Probabilistic Foundations for Operator Logic B. H. Slater The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 44, No. 3. (Sep., 1993), pp. 517-530. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0007-0882%28199309%2944%3A3%3C517%3APFFOL%3E2.0.CO%3B2-F The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science is currently published by Oxford University Press.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/oup.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.
JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact
[email protected].
http://www.jstor.org Mon Jun 4 08:34:44 2007
Brit. 1. Phil. Sci. 44 (1993), 5 I 7-530 Printed in Great Britain
Probabilistic Foundations for
Operator Logic
B. H. SLATER
1 2 3 4 5 6
Introduction Privileged Access Some Probabilistic Definitions The Case of Knowledge lrnrnediate Consequences The Parallel w i t h Obligation
I INTRODUCTION
I give in this paper a doxastic and epistemic logic based on probability theory. A deontic logic of this kind has been provided before, by George Schlesinger (Schlesinger [I985 (a)], [ l 9 8 5 (b)]),and I will have a word to say later in further explication of that. Also, it is well known that Frank Ramsey based his account of probability on belief (Ramsey [19 78]),so he formulated the reverse connection to one established here. But I take my start from a basic question in modern philosophy, which enables me, in the first place, to deal with belief and knowledge in the same way as obligation, and specifically permits the doxastic logic to be easily extended to an epistemic one. That basic question in philosophy, which underlies much of epistemology, was traditionally answered by empiricists in a well known way (Ayer [1936], [1956]). Our knowledge of the world, they held, was formed from a series of inferences made on the basis of immediate experiences. These immediate experiences, providing 'sense data', were the unshakable foundations for our knowledge of the external world. The story will be familiar to most readers, even if they have been persuaded that the theory of knowledge is more adequately dealt with within, say, Idealism. In particular, from within Idealism it may seem to be easier to construct a theory of moral knowledge, and social concepts generally. Now it will be a central part of the present account that we do not have access to objective sense data-a difficulty which sometimes persuades people that Idealism must be right. Also there will be room within the theory for choice and varying culturally determined concepts-further features traditionally associated with the imaginative base
518
B. H. Slater
of Idealism. But the theory of belief, knowledge and obligation which will emerge is instead stamped more with twentieth century movements like Existentialism than with either of the two traditional rival philosophies. For it places action at the base of epistemology in place of any kind of experience, whether sensory or imaginative. What is firm and unshakable, in the first place, if anything is, is an action, not a sensation, and, even less, an image. What we have privileged access to is not something given but something made. 2 P R I V I L E G E D ACCESS
It will be useful to have some definitions at the outset, of some key concepts in epistemology: Knowledge, Belief, and Wonder. Writing 'Kap' for the operator expression 'a knows that p', we can say that, according to empiricism, a defining feature of an immediate experience is that it is a part of consciousness, and so is one about which the owner of the experience must have complete knowledge. Alston (Alston [197l]) formulated this 'Omniscience' by making p 3 Kap, necessary, when 'p' describes the immediate experience in question. Because of the properties of knowledge, however, this expression for basic experiences may be tightened so as to make it necessary that
-
p Kap. As I said, it is part of my brief to attack empiricism on this matter, and one can do so very firmly with this point. For not only, as a result, is the knowledge operator redundant in this context, the full equivalence leaves the supposed experience entirely without any content. For the experience is revealed to be no more than just the knowing of itself. Now it is sometimes said, regarding taking omniscience as defining certain experiences, that it presumes the experiences in question cannot be too subtle. Thus someone seeing magenta, it has been said, need not recognize it as such, and the empiricist defence to this charge is commonly "Well even if I don't know it is magenta, at least I know it is that colour!' To this maybe there is an inclination to respond 'He is left with that personal ostension even if the colour is crude', or 'How can he even be sure it is a colour? Personal ostension cannot define anything' (cf. Hacker [1972], p. 233f., Kenny [1973], p. 182f.).But the above equivalence gives us a stronger point to make than these. For the content of all 'immediate experiences' is shown to be quite empty by that equivalence, so it is a logical point which settles the matter, and absolutely. Maybe an omniscient being contingently knows everything, but if it is a definitional part of some event that it be known, that can only be 'navel gazing'.
