spheres without a (modern) identity of their own, they must perish with the substance that is their inner being.185 The subsequent development will rectify this neglect of individual autonomy and let the ethical substance renew itself through an ultimate act of self-limitation of the autonomous individual in the moment of mutual forgiveness, an act through which both regain genuine freedom and independence. The further development in Spirit is thus determined by two issues. On the one hand, the breakup of the ethical substance into two spheres that are both of them “Spirit in its entirety” (PS § 446/3, 329) needs to be overcome, the two totalities need to be reunited or, rather, their essential identity must be demonstrated. On the other hand, this identity must be brought about by the autonomous individual selfconsciousness for the simple reason that unless the autonomous individual is seen to embody spirit, spirit does not exist in the world as subject but only as substance or only as the object of self-consciousness and not in the form of self-consciousness. The difference over against the immediate embodiment of spirit as it occurs in the ethical order of the Ancients is therefore that in the modern era spirit must be shown to be embodied by the self-determining individual self-consciousness. By contrast with the hero of ancient Greek tragedy, the content of spirit (i.e. Substance) must be reflectively endorsed by this self-consciousness (and thus become Subject). This development culminates in the sub-section entitled “c. Conscience. The “beautiful soul”, evil and its forgiveness” (PS §§ 632 ff./3, 464 ff.) at the very end of the third sub-chapter of Spirit called Morality, to which we now turn. To recapitulate the argument in Morality very briefly. Kant’s idea of a “harmony” of the noumenal and phenomenal worlds or of “morality and Nature” (PS § 602/3, 445) that constitutes the metaphysical backbone without which a duty to strive for the realization of the highest good would not make sense marks the first step towards
184 “The ethical consciousness, because it is decisively for one of the two powers, is essentially character” (PS § 466/3, 343). 185 According to Hegel, the characters of ancient Greek tragedy possess that ethical disposition that was absent in the sphere of Reason. The individual self-consciousness, “qua ethical consciousness, . . . is the simple, pure direction of activity towards the essentiality of ethical life, i.e. duty. In it there is no caprice and equally no struggle, no indecision, since the making and testing of law has been given up; on the contrary, the essence of ethical life is for this consciousness immediate, unwavering, without contradiction” (PS § 465/3, 342).
3.6
The Internalization of Spirit: From Ethical Substance to the Spiritual Individual
197
the reunification of the two spheres of the ethical substance.186 However, Hegel criticizes that because the projected harmony is a postulate or a harmony in thought only and not in reality, the two spheres of universality (or pure duty) and particularity (or inclination and personal interest) remain in fact opposed to one another. This constitutes a perfect “antinomy” (PS § 632/3, 464), since it means that in the end the Kantian “moral view of the world” is a self-defeating project: “Because the universal best ought to be carried out, nothing good is done” (PS § 619/3, 455) – i.e. nothing morally good.187 If duty requires of me unconditionally that I should develop a holy will, then of course I will forever fall short of moral goodness. Hegel is right, I believe, in pointing out a fundamental ambiguity in Kant’s view of morality that on the one hand understands moral goodness as the striving towards the realization of a good will, but on the other as the realization of a perfectly good, i.e. holy will, which realization is, moreover, an unconditional duty. However, if the striving is what makes me morally good and worthy of happiness, then really achieving a good will catapults me beyond morality. The point of striving to be morally good becomes contradictory since the fulfillment of the striving would mean not the realization of moral goodness, but of holiness, i.e. of something superhuman and beyond morality altogether.188 To put it slightly differently, to strive to be moral means that one is not yet moral, but morally good one should not become for then one could no longer strive to be moral. Hence Hegel’s point that Kant’s categorical “ought” cannot be meant seriously, for whether I am striving or not, I never really am nor can I ever become morally good.189 Assuming, then, that the moral world view proves incapable of bringing together the idea of pure duty (i.e., universality) and actual human existence (i.e. particularity), or morality and nature, what other paradigm of morality is there that would allow for the unification of the two in real life? Hegel suggests an ethics of conscience as the next candidate. In an ethics of conscience, the universal and the particular, duty and motivation, coincide immediately in the individual agent. The
186 Note that the concept of the highest good represents the consummation of the unification of the
sensible with the noumenal in the idea of a happiness commensurate with moral worthiness. 187 Kant admits that something honest may be achieved, and yet, strangely, what is honest is not good enough to be of moral worth (cf. Groundwork IV 397). I believe that Hegel’s critique of Kant’s conception of morality is largely valid, but this is not the place to defend it against its many critics. It all depends ultimately, however, on how stringent we want to make the requirements for moral goodness. If developing a good will means to acquire a holy will – as I think it does for Kant -, then there will be no moral acts done by humans. If moral goodness means something like Aristotelian practical wisdom combined with temperance, then our chances of achieving moral goodness at least occasionally will be much better. 188 Cf. PS § 620/3, 456: “The postulate of the harmony of morality and reality [to be realized in the highest good] . . . is expressed . . . in the form: “Because moral action is the absolute purpose, the absolute purpose is, that there should be no such thing as moral action.’ ” 189 “That consciousness is not in earnest about the perfection of morality is indicated by the fact that consciousness itself shifts it away into infinity, i.e. asserts that the perfection is never perfected” (PS § 622/3, 458).
198
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
individual agent is here the sole arbiter of the moral worth of his actions or motivations. This individual is therefore “Spirit that is directly aware of itself as absolute truth and being” (PS § 633/3, 465).190 This is so because the judgment of conscience is absolutely personal, i.e. one that cannot be carried out by any other person or in turn be questioned by anybody else. Whatever conscience tells this particular individual morally justifies or invalidates the motivation or action of this particular individual, and this verdict has to be accepted as valid by all. The individual appealing to his conscience “is itself in its contingency completely valid in its own right, and knows its immediate individuality to be pure knowing and doing, to be the true reality and harmony” (PS § 632/3, 465). The appeal to conscience has something in common with the squaring of the circle, so to speak. Conscience can declare something to be morally right or wrong without any justification whatsoever, simply because the individual feels that he cannot act or decide differently. This is moral justification by fiat. It is not subject to adjudication, and it is inscrutable and incorrigible since a) the individual claims to be the only and the final judge, and b) no explanation or giving of reasons is necessary because the whole point of a judgment of conscience is that the verdict should depend entirely on the say-so of the conscientious agent. Obviously, we presume that the agent who judges himself by appealing to his conscience will be extremely scrupulous in reaching his decision, will deliberate seriously and be sincere enough to accept the verdict of his conscience whatever it may turn out to be. Nevertheless, an ethics of conscience, while it may stipulate such rules and criteria, cannot demand that the agent justify to others that he actually heed or satisfy them. As soon as we require that the agent must also justify his actions or motives to others, we have shifted ground and are operating within the framework of an ethics of responsibility rather than conscience. If this is correct, then an ethics of conscience is as dubious as a private language, and similar arguments can be advanced against it. Now it can be objected that our moral intuition tells us that there is a legitimate role for moral conscience, and our moral practice honors conscientious decisions. We think that there must be a role for conscience precisely because not everything can be determined on the basis of a categorical imperative or by estimating the potential benefit for the greatest number of people, for instance. Hegel would agree with this intuition and practice. He explicitly allows conscience a place in our moral practice in the Philosophy of Right.191 His point in the Phenomenology is, however, that with the breakdown of the ethical substance after the ethical order of the Ancients no firm basis exists anymore for the development of a universal ethical content of conscience. If we allow conscience to play a role we want to be sure that the norms informing it are universally recognized and shared by the community. Without such a basis, and without an “ethical disposition” to boot an ethics of conscience becomes a private morality whose norms are 190 Incidentally, this sound much like the characterization of the relationship between individual and universal in the chapter on Reason. The difference, however, consists in the fact that the content of the individual’s ethical beliefs is now the ethical substance, not abstractly rational ad hoc principles. Also note the direct identification of Spirit with individual consciousness. 191 On the role of conscience in Hegel’s Philosophy of Right see Brinkmann, 2003b, pp. 250–258.
3.6
The Internalization of Spirit: From Ethical Substance to the Spiritual Individual
199
at the disposal of each individual. Interestingly, when Kant discusses conscience in the Metaphysics of Morals, he, too, does not provide any other content for it than the general idea of duty.192 That the verdict of conscience is incorrigible and inscrutable does not mean, however, that others must refrain from evaluating a moral decision based on conscience. To the contrary, the fact that an agent expects his conscientious decision to be respected by others in and of itself constitutes an admission that the verdict of one’s conscience claims universal recognition. Generally speaking, if morality by definition concerns not only duties to oneself but also duties to others it must be legitimate to adjudicate the moral quality of motivations and actions affecting others from a third person point of view. More importantly, however, morality is also the way in which what we are to ourselves is displayed to others, or it concerns our being-for-others insofar as it is supposed to be identical with our being-forourselves. Sincerity and honesty are therefore crucial for morality. There is no other relationship in which we stand to others generally that requires that we show ourselves to be the person “on the outside” that we are also “on the inside”, so to speak. Morality is the window through which others gain insight into our inner being. As moral beings we are not windowless monads. Morality as a relationship to others concerns the exteriority of our interiority, a showing to others of who we are “in truth”. This is the condition of the possibility to pass moral judgment on others. But not only that. To the extent that as persons and agents we are dependent on the recognition by others of who we are, we are not fully ourselves unless we are recognized by others as moral beings or persons, i.e. unless we enable others to determine whether our persona corresponds to our essential being. To let oneself be judged as a moral being is thus not an option that we have, it is a requirement for our existence as persons. The incorrigibility and the inscrutability of a judgment of conscience cannot eliminate its intrinsic demand for recognition.193 For an ethics of conscience, however, there exists the discrepancy mentioned above between the inscrutability of the moral claim on the part of the agent and the ability of others to evaluate the sincerity of a judgment of conscience. Hegel uses the inherent contradiction to trigger a dialectic between a judging and an acting consciousness that are at first diametrically opposed to one another until they supersede their alienation in the moment of reciprocal forgiveness. The details of the development need not occupy us here.194 Suffice it to say that the judging conscientious consciousness exemplifies the immediate identity of universality and individuality while the acting conscientious consciousness embodies the immediate identity of particularity and individuality. Both are the result of the two contrasting attitudes one may develop in
192 Cf.
MM VI 401. does indeed develop a scenario in which the conscientious decisions of everyone would be accepted without question by everybody else and then shows that such a community of “moral geniuses” would soon degenerate into a state of total hypocrisy (cf. PS §§ 648–658/3, 477–484). 194 For a reconstruction of the argument see Brinkmann, 2003b. 193 Hegel
200
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
response to the dilemma just described, viz. the claim of the judgment of conscience to be recognized as valid by others and the impossibility of assessing its sincerity due to its inscrutability. The judging consciousness for its part concludes from this that any action will necessarily compromise the purity of its motivation and therefore declines to act at all.195 It does, however, relate to the particularity of the acting consciousness as the universal consciousness, the one that insists on duty as the standard of one’s motivations and actions, and as such passes judgment on it. The acting consciousness draws the opposite conclusion that to be moral is an impossibility, that there is no harmony of abstract duty and particular motivation, and that the best one can do is pretend to have acted morally, a pretense made possible by the inscrutability of one’s conscience. But to pretend to be moral is worse than being immoral without pretending to be the opposite. It in fact means to be “hypocritical” and “evil” (PS § 660/3, 485), not just bad. Judging consciousness therefore regards the acting consciousness as evil. It second-guesses its motivation and declares it to be “selfish” (PS § 665/3, 488). Acting consciousness sins against morality itself by posing as a moral being while hiding its being-for-self from the judging consciousness. Its moral identity becomes opaque. Judging consciousness does not fare any better, however. Its withdrawal to the position of inaction is itself hypocritical. It is an admission that acting from duty is possible only if one does not act – an open contradiction that judging consciousness masks by declaring its passing of moral judgments to be as good as acting. It expects “its words without deeds to be taken for a superior kind of reality” (PS § 666/3, 489). Judging consciousness thus reveals itself as “base” (ibid.). Cynical acting consciousness recognizes itself in its opposite and “gives expression to their common identity” by confessing its wickedness to the judging consciousness. Its expectation that its sincerity will be honored by the judging consciousness and that the latter will therefore extend its forgiveness to the former is harshly disappointed. The judging consciousness “repels this community of nature, and is the hard heart that is for itself, and which rejects any continuity with the other” (PS § 667/3, 490). No “reciprocal similar confession” is forthcoming. The acrimonious stand-off between the two protagonists becomes even more acrimonious. The reaction of the judging consciousness makes sense, however. First, by its confession the confessing consciousness invites the judging consciousness to admit to its own insincerity since it looks at the latter as his equal. This equality, however, the judging consciousness cannot accept – after all, in its identification with the standpoint of pure duty it deems itself to be superior to the acting consciousness. Consequently, it “rejects any continuity with the other.” Second, the forgiveness coming from a consciousness that is itself hypocritical would not be worth having. As a result, the dialectic between the two consciousnesses needs to be prolonged in such a way that the “hard heart” comes to realize its own insincerity. Only then will it be ready to recognize itself in the acting consciousness it condemned. But even this cannot be the ultimate resolution of their antithesis since the
195 Hegel’s “beautiful soul”. For the literary background to the chapter on Forgiveness see Speight, 2001, pp. 94–121.
3.6
The Internalization of Spirit: From Ethical Substance to the Spiritual Individual
201
mere mutual acknowledgement of their essential particularity (i.e., their “baseness”) would not mean their mutual redemption. They must also realize that their universality and continuity with each other is more important and “stronger” than their particularity. In rejecting the confession of the acting consciousness, judging consciousness, too, sins against the spirit of morality since he “refuses to let his own inner being come forth into the outer existence of speech” and “confronts the confession of the penitent with his own stiff-necked unrepentant character, mutely keeping himself to himself” (ibid.). What the acting consciousness did, viz. to offer to “surrender its one-sided, unacknowledged existence of its particular being-for-self” (PS § 669/3, 492), judging consciousness must likewise do. Through its confession, the acting consciousness had let go of its self-righteousness. In repulsing this opening up of the inner being of the acting consciousness, the judging consciousness puts itself in the wrong – now it insists on the atomicity of its singularity and fails to realize its equality with the other. However, by letting go of its exclusionary being-for-self the confessing consciousness had displayed itself “as in fact a universal” (PS § 670/3, 492), i.e. as someone who is able to posit his particularity “as a moment” (PS § 669/3, 492) rather than an essence. Judging consciousness that takes itself to be the protagonist of the universality of duty can now finally recognize itself in the other. It renounces the divisive thought, and the hard-heartedness of the being-for-self which clings to it, because it has in fact seen itself in the first [i.e., the confessing consciousness]” (PS § 670/3, 492).
With this we have finally arrived at the moment of forgiveness Hegel had pointed to as far back as the beginning of the chapter on Self-Consciousness. The judging consciousness abandons its “subjectively determined judgment” [sein fürsichseiendes bestimmendes Urteil] (PS § 670/3, 492) at last. The “word of reconciliation” is the objectively existent Spirit, which beholds the pure knowledge of itself qua universal essence, in its opposite, in the pure knowledge of itself qua absolutely self-contained and exclusive individuality – a reciprocal recognition which is absolute Spirit (ibid.).
The complicated structure Hegel suggests here involves several levels of recognition that may perhaps be analyzed as follows. On a first level, Hegel’s characterization is about the two consciousnesses we have been discussing, one of which represented the identity of individuality and particularity (= acting consciousness), the other that of individuality and universality (= judging consciousness). After the acting consciousness had given up or “negated” its particularity through the confession of its false pretense to universality the judging consciousness comes to see that its insistence on the identity of universality with its individuality likewise affects it with particularity. Its pretension to universality is therefore equally false. Both consciousnesses, then, recognize the contradiction between their pretense to universality – i.e. to being exclusively and categorically in the right – and acknowledge their pretentiousness to each other. This means that they now each realize their true identity as individuals who are necessarily particular, i.e. finite, but through
202
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
the act of forgiveness nonetheless are capable of superseding their finitude and thus of transforming their individuality into a moment of the universality that they both actualize through uttering the “word of reconciliation”.196 The two consciousnesses are thus both a self-consciousness that qua individual knows itself to be at bottom a particularized universality. This knowledge makes them each a concrete universal, i.e. a particularized universal existing as an individual. They are equal in their individual identity in that they both exhibit the structure of the Notion (note the plural “Notions” in the following quote): For these Notions, while specifically different, are yet simultaneously in themselves universal, such that they fill out the entire compass of the self . . . for one determination [of the two determinations of the Notion], viz. the absolute universal, is just as much pure self-knowledge as the other, viz. the absolute discreteness of singularity, and both [sc. determinations] are merely this pure self-knowledge (PS § 671/3, 493–494, my translation).
In other words, both selves are totalities and are therefore one, since qua universal they are indistinguishable. And yet they are also individuated like monads. They must, then, be mirrors of one another. As a result, while being “Notions”, the two selves are not the Notion. Instead they are individual moments of the Notion that possess the structure of the larger whole they instantiate. On a second level, therefore, the two selves in question not only recognize each other as individuals that are equal but also as individuals that are both exponents of the same universal substance. They re-establish the “continuity” among themselves that the confessing consciousness had recognized and that the hard heart had initially rejected. Not only do they re-establish that continuity, they also acknowledge it as the overriding factor in their relationship to each other, i.e. qua individuals they subordinate their individuality to their shared universality in the moment of reconciliation. This is the other side of giving up their particularity as a feature that separates and antagonizes them and thereby makes them atomic singularities vis-à-vis each other. Looked at in this way, the universality of the Notion emerges in and through the act of mutual forgiveness. It is in this sense that Hegel says that the word of reconciliation is the “objectively existent spirit”. Insofar as each self beholds its essential universality in the other that, for each, is simultaneously perceived as an “absolutely self-contained and exclusive individuality”, i.e. as a Notion or concrete universality, they are aware of the fact that their commonality constitutes their true essence. They perceive themselves as essentially belonging together even though as individuals they are and remain separate singularities. Spirit that exists objectively becomes actual through “the reconciling Yea, in
196 The reconciliation of the two selves consists and exists for Hegel essentially in an act of speech. It is through language in the sense of parole that forgiveness manifests itself and gains actuality (cf. PS § 667/3, 491). Hegel could make a good case for claiming to have been the first speech act theorist. Language in the sense of parole is “the existence of Spirit” or the existence of “selfconsciousness for others, self-consciousness which as such is immediately present, and as this self-consciousness is universal” (PS § 652/3, 478–479).
3.6
The Internalization of Spirit: From Ethical Substance to the Spiritual Individual
203
which the two “I”s let go their antithetical existence (PS § 671/3, 494). Objectively existing spirit is the existence of the ‘I’ which has expanded into a duality, and therein remains identical with itself, and, in its complete externalization and opposite, possesses the certainty of itself: it is God manifest in the midst of those who know themselves in the form of pure knowledge (ibid.).
The reference to an expansion into a duality echoes the emergence of a “We” that had been announced at the beginning of Self-Consciousness, but that can only now be consummated. This “We” thus reveals itself as the community of those who forgive each other or, rather, have always already forgiven each other, i.e. a community of believers whose brotherly and sisterly love for each other signifies the parousia or living presence of the divine spirit. God is here understood as the unifying bond of brotherly and sisterly love that both emerges from and supervenes upon those who forgive each other and transforms their “judgmental” moral relationship into one of love and charity: The wounds of the Spirit heal, and leave no scars behind. The deed is not imperishable; it is taken back by Spirit into itself, and the aspect of individuality present in it, whether as intention or as an existent negativity or limitation, straightway vanishes. The self that carries out the action, the form of its act, is only a moment of the whole, and so likewise is the knowledge that by its judgment determines and establishes the distinction between the individual and universal aspects of the action” (PS § 669/3, 492).
With the objectively existing spirit, therefore, we have finally arrived at the moment of the complete coincidence of ground and grounded. Ground and grounded are both spirit. The life of the community of those who forgive is nothing other than the presence – or the “presencing” – of the divine spirit, and the existence of the divine spirit is nothing other than the mutual love of the individual members of the community. If the latter withers, so will the former. There is no “beyond” here, no separation of the divine (ground) from the human (grounded). The divine is the immanent universal substance of the community of those who have forgiven and have been forgiven. Religion forms the topic of the Phenomenology’s next chapter, because it is the way in which the identity of human spirituality and divine presence manifests itself. By calling the objective reality of spirit “absolute Spirit”, as we saw above (cf. PS § 670/3, 493), Hegel makes yet another point. The community of those who have forgiven each other exhibits the structure of the Notion or of the One itself, i.e. the singularity that is simultaneously a plurality. But this One is not only an objectively existing One but a One that is conscious of itself. At a third level of analysis, then, the community of believers represents spirit that is implicitly conscious of itself as such. As Hegel makes clear at the beginning of the chapter on Religion, consciousness has up to this point been conscious of spirit in various ways, as the supersensible in Consciousness, as a beyond for which self-consciousness yearns in the Unhappy Consciousness, as the Divine Law or as morality in Spirit (cf. PS §§ 673–6/3, 495–496). However, in these preceding “shapes” of consciousness spirit
204
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
has not yet attained to a self-consciousness of itself. Spirit has so far been conscious of itself only in the sense that the individual consciousness itself is implicitly spirit. However, as a self whose object-consciousness is still perceived to be other than itself – the internal opposition we talked about earlier –, consciousness could have spirit for its object only in ways that concealed the fact that the object was indeed spirit itself. The supersensible or the postulated world in which morality and happiness coincide are not spirit in the form of spirit because they are not spirit in the form of subjectivity. Instead, they are spirit in disguise, as it were. But, claims Hegel, in conscience that has forgiven spirit “brings itself, as well as its objective world in general, into subjection . . . and is now a self-consciousness that communes with its own self” (PS § 677/3, 497). It takes a consciousness that has become an instance of spirit to recognize spirit as spirit – or it takes one to know one, as the saying goes. And an instantiation of spirit is what consciousness has now become.197 The resolution of the standoff between the two conscientious consciousnesses through reciprocal forgiveness therefore creates a self-referential totality in which “Spirit . . . knows itself as Spirit” (PS § 673/3, 495). What exactly this self-knowledge of spirit involves will be a topic for the following section.
3.7 Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing With the moment of forgiveness we seem to have made the final step in the complex and drawn out argument of the Phenomenology. What reason is there, we might ask, then, to proceed any further, if mutual reconciliation through forgiveness lets emerge absolute spirit? Has not everything been accomplished that needed to be accomplished? Has not the object of consciousness become the subject that grounds consciousness and of which consciousness now knows itself to be a moment? All this has indeed been demonstrated or at least attempted, and it has even become apparent for consciousness and not for us only. If, then, the argument of the Phenomenology has not yet come to a close it must be because some internal opposition or oppositions still remain to be overcome. The opening sections of the Religion chapter explain wherein these internal oppositions consists. The systematic role of the chapter on Religion is complicated by the fact that it forms the middle term of the argument of the Phenomenology as a whole whose extremes, so to speak, are formed by the chapters from Consciousness through Spirit on the one hand and the chapter on Absolute Knowing on the other. Earlier I suggested that overall the Phenomenology exhibits a tripartite structure, the first part of which comprises the chapters from Consciousness through Spirit, with Religion as the second, and Absolute Knowing as the third part. In an attempt to describe
197 Note that at PS § 671/3, 493 the two consciousnesses are referred to as “these two self-certain Spirits” and “these Notions.”
3.7
Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing
205
the roles played by these parts I suggested that the first part constitutes consciousness’ lived experience of its ascent from sense-knowledge to spirit while religion parallels this same ascent, albeit now from the other side, as it were, i.e. from the point of view of spirit and insofar as spirit’s own development is represented by consciousness. Finally, in Absolute Knowing consciousness qua spirit comprehends that its lived experience and its represented self-development are two sides of the same coin. Absolute knowledge consists in the realization that the experience of consciousness and the faith of religion are like the body and soul of spirit, which are both incarnations of spirit’s own concept. The Phenomenology’s overall architectonic thus follows the well-known Hegelian sequence of spirit existing in-itself in consciousness’ experience (spirit in immediacy), spirit existing for-itself or representing itself to itself in religion (spirit as such as object of consciousness), and spirit existing in-and-for-itself or comprehending its nature as a thinking that is operative in both incarnations. Looked at from the point of view of consciousness, this same process may be articulated as follows. (1) Consciousness recognizes its other as spirit (= Consciousness through Spirit); (2) consciousness recognizes itself in spirit (= Religion); (3) consciousness recognizes that its object, viz. spirit, is its own self (= Absolute Knowing). Insofar as spirit comprehends the identity of what it is in-itself and what it is for-itself it is absolute spirit, i.e. spirit that knows itself as itself, it is noesis noeseos, thought thinking itself. In what follows, I will discuss this structure in some more detail. Because spirit in Religion forms the middle term between spirit in immediacy, or spirit as it makes its appearance in human consciousness, and spirit as absolute knowledge, it must, according to Hegel’s dialectic, which here follows what he will later call the “logic of essence”, contain spirit in immediacy within itself, albeit as a superseded and dependent moment. The history of human consciousness will therefore in some way be reflected in the history of spirit that has itself for object. Or, just because the history of human consciousness must be reflected in spirit in Religion, this spirit will again display itself in different forms, although not in the way in which it appeared in the history of human consciousness. There, spirit was not yet known by consciousness to be spirit proper, i.e. spirit as selfconsciousness. The history of the experience of consciousness will therefore be recapitulated in Religion, but now as a history of the consciousness of spirit as spirit or as the history of the self-consciousness of spirit, whereas previously, in Consciousness through Spirit, consciousness was conscious of spirit not as selfconsciousness but of spirit as a world that took the form of thinghood, laws, culture, or of a postulated kingdom of grace and for which spirit proper was still a beyond, except for the moment of forgiveness. Simply put, we are still focusing on the relationship between consciousness and its object, except that now the object of consciousness is known by consciousness to be spirit itself, whereas previously it knew its object only as object or substance. In Religion, then, substance is subject for consciousness from the start. This is what we generally understand by saying that in religion man relates to God. God, for Hegel, is spirit that knows itself as spirit. God is therefore the object and content of human consciousness in Religion. To clarify and emphasize the difference between spirit as immediate object
206
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
of consciousness in Consciousness through Spirit and spirit as object of consciousness in Religion, Hegel points out that spirit as it appears in Religion, viz. spirit as self-consciousness or subject, is no longer a transcendent beyond but rather “the universal Spirit that contains within itself all essence and all actuality” (PS § 677/3, 497). This is the spirit as a totality that contains human consciousness and the world as its moments. To mark the distinction between spirit in immediacy and spirit as self-conscious subject terminologically, Hegel refers to the former as “Spirit in its world,” “Spirit’s existence,” “immediate Spirit, which is not yet consciousness of Spirit,” “Spirit in its mundane existence” or “consciousness proper” – which comprises “consciousness, self-consciousness, Reason, and Spirit” as its moments – (PS § 679/3, 499), and to the latter as “self-knowing Spirit” (PS § 677/3, 496), “self-conscious Spirit,” “Spirit conscious of itself as Spirit,” “Spirit in religion” (PS § 678/3, 497) or “Spirit as such” (PS § 679/3, 498). In other words, these two forms of spirit are the ones that underlie the first and second part of the Phenomenology’s overall argument, respectively. The two are said to be different such that “Spirit’s existence is distinct from its selfconsciousness” (PS § 678/3, 497). However, since spirit’s existence is now a moment within spirit as such this difference carries over into spirit in Religion – the first of the internal oppositions we suspected must still be present. Furthermore, since spirit in Religion “contains the previous structured shapes” (ibid.) of “Spirit in its mundane existence,” we will not be surprised to learn that the forms of religion and their varieties correlate with certain cognitive modes of consciousness such as the religion of light with sense-certainty (PS § 686/3, 505), religions that associate divine power with plants and animals with perception (PS § 689/3, 507) – albeit now a “spiritual perception” (ibid.) – or religion in the form of art with the “ethical Spirit” of the Ancients (PS § 700/3, 512), to mention a few. The fact that Religion will recapitulate the history of human consciousness in a different form does not mean, however, that the chapter on Religion is merely about the ways in which humans have conceived of the divine throughout history. Still less does it mean that Hegel believes the content of religious faith to be essentially a human construct or a projection of the human imagination à la Feuerbach such that the Religion chapter would contain a series of human ideas about the divine. To the contrary, for Hegel the core idea around which the Religion chapter revolves is that spirit here is, and is known by human consciousness to be, conscious of itself. “Spirit in religion” is “Spirit conscious of itself as Spirit” (PS § 678/3, 497). Since spirit in Religion is self-consciousness, a self relating to itself, we find that the same I = I formula forms the structural basis of the Religion chapter that became fundamental for the development in “consciousness proper” from Self-Consciousness through Spirit. Here is the point, therefore, at which the methodological complication of the Religion chapter comes clearly to the fore. For, as we can now see, spirit in Religion must be the object of consciousness in a dual sense. To the extent that spirit in Religion contains human consciousness as its moment, human consciousness will be conscious of spirit as (divine) subject. To the extent that spirit in Religion is conscious of itself, however, spirit will have itself for object, i.e. the content of its
3.7
Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing
207
object-consciousness will be itself. Evidently, the same cannot be said of human consciousness, since the object of its consciousness is not itself but rather the divine spirit. In other words, there is here yet another opposition within spirit as such that needs to be resolved. On the one hand, spirit has itself for object, on the other spirit is the object of human consciousness, which on its part is not spirit as such, but only a moment within spirit. Now this situation might just mean – as I believe it does in the case of Aristotle’s noesis noeseos – that human consciousness of the divine can never really be the same as the divine self-consciousness. But not so for Hegel, or at least not quite. For Hegel has already made human consciousness a moment of absolute spirit. More importantly, he must also assume that absolute spirit can be conscious of itself and know itself only through human consciousness, even to the extent that human consciousness is the form in which absolute spirit exists or has Dasein. Without existing as such in human consciousness, spirit would remain a beyond. Admittedly, it is not any one individual consciousness through which the divine is conscious of itself (except in the shape of the “divine Man”, PS § 781/3, 568), but “the life of the [religious] community” (PS § 766/3, 557; cf. § 781/3, 568). The communal life that celebrates the reconciliation and the unity of the human and the divine is Hegel’s answer to the question how absolute spirit can be conscious of itself. It is conscious of itself in and through the worshipping of God in religion (as well as, in the Encyclopedia system, through the works of art and through philosophical thought). The piousness of the religious community is thus for Hegel the presence of the divine on earth. The divine spirit “dwells in His community, dies in it every day, and is daily resurrected” (PS § 784/3, 571). Mortals are immortal, immortals mortal, the ones living the death of the others and the others dying the life of the former, to quote Heraclitus. The fact that spirit is conscious of itself in a dual sense allows Hegel to derive the strategic contradiction that is necessary to propel the development of spirit in Religion forward and to implement what Hegel calls “the perfection of religion” (PS § 678/3, 497). The object of the divine self-consciousness is itself, I = I. At the same time, however, the divine is also the object of human consciousness and, crucially, human consciousness and its object must also be the consciousness through which the divine is conscious of itself. However, just because the development of spirit in Religion recapitulates the history of human consciousness, divine spirit cannot initially be conscious of itself through human consciousness as a self that is equal to itself. To put it differently, while spirit’s self-consciousness in Religion is in principle equal to itself, it is unequal to itself insofar as spirit is represented by human consciousness. The development in Religion will therefore consist in delineating the process through which human consciousness becomes the self of divine self-consciousness, which for Hegel, as we have just seen, happens in the case of the religious community of revealed religion. Insofar as this community constitutes the parousia of the divine that is conscious of spirit as subject, spirit through it relates only to itself. The two sides of the I = I formula will then have become equal again, spirit will be conscious of itself as subject in its object-consciousness. At that moment,
208
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
[t]he distinction which was made between actual Spirit and Spirit that knows itself as Spirit, or between itself, qua consciousness, and qua self-consciousness, is superseded in the Spirit that knows itself in its truth; its consciousness and its self-consciousness are [at that moment] on the same level (PS § 682/3, 501).
