This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
; b d' + c)(d c e)(e d e)(r) :e:e). :
:
:
:
:
:
:
»/
:
the final result with every limit expressed.
Omit-
UNRESTRICTED FUNCTIONS
42-44]
§§
ting the superior limit
and the
>/
:
\Jr
= (a
:
&'c
+ ce')(b
:
wherever
inferior limit e
they occur, and also the final factor formal certainty (see § 18), we get e
39
ri'
>j
c
:
+ e)(d
:
because
e
:
c)(e
:
a
it is
rf).
Suppose next we arc required to find the limits in the order e
:
y$r
d,
e,
= (e = (e
d
:
:
&'c
+
:
b'c
+ ce)(e
d
:
Our
a. b.
c,
final result in this case will :
:
e
:
a'c
a'c
+ b'c){a
+ b'c)(a
:
:
c
e)(>7
:
:
a
be :b:e)
e)(>/
:
c).
When
an alternative
(A) implies that the individual represented by A has a real Firstly,
<j>).
e
e
£
e
(8 (9
(10 (11
(12 (13
(14 (15
(16 (1<
(18
e
.
6
e
e
e
e
.
e
e
I)
e
9
£
9
e
e
!
e
.
:
e
6
:
£
:
e
:
f
:
:
.
The formulae (15) and (16) may evidently be deduced from (13) and (14) by changing B into B'. Formula (17) asserts that the weakest data from which we can
APPLICATIONS OF SYMBOLS
G9]
§§ 68,
A
conclude that
A
either
B
:
B)'
the alternative that
is
and B uncertain, or else A possible and The formula may be proved as follows
certain
is
impossible.
W(A
B
does not imply
73
= S'(A B) = (A" + B + A BV = (A") (B') = A-^B-^A" + B' = A*B + A-"B" e
,
fl
/
:
e
9
(A e B e )
/
e
)
for,
A^A^M and B
evidently,
B = B". may be proved e
e
from first § 68 though some may be deduced more readily
69. All the formulae of principles,
Take, for example,
from others.
We
(1), (2), (3).
are
We first S(AB) W(AB)" 9 the product constitute which terms nine the write down required
W(AB)
find
to
fl
fl
.
,
,
A + A" + A
and B' + B" + B as term that implies every underdot we done, This in § 68. 9 variable we underline is a AB that asserts (AB) which 5 that AB is asserts which (AB)" implies every term that term every brackets in enclose we not a variable; and 9 thus We get (AB)nor (AB) that neither implies e
of the two certainties
fl
fl
,
;
,
,
.
A B + A'B' + A B + A"B + A»B*» + A"B + A B + A B" + (A B e
e
€
1
9
e
9
9
9
9
e
9
).
By our
definitions in § 67
we thus have
W(AB) 9 = A B + A B By
9
9
£
definition also Ave
e
(1)
9 have V(AB) 9 = A B 9 and therefore ,
+ V(AB) = A B + A°B + A B = A B + A B + A B + A B for a = a + a = + A )B + A*(B' + B = A"B (2). + A B-"
S(AB) 9 = W(AB) 9
9
e
e
9
e
9
9
f
9
9
9
e
9
9
,
e
9
9
(
9
9
)
fl
We may similarly deduce
(3) and (4) from first principles, more easily from the two deduced but they may be
formulae
+ ^) = W(£ + Wxfr S(
....
(a) (£)>
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
74
[§§ 69,
70
as follows
+ AB)" = W(AB)« + W(AB/> = A B + A" + B", from § 08, Formulae 7, 13. = S { AB) + AB)" } = S( AB) + S(AB)» = A B« + A" + B" + A B from § 08, Formulae
W(AB)-" = W{(AB) C
S( AB)-
9
f
(
(
€
£
e
(
(
e
e
9
,
14.
7,
The
70.
following
is
an example of inductive, or rather
inverse, implicational reasoning (see §§ 11, 112). The formula (A x) + (B x) (AB x) is always :
when (if ever) is the (B
:
x), false
while
We
denotes
converse, implication
Let
?
true
:
:
:
(AB
:
x)
:
(A
:
x)
;
+
denote the first and valid formula, converse formula to be examined.
its
get
=(ABxy:(Ax'y + (Bx'y
= (Ax' = (a(3) Hence
(see e
r,
a
Bx'f :
§
11),
7,
fir
{Ax'y
we
i
+ (Baj')" Ax, and
putting a for
!
(a/3)"a-"/3~"
!
it
for Bx'.
(a/SjV/S*
Bx')\kxy(Bxy (ABxy(Ax') (Bxy !
implication
(p c
the
in
fails
case
which represents the statement
(ABa/yCAa/r^V and
(3
get
+ /3")'
converse
the r,
.
:
+ ffr,
oP
(Ax'
!
(a{$)
<
(a/3)Xa"
I
(f>'
Thus,
.
r
•
•
the case (afiy>a
therefore also fails in
•
•
9
fi
,
(
1 );
which
represents the statement (ABa/)"(A#')"(Ba/)6 for the
....
(2)
The failure second statement implies the first. may be illustrated by a diagram as
of
on opposite page.