Probabilistic Foundations for Operator Logic
519
But while there must be vacuity with basic experiences, there can be no vacuity with basic actions. If you believe your hand is rising, and it is subject to your will, then your hand is rising. But even if your hand is rising you need not believe this, since, for instance, you may be asleep. So no corresponding equation between the belief and its object is obtainable with the cognition involved in conation. If we write 'Bap' for the operator expression 'a believes that p', and take 'p' to describe a movement entirely subject to a's will, we can follow Alston again and define 'Infallibility' by making it necessary that Bap 2 Kap, which entails the necessity of B~PIP for the specific 'p's in question. But while that anchors the mind in behaviour, at a n appropriately basic level, there is no reverse requirement, p 2 Bap, reducing the possession of the belief completely to the physical movement. Thus the movement can occur without the mental element-it is then simply not an action. But we must be careful to rule out the inactive imagination, allowed within Idealism, when we thus link basic actions and beliefs. For beliefs invariably are linked with actions, since one cannot be said to have a belief unless one acts accordingly. And the same is not true of imaginings. Moreover, it is a special kind of belief that is involved with basic actions, which makes the link, in that case, even more immediate. Actions are generally thought of as the result of a complex of beliefs and desires. Schematically, when wanting W, and believing action A will lead to obtaining W, we do action A. The case of basic actions, however, cannot be construed on quite this model, since there is no prior action then needed to obtain the desired end, and so no causal belief about how to satisfy any want. Being intentional, however, means that another kind of belief is central to basic actions, namely the belief just that we are doing them. It is that belief alone which, as above, logically guarantees the action. Maybe we often do such actions 'just because we want to', but the relation between any such want and the resultant action is not logical but causal. The relation between the action and the belief that we are doing it is not a causal relation. This kind of belief is expressed in the action itself, by the action being done knowingly, i.e. 'willingly'. So possession of the belief is not separate from or antecedent to the associated behaviour. This point needs to be appreciated to understand the difference between Belief and Thought. Certainly one's hand need not move if one merely thinks one's hand is moving, but that is expressly because thoughts, unlike beliefs, need not be apparent in overt bodily behaviour. Thoughts, after all, may just be
520
B. H. Slater
expressed in words, and so may be insincere, or impotent, i.e. not lead to the appropriate deeds. In connection with such insincere and impotent thoughts, there is therefore one further important concept in the current series. The notion of 'wonder' characterizes a third alternative, where there is neither belief nor knowledge, but just thought. Thus, for example, in the above cases of basic actions, there is a one-way gap in between the belief and the movement. So while with basic actions if a believes that p, then p, and if a believes that l p then l p still p or l p may occur without either Bap or Balp. But we say, if someone neither believes that p nor believes that l p , that he wonders whether p. So the exceptional case where a's hand goes up although he does not believe it is a case of this wonderment. We enter 'wonderland' characteristically when we are asleep, though if, while awake, one's hand is 'asleep' one can have the same kind of detached experience. One of the failures of Idealism is that it did not separate out this area of the mind from more practical areas. More recent twentieth century traditions, however, have sieved out such non-functional parts of the mind, while basing their positive account of knowledge and obligation on action. This points to the centrality of belief in the above sense. Ramsey, it will be remembered, required beliefs to be evident in practical action, if only to the extent that they were related to the individual's preparedness to bet. But we go further than that here, since preparedness to bet only certainly relates to subjective assessments of belief, and so does not take into account beliefs the agent may be unconscious of, or indeed mistaken about. Many other philosophers have recently essayed such more 'activist' views, including Wittgenstein, for instance: Giving grounds, however, justifying the evidence, comes to a n end;-but the end is not certain propositions' striking us immediately as true, i.e. it is not a kind of seeing on our part; it is our acting which lies at the bottom of the language game (Shiner [1977/8], p. 105).