The equality of spirit’s object-consciousness and self-consciousness marks the moment of the transition from Religion to Absolute Knowing, and it will be reached in revealed religion.198 But why, we need to ask yet again, is a transition to absolute knowing required, and in what could its absolute knowledge possibly consist? If Spirit’s own consciousness has become identical with its self through the life of the religious community, what else has still been left unaccomplished? Why is not the identity of God with Christ (who for Hegel is synonymous with mankind and the world) and his being reflected in the worship and active love of the religious community itself already the highest form of self-relationship in which self and other are completely the same in content? It is helpful to remind ourselves again what the purpose of the Phenomenology was supposed to be, viz. the demonstrated overcoming of the opposition of consciousness. To examine Hegel’s argument primarily from this methodological perspective has been our guideline from the start. And the answer will have to be the very same that we gave just now with respect to the transition from Spirit to Religion: If the argument is still incomplete at the end of the Religion chapter, it must be because there is yet another (internal) opposition that needs to be transcended. We have reason to suspect, however, that this ultimate opposition will differ from the preceding ones, since the opposition between consciousness and religious spirit has already been overcome due to the lived identity of divine and human spirit in the religious community of the revealed religion. What, then, are we to make of the following remarks with which the chapter on Absolute Knowing opens? Hegel there says that [t]he Spirit of the revealed religion has not yet surmounted its consciousness as such, or what is the same, its actual self-consciousness is not the object of its consciousness; Spirit itself as a whole, and the self-differentiated moments within it, fall within the sphere of representational thought [das Vorstellen] and in the form of objectivity. The content of this representational thinking is absolute Spirit; and all that now remains to be done is to supersede this mere form . . . (PS § 788/3, 575, modified after Miller).
Hegel claims that there is still a difference of form that needs to come, even though the contents of the object-consciousness (“I”) and consciousness of religious spirit (“I”) have already become identical. mal difference is attributed to “representational thought” or to “the
be overthe selfThe forform of
198 This formulation anticipates structurally the one in E § 6 according to which “it is the supreme and ultimate purpose of science to bring about the reconciliation of the reason that is conscious of itself with the reason that is, or actuality, through the cognition of this accord.” The fulfillment of this purpose is the goal of the Encyclopedia system as a whole. Consequently, Absolute Knowing, which achieves the same goal, is the foundation of the system (and of the idea of spirit), not just the foundation of the Logic.
3.7
Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing
209
objectivity”.199 A little later in the text, the task of overcoming this difference is referred to as a “reconciliation of consciousness with self-consciousness” (PS § 794/3, 579). So is it not the case that precisely this difference of form has also already been overcome, and overcome twice even, once in the act of forgiveness at the end of the chapter on Spirit and then again at the end of Religion? Hegel’s claim seems to become even more bewildering when immediately following the above quote he confirms this assumption by continuing . . . or rather, since this [sc. difference of form] belongs to consciousness as such, its truth must already have yielded itself in the shape of consciousness (PS § 788/3, 575).
In other words, the overcoming of the ordinary idea of objectivity with its opposition of objective reality or truth on one hand and its representation or reflection in the mind on the other has indeed been overcome “in the shape of consciousness”, i.e. by and for consciousness. On the other hand, however, it is also the case, Hegel claims, that what “now remains to be done” is to “supersede this mere form,” as we just saw. We seem to be confronted with a contradiction, then. As usual, it is a contradiction that is used to motivate a resolution. After all, in Hegel’s dialectic contradictions are a means to propel the argument forward. They are neither the result of faulty reasoning nor can they be left standing. How, in the light of this, can the contradictory statements that the representational mode of thought has been overcome and that it equally still needs to be overcome be reconciled with each other? It seems to me that in this situation Hegel has no other recourse than the old and tried Aristotelian method of distinguishing between different aspects of one and the same thing or claim. The failure of the understanding, according to Hegel, is not that it distinguishes between different aspects of one and the same thing or proposition, even if what Hegel says in this respect in the sub-chapter on Perception sounded polemical enough.200 Indeed, without such analytical distinguishing no progress in intelligibility could be achieved. Rather, Hegel’s critique is directed against the understanding’s habit of keeping the distinguished aspects apart for fear of falling into contradiction should a serious attempt be made at unifying them again. Hegel’s
199 Miller’s translation uses “picture-thinking” for Vorstellen. As we explained earlier, what Hegel means by Vorstellen as a technical term is the common philosophical conception of a referentiality of thought where thinking is supposed to relate to a mind-independent reality which is typically assumed to be represented by some mental content or other, be it a Cartesian or Lockean “idea”, a Kantian Vorstellung or some representational mental content as in contemporary philosophy of mind. The important point is that “representational thinking” for Hegel captures the idea of a relationship between some mental content on one hand and a reality or object “out there” on the other. 200 See, for instance, PS § 130/3, 105: “The sophistry of perception seeks to save these [conflicting] moments [of a being-for-self which is also not a being-for-self] from their contradiction, and it seeks to lay hold on the truth, by distinguishing between the aspects, by sticking to the “Also” and the “in so far”, and finally, by distinguishing the “unessential” aspect from an “essence” which is opposed to it. But these expedients, instead of warding off deception . . . prove themselves on the contrary to be quite empty . . ..”
210
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
“expedient” in the current situation is to qualify the two resolutions of the opposition of consciousness that have already been accomplished, i.e. the one at the end of Spirit and the other at the end of Religion, as representing spirit’s self-knowledge as it is for-itself and as it is in-itself, respectively: This reconciliation of consciousness with self-consciousness thus shows itself as brought about from two sides; on one side, in the religious Spirit, and on the other side, in consciousness itself as such. The difference between them is that in the former this reconciliation is in the form of being-in-itself, or implicit being, and in the latter in the explicit form of beingfor-self. . . . The unification of the two sides has not yet been exhibited; it is this that closes the series of the shapes of Spirit, for in it Spirit attains to a knowledge of itself not only as it is in-itself or as possessing an absolute content, nor only as it is for-itself as a form devoid of content, or as the aspect of self-consciousness, but as it is in- and for-itself (PS § 794/3, 579, with modifications after Miller).
Several things are remarkable about this passage. First, we see that Hegel does indeed offer a resolution to the above-mentioned contradiction in the way indicated. Although the “reconciliation” has already happened twice, it has happened in a one-sided form each time, i.e. in the form of the for-itself and that of the in-itself, respectively. Consequently, the two moments of reconciliation need to be connected and unified in order to complete the identity of the knowledge spirit has of its communion with itself in and through consciousness as such on one hand and religious consciousness on the other. This is the task still to be achieved in order to bring the “series of the shapes of Sprit” to a close. Second, our earlier suggestion regarding the overall structure of the Phenomenology is now confirmed. The argument did indeed come to a preliminary close at the end of the chapter on Spirit and to another preliminary close at the end of Religion. This means that the three parts of the Phenomenology, i.e. Consciousness through Spirit, Religion, and Absolute Knowing, constitute three “shapes of Spirit”, not consciousness, and that the shapes of consciousness of which Hegel speaks in the Introduction form the individual moments or stages within these moments of spirit (except for Absolute Knowing, which contains no shapes of consciousness at all). Third, in retrospect Hegel now also admits that the entire experience of consciousness from Consciousness through Religion is in fact to be understood as the process through which Spirit comes to know itself. In other words, the fact that consciousness is only a moment of spirit or the Notion is an implicit premise from the start, as we pointed out earlier with reference to the Encyclopedia version of the Phenomenology, and that the argument is in this sense unavoidably, if not fatally, circular. (It is “Platonic” in the sense that it makes one see what someone else who is therefore able to act as a guide or midwife has already seen.) For this reason, the Phenomenology is the “science of the appearance of Spirit”, viz. the science of how spirit displays itself from the point of view of consciousness. The “Thises”, “Heres” and “Nows” of sense-certainty are, as we said earlier, spirit in disguise. The initial experience of consciousness in sense-certainty and perception is thus as much a “disclosure” of spirit as it is “in fact concealment” (PS § 801/3, 584), a concealment which – unlike the Heideggerian concealment of being – is then successively removed in synchrony with consciousness’ ascent and “purification”. Fourth, we
3.7
Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing
211
may be surprised to gather from the above quote that in point of dialectical sequence the moment of spirit’s being-for-itself precedes the moment of its being-in-itself. This looks like a reversal of the typical dialectical progression from the in-itself to the for-itself that we find in every dialectical triad.201 The irregularity is important enough for Hegel to mention it explicitly. He points out that consciousness as such (i.e., consciousness from Sense-Certainty through Forgiveness) “reached the individual moments of those shapes [of consciousness] and their unification long before ever religion gave its object the shape of actual self-consciousness” (PS § 794/3, 579). The priority of the reconciliation in and through consciousness as such should, however, not be taken in a temporal sense, since chronologically speaking the development in religious consciousness obviously does not begin only after the moment of forgiveness at the end of the Spirit has occurred, but rather must be roughly contemporaneous with the experiential stages of consciousness proper.202 The reason why the usual order of precedence is seemingly reversed can therefore only be methodological. First, one could argue that the experience of consciousness proper is the more immediate experience of spirit as compared to religious consciousness. In this immediate experience of consciousness, however, the object exists entirely for it, i.e. on the surface or in externality, and its deeper meaning or in-itself is still hidden from it.203 But secondly, taking into consideration the architectonic of the later system, the Encyclopedia Phenomenology, which contains consciousness proper, forms the second moment of Subjective Spirit and hence does indeed occupy the position of subjective spirit’s being-for-self in that context. Hegel next argues that this “unification,” i.e. the one between mundane and religious spirit, has already happened, and again happened twice, once in consciousness itself as such and then again in revealed religion (cf. PS § 795/3, 579). This constitutes a second reconciliation after the one just discussed between self-consciousness with consciousness. However, this reconciliation or synthesis has occurred “in principle” (ibid.) only and with a qualification on both sides. It is true that on the side of religious spirit the representational form had been overcome at the very end through the “return of representational thinking into self-consciousness” (ibid., my
201 For instance, the Logic is organized in such a way that the Logic of Being is supposed represent
the Notion in-itself, the Logic of Essence the Notion for-itself, and the Logic of the Notion the Notion in and for itself (cf. E § 83). But each lower triad down to the elementary dialectical triad of, say, in-itself, being-for-another, and their unity called determination in the triad titled “Something and an Other” (cf. SL 117–20/WdL I 104–107) exhibits the same structure. 202 To reconstruct an exact parallel between the sequence within these two moments of spirit might nonetheless be difficult, a difficulty due in part, I assume, to the initial “work in progress” character of the Phenomenology. 203 For a different explanation of this reversal of the order of precedence see J. Heinrichs’ succinct analysis of the concluding chapter of the Phenomenology in Heinrichs 1974, 473–476. Heinrichs does not seem to capture the significance of the next step in the argument, however, which we will discuss presently when he calls it a “repeated interpretation” and a “recapitulation” of the reconciliation through the act of forgiveness in PS §§ 795–6/3, 579–582. This does not detract, however, from Heinrichs’ superior analysis of the Phenomenology as a whole as well as its concluding chapter.
212
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
translation).204 Nonetheless, the reconciliation of mundane and religious spirit in religious spirit constitutes merely “the aspect of the in-itself which stands over against the movement of self-consciousness” (ibid.). That is to say, in religious spirit the reconciliation is believed to have been brought about by the divine power itself as a gift and an act of grace to men. Human consciousness therefore comports itself towards this event in a receptive way – religious consciousness is a believer’s consciousness, i.e. one that accepts the content of faith as a given truth. It is, however, crucial for Hegel that the truth should become real for consciousness in the sense that it be actively appropriated so that through its own action and experience consciousness brings about the certainty of its knowledge. As a result, the reconciliation proper must have occurred in the mode of being-for-itself through “this other aspect” (ibid.), viz. in mundane spirit, and there in the act of forgiveness at the end of Spirit. The self that forgives and is being forgiven contains the element of self-referentiality of the I = I not merely as a given content but as the product of its action. And yet, the reconciliation on the side of mundane spirit has occurred in the form of “a particular shape of consciousness” (ibid.) and not, we are supposed to supplement, in the form of spirit itself as a totality. Because of this limitation, the unification of the two shapes of spirit has been achieved only “in principle” so far. Hegel suggests that in order to complete this second reconciliation he must show how, in the act of forgiveness, the self-referentiality of spirit has already become actual or how, in other words, the self involved in the act of forgiveness “contains both its own self and its opposite, and not only implicitly or in a universal sense [as in revealed religion], but explicitly or in a developed and differentiated way” (ibid.). Only then will it be true that “what in religion was content or a form for presenting an other, is here [sc. in the act of forgiveness] the Self’s own act” (PS § 797/3, 582). Once this is demonstrated, we can see that the self-referentiality characteristic of both acts of reconciliation, the one in mundane spirit and the one in religious spirit, exhibits the structure of the “simple unity of the Notion” (PS § 795/3, 580). The details of this demonstration need not concern us here. Suffice it to say that Hegel now interprets the “beautiful soul” as an analogue of the divine spirit that externalizes itself in Christ as the representative of the finite human spirit whose humanity is redeemed and reconciled again with the divine in the emergence of the community of believers. The beautiful soul here stands for the divine as a judging consciousness or the moment of universality while Christ epitomizes the acting consciousness, i.e. the moment of particularity. As we suggested earlier, the act of forgiveness results
204 A good way to illustrate what Hegel means by the representational aspect of religion is to recall that Christian faith, for instance, is inherently eschatological. That is to say, the faithful knows that he or she has eternally been redeemed, that his or her sins have eternally been forgiven, and that they can be eternally assured of God’s benevolence, and yet he or she believes that the real redemption is still outstanding, that it has still to happen, that there will be a Second Coming of Christ and a Judgment Day at the end of time. In other words, an element of the opposition of consciousness, of an outstanding, but expected fulfillment that would be the real event, is still present. For Hegel, such representational thinking is a sign that what has actually occurred has not yet been fully comprehended.
3.7
Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing
213
in the “concrete universal” or plural totality and can thus be seen to exemplify the trinitarian structure of the Notion.205 In this way, the Notion has “fulfilled itself on one side in the self-assured Spirit that acted, and on the other in religion” (PS § 796/3, 580). With this, the second reconciliation, the one between mundane and religious spirit, is supposed to be completed. What, then, is the result of the reflective appropriation of this second reconciliation that had “in principle” already been accomplished? We should now be able to see, Hegel believes, first, that with this unification of mundane and religious spirit the “last shape of Spirit” has come before us. It emerges from the insight that each of these two shapes “in principle exhibits the life of Spirit in its entirety,” and that the life of spirit is nothing but the embodiment of the Notion since “the Notion in the form of the Notion” has now been identified by us on both sides (PS § 797/3, 582). This latter insight is in effect what the knowledge of absolute knowing consists in: This last shape of Spirit – the Spirit which at the same time gives its complete and true content the form of the Self and thereby realizes its Notion as remaining in its Notion in this realization – this is absolute knowing; it is Spirit that knows itself in the shape of Spirit, or a comprehending knowing. . . . As a result, that which is the very essence, viz. the Notion, has become the element of existence, or has become the form of objectivity for consciousness. Spirit, manifesting or appearing in consciousness in this element, or what is the same thing, produced in it by consciousness, is Science (PS § 798/3, 582–583, modified after Miller).
In other words, what Hegel calls science or, rather, the concept of science, is the realization or comprehension of the identity of mundane and religious spirit. Spirit as it understands and know itself – i.e., religious spirit – is certain of being the same spirit that has Dasein in the world. World and spirit are one – the structures of spirit are the structures of the world, thinking is objective thought. We are apparently witnesses here to the final step of Hegel’s argument. Consciousness has climbed the last rung of the ladder and has grasped the concept of philosophy as science that will be the foundation of Hegel’s Logic. The content of absolute knowing has now disclosed itself to consciousness or, rather, to thinking. What consciousness knows is that the standpoint of absolute knowing has been reached when spirit recognizes in the content that is nothing but itself the form of the self, i.e. the Notion, I = I.206 This means more than that the object of spirit has become the self of spirit, as in revealed religion. Rather, it means that the self that has itself for object has itself for object in the form of explicit self-referentiality. In its object it recognizes only itself, because the object is itself, i.e. it negates the non-identity between itself as self and itself as object and is thus simple communion with itself in the other, Bei-sich-sein-im-Anderen. However, to recognize itself in this way, it must recognize its own concept in its objectified self, since this objectified self, i.e. actual spirit, exists in externality. To recognize itself in its objectified
205 Hegel
develops this interpretation at PS §§ 795–796/3, 579/82. Nuzzo has pointed out that absolute knowing is a cognitive structure and that the absoluteness here at play is epistemological, not metaphysical. Absolute knowing is knowledge as the “absolute modality of philosophical knowledge”: see Nuzzo, 2003, p. 286, p. 277. 206 Angelica
214
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
self means, then, that spirit recognize its own essence in its existence and thus simultaneously its own essence as it exists.207 But its existence is its objectivity. That the truth be objective means that its existence be equal to its concept. Consequently, if spirit recognizes its own concept in the very form in which it exists in actuality, its knowledge of itself is objective – it is its inner truth replicated in externality. Absolute knowing therefore displays the structure of pure self-knowledge, or of I = I: . . . this knowing is a pure being-for-self of self-consciousness; it is ‘I’ that is this and no other ‘I’, and which is no less immediately a mediated or superseded universal ‘I’. It has a content which it differentiates from itself . . . This content is, in its difference, itself the ‘I’ . . . In it, as differentiated, the ‘I’ is reflected into itself; it is only when the ‘I’ communes with itself in its otherness [in seinem Anderssein bei sich selbst ist] that the content is comprehended [begriffen] (PS § 799/3, 583).
Absolute knowing exhibits the structure of self-recognition in an other that is not an other nor tautologically the self but whose otherness is just the element of the self’s existence.208 Not only, however, does absolute knowing have this structure. According to Hegel, comprehending knowledge (begreifendes Erkennen or begreifendes Wissen) in general has the form of the recognition of the identity of concept and object since comprehension (Begreifen) consists in grasping the concept of the object and in knowing that object and concept are the same in terms of conceptual structure. If they are the same, then knowledge is indeed objective, since this is what Hegel means by objective knowledge, viz. that the object correspond to its concept or that the concept capture the object.209 In other words, if what exists is identical with its own concept and if this is known to be the case, then such knowledge constitutes an objective truth. There is, however, one important difference between objective knowledge generally and absolute objective knowledge. In objective knowledge generally speaking the object need not, and for the most part does not, have the same conceptual structure as the self or thinking, i.e. it is not or not fully a self relating only to itself or a self-referential totality. Consequently, in objective knowledge as such the object must be shown to coincide with its concept and simultaneously be shown not to coincide with the Concept. If this difference
207 This
explains why Hegel understands the Cartesian thinking self that identifies with itself in an act of reflection essentially as a precursor of the standpoint of absolute knowing. The same holds mutatis mutandis for Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception and Fichte’s absolute I. The selfreferentiality of the Notion may also be discovered in Aristotle’s noesis noeseos, albeit with the qualification that despite its self-referentiality Aristotle’s Prime Mover is substance, not subject. 208 As Hegel comments elsewhere (E § 377), this is an expansion of the philosophical maxim gnothi seauton – Know thyself! – of the Ancients, enriched by the idea that such knowledge can be obtained only by appropriating what appears to be the externality of consciousness, i.e. the mind-independent world. 209 Cf. E § 213R, § 213A; E 24A2. Again, it is important to emphasize that the object correspond to its concept – not just to my representation or idea of it.
3.7
Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing
215
did not exist, all reality could be known only in the form of one indistinguishable whole, like a Parmenidean One.210 In the above quote from PS § 798/3, 582 Hegel claimed that the Notion or Concept which is the essence of spirit or its true conceptual structure has also become the element of spirit’s existence. We interpreted this to mean, not that actual spirit as such or spirit in existence has become identical with its concept or pure self (which is the Concept), but rather that the actual spirit exists in the form of or as the embodiment of its own Notion or Concept. According to this interpretation, there still remains a distinction between actual spirit and its concept or pure self. The pure self of spirit (“I” or Notion) recognizes itself in its embodied self (“I” qua embodied Notion) insofar as the embodied self is identical with or determined by the pure self or Notion. That spirit exists in the element of the Notion would then mean that its existence or actuality manifests itself or is determined by its Notion. I interpret this as saying that the Notion exists in externalized form in actual spirit such that the Notion is in this sense the “element” of spirit’s existence. Still, actual spirit is not merely the Notion, not merely the pure self, but the embodied Notion. If this is correct, there is yet another, albeit now an ultimate internal opposition within spirit, viz. its pure Notion as distinguishable from its embodiment. Neither is in fact separable from the other since spirit would not be spirit without its concept and its concept could not exist at all without being embodied. Nonetheless it is also true that spirit’s concept is only complete at the end of spirit’s actual history, for spirit that does not know itself as spirit is not spirit in its fully developed form. In other words, the science that grasps the concept of spirit can emerge only at the end of spirit’s development: As Spirit that knows what it is, it does not exist before, and nowhere at all, till after the completion of its work of compelling its imperfect ‘shape’ to procure for its consciousness the ‘shape’ of its essence [i.e. its own concept, the Notion], and in this way to equate its self-consciousness with its consciousness (PS § 800/3, 583).
Or again, . . . until Spirit has completed itself in itself [i.e. as spirit in history], until it has completed itself as world-Spirit, it cannot reach its consummation as self-conscious Spirit (PS § 802/3, 585).
In short, we face a final contradiction. Spirit and its concept are inseparable, and yet the concept of spirit – and thus philosophy as science – is said to surface only after spirit’s development is complete, i.e. at the end of the itinerary of the experience of consciousness that the Phenomenology has reconstructed. Put differently, the emergence of spirit’s concept presupposes its actual history – what Hegel here calls the world-spirit –, and yet spirit’s concept must also be presupposed from the start, if it is spirit that undergoes this history. But it seems that this cannot be since
210 Hegel’s dialectic will account for this difference by subjecting each synthesis to a completeness test with a view to its intrinsic determinacy (see Section 4.5 below).
216
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
at the beginning, for instance in Sense-Certainty or Perception, or even in SelfConsciousness, Reason, or Spirit, sprit is not spirit that knows itself as spirit. The conundrum can be put in a very simple form, viz. that the history of spirit must be presupposed for its concept to emerge at the end, but that likewise its concept must be presupposed for its history. The temporal existence of spirit is here opposed to spirit’s Notion, its externality to its interiority. The contradiction can only be resolved if one presupposition is claimed to be essential while the other becomes a necessary, but less essential moment, as we would expect on the basis of previous dialectical syntheses. It seems obvious that the concept of spirit must take precedence as the primary essential condition of the existence of spirit. From the point of view of logic we seem to have no other choice. Just as the sun alone cannot produce a man, so spirit cannot emerge out of what is not spirit, nor is the universal form of man already a man.211 We may want to say that spirit is at first undeveloped or underdeveloped,212 but this will not eliminate the problem that the essence of spirit must be present from the start. This would imply that its concept and hence science also be present from the start since self-knowledge belongs to its essence. However, this manifestly is not the case – or else both the history of spirit and the Phenomenology would be redundant. We are up against an aporia. It is reminiscent of the tension we detected earlier in the Phenomenology’s Introduction when Hegel seemed to say both that at the beginning of the Phenomenology Science has not yet appeared on the scene and that it nonetheless is able to hand consciousness the ladder with which to ascend to its standpoint. We are obviously dealing with the same aporia here. It will go away only, if we can say that the concept of spirit is indeed present from the start while at the same time its historical development is also necessary in some respect. In other words, it will go away only, if spirit, its history or temporality included, is timeless. This looks very much like a paradox, but it is the solution Hegel will eventually adopt in the Introduction to the Lectures on the History of Philosophy.213 It seems, however, that on the final pages of the Phenomenology he is not yet aware of the full force of the aporia. The solution he suggests there is to say that the externality of spirit, i.e. its development in time, is both constitutive of its concept as well as unessential for it. This, however, does not eliminate the dilemma that the concept of spirit must then be both timeless and dependent on time or that temporal spirit becomes timeless at the end of its development. It is in this context that Hegel speaks of the annulment (Tilgung) of time in the moment of spirit’s recognition of itself in its externality: Time is the Notion itself that is there and which presents itself to consciousness as empty intuition; for this reason, Spirit necessarily appears in Time, and it appears in Time just
211 Cf. Aristotle, Phys. II 2: “For a man owes his birth to another man and to the sun” – and not as Plato perhaps suggests in the Republic’s Sun simile, to the sun alone. 212 As Hegel also does: see PS § 801/3, 584. 213 We will take up this issue again in our concluding reflections in the next chapter. Hegel will thus come even closer to the changeless Parmenidean One.
3.7
Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing
217
so long as it has not grasped its pure Notion, i.e. it has not annulled Time. It is the outer, intuited pure Self which is not grasped by the Self, the merely intuited Notion; when this latter grasps itself it sets aside its Time-form, comprehends this intuiting, and is a comprehended and comprehending intuiting. Time, therefore, appears as the destiny and necessity of Spirit that is not yet complete within itself . . . (PS § 801/3, 584).
As we see, Hegel believes that he can have it both ways. Spirit is both temporal and atemporal. It is temporal as long as it has not reached its entelechy. Once it has completely unfolded its Notion, it becomes timeless. The Phenomenology’s argument ends on this seemingly paradoxical note.214 I will address the question in what sense the Phenomenology prepares the way for the Logic and the system in the following chapter. But apart from the fact that Hegel always thought of the Phenomenology as the Introduction to the system of philosophy as science, I also suggested that it constitutes a necessary prerequisite for the achievement of Hegel’s project, viz. the completion of the Copernican revolution. Hegel’s text supports such a view. In the Phenomenology itself Hegel claims: In this [absolute] knowing, then, Spirit has concluded the movement in which it has shaped itself, in so far as this shaping was burdened with the difference of consciousness, a difference now overcome. Spirit has won the pure element of its existence, the Notion (PS § 805/3, 588).
It will not be necessary to satisfy ourselves again that all external and internal oppositions of consciousness have been overcome. I have tried to show throughout that Hegel made at least a convincing attempt at doing so and in the process have raised and responded to a number of critical questions and objections. If we accept his premises and his arguments for the time being, the result has been that the Kantian unity of self-consciousness has now been expanded to include all reality, i.e., the full range of human experience. In short, Hegel has derived what he needed to derive, viz. a quasi-Parmenidean totality that can be called the absolutely unconditioned. The content and form of this unconditioned is the Notion or Concept, i.e. the conceptual structure of spirit. It is the concept of spirit, then, as distinct from its embodiment, that will form the content of Hegel’s Logic. The Logic thus immediately assumes the role of the core of the system itself, since the system is the explication of spirit in its full signification, its embodiment included. This means that in unfolding the Notion or Concept, the Logic will unfold the conceptual structure or the inner organization of spirit that, at the end of the Logic, will be interpreted as externalizing itself yet again.215 214 It should be noted that what is being annulled here is not finite temporality itself, but only the fact that it is constitutive of the evolution of the concept of spirit. For a discussion of these final reflections on time and the Notion and a reference to the celebrated interpretations it has received from Kojève and Heidegger and in recent scholarship, see Baptist, 1998. 215 Hegel hints at this new self-externalization towards the end of the Phenomenology in somewhat enigmatic terms and even indicates the tripartite structure of the system: “The self-knowing Spirit knows not only itself but also the negative of itself, or its limit: to know one’s limit is to know how to sacrifice oneself. This sacrifice is the externalization in which Spirit displays the process of its becoming Spirit in the form of free contingent happening, intuiting its pure Self as Time
218
3
The Argument of the Phenomenology
At first glance, this looks like the preview of a repeat performance of the Phenomenology. However, for one thing the Logic and the system will start from a different standpoint, viz. this side of the opposition of consciousness, and this means that its thought-determinations will immediately have objective validity.216 First, let us recall the following passage from the Science of Logic: . . . pure science presupposes liberation from the opposition of consciousness. It contains thought in so far as this is just as much the object in its own self, or the object in its own self in so far as it is equally pure thought. . . . This objective thinking . . . is the content of pure science (SL 49/WdL I 30–31).
The Phenomenology, in comparison, expresses the same thought as follows: Whereas in the phenomenology of Spirit each moment is the difference of knowledge and Truth, . . . Science on the other hand does not contain this difference and the canceling of it. On the contrary, since the moment has the form of the Notion, it unites the objective form of Truth and of the knowing Self in an immediate unity (PS § 805/3, 589).
Next, the Logic – or, what here comes to the same thing, the system – will begin “at a higher level” (PS § 808/3, 591). In so far as the Phenomenology was the recapitulation of the experience of consciousness and of spirit’s coming to know and understand itself in the process, this review has led to spirit’s “withdrawal into self in which it abandons its outer existence and gives its existential shape over to recollection” (ibid.). At the same time, Hegel assures us, . . . [spirit’s] vanished outer existence is preserved, and this transformed existence – the former one, but now reborn of the Spirit’s knowledge – is the new existence, a new world and a new shape of Spirit (ibid.).