3
SOME PROBABILISTIC DEFINITIONS
Now 'wondering whether p' may clearly be defined probabilistically as that state of awareness where the probabilities of p happening and not happening are the same. When the probability is one-half, there is no belief that p nor belief that l p . The states of positive belief, therefore are simply when the probabilities are not one-half. So we can start to formulate exactly some of the above ideas by separating out three cases, as follows,
Probabilistic Foundatior~sfor Operator Logic
521
which specifically formulate belief, wonder and disbelief, respectively. Knowledge is then clearly given by
though much more will have to be said about this key concept later. We can then define 'thought' by the obverse relation
This covers knowing p, believing p, wondering whether p, and most ways of disbelieving p, but excludes knowing otherwise, i.e. excludes
So there is knowledge when and only when there is no thought of the reverse. Contrariwise, there is most often a state of 'uncertainty' when one both thinks that p and thinks that l p , which state is more general than, but includes the case of wonder. We may also include in the latter case matters about which one simply has no opinion, i.e. whose probability is one half by the principle of indifference. It remains to remind readers of the axioms of probability theory, before we tie in these probabilistic expressions with expressions for different individuals' beliefs. In fact we rieed only say (Rescher [1968], p. 183) that, given a domain D of statements closed under the statement generating operations of propositional and predicate logic, then, for all p in D
If p is necessary then pr(p)= 1,
+
If l(p.q) is necessary then pr(p v q) = pr (p) pr (q). These axioms are sufficient to define a probability measure, although, importantly, they do not finalise pr(p v q) when p and q are compatible. That probability is formally indeterminate, being simply not greater than the sum of pr(p) and pr(q),but not less than each separately. This looseness will feature when we come to assess how knowable probabilities are, in section 6, but we shall see that the more determinate aspects of the probability calculus are themselves already sufficient to tell us a great deal about knowledge and belief, in Section 5 .
4
T H E CASE O F K N O W L E D G E
But clearly, to get expressions specifically for individuals' beliefs we must, first of all, relativise the above probabilities in some way. But using the looseness in the definition of probability to allow self assessments of beliefs in terms of subjective probabilities would run into trouble with the definition of know-
52 2
B. H. Slater
ledge. A person's own avowal of certainty would then establish it. More plausible is the quasi-empiricist move, which would conditionalize the probabilities on the immediate knowledge available to each individual. So long as we do not take the subject's immediate knowledge to be given to him as a n experience, or derived from his imagination, but instead see it as created by him, through his actions, we will have escaped the major philosophical difficulty with this approach which we identified at the start. For individual a we may then write.
to express the fact that he has a belief that p. Here LY describes a's immediate knowledge, and so the conditional probability is defined, i.e. not pr(cc)= 0. As a result, we get a n objective estimate of the probability of p, from a's perspective, i.e. conditional on a's immediate knowledge, although what is used as the probability measure may vary, as before. Being objective others must be able to judge it on the overt behaviour of a, and so, again, his own self-estimate is not necessarily a guide to it. What someone believes he believes he does not necessarily believe, since pr(Bap/r) > does not entail Bap. But the major technical problem with the above formulation of belief is this: how can it be extended to give a n account of knowledge? How can
3
express a's knowledge that p, i.e. entail that p? For might it not be the case, while that expression held, that, say, for individual b
Then we would seemingly be committed to saying p was both true and false, or at least 'true for a', 'false for b' etc. The rationalist solution to this general problem of personal access to objective truth was to limit all that can be known to the necessary truths of mathematics and logic, i.e. things independent of a and b. But that produces a 'modal collapse', with no discrimination between 'Necessarily, p' and 'p'. The empiricist solution, as we have seen, was to limit the conditions in the probability judgements to immediate experiences, now shown to be vacuous. The subjective idealists, giving a spurious legitimacy to imagination and the resultant wonder, believed knowledge did not have a guaranteed intersubjective consistent form, and so saw no solution to the problem, with many of them even ending up accepting, as true, contradictions, But other idealists, notably Kant, saw another way out of the impasse, and it is easy to see that line of thought is all we need to follow here. For the logic of the matter only requires, if pr(p/a) = 1 entails p, that it rule out pr(lp/B) = 1, for all p, i.e. for all statements of the type which
Probabilistic Foundations for Operator Logic
523
can occur in place of 'a' in this entailment. But since, in particular, we must have
what that means is that LY must be true, while we must not have, for instance, i.e. that P is incompatible with r. Yet that compatibility is automatically achieved, since also, P must be true, i.e.
But quite generally, if pr(P/r)>O then, given pr(a)> 0, one cannot have pr(p/cx)= 1 and pr(lp/b) = 1, though, of course one can still have pr(p/a)>+ and pr(lp/P) > To operate with a concept of knowledge on the above lines, therefore, people must just be presumed to have beliefs which are based on facts. Incompatible beliefs are then not ruled out (justifying the subjective idealists to some extent), but all proper knowledge will be consistent. This might look like a form of causal theory of knowledge, but the present transcendental deduction from the possibility of consistent knowledge has a conclusion which is not a causal hypothesis. Its regulative conclusion merely requires we treat basic actions as providing the ultimate unshakable facts upon which we found any firm beliefs.
t.
5
IMMEDIATE CONSEQUENCES
Now, as was mentioned before, there are already some clear advantages of the present account of knowledge and belief, deriving from the more determinate aspects of the probability calculus, which we may check through before proceeding further. (i) Perhaps the prime virtue of the present account is that it allows the 'logicality' of the mind to be quite limited. Other theories have required 'deductive omniscience', i.e. the power to generate all inferences. But it is not a theorem, on the present account of belief, for instance, that
so whatever follows from p.q is not a conclusion which needs to be drawn when p and q are believed separately. In technical terms, Adjunction is not automatic. (ii) What is a theorem, however, is
and this traditionally has been a source of worry (Cresswell [1985], Ch. I), since everyone as a consequence believes all necessary truths. But fear of this
5 24
B. H. Slater
consequence is much reduced once it is realized Adjunction is not given. Distinctions amongst learners of mathematics and logic can then still be made-though in a more practical content. For it is now respected as quite reasonable that people don't always 'put two and two together'. Hence someone who believes he has two apples, and also believes he has a further two apples need not believe he both has two apples and a further two apples-and only from the latter belief does the belief immediately follow that he has four apples. (iii) Thus what is also a theorem is
+
allowing Ba(x = 2 2) to entail Ba(x = 4), and also, for instance, Ba(p.q) to entail Bap. But this means we have a characterization of the 'obvious' inferences commonly taken to delimit the extent to which the mind can be guaranteed to operate. The inferences it alone draws are the irnrnediate ones. The mind thus does not draw all consequences of all beliefs, but indeed without some consequences being inferred what could be the content of any single belief? That content, we can now see, is given simply by producing, and unpacking the implications of that single belief. Even so there theoretically could be a n infinity of such implications, which runs counter to some views of the mind-as a physical instrument running occurrent brain processes. Clearly the product of any such instrument must be finite. But the 'producing' and 'unpacking' of implications are on our part, they do not describe any temporal brain process on the part of the agent. For, as before, having a belief is a matter of relating to the world in a certain way. But from this it logically, and not causally follows that the subject has another belief, i.e. relates to the world another way. So what we unpack or produce are merely third party re-descriptions of part of the agent's behaviour pattern. (iv) Likewise we can often tell the agent does not have a certain belief. For on the present definition we have Bap 2 TBalp, and we also have
Hence we resolve the further question whether beliefs in the impossible are possible. They are impossible, in both ways that this can be taken. On the present definition of thought, however, contradictory choughts are not ruled out. For the quite consistent pr(p/a)= p r ( l p / a ) =+, means that a both thinks that p and thinks that l p . But still the agent cannot think that p.lp, since P~((P?~P =)0./ ~ ) The point gives us a solution to Kripke's puzzle about belief (Kripke [ I 9 791). For if Kripke's Pierre says 'Londres est jolie' and 'London is not pretty' then, at
Probabilistic Foundations for Operator Logic
525