It is not entirely clear whether the “new world” refers to the Logic alone or to the tripartite system. In any case, Hegel suggests that in the reflection on the history of Spirit’s becoming that is the Phenomenology the content of the experience of consciousness is both preserved and transformed. Exactly how this content has been transformed Hegel does not say. It is natural to assume that with the attainment of the structure of the Notion all its fundamental determinations need to be gone through again, but now as moments of the Notion or the Absolute. In this vein, the Encyclopedia Logic, for instance, will maintain that the three major aspects of the Logic, viz. Being, Essence, and Notion (or Idea as the unity of Subjective Notion and Objectivity), can each of them be regarded as a definition of the Absolute such that the Absolute may inadequately be thought of as Being, or more adequately as Essence, or, finally, adequately as the Notion or self-referential totality.217 It outside of it, and equally its Being in Space. This latter becoming of Spirit, Nature, is its living immediate Becoming; Nature, the externalized Spirit, is in its existence nothing but this eternal externalization of its continuing existence and the movement which reinstates the Subject ” (PS § 807/3, 590, modified after Miller). Note the phrase “eternal externalization.” It seems to point in the direction of the later conception of the relationship of temporality and the Notion. 216 Again, the reader will recall that the Phenomenology itself already started “this side” of the opposition of consciousness, just not for consciousness, only “for us”. 217 Cf. E §§ 85, 112 R, 213 R.
3.7
Spirit That Knows Itself as Spirit: From Religion to Absolute Knowing
219
is uncertain what the exact correspondence between the fundamental categorial aspects of the Phenomenology would be, or whether such a correspondence can at all be established, apart from the very basic structure of the dialectical triad that is clearly recognizable.218 In the light of the following quotation, however, this concern seems of relatively minor importance. For while the content of the experience of consciousness is preserved, it is also transformed to such an extent that [I]n the immediacy of this new existence the Spirit has to start afresh to bring itself to maturity as if, for it, all that preceded were lost and it had learned nothing from the experience of the earlier Spirits (ibid.).
In this passage, Miller’s translation leaves out the word unbefangen after “to start afresh.” The word means either “unbiased, impartial” or “uninhibited, unconstrained, unself-conscious.” Presumably, what it is supposed to express here is that in its novel reconstruction of the content of consciousness, now from the point of view of the Notion or pure thought as such, spirit will not be bound by the form, sequence, or organization of this content as it evolved in consciousness’ experience. This is important because it gives Hegel free rein to organize the content of the Logic and the system as a whole strictly in terms of the Notion. Whether this alone can account for the particular content of the Logic and its arrangement is another question. Despite all that, the experience of consciousness will not be lost, because, Hegel continues, “recollection,” i.e. the interiorization of that experience, “has preserved it and is the inner being, and in fact the higher form of the substance” (ibid.). In other words, the Logic will be able to rely on the same content, but neither the standpoint of the Phenomenology nor the organization of its content will be applicable anymore to its project. Instead, we may assume, the re-organization of this content will be undertaken with the knowledge in mind that all objective determinations will reach their entelechy in the Notion, just as the shapes of consciousness reached theirs in Spirit.
218 In his indispensable study of 1974 J. Heinrichs had attempted to unearth the logical skeleton of the Phenomenology in the light of the Jena System. It is questionable, however, whether Hegel thought that even the fundamental logical determinations of the later Science of Logic were in some sense already prefigured in the Phenomenology. That a number of basic categories are at play in the 1807 work is, however, beyond question. The issue is whether anything like the structural organization of the later Logic can be detected in the Phenomenology. I may be allowed to set this question aside here.
Chapter 4
Objective Knowledge and the Logic
4.1 Interlude: Does the System Need a Ladder? As was mentioned earlier, Hegel’s position in the Logic, and hence the system, presupposes the overcoming of what he calls the “opposition of consciousness” (SL 49, 51, 45/WdL I 30, 32, 24f.; cf. E § 3), or the epistemological hiatus between subject and object. It is generally assumed that the Phenomenology of Spirit is supposed to shoulder this burden by presenting us with the genealogy of the emergence of spirit in and for consciousness. Thus the Phenomenology is supposed to serve not only as a “ladder” to the standpoint of the Logic but, more importantly, as its justification. But as we have already seen, the 1807 Phenomenology has strictly speaking left this opposition behind before it even begins. Instead, the opposition emerges within it as one of the shapes of consciousness called “Perception.” Nevertheless, Hegel seems to have held on to the justificatory function of the Phenomenology at least up to the point at which he had revised Book One of the Science of Logic, i.e. until shortly before his death in 1831. On the other hand, he himself had denied the Phenomenology a justificatory role as early as 1817. This conflicting evidence is reason enough to examine once again Hegel’s view(s) on the role of the 1807 Phenomenology vis-à-vis the system. It was with the 1817 Heidelberg Encyclopedia that Hegel dispensed with a preliminary justification of the position of the system and made the Logic its first part, while at the same time questioning the suitability of the 1807 Phenomenology to serve as a justification. While there is still an opening section called Introduction as well as a so-called Preliminary Conception of the Logic, these are not supposed in any way to justify the system’s standpoint of the identity of thinking and object of thought. Second, the Science of Logic, while not denying that the Phenomenology continues to be not only an introduction but indeed a justification of the standpoint of the Logic, also claims that that justification emerges independently in the Logic itself and that all that is needed to assume the standpoint of “objective thought,” as the standpoint of the Logic is there also called, is simply to resolve to adopt the position of pure thinking (SL 70/WdL I 54). Third, the 1827 and 1830 editions of the Encyclopedia substitute a more elaborate “introduction” to the system in the form of a general characterization of philosophy (E §§ 1–18), a “Preliminary Conception
221 K. Brinkmann, Idealism Without Limits, Philosophical Studies in Contemporary C Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Culture 18, DOI 10.1007/978-90-481-3622-3_4,
222
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
of the Logic” (E §§ 19–25) and, most importantly, a kind of derivation of the standpoint of the Logic in the form of a dialectic of three “Positions of Thought With Respect to Objectivity” (E §§ 26–78) that is supposed to “lead into” the standpoint of the Logic (E § 25). The 1830 Encyclopedia comments only once on the earlier Phenomenology and treats it as an introduction not to the Logic per se, but to the standpoint of philosophy in its richer meaning, including “the subject matters of special parts of philosophical science,” such as “morality, ethical life, art, and religion” (E § 25R). It seems, then, that the 1807 Phenomenology has either become redundant or an alternative introduction or justification, or a Wittgensteinian ladder1 that can be discarded once one has reached the desired standpoint, i.e. a propaedeutic of some kind. So with the benefit of hindsight afforded by Hegel’s later comments on the Phenomenology, the question to be raised is indeed whether the system needs the Phenomenology of Spirit in order to get off the ground. Furthermore, some of the tenets Hegel embraced in this connection seem contradictory. As we shall see, he claims that the system is self-grounding and thus not in need of an external justification of its standpoint, but he also insists that the 1807 Phenomenology is the only possible “deduction” of the Logic’s standpoint – and he holds on to both of these assertions until the very end. Despite some forty years of very detailed and thorough discussion of these puzzles in the Hegel literature, no satisfactory solution to these questions seems to have emerged. Consequently, another attempt at responding to them may be warranted. After this introductory sketch, let me rehearse in somewhat greater detail the essential elements of the otherwise rather complicated story concerning the role of the Phenomenology of Spirit in Hegel’s philosophy. The complications arise from the fact that that role changed after the publication of the Phenomenology in 1807, a fact that gave rise to a long debate, starting with Hegel’s immediate pupils, about the real contribution that the Phenomenology could be seen to make to Hegel’s mature system.2 As is well known, Hegel initially conceived of the Phenomenology as the first part of a still to be developed “system” of philosophy that he hoped to publish in its entirety while still at Jena. That plan was never realized in this particular form. According to this plan, the Phenomenology was supposed to be followed by a “second volume,” containing the “system of the logic as speculative philosophy and the two further parts of philosophy, viz. the sciences of nature and of spirit”.3 Its title was originally to be that of a “science of the experience of consciousness”, but Hegel changed that title to Phenomenology of Spirit even while
1 As
is well known, Sextus Empiricus anticipated Hegel and Wittgenstein’s use of the ladder analogy. Sextus argued that the contradiction that results from trying to prove that nothing can be proved could be avoided, if that proof is discarded once it has served its purpose. 2 For an overview of that often-controversial discussion see Fulda, 1965, pp. 58–78, Pöggeler, 1973, p. 170ff, and Kainz, 1998, pp. 16–23. 3 Cited in Fulda/Henrich, 1979, pp. 7–8 from the publisher’s announcements preceding the publication of the Phenomenology and confirmed by Hegel’s announcement of his 1805 lectures at Jena: see Siep, 2000, p. 63. Interestingly, the same plan seems still to have been in place in 1812 when Hegel published the first volume of the Science of Logic: see below.
4.1
Interlude: Does the System Need a Ladder?
223
the manuscript was still in press.4 The core meaning of either, however, was that of an examination of the emergence of spirit in the experience of consciousness. During the Nuremberg years, the role of the Phenomenology gradually seems to change. As Pöggeler describes in detail, Hegel experimented with an introduction to the system that would have started with the Phenomenology and continued with a Psychology, after which the Logic was supposed to begin.5 While Hegel initially (1808/09) planned to teach the Phenomenology in its entirety to his high-school students, he soon began to teach a truncated version of it including the chapters on Consciousness, Self-Consciousness, and Reason, followed by a Psychology. In other words, already in Nuremberg a truncated Phenomenology that would later become part of the Philosophy of Subjective Spirit took shape. However, at that time both the Phenomenology and the Psychology were still conceived of as part of the introduction leading up to the Logic, i.e. as the introduction to the system. Indeed, the 1812 Preface to the Science of Logic continues to treat the Phenomenology as “the first part of the System of Science” (SL 29/WdL I 7) and refers to its original publication in 1807. Hegel explains that due to the considerable “expansion” that the Logic had demanded he decided to publish the latter separately (SL 29/WdL I 7–8). The Logic thus continued to be “the first sequel to the Phenomenology of Spirit” (SL 29/WdL I 7) Up until this point, then, the Jena idea of a system of philosophy with the Phenomenology as its introduction seems to be essentially intact. When we get to the 1817 Heidelberg Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, something significant seems to have happened in Hegel’s thinking about the Phenomenology’s suitability to serve as an introduction to and justification of the system. Towards the end of the section entitled Preliminary Conception of the Logic – itself an introduction to the Logic that follows – he questions whether the 1807 Phenomenology can function as the “first part of the system,” since “like any other philosophical science [it is] not an absolute beginning, but a component [Glied] in the circle of philosophy” (E 1817, § 36). Clearly, Hegel has now decided that the Logic, not the Phenomenology, is to be the first part of the system, and that the Phenomenology, in a new, truncated version, properly constitutes a subdivision of Part Three of the system. There, its title is simply “Consciousness,” and it forms the second subsection of Subjective Spirit within The Philosophy of Spirit,6 an arrangement Hegel was never again to change. Let us stay with § 36 of the Heidelberg Encyclopedia for a moment. Following the remark on the 1807 Phenomenology, Hegel next addresses other potential methods of offering an introduction to philosophy. He comments on the shortcomings of skepticism as a systematic critique of all forms of finite knowledge and on the selfdefeating Kantian strategy to examine critically the capacity for knowledge prior to the actual process of acquiring knowledge, a comment familiar from the 1807
4 See,
among others, Siep, 2000, p. 63. Pöggeler, 1973, p. 199ff. 6 See §§ 329–362 in the Heidelberg Encyclopedia. 5 See
224
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
Phenomenology Introduction. What he says next, however, deserves our full attention. “Incidentally,” he continues, “the Logic, too, is that examination demanded [sc. by the Kantian philosophy], albeit in a more truthful manner [auf eine wahrhaftere Weise] than the critical procedure, which should above all have examined its own presuppositions and the nature of its action [die Natur seines Thuns]. . . .” This seems to be an indication on the part of Hegel that there is an alternative, internal to the system, to providing a justification of the standpoint assumed by the Logic, but obviously such a justification could never be an introduction, because it is already part of the system proper. Moreover, it may also be an indication that the Logic or the system may not need the introduction or justification provided by the Phenomenology.7 It is, however, conceivable that while the system is selfgrounding, there is yet a need for a demonstration that it is in fact necessary to occupy its standpoint. It is a natural conclusion that such a demonstration would have to be directed at a consciousness that was not yet convinced or aware of the necessity of the speculative standpoint itself. In other words, it would have to be precisely the kind of demonstration the 1807 Phenomenology tries to offer, except that now the Phenomenology would no longer be a necessary justificatory argument of the system from the point of view of the system itself. Instead, from the point of view of the system, it would now be dispensable. Going back again to Hegel’s time at Nuremberg, the strongest evidence that in 1812 Hegel continued to regard the 1807 Phenomenology as an introduction to and a justification of the standpoint of the Logic comes in the 1812 Introduction to the Science of Logic. The Phenomenology, he tells us there, was nothing other than the “deduction” [Deduction] of the concept of the pure science (SL 1812, 20), and that concept may therefore be “presupposed in the present work” (ibid.). Moreover, he claims that because of the Phenomenology the Logic does not need a justification [Rechtfertigung] here and that “it cannot be justified in any other way than by this emergence [Hervorbringung] in consciousness” (ibid.). This sounds like a definitive statement about the indispensable function of the Phenomenology for the system, were it not for a little parenthesis inserted into the sentence. To quote the parenthesis in context: The path taken by the 1807 Phenomenology “has the concept of the science for its result. Therefore, this concept does not require a justification here (independently of the fact that it emerges [hervorgeht] within the Logic itself)” (ibid., my italics). Two things are very puzzling about this passage. First, it seems to make a contradictory claim, viz. that the concept of pure science cannot be justified in any
7 Fulda has tried to argue that Hegel’s “self-correction” in § 36 of the Heidelberg Encyclopedia does
not affect the role of the 1807 Phenomenology as an introduction to and derivation of the standpoint of the system, but only the question of its inclusion in or exclusion from the system proper: Fulda, 1965, 112–113. This argument seems inconclusive. The passage seems to imply that the correction of the 1807 Phenomenology’s role concerns not only its exclusion from the system but likewise its function as an introduction to it. That Hegel’s Encyclopedia generally treats the 1807 Phenomenology as (a) external to the system and (b) dispensable as its introduction/justification is made clear in Heidemann, 2007 and his discussion of E § 78 (see pp. 339–340).
4.1
Interlude: Does the System Need a Ladder?
225
other way than through its emergence in consciousness, but that, nonetheless, it also emerges in the Logic itself. Does that mean that it emerges in the Logic as well, only without justification? This interpretation seems hardly acceptable. If the identity of thought and being that makes the beginning is re-confirmed through the logic of the Concept, then clearly this return into the ground is equally a justification of the initial position. To resolve this conflict, it is tempting to amend the text to read: The concept of pure science cannot be justified in any other way to subjective consciousness than through its emergence in that consciousness. This does not exclude, the implication might be, that the concept of science can also be justified in a different way in pure thought. Secondly, and perhaps even more puzzling, Hegel retains this entire passage verbatim in the revised 1831 edition of volume one of the Science of Logic (cf. SL 1831, 48–49/WdL I 29–30). In other words, the 1817 remark questioning the suitability of the Phenomenology to serve as an introduction to and justification of the system is not only ignored, but is now contradicted by the opposite claim that makes the Phenomenology indispensable as a justification of the Logic’s standpoint. At the same time, the suggestion from the 1817 Heidelberg Encyclopedia that the Logic likewise offers some kind of justification of the identity claim is reaffirmed. To muddy the waters just a little further, we may add to this the footnote appended in 1831 to the 1812 Preface to the Science of Logic. Referring to the 1807 Phenomenology, Hegel there feels a need to clarify that the exposition of the new scientific method presented in the Logic is itself “the cognition of the method” and that this cognition “has its place in the logic itself” (SL 27, footnote/WdL I 6, footnote), thereby implying that it does not have it in the Phenomenology. But the method is nothing other than the dialectic that is predicated on the identity of form and content of thought. Does this mean that despite the indispensability of the Phenomenology for the system the former does in fact not lead to the knowledge of the actual scientific method? The most likely explanation seems to be that the Phenomenology is indeed guided by the method but that this guidance occurs “behind its back,” i.e. that it is not transparent to consciousness. So the 1812 Preface to the Science of Logic continues to regard the 1807 Phenomenology as the first part of the system (cf. SL 29/WdL 8), and thus not yet as an introduction/justification external to it. In the 1812 Introduction, then, Hegel must have been comfortable with the idea that the justification of the system’s standpoint can in fact also be the first part of that system. It is on this point that § 36 of the 1817 Heidelberg Encyclopedia is diametrically opposed to the position of 1812 when it excludes the Phenomenology from the system and implicitly also denies it a justificatory role outside the system. This seems to be an indication that there is a change in Hegel’s conception of philosophy between the original Jena project and the later Encyclopedia project. For the original Jena conception of philosophy the Phenomenology is an integral part of the system. Once the Encyclopedia conception of philosophy as a science emerges, Hegel dispenses with the Phenomenology as a necessary justification. Nonetheless, it remains a fact that until the very end Hegel endorsed the argument of the Introduction to the Science of Logic that the 1807 Phenomenology was indispensable, even though the Logic was considered to be self-grounding. In other words, Hegel seems to accept a dual interpretation of
226
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
the role of the Phenomenology. Whenever he conceives of philosophy as a system of the philosophical sciences, there is no grounding role for the Phenomenology. Instead, the categories typically deployed by consciousness and self-consciousness are discussed in the context of Subjective Spirit. When, however, the relationship between the Phenomenology and the Science of Logic is in question, he maintains that they systematically belong together in a justificatory relationship where the Phenomenology is the ground and the Logic the grounded, even though the Logic itself is also self-grounding. This leaves us with two questions: 1) How can Hegel maintain a dual interpretation of the function of the 1807 Phenomenology – viz. that it is and that it is not an indispensable part of philosophy – without contradiction? And 2) How do we explain the unusual grounding relationship between the Phenomenology and the Science of Logic, in which the Logic both is and is not dependent on the Phenomenology? I propose to address the second issue first, and then return to the first issue. In order to clarify the puzzle concerning the grounding relation between Phenomenology and Logic, I suggest that we examine a text in the Science of Logic in which Hegel discusses both the question of the beginning of the Logic and the role of the Phenomenology in an explicit and detailed manner. The place that suggests itself here is the chapter preceding the opening argument of the Logic.8 The text I am referring to is the famous chapter entitled “With What Must the Science Begin?”, and to it I now turn.9 The chapter is mainly concerned with defending the notorious opening argument of the Logic that demonstrates the identity and non-identity of being and nothing and their (preliminary) unification in the concept of becoming. However, this discussion is prefaced by another slightly convoluted discussion, this time concerning the typically modern vexation with whether to begin philosophy with an immediate or a mediated principle. Hegel comments, “. . . it is easy to show that it can be neither the one nor the other; thus either way of beginning is refuted” (SL 67/WdL I 51). Hegel takes this problem very seriously, for he believes that it is indeed a genuine problem and an important one and that, moreover, his fellow philosophers – Reinhold, Fichte, and Schelling in particular – have failed to understand its ramifications properly. We recognize here Hegel’s well-known dismissal of a Fichtean beginning with a self-evident proposition or principle that is the result of an unacknowledged mediation and thus relies on an unjustified presupposition. We also recognize his critique of a Schellingian beginning with, as it were, “a shot from a pistol” (ibid.) or a Reinholdian problematic and hypothetical beginning, which although smart turns out to be too clever by half (cf. SL 70/WdL I 55). These are all issues central to Hegel’s conception of the overall structure and architectonic of 8 Hegel’s discussion of the beginning towards the conclusion of the Science of Logic may be ignored
here since it does not address the issue of the relationship between the Phenomenology and the Logic. 9 I base my analysis on the 1831 version of the text. The earlier 1812 version is identical to the 1831 version in substance, although the arrangement of the paragraphs and the wording is somewhat different. Apparently, Hegel rethought the argument very thoroughly during the 1831 revision.
4.1
Interlude: Does the System Need a Ladder?
227
philosophy as a science, a structure that cannot but be circular [ein Kreislauf in sich selbst] (cf. SL 71/WdL I 56). Consequently, beginning philosophy without a consideration of the circularity of its overall argument is either naïve or dogmatic.10 Hence, since a beginning has to be made, any immediate beginning must also be shown to be a mediated beginning and vice versa. The impossibility of making only one beginning is overcome by having two beginnings and then let both of them result in the beginning of the other. Looked at more closely, there are actually two types of circularity involved. Each major part of the system is structured in this circular fashion, starting with an immediacy and ending with a mediated result that can itself be taken to be the beginning, not only of the next part of the system but of this very part itself. Hegel calls this progression “a retreat into the ground, to what is primary and true, on which depends and, in fact, from which originates [my italics], that with which the beginning is made” (SL 71/WdL I 55). In the case of the Logic, the concluding absolute idea is both the ground of the beginning of the Logic as well as the immediate beginning of the Philosophy of Nature (cf. SL 71/WdL I 55–56). Hegel also offers the Phenomenology as an example: Thus consciousness on its onward path from the immediacy with which it began is led back to absolute knowledge as its innermost truth. This last, the ground, is then also that from which the first proceeds, that which at first appeared as an immediacy (SL 71/WdL I 55).
Taking the mediated result of the progression that is likewise a regression as our point of departure, we see that we always have two mediated immediate beginnings, viz. the beginning of the regression into the ground on the one hand and the beginning of the next part of the system on the other. Consequently, then, the absolute knowing with which the Phenomenology concludes mediately grounds its beginning with Sense-Certainty and immediately grounds the beginning of the Logic. In this way, what is initially an immediacy turns out to be already mediated, and what emerges as a mediated result must be capable of being reinterpreted as an immediate beginning. By making immediacy the result of mediation and mediation the result of immediacy circularity loses its vicious character. The argument is entirely self-contained, each immediate beginning is justified by being seen as the result of a process of mediation. Or, as Hegel also puts it, “the beginning [i.e., all beginnings] remains immanent” (SL 69/WdL I 53). It is in this sense that even the beginning of the Phenomenology with Sense-Certainty is already “immanent”. Incidentally, this is the typical movement in any dialectical triad in which the last stage of the argument that integrates the contradictory positions of the previous stage is also reinterpreted as the beginning of a new dialectical triad.11
10 Hence
Hegel’s interest in skepticism as a way of identifying unfounded presuppositions of knowledge claims. For the most recent examination of the topic “Hegel and skepticism” see the comprehensive and penetrating study by Heidemann, 2007. 11 Any dialectical triad will do as an example, but one that suggests itself is the triad that leads to being-for-itself, which is then reinterpreted as the One (cf. SL 157/WdL I 147).
228
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
From here, it is only a small step to understand Hegel’s decision during his Nuremberg years to develop the so-called truncated version of the 1807 Phenomenology that would then become a part of the Philosophy of Subjective Spirit in the Heidelberg Encyclopedia. For, once Hegel started to think through the circular structure of the system, he must have realized that the Phenomenology would have to form part of Subjective Spirit and that its conclusion could therefore no longer be absolute knowing but the abstract form of spirit, i.e. reason (cf. E § 439). Thus, the conclusion of the truncated Phenomenology would not lead up to the standpoint of the system itself, but to the beginning of the Psychology instead. But note that the system itself would have circular structure, such that its end would immediately ground the beginning of the Logic, not the beginning of the Phenomenology, while the Logic itself would also mediately ground its own beginning through the identity of thinking and being reached in the absolute idea. Due to the circularity of the system as a whole, the 1807 Phenomenology would have no grounding role to fulfill anymore and hence it would drop out of the system entirely. As a result, the 1817 Heidelberg Encyclopedia no longer considers it to be the justificatory introduction to and first part of the system. But if this is correct, the question why the Introduction to the Logic endorses the 1807 Phenomenology in the strongest terms and why its 1831 revision confirms that endorsement seems to become all the more enigmatic. Here, Hegel’s reflections under the title “With What Must the Science Begin?” prove again to hold the key for a clarification that has the potential to resolve our puzzles. For apart from the concern with circularity, there is another issue at stake here, and that is the concern with the epistemological hiatus between subject and object or the so-called opposition of consciousness. As we know from the Introduction to the Science of Logic, philosophy proper begins this side of the opposition of consciousness, such that that opposition is supposed to be overcome, before philosophy proper begins.12 Indeed, to hold on to this opposition and to extend it even to the sphere of reason, as Kant did, causes . . . errors the refutation of which . . . is philosophy, or, rather, as they bar the entrance to philosophy, must be discarded at its portals (SL 45/WdL I 25).
Nonetheless, Hegel thinks that the relationship of the epistemic subject and its object cannot just be ignored, even if the epistemological hiatus itself is not an acceptable basis for philosophy (as it was for modern philosophy since Descartes). And not only can it not be ignored, it must be made the point of departure of philosophy itself, because “the cognitive process” [das Benehmen des Erkennens] or “the subjective act[ivity]” of cognition (SL 71/WdL I 52) is itself “an essential moment of objective truth” (SL 71/WdL I 51.). Whereas earlier philosophies were primarily concerned with the content of thought, making this content the principle and starting with a consideration of this principle right away, the inner development of thinking forced the realization (with Kant) that the form or method of explicating the content must likewise be paid attention to. But the form concerns the way in 12 “Thus
pure science presupposes the liberation from the opposition of consciousness” (SL 49/WdL I 25).
4.1
Interlude: Does the System Need a Ladder?
229
which thinking as subjective activity generates true content, and this means, Hegel says, that there is now . . . the need to unite the method with the content, the form with the principle. Thus the principle ought also to be the beginning, and what is the first [das Prius] for thought, ought also to be the first in the process of thinking (SL 67–8/WdL I 52).
In other words, it is necessary to integrate the subjective activity of thinking with the unfolding of the objective content of philosophy. To put it differently, the path that began with making the transcendental unity of apperception and its synthetic activities the foundation of knowledge must be completed by developing this subjective foundation into the foundation of the objective content of philosophy itself. Or, to put it yet another way, the unity of subjective thinking and its object had to be transformed into the objective unity of thinking and being on which it is predicated. Thus, if philosophy was to demonstrate in a methodical way the Kantian insight that subjectivity is an essential factor in objective truth and hence itself the source of objectivity, it had to make this subjective identity of thinking subject and object the beginning of philosophy itself in order then to develop it into the comprehensive unity of thought and being. In this way, subjective idealism becomes speculative philosophy. The beginning with subjective thinking, Hegel now argues, constitutes the “real [eigentlicher] immediate beginning of thinking” or “immediate knowledge in the strict sense of the word [das eigentliche unmittelbare Wissen]” (SL 69/WdL I 53), whereas the beginning with being is already a “mediated result” of the former (SL 68/WdL I 53). In the words of the Introduction to the Science of Logic: . . . if [after Kant] philosophy was to make any real progress, it was necessary that the interest of thought should be drawn to a consideration of the formal side [of cognition], to a consideration of the ego, of consciousness as such, i.e. of the abstract relation of a subjective knowing to an object, so that in this way the cognition of the infinite form, that is, of the Notion, would be introduced. But in order that this cognition may be reached, that form has still to be relieved of the finite determinateness in which it is ego, or consciousness. The form, when thus thought out into its purity, will have within itself the capacity to determine itself, that is to give itself a content . . . in the form of a system of determinations of thought (SL 63/WdL I 46).
This quote from the Science of Logic’s Introduction matches precisely the requirement put forward in “With What Must the Science Begin?” according to which the subjective activity of thinking is to be made the point of departure of an argument that leads to the identity of thought and being generally. Just because subjectivity is an essential moment of objective knowledge, it must be shown to be its formal source, though not the source of the content of cognition itself. That content is reconstructively generated in dialectical fashion in the Logic itself. And obviously, what we have here in front of us is nothing other than Hegel’s rationale for the 1807 Phenomenology, which leads to (and I quote again from “With What Must the Science Begin?”) . . . the certainty which has become truth, the certainty which, on the one hand, no longer has the object over against it but has internalized it [ihn innerlich gemacht hat], knows it as its own self – and, on the other hand, has given up the knowledge of itself as of something confronting the object of which it is only the annihilation, has divested itself of this subjectivity and is at one with its self-alienation (SL 69/WdL I 53).
230
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
Earlier we pointed out that the Phenomenology does indeed fulfill the requirement stipulated above, namely that its beginning, too, be already a scientific, i.e. an immanent beginning, a beginning this side of the opposition of consciousness. It is not the business of the Phenomenology to start with this opposition and then to show how it is overcome. If that were the case, Hegel would have fallen prey to the error he attributes to Kant and others, viz. to try to explain the possibility of cognition prior to starting the process of cognition: . . . to want the nature of cognition clarified prior to the science is to demand that it be considered outside the science; outside the science this cannot be accomplished, at least not in a scientific manner and such a manner is alone here in place (SL 68/WdL I 52–53).
Consequently, as we saw Sense-Certainty is already an immediate identity of knowing and its object. Moreover, the entire trajectory of the Phenomenology’s argument takes place within the immanence of consciousness, self-consciousness, reason and spirit.13 According to the Phenomenology’s Introduction the being-initself (or essence) of the object is just as much for consciousness as the object’s being-for-consciousness (i.e., its appearance).14 The epistemological hiatus is overcome from the start – but only for us, not for consciousness. It emerges within the immanence of consciousness in the chapter on Perception, only to be again overcome towards the end of Consciousness, when the I gazes into the background of things and realizes that . . . behind the so-called curtain which is supposed to conceal the inner world, there is nothing to be seen unless we go behind it ourselves, as much in order that we may see, as that there may be something behind there which can be seen (PS § 165/3, 135–136).
To step back for a moment and to ponder the implications of what we have now established. The section “With What Must the Science Begin?” develops a systematic argument for the indispensable justificatory role of the 1807 Phenomenology. At the same time, it also stops short of making it a part of the system proper, as we will see in a moment. Hegel argues that the subjective path of cognition is an essential component of a comprehensive scientific account of the truth, because subjectivity constitutes the formal aspect of scientific cognition. He also argues that the beginning with the subjective activity of thinking is a beginning with what is immediate knowing in the proper sense, hence a truly immediate immediacy. Both arguments together lead to the Phenomenology and determine its overall function to be a formal justification of the system’s standpoint. Moreover, any progression starting with Sense-Certainty is an immanent progression, so the so-called scientific nature of the argument is preserved. In sum, the necessity of the Phenomenology for the system has been vindicated. In other words, in 1812 Hegel had worked out the justification for the claim that the 1807 Phenomenology is an integral part of his speculative
13 See
again E § 413 where consciousness, as the I that has an objective world over against itself, is said to overarch its object (greift über das Object als ein an sich aufgehobenes über) and to be at once one side of the relationship and the relationship as a whole. 14 Cf. PS § 84/3, 77.