least, his mind is clear to the extent that it is guaranteed to lack a thought which would lead to absurdity-that London both is and isn't pretty. And that perhaps eases Kripke's reluctance to saying that, despite Pierre's impeccable reasoning abilities, he still has contradictory thoughts. He certainly does have contradictory thoughts, even though he cannot adjoin them, as thoughts. What is more in question though is whether he has contradictory beliefs. For it is now clear that the disquotational principles Kripke uses to locate Pierre's beliefs shows Pierre is insincere in at least one of the things he says. Sincerity is not a matter of stressed expression, after all, it is a matter of whether the assertion leads to the appropriate behaviour. So the inconsistency of Pierre's thoughts expressly shows that only thought can be involved in at least one side of the case. The question is, what will Pierre do when he gets to London-love it or hate it? Whichever he does he goes against his other word. So his thinking, at least part of the time, must be idle; and perhaps all the time it is idle, if he is not put in a situation where he has to act. (v) In this connection we may remember that Ramsey's theory of probability, which we are largely reversing, has sometimes been criticized for presuming beliefs are 'rational'. But beliefs are by definition 'rational', at least to the extent of being consistent, though they may fail to be entirely 'logical' in other ways, because of the absence of Adjunction. Thus while it is never possible to have Bap. Balp, it is quite possible to have Bap. Baq. Bal(p. q). Thus, as has often been remarked, one might well believe, individually, each of a series of propositions, but still have a proper suspicion that at least one of them is false. But notice that we avoid here standard 'Dutch Book' difficulties with subjective assessments of probability (cf., for instance, Van Fraassen [1984]),because we are using objective judgements of belief, which may be at odds with the agent's self-assessments (cf. Mellor [1980]). A quasi-Freudian 'unconscious' thus naturally enters our present picture of the mind, with the agent's beliefs about his beliefs not necessarily being reliable. (vi) Of more importance for later issues is the related matter that there is no difficulty now with the 'rationality' in the standard definition of knowledge. Indeed, the present analysis shows the way out of Gettier's problem with the standard definition (Gettier [1963]). For, from (iii) we see, for example, that if a believes there is a man in the room, he believes there is a person in the room. But maybe there is only a woman in the room, although a believes there is a man in the room, and cannot be blamed for believing this, i.e. he has taken all reasonable care. Do we want to say that a knows there is a person in the room, since he justifiably believes this, and it is true? But even when one has taken all
526
B. H. Slater
the care one could reasonably be expected to take one needn't (strictly, absolutely) know, simply because the case may be 'unreasonable', and one may still have been deceived, as the skeptic will continually remind us. Hence, as Gettier showed, perfect knowledge is not a matter of justified true beliefwhen 'justified' is taken in the quasi-moral sense just indicated, i.e. that in which it is linked with such legal concepts as having taken all reasonable care. However, there is a logical, and not quasi-moral justification in the present concept of knowledge which leads to a re-establishment of 'justified true belief' as a proper definition of knowledge. For it is easily seen, for example, that (Kap. Kaq) 3 I
Now one further advantage of the present account of knowledge and belief is not just that it formalizes some traditional epistemological conceptions, but that it does so in a way that links them, through action, to morality. For the immediate knowledge which is the base of the epistemological edifice is not a given datum, nor contrariwise a wild imagining, but concrete facts created by our engagement with the human and physical world. There is another way, as well, that questions of value now enter the discussion. For when philosophers and logicians started to turn their attention to formalizations of propositional attitude notions in the middle years of this century more rationalist conceptions were dominant. Going with that, the logical approaches then developed separated themselves from measurable quantities, with logics of belief being assayed, for instance, which did not allow, as here, for degrees of belief. This lack of measure was also evident in the study of deontic logic, to which of course, degrees of value must somehow relate. But early logical studies of obligation did not even take the concept of xralue into account. Van Fraassen, however (Van Fraassen [1972], see also Slater [1988]),made a n important move when he defined the obligatoriness of the act p in terms of the greater value of p over l p . But it was Schlesinger's
Probabilistic Foundations for Operator Logic
52 7
work which showed that these values were boolean, and so not of the complex sort van Fraassen had nominated. What Schlesinger, following Chisholm, actually showed was that deontic logic is isomorphic to probability theory: This method requires that when confronted with a statement asserting that a certain set of deontic expressions implies another set and we wish to find out whether the statement represents a valid theorem, what we need is to change the operator '0'-which stands for 'it is obligatory to see to it that . . .'-into the epistemic operator 'E' and see whether the resulting statement is or is not a valid theorem (Schlesinger [1985(a)],p. 61).
In present terms Schlesinger thus showed that moral expectations are a form of natural belief. Strangely, though, Schlesinger did not investigate why this formal correspondence arises: he only showed that understanding obligation his way resolved the standard paradoxes. The current discussion however, now indicates the reason for the Chisholm/Schlesinger isomorphism, and its further development in a moment wiI1 reveal more relevant aspects of morals and ethics. For, given that moral obligations are to be seen merely as special kinds of beliefs, it is clear that they are, for a start, social expectations, and their probabilistic logic thus arises principally through the numerical form of mass attitudes like 'most people in society S expect that p'. Here, as before, 'p' is a description of some aspect of an individual human's behaviour which is entirely subject to his will. But, as with matters of personal conation, there is a close link between such expectations and the associated actions, and, as a result, it in fact becomes possible to formulate a probabilistic theorem in this area to parallel the exact logical relation between belief and action we studied in the individual case. For suppose that the agent is a member of the society S, then, if, as above, the mass attitude has the form 'most people in society S believe that p', i.e. mx(Bxp),we get, a priori, For, if we know no more about a's beliefs, the a priori chance that he believes that p, given that he is a member of S, is just the ratio of the number of members of S that believe that p, over the total number of members of S. And this ratio is greater than one half when most p e ~ p l ein society S do in fact have the belief. But if 'p' is specifically a statement about a's actions, say that a will do A, we have, in addition, necessarily Bap 2 p, as we saw before. It follows that we have
which says everyone with no further knowledge must expect that, if most
B. H. Slater people in a society expect some member will do A, then he will do A. Now this result might be thought to reflect some causal mechanism, perhaps 'social pressure' working on members of the society. But the above proof assumed no such process was involved: the behaviour of each individual can be quite free, and yet the probabilistic result will stand. The similarity of the result to Hintikka's distinctive axiom for deontic logic (Hintikka [1970], p. 71, see also Chellas [1980], p. 1 9 3 ) is apparent. That axiom, viz.,
states that it ought to be the case that what ought to be the case happens-but that is derivable from the logical truth just given, if most people in the society have no further knowledge. In this way public expectations about behaviour become prescriptive rather than just descriptive; they are self-fulfilling prophesies to a certain extent. But not only the social base, and prescriptive nature of ethics is derivable on the present account, also its relativistic content. For we cannot invariably support the other characteristic axiom of Hintikka's deontic system, Op 1oop, which requires for whatever is obligatory that it is obligatory that it is obligatory. That is because there is no general rule regarding the probability of probabilities, on account of the indefinition within the notion of probability measure noted before. Certainly rules may be imposed which are consistent (Skyrms [1980]), and Rescher, for instance (Kescher [1968]), constructs a probability logic which makes all probability judgements certain. But Kescher does not argue for his rule being necessary, and we have seen that beliefs about beliefs are not necessarily true. Schlesinger (Schlesinger [1985(a)], p. 42) shows that iteration of justified belief requires that, in order to justify a belief, it would be necessary to justify belief in the validity of the justification of it. Clearly that leads to a n infinite regress. Hence what is expected may itself be unexpected. We noticed this looseness introduced a n 'idealist' aspect into the otherwise empiricist form of the probability calculus. In terms of our moral life and the structure of ethical theory, this allows for the variability of values, and codes of behaviour which are witnessed: Hintikka's iterative axiom would require an absolute set of standards. This division into different societies was also a possibility with the theorem just proved above: only a mass attitude directed towards members of a society which contains that mass can have any logical expectation of success. On the other hand, if we consider the whole of humanity, and our judgements are moral judgements in the Kantian sense that they obey the Golden Rule, and apply to everyone equally, the content of judgements of this