4.1
Interlude: Does the System Need a Ladder?
231
philosophy, even if not necessarily of the system proper. Again, a look at the argument in “With What Must the Science Begin?” proves to be helpful in this connection. The point is that the absolute knowing that concludes the Phenomenology is “pure knowledge,” i.e. a “simple immediacy” that has lost all reference to an other and to the process of mediation of which it is the result (SL 69/WdL I 54). As such, pure knowing is not only the mediated result of the Phenomenology, but also an unmediated beginning that is equivalent to pure being (cf. ibid.). By interpreting pure knowing as the result of superseding mediation, i.e. as pure being, Hegel claims to make a new beginning that is now called “absolute” (SL 70/WdL I 54). The Logic has thus isolated itself from the argument of the Phenomenology. It can be seen as making no presupposition whatsoever. In this situation, . . . [a]ll that is present is simply the resolve, which can also be regarded as arbitrary, that we propose to consider thought as such (ibid.).
The Logic, i.e. the system, can therefore be understood to have an autonomous beginning that is self-grounding and independent of the Phenomenology, even while the Phenomenology’s argument remains the indispensable justificatory ladder to the system for a consciousness that is as yet unaware of or not yet convinced of the legitimacy of the speculative standpoint and for which the Science is as yet in its infancy (cf. PS § 12/3, 19). On the other hand, a thinking that does no longer need this ladder to reach the standpoint of the Science, because the Science has been fully worked out, can simply resolve to begin at the absolute beginning, without presupposing anything determinate. The answer to our initial question then has to be that strictly speaking the system does not need the 1807 Phenomenology, but that a subjective consciousness that is not yet convinced of the legitimacy of the speculative standpoint (or any skeptical consciousness) will. This practically answers the first question raised above, viz. how Hegel can maintain a dual interpretation of the function of the 1807 Phenomenology without contradiction. That he did hold these two interpretations, one including the Phenomenology in his conception of philosophy, the other excluding it, is evident from a number of clues. Chief among them is § 36 of the Heidelberg Encyclopedia discussed above. Next is the fact that the later versions of the Encyclopedia fail to indicate any necessary role for the Phenomenology. The 1830 Encyclopedia even dismisses the requirement of a justificatory introduction when it describes any preliminary exercise in skepticism as “superfluous” and claims that to resolve to think purely is equivalent to embracing the position of radical skepticism (E § 78). Where if not here would we expect Hegel to refer to the justificatory role of the 1807 Phenomenology, if indeed it were still a requirement? And when Hegel discusses the question with what the beginning of philosophy is to be made in the 1830 Encyclopedia, he simply ignores the Phenomenology and treats the system as autonomous: . . . what we have here is the free act of thinking putting itself at the standpoint where it is for its own self, producing its own object for itself thereby, and giving it to itself. Within the Science, this standpoint, which in the first act appears as immediate, must make itself into the result . . . in which it reaches the beginning again and returns into itself (E § 17).
232
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
In a similar vein, the one passage in the 1830 Encyclopedia Introduction that does refer to the 1807 Phenomenology more than anything else reads like an excuse for having once regarded the Phenomenology as the first part of the system and as the justification of the necessity of its standpoint (cf. E § 25R). And, finally, there is Hegel’s characterization of the 1807 Phenomenology as a work that owed its raison d’être to the philosophical climate of the early 1800s. This assessment is expressed in the handwritten note on the contract for the projected second edition of the Phenomenology jotted down just a few weeks before Hegel’s death and which says that this was a peculiar earlier work that should not be revised, that it was to be understood in the context of the times, when the “abstract absolute” dominated the day (PhdG 578). Clearly, if we want to take seriously these indications of the later Hegel’s re-thinking of the role of the Phenomenology, we cannot without qualification believe that he also fully embraced the argument repeated in the 1831 revision of the Introduction to the Science of Logic that the Phenomenology remained the only possible deduction and justification of the system?15 After what has been said the conclusion suggests itself that the 1807 Phenomenology continued to be an indispensable argument in support of the system only for those for whom the legitimacy of the speculative standpoint was itself still in doubt. Once the scientific philosophy had in fact been worked out in the form of a system (as represented by the Encyclopedia) such an anti-skeptical argument was no longer needed, or it was needed only to show the skeptic the way out of the bottle of ordinary consciousness. In the end, then, the 1807 Phenomenology turns out to be indispensable not to the system or the Encyclopedia but to those who may still hold on to a position of subjective idealism or the finitude of human cognition. It provides an argument for overcoming the limitations of subjective idealism and the lingering problem of the epistemological hiatus. This need was no longer felt to be urgent once philosophy had been established as a science and its ambit worked out in systematic form. Now the “Three Positions of Thought Towards Objectivity” that contain a critique of scholasticism, Descartes, Kant and Jacobi could more readily be seen to be an adequate introduction, even if not a justification,16 of the system’s standpoint, which,
15 Fulda’s
penetrating and profound interpretation of the relationship of Phenomenology and system does not believe in the relativization of the role of the Phenomenology by the later Hegel. The important point is that Fulda is able to identify a systematic argument for the indispensable role of the Phenomenology for the system. According to his argument, the concluding syllogisms of the system, in particular E § 574, make it necessary to acknowledge that the system remains dependent on a system-independent confirmation (“systemexterne Beglaubigung”) of its claim to absolute knowledge: Fulda, 1965 p. 300. We have identified the same indispensability argument by basing our interpretation on “With What Must the Science Begin?” However, if this were Hegel’s final word, how then are we to understand Hegel’s silence on that systematic role whenever he treats the system as complete in itself, something he does in the Encyclopedia? Fulda’s argument fails to explain what one might call the later Hegel’s lack of enthusiasm for the 1807 Phenomenology. 16 Note that the 1830 Encyclopedia characterizes the “Three Positions” as “a further introduction” (E § 25). Heidemann likewise emphasizes the difference between a merely “historical” introduction and a justification: see Heidemann, 2007, p. 336. According to Heidemann, the later Hegel’s
4.2
Hegel’s Paradigm Shift: From Referentiality to Intelligibility of Thought
233
let us remember, was in any case supposed to emerge within the system itself. Once the system itself is firmly established, the need for its justification via a “subjective path” in the form of the Phenomenology of Spirit falls away.
4.2 Hegel’s Paradigm Shift: From Referentiality to Intelligibility of Thought In Chapter 1, I argued that contemporary interpretationism found a way out of the Cartesian representational model of cognition but in the process was unable to preserve a satisfactory conception of objectivity based on normative standards of truth. I suggested that a strong notion of objectivity needed to be based on a transcendental approach such as Kant’s version of transcendental idealism. According to this approach, concepts determine objects a priori and normatively. In Chapters 2 and 3 I focused explicitly on the reasons why Hegel thought it necessary to push the Kantian project beyond the limits set for it by Kant and the path Hegel charted in the Phenomenology of Spirit to accomplish the task of transforming the finite into an infinite, i.e., unconditioned unity of apperception. A remark in the Introduction to the Science of Logic served as our initial clue. Hegel there proposed that it was necessary to “purify” the finite principle of the original unity of selfconsciousness (cf. SL 63/WdL I 46), i.e., to transform it into an infinite principle, a quasi-Parmenidean immanence of thought, as I would like to call it, within which thought reconstructs the fundamental structures of what is to count as normative and objective. I have argued that this move was prompted by an immanent critique of Kant’s position, a diagnosis of the difficulties Kant encounters in laying the foundations for transcendental idealism in the First Critique (among which the dualism of matter and form, the resulting problem of the indeterminacy of appearances of inner sense, and the notion of a subjectively objective truth are the most pressing). It is of course perfectly legitimate to point out that Kant never intended to go in the direction Hegel believed he should have gone.17 It is worth noting, however, that this criticism, true as it is, does not invalidate the interpretation given here. For even if Kant’s intention was not to develop an ambitious system à la Reinhold or Fichte or Hegel, it remains true that the particular version of transcendental idealism defended by Kant seemed to run into difficulties of such seriousness that a radical rethinking of its basic assumptions had to be undertaken. The specific aspect that seemed to cause the greatest problems was ambivalence about the justificatory role of the 1807 Phenomenology is due to Hegel’s tacit admission of a circularity in the argument: If the Phenomenology is already guided by the categories of the Logic, then it cannot provide a presuppositionless derivation of the Logic’s standpoint: see Heidemann, 2007, p. 347. I have argued above that Hegel understood this circularity not to be of the vicious kind, and in “With What Must the Science Begin?” he in fact saw it as the only resolution to the problem of the beginning of philosophical cognition, which had to be both immediate and mediated. 17 Cf. Ameriks, 2000.
234
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
the attempt on Kant’s part to preserve the element of empirical realism and thus a dual source model of cognition that came into conflict with the very idea of a transcendental grounding of knowledge. I concluded that it is not possible to combine transcendental idealism and empirical realism as two independent sources of knowledge. (Consequently, Hegel, in the Phenomenology, derives empirical realism, or the first opposition of consciousness, from within the immanence of experience, as a transitory stage in the relationship between consciousness and its object.) It is not surprising, then, that given this diagnosis empirical realism should be the element that has to go in favor of a pure form of transcendental idealism, an idealism without limits, so to speak, since a return to empiricism would mean the abandonment of the transcendental strategy altogether. It is therefore quite possible to argue that even though Hegel transformed Kant’s project beyond recognition from Kant’s point of view, that radical transformation was nonetheless prompted by the desire to preserve the transcendental strategy itself. The point is simply that the Kantian attempt to show the necessity of imposing the a priori structures of intuition and thought onto nature – to prescribe laws to nature18 – fails due to the lack of something that would allow of being ordered, since an undetermined manifold offers no orderable material. This failure is no accident. It has its basis in the systematic impossibility of determining objects a priori when empty concepts (rules) and an undetermined manifold are all we have to go on. This can also be read as a kind of refutation of Kant’s moderate idealism: It is not the case that subjective consciousness can prescribe laws to nature. Consequently, if we want to maintain the possibility of an a priori knowledge of objects, there is only one alternative left, viz. to accept the conclusion that the objects of our experience are already determined a priori and objectively in and of themselves, not by us. Rather than show how consciousness must constitute or construct reality or “nature” in accordance with universal and necessary rules, we should show how thinking is able to reconstruct the a priori determinations already existing in our experience and to bring these structures of intelligibility into a coherent system of a priori knowledge. This is Hegel’s program. As we can see very clearly now, for him Kant’s Copernican turn gets stuck halfway on the path towards demonstrating the a priori determinacy of reality. The solution consists in the overcoming of the dual-source model of cognition in favor of a single-source model in which the structures of intelligibility and reality constitute an original unity. The divide between empirical realism and transcendental idealism must be rejected in favor of an immanentist position – the position that holds that reason determines reality prior to and independently of our reconstruction of it. Only thus can the objectivity of the a priori determinations be maintained. In Hegel’s reconstructive approach, the a priori determination of reality is embedded in the world of experience and subsequently “translated” into the form of thought. This is the conclusion I drew earlier at the beginning of our discussion of the Phenomenology of
18 Cf.
A 127–128: “However exaggerated and absurd it may sound to say that the understanding is itself the source of the [a priori] laws of nature . . .”; see also B 159, 164–165.
4.2
Hegel’s Paradigm Shift: From Referentiality to Intelligibility of Thought
235
Spirit. The given, I argued, must already be saturated with thought-determinations. There is therefore no need to constitute or construct the structure of the given, only to reconstruct its inherent rationality. Thinking extracts this rationality from its sensible embodiment and makes it the object of its own investigation in a logic of categories, i.e. explanatory ontological concepts that capture the intelligible structure of being as it reveals itself in experience. Philosophy becomes an enterprise in translating the rationality already inherent in experience in representational form into the “form of thought.”19 However, for Hegel, the completion and radicalization of Kant’s project is not an end in itself. In the greater scheme of thought’s self-reflective nature, the completion of the Copernican revolution in philosophy is one necessary component in the attempt to justify the claim of knowledge to objectivity.20 To the extent that Hegel is able to provide these foundations, his thought is also an answer to the shortcomings of the contemporary positions discussed in Chapter 1. As we saw, consciousness in the Phenomenology is not entitled to claim to occupy the position of the objectivity of knowledge right from the start or out of the blue. It is not the case, that is to say, that consciousness can claim to be in possession of a God’s eye point of view. The final position of an “absolute” framework of objectivity is achieved by an immanent self-critique of all relative frameworks as partial and hence inadequate on their own terms. This, it seems, is the only way to arrive at a standpoint of non-relative objectivity without running the risk of a petitio. It seems that Hegel’s procedure is still the only one that can yield an affirmative outcome of a critique of reason without presupposing an Archimedean point of absolute certainty. If despite the overall circularity of Hegel’s position question begging can be avoided in the actual (re)construction of a position of “objective thinking”,21 then Hegel’s method of an immanent self-critique of standards of objectivity based on terms recognized by consciousness itself seems to be the best one can do. Hegel’s revision of the Kantian project raises a number of critical questions. I will deal with only one of them here, namely, the rejection of the idea of a nonconceptual sensible material of intuition. This Hegelian move represents one of the more contentious aspects of his theory, because it seems to undermine the ability to identify and refer to objects and events in space and time. However, there are two issues involved here that need to be kept separate. One is the issue of Hegel’s
19 E
§ 2; cf. E § 2R, E § 3R, E § 5, E § 20R; cf. SL 31, 35–36, 39/WdL I 9, 13–14, 18–19. again Hegel’s remark in the Introduction to the Science of Logic that the modern “turn taken by cognition, which appears as a loss and a retrograde step, is based on something more profound on which rests the elevation of reason into the loftier spirit of modern philosophy” (SL 46/WdL I 26). The Three Positions of Thought with Respect to Objectivity that serve as an introduction to the Logic in the Encyclopedia (E §§ 26–78) present a dialectic in which Kant’s critical philosophy functions as the complementary opposite to the initial position (viz. that of preKantian metaphysics) in order to be sublated as one moment into the resulting position of a new immediacy of the unity of thought and being. 21 Cf. E §§ 24, 25; cf. SL 47/WdL I 28 (“forms of objective thinking”); SL 49/WdL I 31 (“objective thinking”). 20 Compare
236
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
rejection of an irreducibly non-conceptual element in perception and perceptual cognition, the other the question why a spatio-temporal matrix that is a pre-requisite in perceptual cognition plays practically no role in Hegel’s philosophy at all. Hegel’s elimination of the non-conceptual sensible material of intuition implies that questions of how the sensible and the conceptual are originally combined in the act of knowing and referring to an object are of minor, if any, interest to Hegel – and with that an entire epistemological tradition in the history of philosophy.22 How should we understand and evaluate Hegel’s strategy of avoiding the problems connected with Kant’s dualism by simply ignoring one of its elements? Here it is critical to remember that Hegel does not deny the existence of a spatio-temporal sensible matrix in cognition. If he did, he would open himself up to the objection that it is impossible to individuate objects by purely conceptual means – something Leibniz thought feasible, but only by a divine intellect. What he does deny is the existence of a purely non-conceptual sensible manifold. Independently of Hegel’s view of the matter, it would indeed be mistaken to refuse to accept the existence of a spatio-temporal sensible component in perception. For one thing, we have already seen that there is a perfectly good rationale behind Kant’s decision to contrast the sensible and the intellectual. Referentiality requires individuated objects existing independently of the perceiver or the judging consciousness, a “this-thing-herenow”. Objects affecting our sensibility satisfy these requirements. Intuition secures the element of empirical realism without which transcendental idealism would be in danger of relapsing into dogmatic metaphysics. For Kant, the positing of a purely sensible, non-conceptual element is important, because it alone secures the objective reality of the categories over and above their objective validity by providing a content of cognition not contributed by the subject. Furthermore, only intuition individuates and only intuition provides a framework for spatio-temporal reference.23 Space and time are the intuitional prerequisites for reference and identification. The spatio-temporal framework makes possible the diversification of objects in space and time such that, to use Kant’s apposite formulation, objects are not only different (sc. conceptually), but in different places (and times), and hence distinguishable as individuals.24 When I discussed the section on Sense-Certainty in the Phenomenology I already argued that it is there that Hegel makes his case against Kant’s dualism of intuition and concept. But in view of the fact that the assumption of a spatio-temporal intuitional element is warranted, Hegel does not so much deny its existence as he argues that the Kantian insistence on an irreducibly non-conceptual element is unwarranted and that the intuitional component by itself can do nothing to contribute to the knowledge of an object. The point may be put as follows: a) A 22 The history of the problem stretches from at least Plato’s theory of perception in the Theaetetus and Aristotle’s explanation of the emergence of the first universal in the soul in Posterior Analytics II 19 to Husserl’s analyses of perception in Logical Investigations VI and elsewhere. 23 To this extent, then, I have no disagreement with Guyer’s defense of the concept/intuition dualism in Guyer, 2000. 24 Cf. B 38.
4.2
Hegel’s Paradigm Shift: From Referentiality to Intelligibility of Thought
237
purely non-conceptual, absolutely heterogeneous element of intuition does not exist; b) An intuitional component with conceptual points of orientation (here, there, above, below, now, a moment ago, etc.) undeniably exists but is of no relevance to the question of how the object referred to is to be conceptually determined, even granted that it can be referred to identifyingly only in intuition. In other words, even though there exists a partly non-conceptual matrix in intuition that functions as the condition of reference and individuation, the sensible is nonetheless conceptually determinable and hence knowable, if only as a series or aggregate of “Thises”, “Heres”, and “Nows”. The latter, the reader will recall, are ontological characterizations of the sensible manifold, not just indexicals. Hence the sensible is capable of being articulated as such, but contrary to what one might expect the result of this translation into the language of thought is hardly worth the effort. The conceptual information collected about these sensible items in this way is minimal, indeed substandard for purposes of knowledge. To be sure, there is something inexhaustible and thus ineffable about those sensible items. And yet, the inexhaustibility and ineffability of the infinitely diverse sensible manifold does not contribute anything essential to the cognition of the sensible object. To try to describe exhaustively each “pixel” on a white piece of paper is an utterly futile undertaking, quite independently of the fact that it would be an interminable task.25 The conceptualization of the merely sensible thus leads to the pointless repetition of the same in a process of bad infinity. Nothing worth knowing is learnt thereby, knowledge of the object itself is in no way furthered by such fruitless reiteration. The infinite determinability of the sensible becomes a wealth that, in terms of thought, is really poverty (cf. PS § 91/3, 82). The individuating features of the individual may be important, indeed absolutely crucial, for purposes of identification and reference, but they are negligible or even irrelevant when issues are involved such as the nature of objects, the causes of or reasons for their behavior, the context in which and the background against which they are to be seen or judged. The upshot is that the intuited sensible matrix can indeed be captured by the universal, but the resulting conceptualization is poor nourishment for cognition. For that reason, it turns its attention away from the merely sensible to the thing and its properties. The argument, then, that there is an ineradicably heterogeneous element of intuition can be countered by asking: So what? Hegel can respond that intuitables, while they can be given only in intuition, can also be thought, viz. as a series of empty universals that do nothing to inform us of the nature of the object sensed or its properties. The series itself is indeed interminable – this being the reflection of the heterogeneity of the sensible –, but its inexhaustibility is no problem for cognition, because the determinations lost in the bad infinite add nothing towards the cognition of the object. They would disclose only more empty universals and thus frustrate the purpose of understanding what it is that one is sensing or perceiving. On the
25 Cf.
PS § 110/3, 92: The paper would have turned to dust before it could be exhaustively described. Moreover, we can infinitely abbreviate this task simply by referring to “the blank piece of paper that was lying on my desk yesterday”.
238
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
other hand, it can be conceded that the sensible matter of intuition is a prerequisite for successful reference and identification. Only the senses individuate. But even the act of pointing can be successful only if it is possible to express the difference between “here” and “over there”. The two different locations can be pointed out ostensively, it is true, but the fact that I mean the one and not the other must be articulated by other means than pointing, means that allow me to introduce a contrast that is not as such given in intuition due to the homogeneity of space and time.26 While this does not contradict Kant’s complementarity thesis, it does mean that the assumption of a spatio-temporal matrix is significant only in a context in which the successful identification of objects in a spatio-temporal system of coordinates is required. Having clarified what Hegel rejects and does not reject, we can now address the question why, if Hegel has nothing against the existence of a sensible spatiotemporal matrix,27 we hear so little about it in his philosophy.28 Why does his philosophy apparently have so little use for this matrix as a component in sensible cognition? The answer is that Hegel radically alters the focus of his theoretical interest, away from reference, identification and instantiation and towards the intelligibility afforded by concepts.29 The spatio-temporal matrix is for him a relatively negligible component of cognition, because his interest lies in the explanatory capacity of concepts. This shift from referentiality to intelligibility marks the difference between thinking in terms of a mind-and-world scenario to a position of the radical immanence of thought.30 Hence the need to appeal to an intuitional element sui generis falls away. The object of knowledge is the universal, the individual is merely its instantiation. The skeptic’s question whether there exist any “Thises” is as sterile for Hegel as the question whether we have sensible experience. The crucial issue is how informative or, in Hegel’s words, how “true” it is to say that the object of sensible experience is a This.
26 We may also note that the mere act of pointing itself already implies that someone is being invited
not just to look at something, but to look at something in order to see something. The simple act of pointing thus already presupposes the understanding of a gesture as meaningful, even if what exactly the gesture is meant to convey may still be in doubt. 27 He calls space at one point a “non-sensible sensibility” (eine unsinnliche Sinnlichkeit) and a “sensible non-sensibility” (eine sinnliche Unsinnlichkeit) (E § 254A). This would seem to support the interpretation offered here that Hegel acknowledges the presence of a non-conceptual element in spatial perception. 28 The only place where Hegel treats of space and time extensively is at the beginning of the Philosophy of Nature, where space and time are regarded as ontological determinations (cf. E §§ 254–259). He criticizes Kant for having made space and time subjective components of intuition: see E § 448A. But see also E § 409, where empty space and time are referred to as “only subjective forms” and as “a pure act of intuition.” 29 There is an associated move from what he calls a concern with correctness of propositions (something we call their truth) to the truth of concepts, i.e. their more or less informative explanatory capacity. For the distinction between correctness and truth see E §§ 172, 172A, 213A. 30 Klaus Hartmann speaks of an “ontology without substrates”: see Hartmann, 1999, p. 35.
4.2
Hegel’s Paradigm Shift: From Referentiality to Intelligibility of Thought
239
Hegel thus takes instantiation for granted. When the concern with intelligibility replaces that with referentiality (which is the reigning model in most epistemological theories), concepts or categories are examined with a view to how well they function as explanatory principles.31 For instance, is it more informative and more appropriate to discuss organic life in terms of the category of teleology than that of forces, mechanical causes, or chemical processes, even though organisms may – and perhaps even must – also be discussed in these other terms? One of Hegel’s major critiques of Kant’s theory of knowledge is that Kant did not examine the content of the categories themselves: . . . because the interest of the Kantian philosophy was directed to the so-called transcendental aspect of the categories, the treatment of the categories themselves yielded a blank result; what they are in themselves without the abstract relation to the ego common to all, what is their specific nature relatively to each other and their relationship to each other, this has not been made an object of consideration. Hence this philosophy has not contributed in the slightest to a knowledge of their nature (SL 63/WdL I 46).32
Due to the shift from reference to intelligibility, Hegel feels entitled to neglect the tradition of accounting for referentiality. He is not interested in questions of reference or individuation or identification of particulars, questions, that is, that have to do with the referential relationship between concepts and objects or statements and facts. The spatial and temporal matrix, however, that is part of intuition is needed only for purposes of reference, individuation, and (re)identification.33 For those purposes, a sensible spatial and temporal matrix is irreplaceable, but it becomes redundant for purposes of explicating the categorial structure of thought that is the methodological prerequisite for our understanding of what is. This structure is intrinsically ontological. If we cannot know reality through it, we cannot know reality. Even the sensible manifold can be articulated in exclusively conceptual terms by way of such abstract universals as “a this”, “a here”, “a now”, or “a this over there”, “the upper this”, “the lower that” etc. Heterogeneity translates into the “bad infinite”, i.e. the iteration of finitude. And yet, to call something a “This” is already to subsume it under a universal. For Hegel, no further argument seems needed to ensure that these concepts have “work to do”. The “givenness” of the given takes care of itself. Hegel is thus essentially left with a purely conceptual space. With the shift from referentiality to intelligibility of concepts a new problem of determinacy arises, however. Because of it, the intuitability requirement or “principle of significance” (Strawson) is now functionless or “on holiday”. The a priori determinations to be examined and analyzed have no other except a purely semantic content. It is no 31 A
reading of Hegel’s mature theory in the Logic as a theory of the explanatory function of categories is defended in Bole/Stevens, 1985. I follow Bole and Stevens in my emphasis on the explanatory character of the categories. 32 Cf. also SL 51/WdL I 32: “. . . the logical determinations were given an essentially subjective significance by the critical philosophy” and were not considered “as they are in their own proper character.” 33 As Strawson has shown so admirably in Individuals.
240
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
longer admissible to define the categories extensionally or by associating them with representations of sensible objects or by reference to so-called extra-linguistic facts (the way in which the standard meter is sometimes supposed to define the meaning of “one meter,” when in fact it is again its definition that defines the meaning of “one meter”). Their explication must occur without such extensional references, since it is these categories that true to transcendental procedure determine the intelligibility of things in the first place. This assumes that the categories have a content of their own, a purely conceptual content that can be articulated. Hegel’s task, then, comes down to this. Let us assume that the a priori determinations of the real have already been extracted from the history of thought, including the history of the experience of consciousness, the empirical sciences, and the history of philosophy itself. How these ontological concepts have been assembled such that Hegel can now proceed with their reconstruction in a “system of concepts” is explained in the Prefaces and Introduction to the Science of Logic and in the Introduction to the Encyclopedia. Their assemblage represents a preparatory task that is not strictly speaking part of Hegel’s system, so we may simply take it for granted that this “material” is already in place.34 Hegel then requires a method with which to determine the normative conceptual content of the categories or “thought-determinations” without reference to intuition. But how are we to define the purely semantic content of categories non-arbitrarily without reference to extra-linguistic facts or givens, i.e. intensionally rather than extensionally? It seems that the normative meaning of these ontological concepts must be determined by thought alone without relying on a presupposed meaning. And yet, the suggestion to generate normative meaning without relying on any pre-existing meaning of those concepts is implausible. Thinking cannot just invent conceptual content. There must, then, be another way to satisfy the conditions already in place. To be sure, the reconstructive process must be free from presuppositions in the sense that no existing usage or understanding of a category may be taken over uncritically and blindly accepted as normative. On the other hand, if a priori structures are supposed to exist prior to their reconstruction, their meaning must likewise pre-exist and be taken into consideration. In short, the reconstruction of those categories must consist in a critical review of their already existing meaning or meanings.35 The reconstructive procedure will therefore be such that it fixes normative meaning in a process of conceptual explication that includes adjustment and correction of traditional conceptual content associated with a category. However, in order for that to be possible some standard is needed to adjudicate between normative and non-normative meaning. It is difficult to see what other standard this could be than 34 As Hegel puts it in the 2nd Preface to the Science of Logic, philosophy must gratefully acknowledge the existence of this material as “a necessary condition” and “a presupposition” of its own task (cf. SL 31/WdL I 9). 35 See SL 63–4/WdL I 46–47: “The objective logic . . . takes the place . . . of former metaphysics which was intended to be the scientific construction of the world in terms of thoughts alone. . . . Former metaphysics . . . employed these forms uncritically . . . Objective logic is therefore the genuine critique of them . . . .”
4.2
Hegel’s Paradigm Shift: From Referentiality to Intelligibility of Thought
241
the overall coherence and consistency of all relevant concepts in one complete system of concepts. Under the circumstances, only the fact that all concepts “fit” into their systematically derived place can serve as a standard of normativity. This means that the concepts to be reconstructed be arranged in such a way as to form a logical sequence that results in its own closure. Moreover, this arrangement must present itself as non-arbitrary. This amounts to saying that the sequence of concepts must be generated in a process of derivation, starting with the simplest concept and arriving at the most comprehensive and complex. We are thus looking for a method that defines the normative meaning or conceptual content of existing concepts by generating a series of non-arbitrary “fits” among them. This method must also satisfy the stipulation that reference to extension, imagery, Kantian intuition, representation, or everyday usage as a priori normative is to be excluded (while illustration of meanings that are already fixed is not). This can only mean that these concepts must be defined strictly inter-conceptually, i.e. through their relation to other concepts. In short, we need a method that would non-arbitrarily generate a series of normative definitions of explanatory categories in a process of the self-limitation of concepts resulting in closure and remaining strictly within the space of conceptual meaning. The procedure Hegel develops to generate such a series of normative definitions of categories is the dialectic. The dialectical method is needed precisely because representational content derived from intuition is no longer admissible. The dialectic uses negation and negation of negation, or exclusion and re-inclusion of the excluded, in order to generate definitions of explanatory concepts or categories in a non-arbitrary sequence. Since the normative meaning of the categories cannot be fixed extensionally, it must be established intensionally. What, then, does it mean to define a category purely intensionally? It means to specify conceptual content by means of exclusion or opposition and limitation and (re)inclusion of the excluded so as to achieve intrinsic determination of the categories, a determination that must be spelled out in complex conceptual relationships. It is with the help of a number of basic logical relationships such as exclusion and (re)inclusion that the normative meaning of the categories is derived.36 The categories thus receive an explanation of how a certain conceptual content is explanatory. To use an example from Hegel’s Logic, a something is what it is, but to make it “this” something rather than “that” something it must not be the other something. The other something, however, while different from the first, is just as much a something. Consequently, both this something and the other something are simultaneously identical only to themselves as well as to each other and yet also different from each other and from themselves. Each is not only different from the other, but because they are both a something, to be the same with themselves and at the same time different from themselves is part of both. The two somethings thus 36 Robert
Brandom has recently taken up Hegel’s dialectic under this perspective. According to Brandom, inferential relationships are guided by inclusion and exclusion of propositions and concepts (see, for instance, Brandom, 2003). Here, Brandom prefers to focus on empirical concepts rather than the categories for which the dialectic was developed. But see also Brandom, 2005 where the difference between empirical and “logical” concepts is taken up explicitly.