Probabilistic Fourldationsfor Operator Logic
529
form may be absolute, in Hintikka's sense. For if there is in fact a universal human expectation, there is, of course, a totally logically justified expectation that it will be fulfilled. Setting out the case where this expectation is necessarily fulfilled, i.e. where there is moral knowledge properly so called, will illustrate one further point, and lead us to our final conclusion about knowledge in general. For if there is unanimity of expectation in the society S, and a is (unavaoidably) a member of S, we can strengthen the previous relation and say, necessarily pr(p/Sa.(x) (Sx 3 Bxp))= 1. and so necessarily pr[pr(p/Sa.(x) (Sx =, Bxp))= l/Sa. (x) (Sx =, Bxp)] = 1. Thus probabilities of probabilities in general might be indeterminate, but there still is a special relationship when the probability is necessarily 1. Likewise in general with knowledge. The probability definition does not require that only necessary truths are known. But it does require that all necessary truths are known. So there is nothing in that calculus to guarantee in all cases that everything known is known to be known. But this does definitely arise in some cases. Konolige [198h], pp. 3 7 , 58), in his recent reworking of the Hintikkan definitions, respects this variability, taking the iteration axiom as an option which might apply generally to certain types of believers. In particular he tries to solve the traditional wise man puzzle, assuming iteration always applies with wise men, at least. But we can now see it would be an accident if this rule applied with any one contingent belief, and any one believer. The rule applies to certain types of beliefs instead-necessary ones. Konolige generally cannot settle what axioms are necessary, because he thinks in terms of different believers rather than different beliefs. Thus he also cannot settle whether an individual's beliefs are consistent, or form a set which is saturated, i.e. logically complete. But it is one's thoughts only which may be inconsistent, and what is known by one which must be logically complete. Konolige does not make these discriminations because he does not investigate the value base on which doxastic, epistemic and ultimately deontic logic is founded. The base of these logics, as we have seen, and I hope now conclusively, is simply the probability calculus.
The University of Western Australia
REFERENCES
ALSTON, A. J. [19711: 'Varieties of Privileged Access', Arrlrricar~Philoso~~hical Quarterly, 8, pp. 223-41.
530
B. H. Slater
AYER,A. J. [1936]: Language. Truth and Logic. Gollancz. AYER,A. J. [1956]: The Problenl of Knowledge. Harmondsworth: Penguin. CHELLAS, B. [1980]: Modal Logic: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press. CRESSWELL. M. J. [1985]: Structured Meanings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. GETTIER. E. L. [1963]: 'Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?' Analysis, 23, pp. 121-23. HACKER, P. M. S. [1972]: lnsight and Illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. J. [1970]: 'Some Main Problems of Deontic Logic', in R. Hilpinen (ed.). HINTIKKA, Deontic Logic: Introductory and Systematic Readings. Dordrecht: Reidel. KENNY.A. [1973]: Wittgenstein. Harmondsworth: Penguin. KONOLIGE, K. [1986]: A Deduction Modelfor Belief. Pitman. KRIPKE,S. [1979]: 'A Puzzle about Belief', in A. Margalit (ed.), Meaning and Use. Dordrecht: Reidel. MELLORD. H. (19801: 'Consciousness and Degrees of Belief' in D. H. Mellor (ed.) Prospects for Pragmatism: Essays in Memory of F. P. Ramsey. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. RAMSEY, F. P., [1978]: 'Truth and Probability' in D. H. Mellor (ed.), Foundations, Routledge. N. [1968]: Topics in Philosophical Logic. Dordrecht Reidel. RESCHER, G. [1985(a)]: The Range ofEpistenlic Logic, Aberdeen: Aberdeen University SCHLESINGER. Press. SCHLESINGER. G. [I 985(b)]: 'The Central Principle of Deontic Logic'. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, XLV. pp. 5 1 5-3 5. SHINER, R. [1977/8]: 'Wittgenstein and the Foundations of Knowledge', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, LXXVIII, pp. 103-24. SKYRMS, B. [1980]: 'Higher Order Degrees of Belief', in D. H. Mellor (ed.) Prospects for Pragmatism: Essays in Memory of F. P. Ramsey. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. SLATER, B. H. [1988]: 'Contradiction and Freedom', Phllosophy. 63, pp. 317-30. VANFRAASSEN, B. [I 9721: 'The Logic of Conditional Obligation' journal of Philosophical Logic, 1, pp. 4 1 7-38. P of Philosophy, LXXXI, pp. VANFRAASSEN, B. [1984]: 'Belief and the Will', T ~ journal 235-56.