242
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
collapse into a new conceptual content of which they are constitutive elements. The result is that something is what it is only by including otherness within itself. For the something to be different from the other it cannot structurally just be itself (which is what the other is also), but must include the difference that it possesses over against the other together with its sameness – it must be both “only” itself and other than itself, i.e. different from what it is, if taken only by itself. However, since the other is exactly that also, the difference between the two is in danger of collapsing. And yet it must not collapse because they are different. There thus results the antinomy that something must be defined as being both the same as itself (A) and other than itself (B). In Hegel’s kind of antinomy, two contradictory definitions of the same thing must both be true, neither of them can be false.37 This generates the necessity of finding a unifying concept of which both definitions are true (if not to the same degree, as we pointed out earlier38 ). The antinomy cannot be undone, because that would mean that it had not been legitimately generated. If the antinomy has been correctly derived, there is no going back. To resolve the antinomy, therefore, we need to propose a concept that includes both opposite definitions, preserving their distinction, but unifying them at the same time. This necessarily implies that none of the two definitions can be absolute (for instance, neither the finite nor the (bad) infinite is unaffected by their union). They can be unified only if they are limited to being aspects or “moments” of a new unity. Their contradiction is “sublated” into an internal difference within the new conceptual content. And, because both represent essential aspects of the new concept, one of them must dominate the other. Hegel’s key insight is that if determinacy is to be intrinsic to a concept – as demanded by the idea of a purely intensional definition – it requires the inclusion of otherness or difference within the concept itself. Something is the same with itself only in opposition to an other whose limiting presence for that reason forces a broadening of the original identity of the thing to include its relation to the other. Or, as Hegel’s treatment of identity and difference in the Logic of Essence suggests, for something to be itself it must include difference.39 The dialectical progression
37 It
thus possesses the structure of Kant’s Third Antinomy. There, both contradictory statements are supposed to be true – the mark of an antinomy. 38 Cf. E § 95R: “. . . in the . . . expression “The Infinite is the unity of the infinite and the finite,” the finite appears to be left as it was; it is not explicitly expressed as sublated. – Or, if we were to reflect upon this fact that the finite, when posited as one with the infinite, could surely not remain what it was outside of this unity, . . . then the same would happen to the infinite, which as the negative would, for its part, also be blunted upon the other. . . . But the genuine infinite does not merely behave like the one-sided acid; on the contrary, it preserves itself; the negation of the negation is not a neutralization; the Infinite is the affirmative, and it is only the finite which is negated [my italics].” For a more detailed analysis of the asymmetrical nature of Hegel’s double negation see Section 3.3 above and Brinkmann, 2010. 39 Cf. E § 117: For diversity to be an intrinsic determination of something it must belong to it. As a result, for something to be intrinsically diverse means for it to include diversity within itself, i.e. to be the same as itself as well as different from its sameness. A similar argument occurs in the Phenomenology and there simultaneously as a critique of atomic essentialism: see the earlier discussion in Section 3.3.
4.2
Hegel’s Paradigm Shift: From Referentiality to Intelligibility of Thought
243
should therefore also be read backwards or regressively. Any concept proposed for definition is in truth only a moment of a larger structure. It is “abstract” or taken “in immediacy”. No category except the final one is truly self-explanatory. All require a derivation. This truth, however, is at first ignored in order to generate an account that will expose this immediacy or abstractness and thus lead to the re-incorporation of the initial concept as a moment in a larger whole. The internal logical structure of the new unifying concept has thus been derived and reconstructed. The dialectic’s triadic rhythm of immediacy, opposition, and re-integration or synthesis (through sublation of the contradiction or negation of negation) can be looked at as the discursive analysis and re-building of what is in truth a unified whole. Within certain limits, then, I would argue that the move from the second to the third stage in any dialectical triad constitutes a leap, a leap, however, that is informed by a survey of the architectonically ordered material. The progressive considerations guiding the logic of exclusion and opposition complement the retrospective logic of inclusion and synthesis. Both mutually reinforce each other. The retrospective view surveying the whole sequence from its end-point makes it possible for thinking to determine where to leap, which means that the leap is neither blind nor a leap into the dark.40 Furthermore, as I suggested earlier, if the second negation, the one negating the proposition that not both opposites can be true of the same subject in an absolute or exclusionary way, is supposed to unify as well as preserve the opposite determinations in a new synthesis, one opposite must be subordinated to the other (as the finite is vis-à-vis the infinite in the unity of the genuine infinite).41 The second negation therefore does not neutralize the first but preserves it and yet also “overpowers” or subdues it. Finally, the circumstance that each dialectical triad is followed by another triad whose first member is both the same and not the same as the last member of its predecessor calls for an explanation. This fact is remarkable, because any integration of opposites constitutes an internally differentiated unity that is complete. It becomes re-interpreted, however, as a simple universal in order to serve as the first stage in the next dialectical triad. What is the rationale for this change of status from concrete to abstract universality? I suggest the following. The synthetic unity represented by the third stage of a dialectical triad must itself be put to the test to see if it can qualify as an ultimate, comprehensive unity. To do this means to posit the new unity as a 40 See
Hartmann’s argument about the “progressive” and the “regressive” reading of the argument in the Logic in Hartmann 1976 and the critical comments by Aschenberg in Aschenberg, 1990. The critical issue is that a regressive reading invites the objection that the end point of the argument – i.e. the conception of the Concept or the Idea – is a foregone conclusion, and the beginning with being and nothing thus fails to be absolutely immediate, a consequence Hegel for his part has no problem embracing (cf. SL 840/WdL II 501). If thinking is truly self-determining and selfgrounding, circularity is unavoidable. The best discussion of issues such as these in my mind is still that by Reinhold Aschenberg in Aschenberg, 1982, especially pp. 389–438. Aschenberg recommends an elenctic-epagogical procedure to take the sting out of the unavoidable circularity. 41 See again E § 95R. Incidentally, it is quite correct to say that two opposites cannot be true of the same subject at the same time, because they are jointly true only of a new, higher order subject. Hence the dialectic does not violate the principle of non-contradiction.
244
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
new universality, i.e. a unity relating only to itself and to nothing beyond itself. But a unity relating only to itself is technically speaking an immediacy that requires an opposite to make it determinate again. In this way, the reinterpreted third stage of the dialectical triad functions as the first stage of the next triad. For instance, the genuine infinite constitutes a unity of finitude and infinitude (in which the infinitude is “stronger” than the finitude). But it is reinterpreted as “being-for-itself”, a oneness and totality that as immediacy “lacks inward distinction, thereby excluding the Other from itself” (E § 96), an Other which, in due course, emerges in the form of the Many. The dialectic as such can only reconstruct a material that is already given. One might be tempted to conclude from this that there thus remains a problem of the given for Hegel, and a massive one at that, which threatens to undermine his system by seemingly committing him to the fundamental petitio of presupposing the validity and truth of what is being reconstructed. This charge would, however, be mistaken. For although the material for reconstruction is presupposed, as Hegel clearly tells us in the Science of Logic42 and its Second Preface,43 the reconstruction itself is carried out on thought’s own terms, i.e., as a critique of the traditional body of logical and ontological concepts. This critical procedure limits the scope and import of the categories, shows their limited “truth value”, i.e., their inadequacy to serve as explanatory concepts of the unconditioned, except for the all-inclusive final concept called Concept or, more specifically, the Idea. It should be evident that the process of opposition for the sake of definition, exclusion and re-inclusion of the excluded can terminate only in a totality, i.e. in the only concept that can claim to be no longer a moment of a still more comprehensive structure, a concept that is self-explanatory not in an immediate way, but because it is the negation of the partiality or limitedness of all preceding explanatory concepts. Looked at in this light, the entire Logic is the discursive analysis and successive rebuilding of the most complex and comprehensive category, viz. the Concept or the Idea. More will be said about the categorial reading of Hegel’s mature philosophy offered here in the following section.
4.3 The Metaphysical and the Non-Metaphysical Hegel According to Hegel, the Logic offers a “system of concepts” (SL 54/WdL I 36) by way of a “reconstruction” (SL 39/WdL I 19) of those categories that throughout the history of philosophy have acquired the status of fundamental determinations of being or reality (with a number of new categorial titles thrown in by Hegel himself).
42 See footnote 34 above. Cf. also SL 51/WdL I 33, where Hegel speaks of a “total reconstruction”
[totale Umarbeitung] of traditional Aristotelian logic. See also E § 1, where Hegel states that philosophy can and even must presuppose some familiarity with its objects. 43 Cf. SL 31–7/WdL I 9–16.
4.3
The Metaphysical and the Non-Metaphysical Hegel
245
Hegel routinely calls these concepts “thought-determinations” and “categories” as well, sometimes also just “thoughts” (cf. E § 3R). The interpretation of Hegel’s Logic and system I have been working with is that of a quasi-transcendental ontology. I use the expression “quasi-transcendental”, because Hegel does not develop any transcendental argument à la Kant, that is, an argument that singles out certain concepts or categories as necessary for there to be knowledge of possible sensible objects or appearances. His theory is not about the a priori conditions of the possibility of experience but about the a priori conditions of the meaning of experience. As we saw, Hegel neither restricts the scope of the categories to intuitables nor does he argue that certain acts of synthesis are necessary for there to arise objects out of sensations.44 Still, the categories of the Logic clearly function as quasitranscendental conditions of cognition and comprehension and of thinking about things generally. This is evident from the way in which Hegel characterizes the role of the categories in language and thought in the 1831 Preface and the Introduction to the Science of Logic as well as in the Introduction to the Encyclopedia.45 Hegel claims that the categories are not merely subjective forms of thought, but that they reflect the nature of things. They are “objective thoughts”.46 Not only do they represent our thoughts about the real, they reveal the intelligible structure of things to us. In this way, Hegel’s “grammar of thought”, as one might call it, also has objective meaning. It is not only a theory of the forms of thought, but an ontology. Hegel’s (transcendental) point is precisely that because it is the former it is also the latter.47 The reason for this is not that Hegel thinks he possesses a God’s eye point of view. Rather, the fundamental nature of things should be understood as the conceptions 44 I
therefore agree with Pinkard’s reading of the transcendental element in Hegel against Pippin’s more Kantian interpretation in Pippin, 1989. In particular, Pinkard’s highlighting of the difference in Hegel between the standpoint of consciousness and that of thought is worth emphasizing (cf. Pinkard, 1990, pp. 833–834). Again, the argument of the crucial passage in the Introduction to the Science of Logic where Hegel explains why he needed to go beyond Kant was that in order to reach cognition of the “infinite form” (i.e., the Concept) the transcendental unity of apperception had “still to be relieved of the finite determinateness in which it is ego, or consciousness” (SL 63/WdL I 46). Thought beyond the opposition of consciousness is “infinite” precisely because it is “untainted by the finitude of consciousness” (ibid.). As I try to argue, this is not equivalent to claiming to possess a God’s eye point of view. It is just to tap into a resource available to all, viz. “thought as such” (ibid.). 45 More on this below. – Note that the 1831 Preface is so to speak Hegel’s final word on the nature and purpose of the Logic. – In the introduction to the Logic of the Concept (“The Notion in General”) in the Science of Logic discussed earlier Hegel goes so far as to assimilate the role of the categories to that of Kant’s categories in the First Critique’s Transcendental Deduction (cf. SL 584–5/WdL II 221–229). That is to say, he argues that the categories function as concepts that turn our subjective into objective representations. Clearly, he does not thereby endorse Kant’s conception of a categorial synthesis of representations (either empirical or pre-representational). I suggest that the passage be read against the background of Hegel’s theory of translation of representations into concepts as detailed in E §§ 1–6. 46 Cf. SL 49/WdL I 31: “This objective thinking . . . is the content of pure science.” See also E §§ 24, 25. 47 CF. SL 49/WdL I 30–31: “. . . pure science [i.e., the Logic] presupposes liberation from the opposition of consciousness. It contains thought in so far as this is just as much the object in its
246
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
developed by thinking to explain and make intelligible the contents of experience. It is just that these conceptions are not merely those of subjective thought (as with Kant), but rather of “pure” thinking or comprehending thought that is universal and objective. We are not supposed to ask how a thought could also be the nature of some entity. Such a question would presuppose the opposition of consciousness that is no longer at play at the level of categorial thought. Instead, we should take seriously Hegel’s belief that the nature of things – or “the true” – exists only for thought, such that the truth about something is indeed a thought, not the agreement between a thought and an entity or state of affairs in the world. This ties in well with the fact that according to Hegel we arrive at the true not by investigating entities in the world, as the sciences do, but by translating representations into thoughts, a process he calls “thinking things over”.48 Hence Hegel’s reorientation from questions of reference to questions of intelligibility and explanatory value that I discussed in the preceding section. The connection between world and thought is preserved by the fact that the material for thinking things over is “actuality” in the form of the contents of human experience.49 The Logic is thus a critical review of the explanatory conceptions developed throughout the history of philosophy and the sciences, conceptions that explain what we mean by reality or being when we understand it in terms of quality, quantity, substance or subjectivity, etc. In this way, the Logic is not only an ontology, but also a critique of the ontologies offered over the course of history or the ontologies implicitly underlying scientific research. But in assessing the explanatory value or adequacy of those conceptions, thought is on its own. In other words, Hegel must assume that thinking thus left to its own devices “gets it right”. The dialectic is meant to ensure that this is the case. Hegel is not a conceptualist in the sense that concepts are real ingredients in things.50 A realistic reading of the categories would run into the difficulty already faced by Plato and Aristotle that a universal cannot also be an individual inherent in things. Because Hegel is concerned with the explanatory power of ontological conceptions (substance ontology, mechanistic ontology, teleology etc.), his Logic and Realphilosophie are not a metaphysics either. Consequently, the ontological
own self, or the object in its own self in so far as it is equally pure thought.” Instead of attributing the transcendental function of the categories to subjective (“finite”) self-consciousness, Hegel attributes it to thought as such: see SL 63/WdL I 46. 48 Cf. E §§ 2, 2R, 3R. 49 Cf. E § 6. 50 This interpretation (which has medieval antecedents) was suggested by Thomas E. Wartenberg in Wartenberg 1993 who also calls his reading of Hegel “unabashedly metaphysical” (103). Wartenberg’s discussion of different metaphysical and non-metaphysical readings of Hegel provides an excellent overview over the debate regarding the nature of Hegel’s philosophy (cf. Wartenberg, 1993, pp. 117–126). This issue is far from having been settled. For an interesting continuation of the debate in terms of a deflationary vs. a metaphysical reading see Beiser 2005, 53–75 and Gardner 2007, 37–45.
4.3
The Metaphysical and the Non-Metaphysical Hegel
247
reading here defended should also be distinguished from a metaphysical reading.51 A metaphysical reading must look for proofs that certain entities must exist and what properties those entities must possess (prime examples could be Aristotle’s unmoved mover, Spinoza’s One Substance or Leibniz’s monads). As already pointed out in the preceding section, Hegel’s Logic is not about entities whose existence is to be proved, but about conceptual content or explanatory conceptions whose instantiation is granted. According to Hegel, it makes (limited) sense to explain being or reality in terms of something and an other, quantity, thing and property, matter and form, ground and grounded, substance, subjectivity, or systemic structures such as teleology while also claiming that none of them is self-explanatory or complete. These conceptions apply; they are not empty, because it is the very content of our experience that is explained through them. The point is how true, i.e. how informative, intelligible, adequate, and comprehensive these conceptions of reality are. I suggest that nobody who reads the second edition Preface and the Introduction to the Science of Logic and the Introduction to the Encyclopedia can deny that Hegel’s concern there is primarily with categories, their contribution to comprehending things, their objective meaning, their limitations, and their systematic unity in a “system of concepts”.52 Recently, Wolfgang Welsch has argued that despite his claims to the contrary Hegel did not manage to transcend the subjective idealist framework set by Kant, because he is unable to make intelligible how it is possible for our human cognition to understand itself as enacting the thoughts of the Idea itself.53 Only if there were an intelligible epistemic path from our cognitively limited standpoint to that of the Idea could Hegel make a case in favor of the identification of our thinking with “pure” thinking. In the absence of such a path it is incomprehensible how our thinking could be known by us to function simultaneously as the Idea thinking itself.54 Welsch states that he has searched in vain for a convincing epistemic model
51 Interesting
contemporary metaphysical readings are offered by Wartenberg, 1993, Beiser, 1993 and 2005. Beiser has criticized the ontological reading of Hegel (also known as category theory, an interpretation originally proposed by Klaus Hartmann, see Hartmann, 1972a, b) in Beiser, 1995. Beiser tries to show that Hegel’s Logic and system should be read as a “naturalistic” metaphysics, not naively or dogmatically, but in a way that allows Hegel to avoid Kantian strictures (see Beiser, 1993, pp. 15–16). In the process, however, he makes a metaphysical entity, viz. the teleological nature-spirit unity or “absolute”, rather than a concept the condition for (self-) knowledge (19). 52 Hence Pippin’s warnings against reading Hegel as pure category theory or as a “bloodless dance of the categories” (Pippin, 1990, p. 848; cf. Pippin, 2008, p. 36) need to be qualified. My impression is that some of the critics of category theory have at least in part misunderstood the meaning of category theory. It is by no means a theory of mere abstract concepts, but of concepts that conceptualize being in all its forms, i.e. concepts with ontological claims attached to them, “objective thoughts” as Hegel calls them. What could be more saturated with reality and less abstract than these “forms of thought which permeate all our ideas” (SL 35/WdL I 14)? 53 Cf. Welsch, 2003, pp. 266–275. 54 As if Aristotle had claimed that the thinking of the unmoved mover, its noesis noeseos, is identical with our thinking reflecting upon itself. At most, Aristotle believes, our thinking is occasionally analogous to that of the unmoved mover (although how he could know this is not clear).
248
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
in Hegel. It would have to be a model that demonstrates how subjective thinking makes itself an integral part of the thinking of the Idea.55 Without such a model of the self-integration of subjective thinking into the Idea, however, Hegel’s conception of absolute idealism collapses.56 Pure thinking remains disconnected from our thinking. The two potential candidates for such a path of self-integration identified and briefly discussed by Welsch are Hegel’s conception of “being-at-home-withoneself-in-the-other” and the dialectic of sublation. Neither of them achieves what it promises.57 For neither of them takes its point of departure from subjective thinking, but from the Idea or from the new conceptual level that represents the resulting sublating term, not the antecedent term that is sublated, or sublates itself, into the new unity. (In other words, Welsch believes that the dialectic works only regressively, not progressively as well.) It is not surprising, then, that Welsch also argues that the Phenomenology remains attached to a “subjectivist-idealist framework”.58 This means, however, that he ignores the explicit claims Hegel makes in the text, claims we discussed in the preceding chapter. The book is manifestly designed to hand subjective consciousness the “ladder” with which to climb to the level of absolute knowing or, rather, shed its subjective limitations and transform itself into pure thinking in a process of self-transformation. As we saw earlier,59 in “With What Must the Science Begin?” Hegel himself pointed out that the demand for a path from subjective consciousness to “thought as such” is a legitimate desideratum and that the Phenomenology was meant to fulfill it. But apart from that, Hegel’ position is precisely that “pure” or “objective” thinking is accessible to any consciousness, because it is already part of being human.60 It only requires attention to the “thoughts” that are already inherent in the experience of consciousness and that can be “translated” into the “form of thought” through “thinking things over” (Nachdenken).61 In other words, the self-thinking of the Idea is part of thinking as an activity of consciousness.62 The thoughts that form the content of the Idea are nothing but the content that is also deposited, so to speak, in the “outer and inner world of consciousness”.63 Subjective consciousness is able to tap into objective thought through reflection.64 To return to the question of metaphysics in Hegel, I would argue, then, that Hegel’s conception of the Logic and the Encyclopedia system is not metaphysical. 55 Cf.
Welsch, 2003, pp. 259–260. Welsch, 2003, p. 261. 57 Cf. Welsch, 2003, p. 260. 58 Cf. Welsch, 2003, pp. 266–267. 59 Cf. 4.1 above. 60 Cf. E § 2: “. . . philosophical thinking will . . . be diverse from the thinking that is active in everything human and brings about the very humanity of what is human, even though it is also identical with this thinking [my italics], and in-itself there is only One thinking.” 61 Cf. E § 2 and 2R, E § 22. 62 Cf. E § 23. 63 Cf. E § 6. 64 Cf. E §§ 24, 25. 56 Cf.
4.3
The Metaphysical and the Non-Metaphysical Hegel
249
However, there is undeniably a metaphysical side to Hegel’s thought. I suggest that the real metaphysical Hegel is that of the Lectures and the oral presentation in the lecture room as reflected in the so-called Zusätze (Additions) to the Encyclopedia. The core of this metaphysics is the doctrine of the self-externalization of spirit and its self-recognition in its other. My claim is that this doctrine does not necessarily make the project of the Logic or that of the system as a whole a metaphysical project.65 The reason is that this doctrine comes in two versions, one a temporal and historical, the other a-temporal and structural, or only metaphorically temporal. I submit that the temporal version is to be found primarily not in what I would like to call the “esoteric” Hegel of the Logic and the system per se, but instead in the exoteric Hegel, i.e., the Hegel of the Lectures and Additions to the Encyclopedia.66 This is the genuinely metaphysical aspect in Hegel also identified by Welsch (but not restricted by him to what I call the exoteric Hegel).67 The temporal version of spirit as development and self-recognition is put forth primarily in the Introduction to the Lectures on the History of Philosophy (LHP), but additional material can be found in the Additions of the Encylcopedia and elsewhere in the Lectures, in particular in the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion. As is well known, the larger architectonic of Hegel’s system is built around the concept of the Idea as a triadic totality (cf. E § 18). There is only one Idea. The logical Idea, the Idea as Nature, and the Idea as Spirit are each the Idea in its entirety, but displayed in a particularizing element (pure thought, externality, and the living, embodied intellect or spirit respectively). How do these three parts of the system hang together? As usual, explanation with Hegel works best, if one begins with the end, the telos of the entire project. The system itself is supposed to achieve the comprehension of the totality of the real in its universality, its particularity, and its singularity. This totality is the Idea as spirit. The task of philosophy according to Hegel can therefore be defined succinctly as the comprehension of the concept of spirit. We saw earlier that in the Introduction to the Encyclopedia Hegel determined the “supreme and ultimate purpose” of philosophy as consisting in the reconciliation of “reason that is conscious of itself” with “the reason that exists, or with actuality” (E § 6). I interpreted this as saying that philosophy is meant to achieve the cognition of the identity of the Idea in its logical form with the Idea as nature and spirit. Philosophy is thus meant to comprehend the agreement of spirit as it exists in itself with spirit as it exists for itself. It comprehends the identity of spirit in its abstract logical form with spirit as “the inner and outer world of consciousness” or “actuality” (cf. E §§ 6
65 This
assumes that the notorious transition from the Logic to nature in E § 244 can be given a categorial interpretation, which I believe is possible. One needs to interpret the self-intuition of the idea along the lines of an immediate confrontation of the idea with itself that due to its lack of discursivity fails to recognize itself and instead confronts itself as the idea in utter externality. 66 Interestingly, a good deal of the textual support cited by those who defend a metaphysical reading of the entire Hegel comes from the Lectures and the Additions to the Encyclopedia. 67 Cf. Welsch, 2003, pp. 256–257. Incidentally, Welsch argues that because Hegel has no convincing account of how subjective consciousness turns into the pure thinking of the Logic, he substitutes the metaphysical story of the self-externalization of spirit instead (cf. Welsch, 2003, p. 260).
250
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
and 383). This agreement is confirmed by reconstructing the spheres of nature and spirit strictly in accordance with the moments of the Concept.68 Up to this point, the doctrine of self-externalization can still be read structurally. The system as a whole can be viewed as a process in the metaphorical sense: the Idea “in and for itself” (i.e., the Logic), the Idea “in its otherness” (i.e., nature), and the Idea “that returns into itself out of its otherness” constitute the three “versions” of the one Idea69 that for reasons of discursive comprehension follow each other in a dialectic of immediacy, opposition, and re-integration. No temporal connotation need be implied; it is all a matter of the discursive explication of what in truth is one synchronic whole. The self-externalization doctrine becomes problematic, however, when it is interpreted as a historical process or when the strictly logical development is conflated with a historical development, as happens in the Lectures on the History of Philosophy. Here, Hegel claims that the historical change in the form of the content “makes all the difference” for spirit (cf. LHP 21). In other words, without that change of form in time spirit would not be spirit. We came across a similar problem earlier when we discussed Hegel’s comments on the role of time and externality at the very end of the Phenomenology. Then it seemed that time and history were on one hand absolutely essential for the process of the self-knowledge of spirit, but on the other hand they became quite dispensable after the moment of self-knowledge had been achieved. At that point, time and history came to be “annihilated”, i.e. declared irrelevant for the concept of spirit. Hegel faces the same contradiction in his doctrine of spirit’s self-development. Indeed, he now suggests that in its application to the temporal development of philosophy the content-form distinction represents a distinction without a difference (LHP 54–55). He argues that the content of philosophy develops in time and that in its varying positions “it is entirely identical with its time,” while yet standing above its time in form (LHP 54). This is so because as a process of reflection philosophy reviews its particularized content in history from a position outside history. After all, these preceding philosophies cannot be critically evaluated without already being in the possession of the ultimate standard of evaluation, i.e. without the final, definitive shape of the science. So now there is an identity of form, viz. the self-objectification of philosophy reflecting on its historical development, and simultaneously a difference in content, viz. the several philosophies as they come to be articulated throughout the history of philosophy. However, this difference in content really is not a substantial difference at all, since it is equally a difference in form only – all particular historical philosophies are at
68 “[The]
idealism which recognizes the Idea throughout the whole of nature, is at the same time realism, for the Notion of living existence is the Idea as reality [. . .]. In real, sensuous being, philosophy recognizes the Notion in general. One must start from the Notion, and even if it should as yet be unable to exhaust what is called the “abundant variety” of nature, and there is still a great deal of particularity to be explained, it must be trusted nevertheless. [. . .] The Notion holds good of its own [. . .], and [the detail of] singularity will therefore yield itself in due course” (E § 353A). The problematic aspects of this procedure cannot be discussed here. I have critically examined Hegel’s reconstruction of the animal organism in this respect: see Brinkmann, 1996, pp. 147–151. 69 Cf. E § 18.
4.3
The Metaphysical and the Non-Metaphysical Hegel
251
bottom an expression of the same idea of philosophy. They represent “the inward birthplace of the spirit which will later arrive at actual form” (LHP 55). The fact that a later philosophy emerges from the critical reflection on its predecessors means that it achieves an understanding of itself and its critically assimilated object-philosophy that was not previously present. There is thus something new arising through the element of reflection in time, which leads to a deepening of what remains essentially the same content. The difference brought about by reflection is a difference in form as well as content: “thus the formal difference is also a real and actual difference” (ibid.). In other words, the same process of self-reflection can also be looked at as an alteration of form affecting content. Consequently, the act of philosophical knowledge reflecting upon itself exhibits a typical dialectical contradiction. On the one hand, the content is fixed or atemporal, and the form varies, on the other hand and simultaneously the form is fixed or atemporal and the content varies. Both characterizations are supposed to be true, so content and form are both temporal and atemporal at the same time. To see that this situation constitutes a real dilemma for Hegel, even if this is not explicitly acknowledged by him as such, we only need to ask what the resolution of such a contradiction would be in the normal course of the dialectic. If we wanted to avoid rendering useless and irrelevant the distinction between the form and the content and the temporal and the atemporal by declaring them to be both equally true of the process of reflection, we would expect to be offered a new synthesis in which both pairs of opposites would be preserved, with one of them dominating the other within a higher form of self-reflection. It is, however, easy to see that there can be no higher form of reflection here, since a reflection undertaken from a position of the definitive self-knowledge of spirit simply does not admit of a higher standard. (In parenthesis, if the position were merely presumptively definitive and thus open to revision at an historically later stage, the situation would be different, but then the self-knowledge achieved would not be scientific but merely hermeneutical. Some have argued that this is the route out of the Hegelian dilemma.70 ) Instead of a higher ontological synthesis, I submit, Hegel proposes a thoroughly metaphysical solution reminiscent of Parmenides, Neo-Platonism, and perhaps Spinoza.71 Given the impossibility of integrating the temporal self-reflection of spirit and the eternal content of truth into a higher form of what one can only imagine to be a paradoxical developing eternity, he in fact withdraws to a position of declaring temporality to be an illusion. In the final analysis, time is annihilated not just at the end of the process of self-reflection as in the Phenomenology but really from the start – as it must be, if spirit is at bottom spirit from the start. The historicity of spirit could be maintained only, if the development were open-ended, if the closure of the system were in principle an “up-till-now” result. Otherwise, the whole historical process of spirit’s self-reflection becomes an
70 See
Gadamer, 1960, pp. 432–449.
71 It is, in fact, not far removed from the later Fichte’s theory of the absolute and its externalization:
see Brachtendorf, 1995.
252
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
illusion. Spirit does not really need to develop, externalize itself, and then reconcile itself with itself through recognizing itself in its externalization, thus sublating or “idealizing” the latter. Instead, spirit has already eternally carried out this process of self-development and has eternally returned back into itself. The history of the selfexternalization and reconciliation of spirit with itself becomes a “play” of the Idea with itself. After emphasizing that the nature of the Concept is development instead of transitioning (as in the logic of Being) or shining-in-another (as in the logic of Essence) in the main text of E § 161 and after illustrating development in terms of the change from seed to fully grown plant in the Addition (E § 161A), Hegel, in the editorial scholium, practically recants and proposes an “as-if” interpretation of his position on development: The movement of the Concept must be considered, so to speak, only as a play; the other which is posited by its movement is, in fact, not an other. In the doctrine of the Christian religion this is expressed by the assertion that God not only created a world that confronts him as an other, but also that he has from all eternity begotten a Son in whom he, as Spirit, is at home with himself (E § 161A, my italics).
This is not an isolated comment.72 One of the most outspoken passages conflating the temporal and logical meaning of development, externalization, and reconciliation is to be found in another editorial addition to a section in the Encyclopedia: In the sphere of the finite we can neither experience nor see that the [infinite] purpose is genuinely attained. The accomplishing of the infinite purpose consists therefore only in sublating the illusion that it has not yet been accomplished. The good, the absolute good, fulfills itself eternally in the world, and the result is that it is already fulfilled in and for itself, and does not need to wait upon us for this to happen. This is the illusion in which we live, and at the same time it is this illusion alone that is the activating element upon which our interest in the world rests. It is within its own process that the Idea produces that illusion for itself; it posits an other confronting itself, and its action consists in sublating that illusion (E § 212A).
What is here said about the absolute good applies with equal force to the entire idea of a self-developing spirit achieving self-knowledge only at the end of a temporal process of self-alienation and subsequent reconciliation. As in Spinoza, this process has to be understood sub specie aeternitatis, i.e. as a process that is completed before it starts. It is in fact a process only in the sense of a logical development or a discursive demonstration. Its interpretation as a temporal and historical process is deceptive. It leads to the infelicitous consequence that the empirical world is both real and an illusion, a real illusion or an illusionary reality, i.e. one that really deceives us.73 The fact that Hegel admits to this conclusion shows that he was aware of the problematic nature of the argument. However, in the Lectures and 72 For
further evidence that the Hegel of the Lectures ultimately opts for an interpretation of the development, i.e. the self-externalization and subsequent reconciliation of spirit, as an eternal “process” see WW 17 (LPR) 221, 234, 241 and my Panthéisme, panlogisme et protestantisme dans la philosophie de Hegel (Brinkmann, 2006). 73 Shankara comes to mind.
4.3
The Metaphysical and the Non-Metaphysical Hegel
253
the Additions he never clearly separates the logical from the historical.74 The conflation of the two is precisely what is responsible for the metaphysical version of the doctrine of the self-externalization of spirit. Self-externalization now appears as an act of creation of world and time that in the end turns out to be no real creation at all and is taken back into the eternity of spirit’s self-contemplation. The finite has finally been idealized to the point of evaporation. There seems to be one solution to this problematic, but Hegel only hints at it and does not seem to be willing to pursue it seriously, since it is entertained only fleetingly. In the Introduction to the Lectures on the History of Philosophy he suggests just once, as far as I can see, that the self-reflection of spirit, its grasping its own concept and structure in its self-objectification (here, in the series of philosophical systems) occurs “in us, the observers” (LHP 35). As such, it also occurs in spirit itself as well, since we are its exponents and its medium of self-knowledge. Nevertheless, it is possible to argue that this act of self-reflection must also occur “in us,” i.e. in the individual and in the community of thinking beings – and is thus always in time and therefore achieves only a preliminary result. It is not clear that Hegel would have wanted to embrace this interpretation of spirit. While he does apparently allow for human history to continue into the future in a non-repetitive, progressive way in one part of his system,75 the above statement from the editorial text of the Encyclopedia contradicts such an open ended development. What is left is not the structural reading, but a metaphysical interpretation of the sublatedness of the finite in an atemporal process in which time is an illusion. As I argued above, the “expansion-contraction” movement, as Hegel also refers to the process of self-objectification and recognition (cf. LHP 35) can be read structurally and need not be understood temporally or metaphysically. The three forms of the Idea as logos, nature, and spirit relate to each other as the purely inner (logos), its externalization as nature, and the re-identification of thought with itself in its externality as spirit. The notorious transition from the logical Idea to Nature should not be interpreted realistically, as Schelling did. The “othering” of logos as nature merely marks the logically required step of the self-externalization of the totality that has been reached with the absolute Idea and that is now reinterpreted as a new immediacy. The system thus follows the fundamental act of cognition itself, so that a reconciliation is brought about between the reason that exists for itself and the reason that is actual and exists as world (cf. E § 6). Philosophy itself is this reconciliation of spirit with itself in the form of theoria, and theoria as self-knowledge is the ultimate and definitive form of reconciliation.76
74 I
have criticized what I regard as a conflation of the logical and the temporal sense of development by Hegel in Brinkmann, 2000. 75 See the Philosophy of Right §§ 341ff. and the final pages of the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, in particular WW 17, 341–342. 76 The primacy of theoria over intersubjective communication has been criticized by Vittorio Hösle in Hösle, 1988, pp. 263–275. But in Hegel’s understanding theoria does not exist in splendid isolation from but is the foundation of praxis.
254
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
This still leaves us with the question, however, where to look for the confirmation of the objective validity of the categories, if the Logic is the reconstruction of an already given material. In other words, can Hegel make a convincing case that the categories of the Logic are in fact true of being? As we saw above, the Logic is the “reconstruction” (SL 39/WdL I 19) of forms of thought whose fundamental objective validity – as opposed to their specific scope and meaning – is granted from the start by Hegel: . . . this traditional material, the familiar forms of thought, must be regarded as an extremely important source, indeed as a necessary condition and as a presupposition to be gratefully acknowledged . . . (SL 31/WdL I 9).
But in the absence of any Kantian style transcendental argument to support the legitimacy of any specific category we still seem to be faced with a potential petitio: How can Hegel show that “thinking gets it right”? An argument showing that each category is a necessary member of the “system of concepts” – something the dialectic arguably does – might guarantee coherence of the theory but not thereby its objectivity. So in addition to the dialectic as an immanent proof of the necessity of any given category and its place in the system an argument must be found that underwrites the general claim that the forms of thought presupposed for reconstruction can rightly lay claim to objective validity. Once this point is established, the dialectic together with the overall architectonic can be employed to justify the position, scope, and definition of each individual category. I suggest that the demonstration of the completeness of the system of concepts is the kind of argument that would allow Hegel to claim objectivity on behalf of the Logic. Objectivity would accrue to the categorial system, because there is no plausible alternative to it. This would be so, because all known alternatives are internal to the system itself and critically assessed in terms of their scope and validity.77 The categorial system as a whole would be exhaustive. What would such an argument look like, and can we find something like it in Hegel’s text? It should be clear that only the Logic in its entirety could successfully carry out such an argument.78 However, there is a place where Hegel comes very close to outlining a quasi-transcendental claim for the Logic. After what has already been said, the reader will not be surprised to learn that I am referring to the 1831 Preface to the Science of Logic, which Hegel wrote at the very end of his life while completing the revision of Book One of the Logic. It is in this Second Preface that we find Hegel’s précis of something like a transcendental argument in favor of the objective validity and truth-constitutive function of the forms of thought qua forms of 77 Vittorio
Hösle (in Hösle, 1988, pp. 123–127) has argued that Hegel’s Logic falls short of the completeness requirement because it does not include the category of intersubjectivity. I have tried to show that Hegel does have a place for intersubjectivity in the Logic of the Concept and that the charge of incompleteness is unfounded, at least as far as the Logic is concerned: see Brinkmann, 1990. 78 It could be argued that the dialectic itself is equivalent to a transcendental deduction of the categories, if the dialectic is understood as a transcendental critique of the forms of thought that critically defines their scope and meaning.
4.3
The Metaphysical and the Non-Metaphysical Hegel
255
thought. The remainder of this section will be devoted to an examination of this argument. The second Preface to the Science of Logic makes a rather clear case for the transcendental function of the thought-determinations or categories of the Logic in general. It argues that there exists an essential connection between language and the forms of thought. For the world (including ourselves) to be intelligible to us, we must first translate experience from its immediate sensory form into the form of representation and further into the form of thought.79 Language generally considered is nothing but the world in the form of representation, i.e. in the form of semantic meaning (cf. SL 31/WdL I 9–10).80 But language would be unintelligible without the activity of thought and its forms, the categories: “. . . the forms of thought . . . permeate all our ideas” (SL 35/WdL I 14). And indeed, one might add, even the most basic linguistic distinctions between nouns and verbs, adjectives and adverbs, etc., while not identical with categories such as “thing” and “property” or “event”, yet presuppose them and, at an even more basic level, depend on categories such as “unity”, “plurality”, “substratum”, “predicate”, and a host of others. More importantly, however, in giving expression not only to grammatical but also to logical relationships among concepts the syntactic structure of language itself is crucially dependent on the forms of thought. In every sentence clause beginning with “because” we invoke a reason, cause, or ground. This obviously presupposes an understanding of a logical relationship between the propositions involved. In a decidedly Kantian spirit, Hegel claims that the categories “serve for the more exact determination and discovery of objective relations” (SL 35/WdL I 13). In short, because language is based on the categorial structures that constitute the “grammar of thought” we are able to represent the world as the coherent whole that it is. Moreover, in introducing objective relations into our representations those categorial structures are constitutive of objectivity, not only for us but per se. Not only is general experience or “natural thinking” thus dependent on the categories, the sciences are so, too, since they operate with explanatory concepts such as whole and part, thing and properties, cause and effect, force and polarity, which represent “the commonest categories” (SL 32/WdL I 11). Hegel is particularly intent on arguing that the categories or forms of thought are not just tools at our disposal but instead set the limit for the kinds of things we are able to think and say. Our thinking must conform to the categories, not the categories to our thinking. They have us in their possession, not we them, “it is our thinking that must accommodate itself to them,” not the other way around (SL 35–36/WdL I 14). We “cannot go outside” or “stand above” the categories (cf. SL 36/WdL I 14). Just as little as we dominate the essence of things, which after all are what they are, so we also do not dominate the categories, since they allow us to formulate the essence of things in the first place (cf. ibid.). Indeed, “for us the object can be
79 This is also the general thesis of the Introduction to the Encylcopedia: see especially E §§ 1–11. 80 This argument can be further supported by Hegel’s analysis of representation (or representational
thinking) at E § 20R and in the Philosophy of Subjective Spirit (see E §§ 460–464).
256
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
nothing else but our concept of it” (ibid.). I would argue that this is not so because of a primarily Kantian transcendental argument, but because categories are “objective thoughts” that permeate thinking in general. It is true that Hegel here endorses the Kantian point that the categories have a transcendental function: By virtue of introducing objective relationships among representations they are ipso facto also constitutive of an objective world. But it is important to be clear about the fact that in translating the representational content of “inner and outer consciousness” into the “form of thought” subjective thinking re-appropriates what is already part of objective thinking itself. As we know, Hegel rejects Kant’s restriction thesis. He does so in two ways. First, he rejects the Kantian dualism between the form and the matter of appearances (of which the concept-intuition dualism is a derivative81 ). He insists that a category is not an empty form, but comes with a conceptual content of its own that determines the meaning of being in its specific differences. As such, it is the “indispensable foundation” [unerlässliche Grundlage] (SL 37/WdL I 15–16) of thought’s conception of the reality of things, their essential basis in the way in which the species-form or genus is the essential characteristic of an individual without which “it would be impossible to say what such an individual could still be if this foundation were removed” (SL 36–7/WdL I 15–16).82 Now admittedly, the Logic is not about species-forms or the genera of things nor does it advocate a naïve universalia in re position. Hegel’s thinking will therefore have to be that categories such as thing, property, force, cause and effect etc. are themselves constitutive of whatever counts as a thing, property, force, etc. The categorial form provides the conceptual foundation for the empirical concept, and as empirical concepts reach down to the level of sensation, so do the categories, so that nothing can escape categorial formation. The task of thinking, as we said earlier, begins with the effable, not the ineffable. In other words, the categories do not supervene either on an already existing heterogeneous, albeit formless content or on already constituted objects. Instead, they permeate all representations right down to the level of mere sensations and can be elicited from them through a process of translation. Second, Hegel argues that the thing-in-itself is just another category, only empty of content and thus “wholly indeterminate” (SL 36/WdL I 15). It is therefore not so much an unknowable objectivity over against our categorially constituted subjective objectivity as it is the as yet empty ground of the sensible world that comes to be filled with the laws of the supersensible world, as the Phenomenology argued.83 In short, the transcendental function of the categories extends throughout the domain of representations, from
81 To remind the reader: The matter-form distinction opposes the forms of intuition, formal intuition
and the categories on the one hand with the (undetermined) empirical manifold (appearances of sensation) on the other. The concept-intuition distinction opposes the categories to the forms of intuition, the formal intuition, and the empirical manifold. The latter opposition structures the first part of the Transcendental Deduction, the former its second part. 82 Cf. E § 24A. 83 On Hegel’s interpretation of the thing-in-itself as a dysfunctional ground see again E § 124R.
4.3
The Metaphysical and the Non-Metaphysical Hegel
257
the sensible to the noumenal, so to speak. Insofar as they are constitutive of objective thoughts, they are constitutive of the objects of those thoughts as well. The position outlined here by Hegel could be called transcendental idealism without limits, i.e. without a thing-in-itself at either the sensuous or the spiritual levels or any level in between.84 The Second Preface to the Science of Logic makes a claim in favor of the objective validity of the forms of thought, i.e. it argues that we are in possession of “objective thoughts”. It emphasizes language as a depository of categorial structures. Language is based on the forms of thought and it also develops names for these forms. It is important, Hegel says, that “in a language the categories should appear in the form of substantives and verbs and thus be stamped with the form of objectivity” (SL 32/WdL I 10). That a language highlights the forms of thought linguistically indicates thought’s reflective nature and is a presupposition for analyzing them for their own sake.85 However, we now need to ask how far Hegel’s defense of a transcendental role for the categories goes in terms of supporting his idealism without limits. It should be apparent that the Second Preface argument outlined so far amounts to little more than an assertion of the objective validity of the categories and is far from constituting a transcendental proof thereof. Hegel has essentially reiterated his claim that the categories in general are both the conditions of “objective thoughts” and are themselves “objective thoughts,” but we should not be misled into thinking that he has thus already proved the unconditional objective validity of the categories. He has made a case in favor of the claim that the forms of thought are objectively valid for us, because they make reality intelligible to us, provided the “system of concepts” that emerges from the reconstruction is itself coherent. This, however, is not the same as saying that the resulting system of concepts is valid in a non-relative sense, i.e. that it is objectively valid not merely for us but valid without qualification. Objective validity for us is relative to the epistemic subject and equivalent to intelligibility. It is constitutive of objects as appearances in the transcendental sense, as Kant argued. Only non-relative objective validity would be equivalent to objective validity without qualification and thus a justificatory basis for a transcendental idealism without limits. Due to the dialectical method, Hegel’s project of a systematic reconstruction of the forms of thought in the Logic undoubtedly has a good prospect of achieving rigorous coherence of the system of concepts. But he cannot simply avail himself of a metaphysical foundation, this time in the form of the doctrine of the selfexternalization of spirit, if he does not want to fall back behind the justificatory standard set by Kant. How, then, might Hegel satisfy the requirement that all other alternatives to his system of concepts be excluded working only “from the inside”? The only answer I can think of is that Hegel must incorporate all categorial frameworks in existence into the Logic and at the same time show that the Logic exhausts
84 And
without a Fichtean Anstoß as well: see SL 397/WdL II 10.
85 Accordingly, the fact that the forms of thought were “made objects of contemplation . . . by Plato
and Aristotle . . . constitutes the beginning of the intelligent apprehension of them” (SL 33/WdL I 12).
258
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
thought’s categorial structures. He could then reconstruct “reason as it exists in actuality” in the light of the categorial framework in the Logic, and if this reconstruction were found to be complete, the system as a whole would achieve closure and the categorial framework of the Logic would have been validated.86 Arguably, this is precisely what Hegel sets out to do. He tries to prove that the Logic exhausts the categorial structures of thought and that the system of concepts is therefore without alternative. He does so working from the inside, i.e. from within the immanence of thought. If the dialectic achieves coherence among the forms of thought, the additional argument in favor of the completeness of the system of concepts by virtue of exhaustion of all categorial possibilities makes a case in favor of its unconditional validity. Here again, the dialectic seems to be designed to achieve this end. It lets each category develop its own limitation such that by itself it requires to be completed by its opposite. Both opposites are reconciled in a new categorial unity that turns out to require yet another complement for its completion. The category that finally proves to be no longer limited by another category because it contains all categorial structures within itself, is the category that has exhaustively absorbed all categorial structures. This final category will be completely self-limiting and selfdetermined, i.e. a self-referential totality. It will be the system of concepts as “a system of totality” (SL 840/WdL II 502). In it, “the Notion is everything, and its movement is the universal absolute activity, the self-determining and self-realizing movement” (SL 826/WdL II 486). In the Second Preface, Hegel does not go into the details of his method. But he does indicate that the purpose of the Logic is to let the forms of thought achieve completeness by having them develop their own need for a complement: When those determinations of thought . . . are truly considered in themselves, this can only result in demonstrating their finitude and the untruth of their supposed independent selfsubsistence, that their truth is the Notion (SL 39/WdL I 19).
Only by working through the limitations of each individual form of thought does thinking achieve its own freedom, he argues. Each category individually is necessary but as such insufficient to think the whole, all categories together are necessary and sufficient to do so. This, it seems, was Hegel’s transcendental argument. It makes the entire system crucially dependent on the success of the Logic. But at least in intent the execution of this argument in the Logic is supposed to show that it would be very implausible that the entire “system of concepts” should be “otherwise than we judge it to be.”87 Whether or how well Hegel achieved this goal will remain controversial as long as the possibility of “objective thought” continues to be an issue. My concern in this study has been to show that Hegel’s theory satisfies a desideratum left open by contemporary positions in philosophy, notably pragmatism and interpretationism. Like them, it overcomes the opposition of consciousness in favor of an immanence of experience, but unlike them it also offers normative orientation 86 Strictly
speaking, the Realphilosophie is reconstructed only on the basis of the Logic of the Concept. 87 Descartes, CSM I 290/AT VIIIA 328 (cf. p. 12 above).
4.4
Hegel’s Integrative Pluralism and Its Limits
259
for evaluating different levels of knowledge within a non-relative framework of “objective thought”. I argued earlier that transcendental idealism could be a consistent position only if it is an idealism without limits, i.e. one in which all content is conceptual content. Content here means thought’s a priori determinations. However, granted that thought is able to generate such categorial structures on its own it still needs to be shown that their a priori “application to objects” or their objective validity can be demonstrated. Hegel’s doctrine of the self-externalization of spirit is one attempt to account for the objective validity of such categorial structures by assuming that the Notion externalizes itself in another called Nature from which it emerges again in the form of Spirit. But self-externalization is a metaphysical theory, not a transcendental one. It has no more force than a Spinozistic self-positing of the one substance as both natura naturans and natura naturata or a Leibnizean argument for the best of all possible worlds. If self-externalization of spirit were all Hegel could come up with, Schelling’s indictment that Hegel had relapsed into a pre-Kantian pre-critical position would stand. We can now see that consistent transcendental idealism has one more option, viz. a quasi-transcendental ontological option. While thought does indeed generate the a priori structures of cognition, the proof of their objective validity or a priori “application to objects” can be undertaken independently of a metaphysically understood theory of self-externalization through the exhaustive critique of all the categorial frameworks that fall short of the totality while showing simultaneously that these partial frameworks are limited or abstract versions of one comprehensive framework. This, I have tried to show, is Hegel’s project in the Science of Logic. In the concluding section of this chapter I propose to view Hegel’s philosophy not only as a monism but also and perhaps more fruitfully as an integrative pluralism of partial frameworks holistically united. I will end with a brief exploration of the limits of Hegel’s integrative dialectic.
4.4 Hegel’s Integrative Pluralism and Its Limits I have so far characterized Hegel’s philosophy as a quasi-transcendental ontology, a grammar of thought that attempts to establish a normative framework of discourse and thus clarifies and justifies our ontological commitments, and that also means our conceptual commitments, i.e. the logic of the categorial distinctions we apply. This reading is based on the belief that the categorial concepts underlying our thinking and discourse, as described in the 1831 Preface to the Science of Logic, possess a (conceptual) logic of their own that is not subject to ad hoc re-definitions and in this sense incorrigible, even though over time we may come to the conclusion that there is need for a revision of parts of the system. This might be true of the Logic, and it is obviously the case for parts of the Realphilosophie.88 Hegel’s overall strategy to 88 Thus one might wonder what Hegel’s analysis would have been of concepts such as emergence or
supervenience, if one wanted to incorporate them into the Logic. On the other hand, it is uncontroversial that much as Hegel may have anticipated a modern understanding of space and time (which
260
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
achieve a position of non-relative objectivity, I argued earlier, is to devise an immanent self-critique of all relative and partial frameworks with a view to achieving completeness. The point has recently been put succinctly as follows, primarily with respect to the objectivity of values in Hegel’s practical philosophy, but extending beyond that to his entire philosophy: Final objectivity of value (as well as of all else) is established by the dialectical exhaustion of holistically complete and sequentially more adequate whole conceptions of how humans (must) conceive of themselves as being in ‘the world’, where ‘the world’ is not just the totality of physical objects but also the world of social fact, the world of art, etc. To reach this final standpoint is no more (and no less) than to be able to survey the series of dialectical progression up to that point as a whole and as exhausting the possibilities. This exhaustivity claim leaves no role for [Kantian] regulative reason that asymptotically approximates to a limit (Rush 2007, 310).
Characterizing Hegel’s categorial theory as a “grammar of thought”, as I have done, invites the analogy between thinking as a system and language as a system. The reference to language as a system of grammatical and semantic distinctions and as a holistic view of the world containing a vast repository of the experience of the human spirit can serve as a means to illuminate the way in which thought as such is objective. First, just like thought language is not the product of any single individual but a collective creation. Second, although in its semantic aspect in particular language evolves over time, its grammatical structure, its logic, so to speak, is remarkably stable and invariant. Similarly, in Hegel’s Logic the basic structure of self-referential subjectivity which is at the core of the entire system is reached as early as the chapter on Quality in the Logic of Being with the concept of the “something”. “Something” is said to be the first negation of negation and thus the prototype of later, more complex structures of being-for-itself such as “life, thought, and so on,” that “determine themselves to become a determinate being, a living creature, a thinker (ego) and so on.”89 Furthermore, the fundamental structural distinctions that make determinacy of thinking possible, such as being and nothing, the positive and the negative, in-itself and for-itself, something and an other or, in general, negation and negation of negation or exclusion and (re-)inclusion, are as basic for thought as the distinction between subject term and predicate term in a sentence or what the sentence is about and what it says about what it is about are for language.90 Third, and most importantly for the purposes of our analogy, it cannot be said that language somehow presents a false picture of the world or of our experience. Neither does thought in its aspect as a universal grammar of thought. Nonetheless, just as it is possible to form grammatically incorrect sentences, so it is possible to
he claims are not containers of objects but rather part of their very fabric) his Physics would be in dire need of revision given Einsteinian and post-Einsteinian quantum theoretical insights. There can also be little doubt that his political philosophy is largely incompatible with the contemporary forms of institutionalized freedom in democratically organized states. 89 SL 115/WdL I 102. 90 Cf. Hegel’s analysis of the function of the copula with respect to distinguishing as well as uniting the subject- and the predicate-term in a proposition at E § 170.
4.4
Hegel’s Integrative Pluralism and Its Limits
261
make false statements or judgments. This, however, is not due to language (langue) or to thought but to the individual speaker of the language (parole) or the individual thinker. Truth and falsity arise at the level of the thinker, not the level of the conceptual framework itself. Thought is not responsible, so to speak, for the employment we make of the categories “in life,” where they “are used.”91 In short, my suggestion is that thinking “gets it right” in just the same way that language “gets it right”. It could be objected that this does not yet amount to a conclusive argument in favor of the objectivity of thought. For even if the universal thinking that Hegel also calls “pure” thinking “gets it right”, it might represent only a partial objectivity, just as an individual language may represent the world from a particular perspective that only partially overlaps with the world-view of another language. However, if the above claim on behalf of the exhaustivity of the Logic has any merit, this objection loses its force. Once all partial frameworks have been integrated into one comprehensive framework, the question whether there might still be a mismatch between thought and reality becomes moot, because there is no way to answer it one way or the other. The force of the objection is the same as Descartes’ dream argument: If dreaming does not make any difference whatsoever to our experience and if there is no absolute criterion to ever find out whether we are dreaming or not, the entire dream argument becomes gratuitous, because it lacks explanatory force. Above, I contrasted this categorial interpretation of Hegel with the reading of Hegel’s philosophy as a form of metaphysics. Now, however, I would like to speak more specifically about Hegel’s potential contribution to contemporary ways of thinking, primarily but not exclusively, with respect to the sphere of the practical. I will briefly address what I believe to be the strengths of Hegel’s method, which I understand to reside (a) in its ability to reconcile incompatible alternatives – also known as opposites or contraries – and (b) in its capacity for transcending the limitations of any partial and abstract framework and to remind us of the holistic nature of the reality we investigate and try to understand. However, in conclusion I want to focus especially on the limits of the dialectic when it comes to the really hard questions concerning the pluralism of world-views in contemporary democratic liberal societies. Here, where what Thomas Nagel has called the “mortal questions” are at issue, it will become clear that reconciliation is not always possible and that this is the point at which the otherwise all-encompassing Hegelian dialectic reaches its limits. Hegel’s theory is often characterized as a monism.92 This is certainly correct and uncontroversial, if we focus exclusively on the monistic principle that grounds the entire system (the Concept, spirit, or the Idea, depending on the level of concreteness one wishes to indicate). But Hegel’s system can be described differently, viz. as an integrative pluralism or a plural-aspect monism, where the important point is to highlight the pluralism of the different ontological layers or partial and relative frameworks that set the parameters for particular contexts of discovery that
91 SL
34/WdL I 13. for instance, Horstmann, 1999 and 1984, p. 100–102. See also Beiser, 2005, p. 63ff.
92 See,
262
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
are all limited and abstract with respect to the whole, but necessarily so (e.g. the mechanistic approach, the chemical analysis approach, the universal connectedness approach, the self-regulating-system approach, the organistic approach, the teleological approach etc.). To do research we need to abstract and isolate. And yet, it is crucial not to lose sight of the requirement to move beyond these partial approaches or frameworks to more comprehensive contexts of discovery and explanation. This kind of contextualization is one of the strengths of Hegel’s dialectic. It is possible due to the dialectic’s ability to unify incompatible alternatives. A well-known example is the integration of infinity with finitude in the Logic that leads to the emergence of the comprehensive, albeit as yet abstract, self-referential totality called beingfor-itself. In sum, besides focusing on the monistic nature of Hegel’s thought it is important also to focus on its aspect pluralism and the methodologically necessary contextualization of the abstract and limited individual frameworks. The specific ontological commitments intrinsic to any given partial framework determine the methodological reduction that is applied to a field of investigation. In this way, the abstraction resulting from the application of any given partial framework reveals itself as falling short of the holistic nature of the reality investigated. Hegel’s dialectic is our antidote against the myopia of our unavoidably reductive methodologies, but it also asserts their relative legitimacy. The dialectic is capable of integrating opposites, because these opposites are complementary contraries. Although they are mutually exclusive of one another taken in their immediate opposition, they turn out to be complementary parts of a whole, i.e. they require each other to make sense of each other. They can therefore be transformed from incompatible alternatives into compatible opposites, in as much as the whole is essentially both and cannot consistently be thought to lack one of them without disintegrating into the preceding mutually exclusive opposites. We thus have a new unified category or framework that allows us to investigate emergent properties that were not present at the preceding level. A traditional example would be the mind-body unity with its psycho-physical integration. While at the level of mind-body interaction we would be looking for causal connections or at least psycho-physical correlations between physiological events and mental experiences expressing themselves through physiological events, at the level of integration the body may become more like a means or tool of the mind, where the question of a causal interaction is moot.93 More importantly, however, we can see that due to the methodological limitations of the causal framework what is supposed to be the effect of a cause cannot have a content that is different in quality from that of the cause itself.94 So not only is causality not the only legitimate way of understanding the mind-body relationship, it also can get us only so far. (This does not diminish the usefulness of this kind of research in any way. The fact that the mechanism
93 Hegel frames the relationship of soul and body in terms of a sign and tool relationship at E § 411. 94 In
other words, neuron firings do not cause thoughts but are expressive of the discharge of electro-chemical potentials. To expect anything different is to overlook the necessary methodological limitation of the categorial framework of investigation.
4.4
Hegel’s Integrative Pluralism and Its Limits
263
through which medicinal compounds are effective is often poorly understood does not compromise their effectiveness.) The benefit of a Hegelian approach lies in the realization that the phenomena we investigate are embedded in more comprehensive contexts that require different conceptual tools or different paradigms than are sufficient at a more abstract level of analysis. Generally speaking, every integrative whole is a reminder that its antecedent opposites are methodologically necessitated abstractions. This is why, famously, the truth is the whole. The problem is, however, that due to the process of Aufhebung, the preceding methodological abstractions are left behind with every new integrative whole, such that the abstract preceding frameworks of analysis are no longer available at the new level. This makes it effectively impossible to discuss the question how lower level mechanisms generate higherlevel phenomena within the parameters of Hegel’s dialectic.95 Once integration has been achieved, we are working within a new framework or paradigm of explanation. There are other examples of paradigm integration. One might think of the conflict between the protection and preservation of nature and the expansion of technologically based forms of life as discussed in environmental ethics.96 The conflict between nature and technology need not be irresolvable, as contemporary discussions about the necessity to slow down global warming seem to show. Unless we attempt to do the impossible and opt for the return to a pre-industrial life-style, there is only one alternative to avoiding widespread catastrophic changes affecting ecosystems and societies worldwide, and that is the acceleration of technological advances in the large-scale generation of so-called green energy. This “greening” of technology would represent a new integration of artifacts, i.e., things not “due to nature”, with things due to nature,97 the eco-friendly symbiosis of our technology based life-style and the autonomous but vulnerable global ecosystem. It would be a new form of a benign technology, different from the historical windmill technologies in its advanced engineering, but perhaps as little intrusive as that older green technology while also exponentially more efficient.98 The dialectic could propose a new category, viz. a life-style that is technologically advanced as well as ecofriendly, a new integration of nature and technology. It could be pointed out that beyond the opposition of “pure” nature (wilderness or the wild, as it is called by
95 The
problem was first identified by Klaus Hartmann who called it the problem of the linearity of Hegel’s dialectic (see Hartmann, 1982, 1999, pp. 31, 33, 85 et passim). The problem is not just one for Hegel’s dialectic. As is well known, the concept of emergence has been introduced to explain the appearance of new properties at a higher level of integration in a system. The challenge is to explain why and how wholes come to “possess properties that their parts lack” (Bunge, 2003, p. 12). 96 See, for instance, Rolston, III, 1999. 97 Cf. Aristotle, Phys. II 1. 98 The argument has been made that humans created a new category of biotic life the moment they began to domesticate plants and animals. According to J. Baird Callicott, for instance, domestic (or domesticated) animals are “living artifacts” (Callicott, 1980, p. 330). Under the title of “the demarcation problem,” Elliott Sober has proposed that the distinction between what is natural and what is artificial is itself artificial: see Sober, 1986.
264
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
environmentalists) and pure artifacts there is another level of the integration of the biotic and the technological, physis and techne. But there are limits to the integrative capacity of a Hegelian dialectic, limits that Hegel did not see or did not anticipate and in any case did not acknowledge. In his practical philosophy in particular, Hegel seems to be overconfident that the customs, institutions, and laws of a given society or state will always be sufficiently homogeneous to support a unified ethical life. It is through acknowledging and identifying with the ethical substance that individual citizens acknowledge and identify with each other.99 Being a member of the political community thus means to share and endorse the values and traditions of one’s fellow citizens because they are also my values and traditions. This is not just about social or political cohesion or creating a basic consensus. The point is that the recognition of individuals as members of the community depends on this universal endorsement.100 Endorsement of core values, customs and laws is thus the deciding factor in determining civic status, and as a result it becomes the criterion for inclusion in or exclusion from the community. Modern pluralist societies, however, are more and more under pressure to maintain cohesion in the face of centrifugal forces of various kinds. They need to find answers to the challenges of diversity, whether in the area of social, religious, or cultural life. As a result, integration has become one of the unresolved problems especially in contemporary Western pluralist democracies. In many cases it seems possible to counteract disintegration and avoid social and economic fragmentation while encouraging cultural and religious diversity. But whereas in some areas of public life such as education and economic activity we at least seem to possess workable integrative strategies and a theoretical basis to justify them – however difficult their political implementation may be –, there are also areas where a universal norm must be established and enforced, although even minimal consensus seems impossible.101 In other words, integration seems possible in some areas of public life and impossible in others. In some areas, integration is achievable, if we can ensure mutual respect for and among diverse practices based on a principle of tolerance. Such is the case when it comes to religious and cultural differences, for instance, as they are expressed in practices and rituals. The principle of tolerance bids us respect the private and/or public display of what are essentially private beliefs, habits and customs whose exercise is protected by the rights of citizenship or by a human rights charter. Arguably, such a principle of tolerance is countenanced by Hegel’s principle of universal recognition as the essential component in universal
99 Cf. E § 515: “The social disposition of the individuals is their sense of the [sc. ethical] substance,
and of the identity of all their interests with the whole; and that the other individuals mutually know each other and are actual only in this identity, is confidence (trust) – the genuine ethical temper.” 100 Cf. E § 436. 101 Even in areas where consensus should be possible, integrative solutions often seem hard to come by. To find ways to integrate some twelve million or more illegal immigrants in the United States seems as elusive a goal as reaching consensus on building codes for mosques in Europe.
4.4
Hegel’s Integrative Pluralism and Its Limits
265
self-consciousness.102 It belongs to the aspect of the individual’s particularity that is recognized as deserving of toleration. Toleration, however, is a private and a civic virtue. It cannot be the guiding principle in areas where private belief is in potential conflict with public law and where the law maker is obligated to intervene. Toleration will still be necessary to ensure peaceful coexistence of incompatible beliefs among private citizens, but it is not an option that is available to the state as the representative of the law of the land.103 Take the example of abortion.104 The state typically has a constitutional obligation to protect the life and liberty of its citizens. In many cases, this obligation extends not just to citizens but to human beings or human life in general. The legislator is thus confronted with the question whether or not to extend legal protection to an unborn child. An answer to this question will depend crucially on how one answers the question as to the legal status of the zygote or the fetus. Many countries have opted for a compromise, either by deciding that the status of legal personhood – and thus the right to constitutional protection – accrues to a fetus only some time into the gestation period or by concluding that the constitutional obligation to intervene on behalf of the fetus becomes effective only some time into the gestation period. Now whatever the legislator or the courts decide, it will be morally unacceptable to one or more parties to the debate. The legal solution, if one wants to call it that, will for that reason often be pragmatic. One party to the debate may find that what is pragmatic is also morally justifiable, but this won’t be so for the other party or parties. The reason is that we are confronted here with a genuine moral dilemma, i.e. a clash of two moral absolutes – the unconditional right to protection of the fetus from the point of fertilization; and the unconditional protection of the right to choose of the pregnant woman. In both cases it is possible to attach qualifications to the unconditional rights in the form of exceptions.105 However, this does not eliminate the basic irreconcilability of the two positions. To see why the Hegelian dialectic would be gridlocked in the case of a conflict between moral absolutes we may recall Hegel’s dialectic of the inverted world in the Phenomenology’s section on Force and Understanding. There we saw that what is right in the first supersensible world – i.e., the world of the ideal (ideell) validity of the law – must also be right in the second supersensible world so that the inversion represented by the second supersensible world (i.e., the violation of what is right
102 Cf.
E § 436 and 436R. I should add, does not mean silent acquiescence in the case of fundamental moral disagreements. It is quite compatible with the public voicing of dissent and public protest. What toleration excludes is violent opposition and the attempt to take the law into one’s own hands. 104 Similar problems arise in the cases of active and passive euthanasia and physician assisted suicide. 105 Thus one can uphold the unconditional right to protection of the fetus while making exceptions for rape, incest or health of the pregnant woman. Conversely, one can limit the pregnant woman’s right to exercise her unconditional “right to privacy” to a certain period prior to a given stage of gestation, as laid down by the Supreme Court of the United States in Roe vs. Wade. 103 Toleration,
266
4 Objective Knowledge and the Logic
in the first world) needed in turn to be inverted. Similarly, what is wrong in one supersensible world must be wrong also in the other. In the case at hand, however, we are dealing with a duplication of the first supersensible world such that what is right in one is wrong in the other. Consequently, there will also be two supersensible worlds. Their inversion will thus lead to the re-establishing of two diametrically opposed first supersensible worlds, i.e. to two moral and legal universes that negate each other. The situation in which two moral absolutes clash with one another is reminiscent of another, chronologically earlier, albeit architectonically later, stage of the Phenomenology’s dialectic, viz. that of the Ethical World of the ancients at the beginning of the chapter on Spirit. Hegel there discussed a similar confrontation of two moral universes, the human and the divine law represented by Creon and Antigone, respectively. That clash found its resolution only in what Hegel characterized as the “ruin of the ethical substance” of that era, a ruin that was followed by the legalistic culture of the Roman Empire and later by the self-alienated world of the Enlightenment. There are many indications that our situation today bears more resemblance to a state of enlightened self-alienation than to that of a harmoniously unified ethical life.
Bibliography
Primary Sources Aristotle. 1967. De Anima. ed. D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Aristotle. 1971. The Works of Aristotle, ed. Ross, W.D. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bacon, F. 1960. The New Organon, ed. Anderson, F.H. New York, London: Macmillan-Collier Macmillan. Berkeley, G. 1987. A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, ed. Winkler, K. Indianapolis: Hackett. Descartes, R. 1985. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, 2 vols. (trans: Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, Murdoch, D.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (= CSM I, II) Diels, R.H. 1952. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 6th edition. ed. Kranz, W. Berlin. (= DK) Fichte, J.G. 1982. The Science of Knowledge: Texts in German Philosophy, ed., trans: Heath, P., Lachs, J. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (= Science of Knowledge) Hegel, G.W.F. 1892–1896. Lectures on the History of Philosophy, 3 vols. (trans: Haldane, E.S., Simpson, F.H.). London: Paul, Trench & Trübner. (= LPH) Hegel, G.W.F. 1952. Phänomenologie des Geistes, hrsg. Johannes Hoffmeister, Die Philosophische Bibliothek, Bd. 114, Hamburg: Meiner, 6. Aufl. (= PhdG) Hegel, G.W.F. 1965. Sämtliche Werke. Jubiläumsausgabe in zwanzig Bänden, ed. Glockner, H. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Friedrich Frommann. (= WW) Hegel, G.W.F. 1967. Wissenschaft der Logik, hrsg. v. Georg Lasson, 2 vols., Hamburg: Felix Meiner. (= WdL I, II) Hegel, G.W.F. 1968. Glauben und Wissen. Gesammelte Werke, ed. Kritische Ausgabe. Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft in Verbindung mit der Rheinisch-Westfälischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Hamburg: Meiner, 1968ff, vol. 4: Jenaer Kritische Schriften, 313–414 (= GW IV) Hegel, G.W.F. 1969. The Science of Logic (trans: Miller, A.V.). London: Allen & Unwin. (= SL) Hegel, G.W.F. 1969–1972. Werke. Werkausgabe, 20 vols. eds. Moldenhauer, E., Michel, K. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. (quoted by volume and page number: 3, 123) Hegel, G.W.F. 1970. Encylopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Outline. Philosophy of Nature (trans: Miller, A.V.), with foreword by J.N. Findlay, Oxford: Oxford University Press. ( = E) Hegel, G.W.F. 1971. Encylopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Outline. Philosophy of Mind. (trans: Miller, A.V.), with foreword by J.N. Findlay. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (= E) Hegel, G.W.F. 1977. Faith and Knowledge (trans: Harris, H.S.). W. Cerf, New York: SUNY. (= FK) Hegel, G.W.F. 1977. Phenomenology of Spirit by G.W.F. Hegel (trans: Miller, A.V.) with analysis of text and foreword by J.N. Findlay. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (= PS)
267 K. Brinkmann, Idealism Without Limits, Philosophical Studies in Contemporary C Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Culture 18, DOI 10.1007/978-90-481-3622-3,
268
Bibliography
Hegel, G.W.F. 1978. Wissenschaft der Logik (1812/1813), hrsg. v. F. Hogemann u. W. Jaeschke, in: Gesammelte Werke, hrsg. von der Rheinisch-Westfälischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Bd. 11, Hamburg: Felix Meiner. (= SL 1812) Hegel, G.W.F. 1989. Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1827), hrsg. v.W. Bonsiepen u. H.C. Lucas, In Gesammelte Werke, hrsg. von der RheinischWestfälischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Bd. 19, Hamburg: Felix Meiner. (= E 1827) Hegel, G.W.F. 1991. The Encyclopaedia Logic (with the Zusätze). Part One of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze, new translation with Introduction and notes by T.F. Geraets, W.A. Suchting, H.S. Harris, Indianapolis-Cambridge: Hackett. (= E) Hegel, G.W.F. 2000. Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1817), hrsg. v.W. Bonsiepen u. K. Grotsch, In Gesammelte Werke, hrsg. von der RheinischWestfälischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Bd. 13, Hamburg: Felix Meiner. (= E 1817) Hume, D. 1999. An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Beauchamp, T.L. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Husserl, E. 1950. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie. Husserliana vol. 3. ed. Biemel, W. Haag: Martinus Nijhoff. (= Ideen I) Husserl, E. 1968. Logische Untersuchungen, 2 vols. (I, II/1, II/2) 5th edition. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer. (= Logische Untersuchungen) Kant, I. 1968. gesammelte Schriften. Akademie edition, ed. Kgl. Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 29 vols., Berlin/Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter. Kant, I. 1973. Critique of Pure Reason (trans: Smith, N.K.). London: Macmillan Press. Kirk, G.S., Raven, J.E., Schofield, M. 1983. The Presocratic Philosophers. A Critical History With a Selection of Texts, 2nd edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Leibniz, G.W. 1991. Monadology. G.W. Leibniz’s Monadology. An Edition for Students, ed. Rescher, N. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. (= Monadology) Locke, J. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. ed. Nidditch, P.H. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (= Essay) Ross, W.D. 1924/1970. Aristotle’s Metaphysics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary by W.D. Ross, 2 vols., Oxford: Clarendon Press. Ross, W.D. 1968. Aristotle, Analytica Priora et Posteriora. Recensuit. Praefatione et appendice auxit L. Minio-Paluello, Oxonii. Sartre, J.P. 1943. L’être et le néant. Essai d’ontologie phénoménologique, Paris: Gallimard. Sartre, J.P. 1988. La transcendance de l’égo. Esquisse d’une description phénoménologique. ed. Le Bon, S. Paris: Vrin. Schelling, F.W.J. 1967. Ausgewählte Werke, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. (= Ausgewählte Werke) Spinoza, B. 1989. Ethics, Including the Improvement of the Understanding (trans: Elwes, R.H.M.). Buffalo: Prometheus Books. (= Ethics)
Secondary Sources Abel, G. 1984. Nietzsche: Die Dynamik der Willen zur Macht und die ewige Wiederkehr. BerlinNew York: Walter de Gruyter. Abel, G. 1989. Interpretations-Welten, Philosophisches Jahrbuch 96: 1–19. Abel, G. 1993. Interpretationswelten. Gegenwartsphilosophie jenseits von Essentialismus und Relativismus, Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp. Abel, G. 1995. Sprache, Zeichen und Interpretation. In Neue Realitäten – Herausforderung der Philosophie. XVI. Deutscher Kongreß für Philosophie, Berlin 1993, hrsg. v. Hans Lenk und Hans Poser, Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 264–285.
Bibliography
269
Abel, G. 1996. Interpretation und Realität. Erläuterungen zur Interpretationsphilosophie. Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie 21: 271–288. Abel, G. 2004. Günter: Zeichen der Wirklichkeit. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 2004 Allison, H.E. 1983. Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. An Interpretation and Defense. New Haven: Yale University Press. Allison, H.E. 2004. Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. An Interpretation and Defense, revised and enlarged edition. New Haven: Yale University Press. Altman. 2008. Matthew C.: A Companion to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Philadelphia: Westview Press, 2008 Ameriks, Karl. 2000. Kant and the Fate of Autonomy. Problems in the Appropriation of the Critical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Aschenberg, R. 1976. Der Wahrheitsbegriff in Hegels Phänomenologie. In Die Ontologische Option, ed. Hartmann, K. 211–304. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. Aschenberg, R. 1982. Sprachanalyse und Transzendentalphilosophie. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta. Aschenberg, R. 1990. Kategoriale Transzendentalphilosophie? In Kategorie und Kategorialität. Historisch-systematische Untersuchungen zum Begriff der Kategorie im philosophischen Denken. Festschrift für Klaus Hartmann zum 65, Geburtstag, eds. Koch, D., Bort, K., 439–456. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann. Baptist, G. 1998. Das absolute Wissen. Zeit, Geschichte, Wissenschaft. In Klassiker Auslegen. G.W.F. Hegel: Phänomenologie des Geistes, eds. Köhler, D., Pöggeler, O., 243–259. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Barth, U. 2003. Religion in der Moderne. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. Beiser, F.C. 1987. The Fate of Reason. German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Beiser. F.C. 1993. Introduction: Hegel and the problem of metaphysics. In The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, ed. Beiser, F.C., 1–24. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Beiser, F.C. 1995. Hegel, a non/metaphysician? A polemic. Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 35: 1–13 Beiser, F.C. 2000. German Idealism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Beiser, F.C. 2005. Hegel. London: Routledge. Bernstein, R.J. 1983. Beyond Objectivism and Relativism. Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Birke, M. 2001. Wenn nicht im Kopf, wo dann?: Der Externalismus als Problem in der Philosophie des Geistes. Berlin-Hamburg-Münster: LIT Verlag. Bole III, T., Stevens, J.M. 1985. Why Hegel At All? Philosophical Topics 13: 113–122. Bonsiepen, W. 1977. Phänomenologie des Geistes. In Hegel. Einführung in seine Philosophie, 59–74, hrsg. v. Otto Pöggeler, Freiburg/München: Alber. Bowie, A. 1993. Schelling and Modern European Philosophy. An Introduction. London: Routledge. Brandom, R.B. 1994. Making It Explicit, Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Brandom, R.B. 2000. Articulating Reasons, An Introduction to Inferentialism, Cambridge, Mass. London, England: Harvard University Press. Brandom, R. 2003. Holism and Idealism in Hegel’s Phenomenology. In Das Interesse des Denkens. Hegel aus heutiger Sicht, eds. Welsh, W., Vieweg, K., 47–88. München: Wilhelm Fink Verlag. Brandom, R. 2005. Sketch of a program for a critical reading of Hegel. Comparing empirical and logical concepts. International Yearbook of German Idealism 3: 131–161. Brachtendorf, J. 1995. Fichtes Lehre vom Sein. Eine kritische Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehren von 1794, 1798/99 und 1812, Paderborn: Ferdinand Schöningh. Brinkmann, K. 1976. Schellings Hegel-Kritik. In Die ontologische Option, ed. Hartmann, K., 117–120. Berlin: de Gruyter.
270
Bibliography
Brinkmann, K. 1990. Intersubjektivität und konkretes Allgemeines. Zur These von der kategorialen Defizienz der Hegelschen Logik. In Kategorie und Kategorialität. Historisch-systematische Untersuchungen zum Begriff der Kategorie im philosophischen Denken. Festschrift für Klaus Hartmann zum 65. Geburtstag, eds. Koch, D. Bort, K., 131–169. Königshausen & Neumann. Brinkmann, K. 1994. Hegel’s Critique of Kant and Pre-Kantian Metaphysics. In Hegel and Transcendental Philosophy, eds. Engelhardt, H.T., Pinkard, T., 57–78. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Brinkmann, K. 1996. Hegel on the Animal Organism. Laval Théologique et Philosophique 52: 135–153. Brinkmann, K. 1997. Hegel sur le cogito cartésien. Laval Théologique et Philosophique. Actes du Colloque International Descartes 53: 639–652. Brinkmann, K. 1998. The Natural and the Supernatural in Human Nature: Hegel on the Soul. In Philosophies of Nature: The Human Dimension, eds. R. Cohen, A. Tauber, 3–18. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Brinkmann, K. 2000. System and History in Hegel. In The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, vol. 7: Modern Philosophy, ed. Gedney, M., 169–177. Philosophy Documentation Center: Bowling Green State University. Brinkmann, K. 2003a. Beyond Platonic Forms: Aristotelian Essentialism. In Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato: The Metaphysical Question, ed. Pierris, A., 57–92. Patras: Institute for Philosophical Research. Brinkmann, K. 2003b. Hegel on Forgiveness. In Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. New Critical Essays, eds. Denker, A., Vater, M., 243–264. Amherst: Humanity Books. Brinkmann, K. 2006. Panthéisme, panlogisme et protestantisme dans la philosophie de Hegel. In Les philosophes et la question de Dieu, eds. Langlois, L., Zarka, Y.C., 223–238. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Brinkmann, K. 2010. The dialectic of the inverted world and the meaning of Aufhebung. In The Dimensions of Hegel’s Dialectic, ed. Limnatis, N.G., 123–139. London: Continuum International. Bunge, M. 2003. Emergence and Convergence. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Callicott, J.B. 1980. Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair. Environmental Ethics 2: 311–338. Carl, W. 1998. Die transzendentale Deduktion in der zweiten Auflage (B129–169). In Immanuel Kant. Kritik der reinen Vernunft, eds. Mohr, G., Willaschek, M., 189–216 (Klassiker Auslegen, ed. O. Höffe, vol. 17/18). Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Child, W. 2003. Causality, Interpretation, and the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Davidson, D. 1984. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Davidson, D. 2004. Problems of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. de Vries, W. 1988. Hegel’s Theory of Mental Activity. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Dickey, L. 1993. Hegel on Religion and Philosophy. In The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, ed. Beiser, F., 301–347. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dodd, J. 1995. The Body as ‘Sign and Tool. Hegel’s Encyclopedia,’ International Studies in Philosophy 27: 21–32. Düsing, K. 1973. Die Bedeutung des antiken Skeptizismus für Hegels Kritik der sinnlichen Gewißheit. Hegel-Studien 8: 119–130. Düsing, K. 1976. Das Problem der Subjektivität in Hegels Logik. Systematische und entwicklungsgeschichtliche Untersuchungen zum Prinzip des Idealismus und zur Dialektik, Hegel-Studien, Beiheft 15, Bonn: Bouvier. Falke, G. 1996. Begriffne Geschichte. Das historische Substrat und die systematische Anordnung der Bewußtseinsgestalten in Hegels “Phänomenologie des Geistes”. Interpretation und Kommentar, Berlin: Lukas Verlag. Ferrarin, A. 2001. Hegel and Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Flach, W. 1959. Negation und Andersheit. München-Basel: E. Reinhardt. Flay, J.C. 1970. Hegel’s Inverted World. The Review of Metaphysics 23: 652–678.
Bibliography
271
Flay, J.C. 1984. Hegel’s Quest for Certainty. Albany: SUNY Press. Føllesdal, D. 1982. Husserl’s Notion of Noema. In Husserl, Intentionality, and Cognitive Science, ed. Dreyfus, H.L. in collaboration with Harrison Hall, pp. 73–80. MIT Press. Förster, E. (ed.). 1989. Kant’s Transcendental Deductions. The Three Critiques and the Opus postumum. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Förster, E. 2000. Kant’s Final Synthesis. An Essay on the Opus Postumum. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Fulda, H.F. 1965. Das Problem einer Einleitung in Hegels Wissenschaft der Logik. Philosophische Abhnadlungen Bd. XXVII, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann. Fulda, H.F., Henrich, D. (eds.). 1979. Materialien zu Hegels “Phänomenologie des Geistes”. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Gadamer, H.G. 1960. Wahrheit und Methode. Grundzüge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. Gadamer, H.G. 1976. Hegel’s Dialectic. Five Hermeneutical Studies (trans: Smith, C.). New Haven: Yale University Press. Gardner, S. 2007. The limits of naturalism and the metaphysics of German idealism. In German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives, ed. Hammer, E., 19–49. London: Taylor & Francis. Graseser, A. 1996. Interpretation, Interpretativität und Interpretationismus. Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie 21: 253–260. Graeser, A. 1998. Zu Hegels Portrait der sinnlichen Gewißheit. In Klassiker Auslegen. G.W.F. Hegel: Phänomenologie des Geistes, eds. Köhler, D., Pöggeler, O., 33–51. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Grundmann, T. (ed.). 2001. Erkenntnistheorie. Positionen zwischen Tradition und Gegenwart. Padernborn: Mentis. Grundmann, T. 2003. Der Wahrheit auf der Spur. Eine Verteidigung des erkenntnis-theoretischen Externalismus. Paderborn: Mentis. Guyer, P. 1992. The Transcendental Deduction of the Categories. In The Cambridge Companion to Kant, ed. Guyer, P., 123–160. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Guyer, P. 2000. Absolute Idealism and the Rejection of Kantian Dualism. In The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism, ed. Ameriks, K., 37–56. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Halbig, C. 2002. Objektives Denken. Erkenntnistheorie und Philosophy of Mind in Hegels System, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog. Hanna, R. 1996. From an ontological point of view: Hegel’s critique of the common logic. In The Hegel Myths and Legends, ed. Stewart, J., 253–281. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Hansen, F.P. 1994. G.W.F. Hegel: ‘Phänomenologie des Geistes’. Ein einführender Kommentar. Paderborn-München-Wien-Zürich: UTB. Harris, H.S. 1997. Hegel’s Ladder. Vol. I: The Pilgrimage of Reason. Vol. II: The Odyssey of Spirit. Indianapolis-Cambridge: Hackett. Hartmann, K. 1972a. The ‘Analogies’ and After. In Proceedings of the Third International Kant Congress, ed. Beck, L.W., 47–62. Dordrecht: Reidel. Hartmann, K. 1972b. Hegel: A Non-Metaphysical View. In Hegel: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. McIntyre, A., 101–124. Garden City: Doubleday. Hartmann, K. 1973. Zur neuesten Dialektikkritik. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 55: 220–242. Hartmann, K. 1976. Die ontologische Option. In Die ontologische Option. Studien zu Hegels Propädeutik, Schellings Hegel-Kritik und Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes, ed. Hartmann, K., 1–30. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. Hartmann, K. 1982. Linearität und Koordination in Hegels Rechtsphilosophie. In Hegels Philosophie des Rechts, ed. Henrich, D., R.P. Horstmann, 305–316. Klett-Cotta: Stuttgart. Hartmann, K. 1999. Hegels Logik. ed. Olaf Müller, Berlin-New York: Walter de Gruyter.
272
Bibliography
Heidemann, D.H. 2007. Der Begriff des Skeptizismus. Seine systematischen Formen, die pyrrhonische Skepsis und Hegels Herausforderung. Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie, Bd. 78, Berlin/New York: Walter de Gruyter. Heinrichs, J. 1974. Die Logik der “Phänomenologie des Geistes”. Bonn: Bouvier. Henrich, D. 1969. The proof structure of the transcendental deduction. Review of Metaphysics 22: 640–659. Henrich, D. 1989. Kant’s notion of a deduction and the methodological background of the first Critique. In Kant’s Transcendental Deductions. The Three Critiques and the Opus postumum, ed. Förster, E., 29–46. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Hintikka, M.B., Hintikka, J. 1986. Investigating Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell. Hösle, V. 1988. Hegels System. Der Idealismus der Subjektivität und das Problem der Intersubjektivität, 2 vols. Hamburg: Meiner. Hofmann, F. 2002. Natur und Begriff des Bewußtseins. Eine repräsentationalistische Theorie des Bewußtseins, Paderborn: Mentis. Hofmann, J.N. 1994. Wahrheit, Perspektive, Interpretation: Nietzsche und die philosophische Hermeneutik. Berlin-New York: Walter de Gruyter. Horstmann, R.-P. 1984. Ontologie und Relationen. Hegel, Bradley, Russell und die Kontroverse über interne und externe Beziehungen. Königstein/Ts.: Athenäum-Hain. Hyppolite, J. 1974. Genesis and Structure of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit (trans: Cherniak, S., Heckman, J.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Jaeschke, W. 1986. Die Vernunft in der Religion. Studien zur Grundlegung der Religionsphilosophie Hegels. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog. Kainz, H.P. 1998. G.W.F. Hegel. The Philosophical System. Athens: Ohio University Press. Kettner, M. 1990. Hegel’s ‘Sinnliche Gewißheit’. Diskursanalytischer Kommentar. Frankfurt-New York: Campus Verlag. Köhler, D., Pöggeler, O. 1998. Einführung. In G.W.F. Hegel. Phänomenologie des Geistes. Klassiker Auslegen, eds. Köhler, D., Pöggeler, O., 1–31. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Krämer, H. 2007. Kritik der Hermeneutik: Interpretationsphilosophie und Realismus. München: C.H. Beck. Lauer, Q. 1976. A Reading of Hegel’s “Phenomenology of Spirit”, 2nd edition. New York: Fordham University Press. Lenk, H. 1988. Welterfassung als Interpretationskonstrukt: Bemerkungen zumethodischen und transzendentalen Interpretationismus. Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie 13: 67–78. Lenk, H. 1993a. Philosophie und Interpretation. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Lenk, H. 1993b. Interpretationskonstrukte. Zur Kritik der interpretatorischen Vernunft. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Lenk, H. 1995. Interpretation und Realität. Vorlesungen über Realismus in der Philosophie der Interpretationskonstrukte. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Löhrer, G. 1996. Einige Bemerkungen zur Theorieebene der Interpretationsphilosophie. Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie 21: 261–270. Longuenesse, B. 1998. Kant and the Capacity to Judge. Sensibility and Discursivity in the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason, tr. C.T. Wolfe. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press. McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. McDowell, J. 1998. Having the World in View: Sellars, Kant, and Intentionality. The Woodbridge Lectures. The Journal of Philosophy 95: 431–491. Nagel, T. 1982. The View From Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nagel, T. 1997. The Last Word. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nuzzo, A. 2003. The truth of Absolutes Wissen in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. In Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. New Critical Essays, eds. Denker, A., Vater, M., 265–293. Amherst: Humanity Books. Peperzak, A. 1987. Selbsterkenntnis des Absoluten. Grundlinien der Hegelschen Philosopie des Geistes. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt (Frommann-Holboog).
Bibliography
273
Pinkard, T. 1988. Hegel’s Dialectic. The Explanation of Possibility. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Pinkard, T. 1990. How Kantian Was Hegel? Review of Metaphysics 43: 831–838. Pinkard, T. 1996. Hegel’s Phenomenology. The Sociality of Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pippin, R.B. 1989. Hegel’s Idealism. The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Pippin, R.B. 1990. Hegel and category theory. Review of Metaphysics 43: 839–848. Pippin, R.B. 1996. Hegel’s metaphysics and the problem of contradiction. In The Hegel Myths and Legends, ed. Stewart, J. 239–252. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Pippin, R.B. 2000. Hegel’s practical philosophy: The realization of freedom. In The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism, ed. Ameriks, K., 180–199. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pippin, R.B. 2008. Eine Logik der Erfahrung? Über Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes. Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes. Ein kooperativer Kommentar zu einem Schlüsselwerk der Moderne, In eds. Vieweg, K., Welsch, W., 13–36. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Pöggeler, O. 1973. Hegels Idee einer Phänomenologie des Geistes. Freiburg/München: Alber. Prauss, G. 1971. Erscheinung bei Kant. Ein Problem der ‘Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. Putnam, H 1981. Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Putnam, H. 1983. Realism and Reason. Philosophical Papers, vol. 3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Putnam, H. 1990. Realism With a Human Face, ed. and Intro. Conant, J. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Quine, W.V.O. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Quine, W.V.O. 1969. Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press. Redding, P. 1996. Hegel’s Hermeneutics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Reid, J.D. 2003. On the Unity of Theoretical Subjectivity in Kant and Fichte. Review of Metaphysics 57: 243–277. Rescher, N. 1997. Objectivity. The Obligations of Impersonal Reason. Notre Dame-London: University of Notre Dame Press. Rickert, H. 1924. Das Eins, die Einheit und die Eins. 2nd edition. Tübingen: Mohr. Röd, W. 1991. Erfahrung und Reflexion. Theorien der Erfahrung in TranszendentalPhilosophischer Sicht. München: C.H. Beck. Röd, W., Thurnher, R., Schmidinger, H., Gombocz, W.L., Holzhey, H. 2002. Die Philosophie des ausgehenden 19. und des 20. Jahrhunderts 3: Lebensphilosophie und Existenzphilosophie. München: C.H. Beck. Rolston III, H. 1999. Holmes, III: Nature and culture in environmental ethics. In Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, vol 1. ed. Brinkmann, K., Bowling Green: Bowling Green State University. Rorty, R. 1980. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Rush, F. 2007. Dialectic, value objectivity, and the unity of reason. In The Oxford Handbook of Continental Philosophy, eds. Leiter, B., Rosen, M., 287–333. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Russon, J. 1997. The Self and Its Body in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Schnädelbach, H. 2000. Philosophie als spekulative Wissenschaft. In Hegels Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften (1830). Ein Kommentar zum Systemgrundriß, 21–86. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Sellars, W. 1997. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, with an introduction by Richard Rorty and a Study Guide by Robert Brandom. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press.
274
Bibliography
Senderowicz, Y.M. 2004. Figurative Synthesis and Synthetic A Priori Knowledge. Review of Metaphysics 57: 755–785. Siep, L. 2000. Der Weg der Phänomenologie des Geistes. Ein einführender Kommentar zu Hegel’s “Differenzschrift” und “Phänomelogie des Geistes”. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Simon, J. 1981. Sprachphilosophie. Freiburg: Karl Alber. Sober, E. 1986. Philosophical problems for environmentalism. In The Preservation of Species, ed. Norton, B., 173–194. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Speight, A. 2001. Hegel, Literature, and the Problem of Agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stederoth, D. 2001. Hegels Philosophie des subjektiven Geistes. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Strawson, P.F. 1989. The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. London: Routledge. Strawson, P.F. 1990. Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Routledge. Taylor, C. 1972. The opening arguments of the phenomenology. In Hegel: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. MacIntyre, A., 151–188. Garden City: Double Day & Co. Taylor, C. 1975. Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Toews, J. 1993. Transformations of Hegelianism, 1805–1846. In The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, ed. Beiser, F., 378–413. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Vieweg, K., Welsch, W. (eds.). 2008. Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes. Ein Kooperativer Kommentar zu einem Schlüsselwerk der Moderne. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. von Kutschera, F. 1993. Die falsche Objektivität. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. Wagner, H. 1959. Philosophie und Reflexion. München: E. Reinhardt. Wandschneider, D. 1982. Raum, Zeit, Relativität. Grundbestimmung der Physik in der Perspektive der Hegelschen Naturphilosophie. Frankfurt: Klostermann. Wandschneider, D. 1993. Natur und Naturdialektik im objektiven Idealismus Hegels. In Die Naturphilosophie im Deutschen Idealismus, eds. Gloy, K., Burger, P., 267–297. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog. Wandschneider, D. 1995. Grundzüge einer Theorie der Dialektik. Rekonstruktion und Revision dialektischer Kategorienentwicklung in Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta. Wartenberg, T.E. 1993. Hegel’s idealism: The logic of conceptuality. In The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, ed. Beiser, F.C. 102–129. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Welsch, W. 2003. Zwei Probleme in Hegels Idealismus. In Das Interesse des Denkens. Hegel aus heutiger Sicht, eds. Welsch, W., Vieweg, K., 247–282. München: Wilhelm Fink Verlag. Westphal, M. 1973. Hegels Phänomenologie der Wahrnehmung. In Materialien zu Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes, eds. Fulda, H.F., Henrich, D., 83–105. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Wiesing, L. 2004. Zur Kritik am Interpretationismus oder Die Trennung von Wahrheit und Methode. Internationales Jahrbuch für Hermeneutik 3: 137–151. Williams, R.R. 1992. Recognition. Fichte and Hegel on the Other. Albany: SUNY Press. Williams, R.R. 1997. Hegel’s Ethics of Recognition. Berkeley: University of California Press. Wood, A. 2000. Kant’s practical philosophy. In The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism, ed. Ameriks, K., 57–75. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Zöller, G. 1998. Fichte’s Transcendental Philosophy. The Original Duplicity of Intelligence and Will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Zöller, G. 2000. German realism: the self-limitation of idealist thinking in Fichte, Schelling, and Schopenhauer. In The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism, ed. Ameriks, K., 200–218. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Index
NOTE: Locators followed by n. refer note numbers A Abel, Günter, 14 n. 35, 15, 21 n. 51, 22 n. 52, n. 54, n. 57, 23–33, 37, 73 Agnosticism Hume’s, 17, 21 Allison, Henry, 43 n. 6, n. 7, 44 n. 11, 51 n. 29, 53 n. 36, 55 n. 41 Alterity, 26, 26 n. 69, 27, 37 principle of, 27 Altman, Matthew C., 52 n. 30 Ameriks, Karl, 233 n. 17 Anaxagoras, 84, 84 n. 7, 121 Anaximander, 34 n. 99 Antigone, 195–196, 266 Antirealism, 21–23 Aporia in the Phenomenology, 89–90 Appearance in Kant, 47, 73 in the transcendental sense, 47, 65, 72 Apperception, see Unity Approach constructionist, 120 hermeneutic, 27 immanentist, xi, 26 transcendental, 27, 43, 120 A priori, the putative, 94, 103, 105, 121, 155 Archimedes of Syracuse, 235 Argument transcendental, 42, 47, 56, 68, 76, 254, 256, 258 Aristotle, 6, 38, 38 n. 105, n. 106, n. 108, 42, 42 n. 3, 105, 105 n. 28, 109, 112, 112 n. 44, 120, 123 n. 59, n. 60, 141, 182, 207, 209, 214 n. 207, 216 n. 211, 236 n. 22,
244 n. 42, 246–247, 247 n. 54, 257 n. 85, 263 n. 97 Aschenberg, Reinhold, 88 n. 13, 99 n. 21, 243 n. 40 Aufhebung, see Sublation Autonomy, 196 B Bacon, Francis, 18, 18 n. 46, 38 n. 107 Baptist, Gabriella, 217 n. 214 Barth, Ulrich, 23 n. 58 Becker, Werner, 117 n. 48 Beiser, Frederick, 75 n. 69, 246 n. 50, 247 n. 51, 261 n. 92 Berkeley, George, 17–18, 21 Birke, Marcus, 15 n. 41 Bowie, Andrew, 143 n. 103 Brachtendorf, Johannes, 251 n. 71 Brandom, Robert B., 67 n. 62, 241 n. 36 Brentano, Franz, 90 Bunge, Mario, 263 n. 95 C Carl, Wolfgang, 43 n. 7, 44 n. 10, n. 13, 55 n. 40 Category in Hegel, 76, 147, 240, 245–247, 254–257 in Kant, 42–44, 51–53, 58, 63–64, 129 Causality, 129 Certainty moral vs. absolute, 11–12 Child, William, 23, n. 58 Circularity, 79, 83, 148, 227–228, 235 Cognition dual-source model of, 44, 53–54, 64, 168, 234 perceptual, 236
275
276 Cognition (cont.) representational model of, 168 Coherence, 12 as opposed to objectivity, 254 Coherentism, 11 Commitment(s) normative, 32 ontological, x, xi, 259, 262 Complementarity thesis, x, 48–49, 62–63, 114, 238 Completeness of the system of concepts, 254, 258 Concept(s) in Hegel, 58–61, 63, 66, 77, 79–80, 82, 88, 102, 139, 147, 182, 217, 250, 252 intelligibility vs. reference of, xi, 239 and intuition, 44, 48, 67 of the understanding, in Kant, 40, 43–44, 46, 49, 56, 62–63 Condition epistemic, 61 transcendental, in Hege, 96 Consciousness content of, 50, 76–77, 146–148, 154–155, 157 different from mind, 19–20 empirical, 86 finite, 79–80, 87, 91–93, 98, 100, 154 immanence of, 21, 74, 79, 89, 91, 94–95 inner sphere of, 8 intentionality of, 9, 90 nature of, 81, 85, 89 opposition of, 68, 71–72, 79–80, 85, 87–89, 99–102, 127, 144, 154–155, 165–167, 181–182, 189, 191, 208, 221, 228, 230, 234, 246, 258 origin of, 81 perceptual, 120 sensory, 105 standpoint of, 99–100 structure of, 20–21, 89–92, 96, 98–99 and truth, 13, 156 unhappy, 155, 172–177 unity of, 3 n. 8, 61, 69 Consensus, 33 Constructionism, 14, 22–23, 120 Contradiction, 149–151, 179, 209 within consciousness, 93 Copernican revolution/turn, ix, xi, 41, 49, 56, 64, 67, 72, 146–147 D Davidson, Donald, 1–2, 2 n. 5, 6, 14 n. 33, 23, 23 n. 58
Index Deduction transcendental, in Kant, ix, x, 26, 40, 43–44, 49–53, 55–57, 58–59, 64–70, 72–73 Descartes, Renéx, 6–16, 9 n. 16, 15 n. 40, 18, 20, 35, 37–39, 41, 71, 85, 91, 91 n. 15, 125, 128, 133, 152 n. 112, 180–181, 228, 232, 261 Descriptivism hermeneutic, 27 Desire, 158–159 Dialectic of consciousness, 84, 93 and its limits, 264 Dichotomy matter-form, 67 Dickey, Laurence, 75 n. 72 Dilemma moral, 265 Distinction true-false, 2 Doubt method of, 10 Dualism epistemological, 127 of intuition and concept, 44, 48, 52, 236, 256 of matter and form, 44, 233, 256 universal, 142 Dual source model, 44, 48, 53–54, 61–62, 64, 118–119, 168, 234 Düsing, Klaus, 59 n. 50, 63 n. 56, 106 n. 29, 117 n. 48 E Einstein, Albert, 260 n. 88 Empiricism, 119–120 Endorsement, 196 of truth claims, 37–38 Epictetus, 169, 169 n. 140 Epicurus, 104 n. 25 Essentialism, 28–29 atomic, 120, 123, 126, 139 Experience content of, 76–77 immanence of, x, 19, 21, 26, 35–36, 39–40, 49, 56, 70, 73–77, 102, 234, 258 scope of, 40 world of, 234 Externality, 83–84 of the material of cognition, 54, 71
Index F Falke, Gustav, 104 n. 25, 135 n. 83, 174 n. 144 Fallacy, 96, 111, 148 of misplaced concreteness, 194 Fallibility, 39 of human cognition, 38 Feuerbach, Anselm, 117 n. 48, 206 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 45 n. 17, 50, 55 n. 40, 56 n. 44, 70, 72, 86–87, 128, 135–136, 144–145, 144 n. 105, 145 n. 106, 148, 181–182, 214 n. 207, 226, 233, 251 n. 71, 257 n. 84 Finitude argument from, 34 of human cognition, 33, 38, 172–175, 177, 179, 232 Flach, Werner, 55 n. 39 Flay, Joseph C., 101 n. 23, 150 n. 111 Form of appearances, 44, 66 of cognition, 81–82, 103 of intuition, 44, 46, 58, 66 of knowledge, 40 of life, 29–30, 32–33, 39, 183, 189 of sensibility, 43 of thought, 77, 234–235, 248, 254–258 Formalism, 63, 68, 185 n. 173, 187–188, 188 n. 176 Kantian, 187–188 Framework categorial, 29 conceptual, 4, 6, 32, 36, 39, 76, 261 interpretive, 29–30, 29 n. 37, 39 non-relative, 259 of objectivity, 39, 93, 235 ontological, xi partial, 259–262 a priori, 39, 93 of reference, 113 Freedom, 160–162, 166, 168–172 Frege, Gottlob, 117 n. 48 Fulda, Hans Friedrich, 222 n. 2, n. 3, 224 n. 7, 232 n. 15 G Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 22, 22 n. 57, 136 n. 85, 251 n. 70 Gardner, Sebastian, 246 n. 50 Given, the mind-independent, 18 myth of, 22 Givenness, 45, 47, 51–52, 68, 121, 239
277 God in Descartes, 12 in Leibniz, 128 and the unhappy consciousness, 174–175 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang, 104 n. 27 Goodman, Nelson, 23 Gorgias of Leontinoi, 115 Graeser, Andreas, 23 n. 59, 24 n. 62, 104 n. 25 Grammar of thought, 76, 245, 255, 259–260 Ground of appearances, 133, 135 infinite, 89 of objectivity, 5, 88–89 reason as, 88 as self, 119 teleological, 179, 179 n. 158 Guyer, Paul, 43 n. 7, 50 n. 27, 55 n. 41, 68 n. 62, 118 n. 50, 236 n. 23 H Hanna, Robert, 150 n. 110 Hansen, Frank-Peter, 132 n. 78 Harris, Henry S., 101 n. 23, 104 n. 25, 108 n. 36, 136 n. 85 Hartmann, Klaus, 55 n. 39, 82 n. 5, 150 n. 110, 162 n. 131, 238 n. 30, 243 n. 40, 247 n. 51, 263 n. 95 Heidegger, Martin, 27, 210, 217 n. 214 Heidemann, Dietmar H., 224 n. 7, 232 n. 16 Heinrichs, Johannes, 101 n.23, 129 n. 74, 211 n. 203, 219 n. 218 Henrich, Dieter, 44 n. 10, 222 n. 3 Heraclitus, 110 n. 41, 119 n. 52, 131, 152 n. 113, 207 Hermeneutics, 22, 22 n. 57 Herz, Marcus, 41 n. 2 Heterogeneity, 42, 47, 62, 113–114, 143, 239 Hiatus epistemological, 10, 14, 18, 228, 230, 232 between ideas and referents, 7 ontological, 9–10 Hintikka, Jaakko, 111 n. 42 Hintikka, Merrill B.111 n. 42 Hofmann, Frank, 149 n. 107 Hofmann, Johann Nepomuk, 22 n. 57, 69 n. 65 Homogeneity, 61, 143 Horstmann, Rolf-Peter, 261 n. 92 Hösle, Vittorio, 253 n. 76, 254 n. 77 Hume, David, 11 n. 25, 17–18, 21, 130 n. 76, 132
278 Husserl, Edmund, 9 n. 16, 10 n. 19, 13 n. 28, 15 n. 37, 19, 27, 66 n. 60, 82 n. 5, 90, 91 n. 14, 96, 96 n. 19, 236 n. 22 Hyppolite, Jean, 101 n. 23, 120 n. 53 I I, the as consciousness, 84 as original synthetic unity, 59–61 as self-consciousness, 83–84 as a ‘We’, 156–157 Idea, 247–249, 252 absolute, 227–228, 253 Idealism absolute, 148, 248 empirical, ix, 45 Fichte’s, 87 German, 14, 19, 57 psychological, 63 subjective, 136, 147–148, 229, 232 transcendental, ix, x, 7, 44, 47, 49, 57, 62, 233–234, 236, 259 without limits, ix, 234, 257, 259 Identity of thought and being, 225, 229 Imagination in Kant, 42, 58–59 Immanence cognitive, 102 of consciousness, 19, 21, 40, 74, 79, 82, 89, 91, 94–95, 230 of experience, x, 19, 21, 26, 35–36, 39–40, 49, 56, 70, 73–77, 102, 234, 258 mental, 15–18, 21, 38, 39, 91 radical, 74, 79 of reason, 88–89 of self-consciousness, 155 of thought, ix, xi, 75, 101, 127, 165, 168, 233, 238, 258 without transcendence, 74 Immanentism Berkeley’s, 17 Kant’s, 39 mental, x, 15–18 Imperative categorical, 187 Indexical, 108, 108 n. 34, 108 n. 35, 113 Ineffability, 115, 115 n. 47, 119 Ineffable, the, 111–112, 111 n. 42, 114–115, 118 Inertia, 130, 131 Inference
Index immediate, 8 n. 14, 12 mediate, 12 Infinite, the, 126, 126 n. 68, 153–154, 239, 242–244 Infinit, see Infinite, the Intellectualism ethical, 169 Intelligibility, 49–51, 53, 234, 238–239, 257 Intentionality, 9, 20–21, 90, 96 Interpretation levels of, 24–25, 30 philosophy of, 23, 23 n. 59, 26–29 primordial, 24–28 Interpretationism, 22–24, 26–27, 29–32, 37, 73, 94, 97, 99, 233, 258 Intuitability thesis, 48–49 Intuition and concept, 44, 48, 53, 53 n. 36, 58–59, 64, 68 continuum of, 51 formal, 52, 55, 57, 65, 68, 103 forms of, in Kant, 40, 42–46, 52, 113 intellectual, 128, 148 manifold of, 42–48, 65–66 pre-representational, 42 Isomorphism in Aristotle, 38, 38 n. 106, 42, 42 n. 3 J Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich, 104 n. 25, 107, 107 n. 33, 232 Jaeschke, Walter, 75 n. 72 K Kainz, Howard P., 222 n. 2 Kant, Immanuel, ix, x, 3 n. 8, 5 n. 10, 7, 11 n. 25, 14–15, 18–19, 21–23, 22 n. 52, 27, 29, 33, 37, 39, 41–70, 71 n. 67, 72–74, 76, 86–87, 89, 92–93, 97–98, 101–103, 113–114, 120 n. 53, 125, 127–129, 133, 135, 135 n. 82, 145, 147, 169, 179, 181–182, 185, 187, 189, 195–197, 199, 214 n. 207, 217, 223–224, 228–229, 232–236, 235 n. 20, 238, 245–247, 247 n. 51, 254–257 Kettner, Matthias, 117 n. 48 Kierkegaard, Søren, 176 n. 150 Knowledge of absolute knowing, 213 empirical, 3, 21, 42, 49 foundations of, 51 objective, ix, 5, 5 n. 10, 8, 23, 40, 49, 95, 164–165, 214 a priori, 41, 48, 54, 234
Index representational, 71 subjective mediatedness of, 14 Köhler, Dietmar, 110 n. 41 Kojève, Alexandre, 217 n. 214 Krämer, Hans-Joachim, 22 n. 57 Kutschera, Franz von, 15 n. 37 L Language deictic, 105–106 descriptive, 108 pre-representational, 109 private, 111 n. 42, 198 representational, 108 Lauer, Quentin, 101 n. 23 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 7 n. 12, 11 n. 25, 15–16, 15 n. 38, n. 39, 42 n. 4, n. 5, 125, 128, 128 n. 71, 133, 152 n. 112, 179 n. 158, 180, 180 n. 160, 180 n. 161, 236, 259 Lenk, Hans, 14–15, 22 n. 52, 23–24, 24 n. 62, 29 n. 77, 73 Life, 141–142, 141 n. 95, 158, 176 Limnatis, Nektarios G., xii Locke, John, 10 n. 18, 10 n. 21, 16, 17, 17 n. 43, n. 44, 21, 69 Logic objective, 76 Löhrer, Guido, 24 n. 62 Longuenesse, Béatrice, 43 n. 6, 55 n. 41 Luther, Martin, 177 n. 152, 178 n. 154 M Manifold empirical, ix, 40, 42–48, 50, 54–57, 66–70, 73–74 of intuition, 42–43, 63, 66, 118 pre-representational, 45, 54 pure, 43–48, 51–55, 59, 68, 114–115, 117 Marivaux, Pierre, 149 n. 108 Master-slave relationship, 161–162 Material pre-representational, 43 Matter of appearances, 44, 66 of cognition, 70, 103 of knowledge, 40, 118 McDowell, John, 67 n. 62 Mentalism, 18–19 Metaphysics in Descartes, 11–12 in Hegel, 75–76, 246–248, 261 Method transcendental, 37
279 Mind different from consciousnes, 19 and world, 9–10, 71–72, 80, 82, 85, 149, 155, 167 Model dual-source, of cognition, 53–54, 64, 67, 74, 168 empiricist, of cognition, 67–69, 74 matter-form, of cognition, 67–68 referential, of cognition, 156 representational, of cognition, 168, 190, 233 Monad, 15, 48, 180, 180 n. 160 Monadicism cognitive, 34 Monism ontological, xi plural-aspect, 261 Moore, George Edward, 108 n. 36 Mozart, Wolfgang Amadeus, 149 n. 108 N Nagel, Thomas, 1 n. 2, 3, 261 Negation of negation, 113, 116, 126, 149, 153 of otherness, 170 in sense-certainty, 110, 112–113 Neo-Platonism, 251 Newton, Isaac, 130, 152 n. 112 Nietzsche, Friedrich, 22, 22 n. 57 Notion in Hegel, see Concept Nuzzo, Angelica, 213 n. 206 O Object of experience, 49 intentional, 19 mind-independent, 17 Objectivity cognitive, 33–36 and coherentism, 11 concept of, 28, 168 as a construct, x, 14, 21 defense of, 14, 32, 76 of empirical experience, 37 epistemic, 34–36 equivalent to reality, 3 and interpretationism, 14, 30 in Kant, 39, 41, 49 levels of, 70 non-relative, x, 39, 235, 260 objective, 92, 98–99, 189, 193 ontological, 35–36
280 Objectivity (cont.) partial, 261 source of, 229 sphere(s) of, 98 standards of, ix, x, 70, 76, 235 subjective, 92, 98, 256 and subjectivity, 5–7 unknowable, 73 Ontology alternative, 29 critical, 76 essentialist, 26 phenomenological, 27 quasi-transcendental, 259 two-aspect, 22 Opposite(s), the in force, 131–132 in magnetism, 134–135 Opposition of consciousness, 68, 71–72, 74, 79–80, 85, 87–89, 99–103, 127, 144, 146, 148–149, 154–155, 165–167, 181, 189, 191, 208, 221, 228, 230, 234, 246, 258 Primordial, 142, 142 n. 199 P Paradigm of cognition, 71–72 Paradigm shift in Descartes, 7–8 in Kant, 72 Paradox of faith, 175 Parmenides, 75, 154 n. 117, 215, 216 n. 213, 217, 233, 251 Particular, the bare, 109, 111 sensible, 104–105, 109 spatio-temporal, 104 Particularism cognitive, 33 Perspective first person, 7–8 third person, 8 Philosophy content of, 76–77, 250 history of, 250 of identity, 145 of indifference, 135 of interpretation, 23, 26–29 transcendental, 39, 41, 49, 87 Pinkard, Terry, 75 n. 69, 94 n. 16, n. 17, 101 n. 23, 108 n. 35, 123 n. 58, 245 n. 44
Index Pippin, Robert B., 50 n. 27, 75 n. 69, 150 n. 110, 191 n. 179, 193 n. 182, 245 n. 44, 247 n. 52 Plato, 111, 119, 127, 188, 210, 216 n. 211, 236 n. 22, 246, 257 n. 85 Play of idea with itself, 252 Pluralism integrative, xi, 259, 261 of world-views, 261 Pöggeler, Otto, 110 n. 41, 222 n. 2, 223, 223 n. 5 Point of view God’s-eye, 33, 36, 235, 245, 245 n. 44 Popper, Karl, 4 n. 9 Pragmatism, 22, 258 Prauss, Gerold, 43 n. 6 Principle of alterity, 27 of consciousness, 20 in Descartes, 10–12 of equipollence, 170–171 of indifference, 127 of interpretationism, 24 n. 62, 31 of non-contradiction, 12, 15, 138, 144, 150, 243 of reasonableness, 33 of sufficient reason, 15, 48 of tautological identit, 135 of tolerance, 264 of universalizability, 185–186, 185 n. 173 of valid coherence, 28 Protagoras of Abdera, 121 Purpus, Wilhelm, 117 n. 48 Putnam, Hilary, 22 n. 53, 23, 30 n. 87, 117 n. 48 Q Quine, Willard van Orman, 16 n. 42, 117 n. 48 R Rationality abstract/formal, 185, 188–189, 191 is inherently objective, 32 standard of, 32, 35 Realism direct, 18, 22 empirical, ix, 7, 54–55, 234, 236 epistemological, 10, 18–19 internal, 16 metaphysical, 9, 15, 18, 23, 36, 38, 123 perceptual, 120
Index Reality and concept, 131 conception of, 3 empirical, of objects, 47 as interpretation, 14 mind-independent, 10, 16, 18, 21–22, 34, 54 nature of, in Leibniz, 15 necessary structure of, 42 objective, 44–45, 49, 54 Reason concept of, in Hegel, 87–88, 126, 177–182, 190, 249 and consciousness, 101 demands of, 33 impartial, 32 natural light of, 12–13 universality of, 33 Reconstruction as a method, xi, 76, 179, 194, 254 Reduction methodological, 262 Reference, xi, 91, 108, 113, 119, 156, 238–239 a priori, 52 Referentiality, 9, 17, 52, 54, 56, 67–68, 166, 236, 238–239 Reid, James D., 53 n. 36, 55 n. 41 Reinhold, Karl Leonhard, 20, 226, 233 Relationship of ground and grounde, 101–102, 117 Relativism, 28–30, 33, 33 n. 96 Representation in Hegel, 77, 94, 109, 147, 156, 163, 166–167, 246, 255 Rescher, Nicholas, 15, 32–36 Restriction thesis, x, 48 Revolution Cartesian, 10 Copernican, 62, 64, 74, 100, 124, 136, 144–145, 217, 235 Rickert, Heinrich, 54 n. 39 Röd, Wolfgang, 14 n. 34, 22 n. 57 Rorty, Richard, 18, 18 n. 47, 23 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 161 n. 128 Rush, Fred, 260 S Sartre, Jean-Paul, 20 n. 49, n. 50, 27, 34 Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph, 57, 72, 127, 135, 137 n. 88, 142–145, 150 n. 111, 152, 226, 253, 259
281 Scheme conceptual, 33, 36 interpretive, 34 Schleiermacher, Friedrich, 174 n. 144 Searle, John R., 117 n. 48 Self and the concept, 102 and world, 80–81, 86 Self-consciousness and another self-consciousness, 160 duplication of, 172 as fulfilled self, 163 and (object-)consciousness, 81, 90, 127, 145–146, 157–159, 162–163, 170, 178, 180, 190 and objectivity, 147 self-determining, 196 universal, 163, 182–183, 192 Self-externalization of spirit, 249, 253, 257, 259 Self-referentiality, 119, 126, 212–213 Sellars, Wilfrid, 22, 22 n. 56, 23, 68 n. 62 Senderowicz, Yaron M., 55 n. 41 Sensibility in Kant, 43–45, 49, 51, 53, 55 Sextus Empiricus, 222 n. 1 Shankara, Adi, 252 n. 73 Siep, Ludwig, 101 n. 23, 150 n. 111, 222 n. 3 Simon, Joseph, 117 n. 48 Skepticism, 5, 21, 72, 106, 106 n. 29, 155, 170, 171 n. 142, 223, 231 Solipsism, 16 Soul, 80–81, 85 Space mental, 16, 18–20 Speight, Allen, 94 n. 17, 140 n. 92 Spinoza, Baruch de, 15–16, 75, 125, 128, 133, 142, 144, 180, 251–252, 259 Spirit absolute, 203–205 concept of, 156, 194–195 historicity of, 251 immediate, 206 self-conscious, 206 self-externalization of, 249, 253, 259 Standard of objectivity, 32–33, 70, 74, 77 of rationality, 32–33, 35 of truth, 92–93 Stederoth, Dirk, 107 n. 33 Stimulus, 16–18 Stoicism, 168, 170
282 Strategy transcendental, 7, 32, 68 Strawson, Peter, 3 n. 8, 48 n. 25, 113 n. 45, 239, 239 n. 33 Subject epistemic, 12–13, 16, 18–19, 41, 50, 54 transcendental, 39 Subjectivity as condition of truth, 10, 229 crisis of, x, 7, 10, 14–15, 39 Descartes’ turn towards, 37–39 as formal aspect of cognition, 230 as ground/source of objectivity, 5, 7–8, 39, 73, 88 and objectivity, 5–7, 142–144, 165 a priori structures of, 40 self-referential, 194 Subject-object divide, 103 duality, 127, 136 relationship, 126 unity, 102 Sublation, 149–151, 153–154, 263 Substance ethical, 184–185, 187–189, 191–198 Supersession, see Sublation Syllogism, 173 Synthesis of finitude and transcendence, 173, 175, 179 in Kant, 17, 42–43, 45–46, 48, 51–58, 60, 63–70 System of concepts, 75, 77, 240–241, 244, 247, 254, 257–258 of determinations of though, 229 interpretive, 31 of language, 30 metaphysical, 15 self-referential, 32 of signs, 14 T Taylor, Charles, 94 n. 16, 101 n. 23, 108 n. 35 Temporality, 251 Thinghood, 120–121 Thing-in-itself, 22, 39–40, 42, 47, 49–50, 73–74, 87, 92, 127, 133 Thinking, see Thought Thought grammar of, 245, 255, 259 holistic nature of, 1 n. 1 immanence of, ix, xi, 75, 101, 127, 168, 233, 238, 258
Index and language, 260 objective, xi, 1 n. 2, 99–100, 147, 155, 164, 213, 221, 235, 245, 248, 256–259 and objectivity, 1, 29, 147, 164, 167, 260 and reality, 49 representational, 146, 166–167 speculative, 153 Tieck, Ludwig, 137 n. 88, 149 n. 108 Toews, John, 75 n. 72 Transcendence, 172–175, 179 within immanence, 22, 74, 94, 102 Translation into thoughts, 77, 156, 256 Truth as agreement of idea and object, 17 as coherence, 36 comparative notion of, 156 as correspondence, 36 Descartes’ conception of, 9, 9 n. 16, 37 empirical, 11, 13, 32, 36 impersonal, 9 metaphysical, 11–13 native realm of, 155 objective, 34, 39, 214, 228–229 referential conception of, 9 representational, 71 and responsibility, 38 synonymous with objectivity, 2 of thinking and being, 182 Truth value, xi, 119, 244 intensive, 156 Tugendhat, Ernst, 117 n. 48 U Understanding, 125–126, 181 in Kant, 43–45, 49, 51, 53–55 Unity of apperception, ix, 52, 56, 58–60, 62–65, 67–68, 73–74, 128, 135, 145, 176, 229, 233 of consciousness, 61, 69 mind-body, 262 of self and other/object, 102, 157 of self-consciousness, 40, 56, 57, 59, 60–61, 64–65, 70, 72, 89, 93, 135, 145, 147, 158, 176, 180–182, 189–190, 217, 233 subject-object, 58, 72, 102, 145 Universal, the, 52, 108–114, 116, 119–120, 185, 237–238, 246 concrete, 202 Universality, 86 abstract, 243 concrete, 61–63, 243
Index V Validity objective, of the categories, 254, 257, 259 objective, of knowledge, 18, 39, 44–45, 49–51, 61 universal, 6 Value of truth, 119 Vieweg, Klaus, 101 n. 23 W Wagner, Hans, 55 n. 39 Wandschneider, Dieter, 150 n. 110 Wartenberg, Thomas E., 75 n. 69, 246 n. 50, 247 n. 51 Welsch, Wolfgang, 14 n. 31, 101 n. 23, 247–249 Westphal, Merold, 107 n. 33, 109 n. 39, 117 n. 48
283 Wiesing, Lambert, 14 n. 32 Will of the individual, 177 universal, 180 Williams, Robert R., 161 n. 127 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 21 n. 51, 29, 111 n. 42, 222 Wood, Allen W., 188 n. 176 World of consciousness, 21, 76 of experience, 21, 26, 49 interpretive, 29 inverted, 127, 135–138, 141, 149–150, 152, 172, 179 limits of, 21 mind-independent, 9–10, 16 objective, 3 supersensible, 117, 127, 132–133, 136–138, 140–142, 149