Out
of the total ten points
take a point A, B, x
P
assert
at
marked
random, and
respectively
(as
in this diagram,
the three symbols propositions) that the let
§§ 70,
CERTAIN DISPUTED PROBLEMS
71]
75
be in the circle A, that P will be in the It is evident circle B, that P will be in the ellipse x. propositions A, B, four the of chances that the respective 2 variables. all are that they so x, AB are T T%, £>> T o It is also clear that the respective chances of the three
point
P
will
%
;
statements AB./,
9
have (ABx'y(Axy(Bx') we found to be insr, ,
We may
failure.
by
direct
as
follows.
asserts
appeal
in both the circles
A
diagram,
a
is
B
and
being also in the ellipse
ment which
this
AB
x
:
P cannot be
point
;
of
show
the
The implication
that the
,
case
a
also to
^
2 so that we also iG reasonsymbolic pure by which,
Bx', are 0,
Axe',
W
without a state-
x,
material
certainty,
from the The implication diagram (see § 109). A x asserts that P cannot be in A without being in x, a statement which is a material impossibility, as it is and B x is inconsistent with the data of our diagram Thus we have AB x = e, impossible for the same reason.
as
it
necessarily
follows
special data of our :
:
;
:
A
:
x = v\,
B
ip cf) c
:
x
=
»/,
so that
= (A x) + (B = AB x) (A :
(
x)
:
:
:
we
:
:
x)
get
(AB
+ (B
:
:
= + v *= e x) = e n + n = h
x)
:
>i
>
:
and (p c equivalent, because they draw no distinction between the true (t) and the certain (e), nor between the false (i) and the Every proposition is with them either impossible (>/). propositions which I call or impossible, the certain
The Boolian
variables (6)
logicians
consider
being treated as non-existent.
ing illustration
makes
it
clear that this
is
The preceda serious
and
fundamental error. 71. The diagram above will also illustrate two other propositions which by most logicians are considered equivalent, but which, according to
the word
if,
arc not equivalent.
my
They
interpretation of are the
complex
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
76 conditional, " If
A
is true, "
the simple conditional, is true!'
Expressed in
pretation
of the
70
point P),
the
that
it
is
is
x
true
is
true" and
are both true, then
and with
my
x
inter-
10), these con-
§
A (B x) and AB x. Giving x, AB the same meanings as in :
:
:
the
to
evident that
same
B
subject,
which
x,
:
random point P cannot be
the
asserts
B
the circle
in
ellipse x, contradicts our data,
without being also in the
and
is
B
notation,
having reference
(all
B
and
conjunction if (see
to the propositions A, B,
random
A
my
ditionals are respectively
§
then if
If
72
[§§ 71,
The statement A, on the
therefore impossible.
other hand, does not contradict our data
neither does
;
its
denial A', for both, in the given conditions, are possible
though uncertain. Hence, A is a variable, and B x being impossible, the complex conditional A (B x) becomes which is equivalent to 0", and therefore an im6 But the simple conditional AB x, instead of possibility. :
:
:
:
1},
:
being impossible,
in the given conditions, a certainty,
it is clear from the figure that P cannot be in both Hence, though and B without being also in x.
for
A A
is,
(B x) always implies AB x, the latter does not always imply the former, so that the two are not, in all cases, :
:
:
equivalent.
A
72.
the
"
question
Existential
make an
much
affirmation
same time,
AB
"
No A
is
or a denial A"
,
B ,
B
Do
?
do we, at the
"
Some A
is
B,"
"
A
?
Do we
the four technical propo-
the traditional logic, namely, B,"
is
When we
Propositions."
of
implicitly affirm the existence of
affirm the existence of sitions of
discussed amongst logicians
Import
Some A
is
"
All
A
is
B,"
not B," taking
each separately, necessarily imply the existence of the Do they necessarily imply the existence of the class A ? My own views upon this question are fully class B ? explained in Mind (see vol. xiv., N.S., Nos. 53-55); here The convention a brief exposition of them will suffice. of a
"Symbolic Universe"
(see
leads to the following conclusions
§§ :
46-50)
necessarily
EXISTENTIAL IMPORT
§§72,73]
77
when any symbol A denotes an individvM any intelligible statement
;
then,
;
existence depends
Secondly,
upon the
context.
when any symbol A denotes
a
class,
then,
statement <£(A) containing the symbol A implies that the whole class A has a symbolic existence but whether the statement (p(A) implies that the class
any
intelligible
;
A
is
wholly
unreal,
wholly unreal, or partly real and partly
real, or
depends upon the context.
As regards
this question of
one important point in which other symbolists
the
is
"
Existential Import," the I
appear to
The
following.
differ
from
null class
0,
which they define as containing no members, and which I,
for convenience of symbolic operations, define as con-
the null or unreal
sisting of is
members
V
2,
3,
&c,
be contained in every class, real consider it to be excluded from every
understood by them
to
whereas I Their convention of universal inclusion leads real class. " Every to awkward paradoxes, as, for example, that form squares round because triangle," round square is a conbe to understood is them) (by a null class, which
or unreal
;
tained in every
class.
My
convention leads, in this case,
to the directly opposite conclusion, namely, that "No round square is a triangle," because I hold that every
purely unreal class, such as the class of round squares, is necessarily excluded from every purely real class, such as the class of figures called triangles.
73. Another paradox which results from this convention of universal inclusion as regards the null class 0, "
paradox that the two universals " All X is Y " and No X is Y " are mutually compatible that it is possible for both to be true at the same time, and that
is
their
;
this is necessarily the case
non-existent.
My
when
convention of a
the class "
X
is
null or
Symbolic Universe
"
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
78 leads,
on the contrary,
to
the common-sense conclusion "
of the traditional logic that the two propositions
X
74
[§§ 73,
All
and " No X is Y " are incompatible. This may be proved formally as follows. Let (p denote the proposition to be proved. We have is
Y"
= (x:y)(x:y ):v = (xy )\xyy:f = (V + xy = {,/•(/ + y) = (x = (xe — (6 /
/
]
(t>
:
tj)
:
>])
:
t]
:
>/
tj)
:
:
tj
:
assumed
In this proof the statement x
is
by the convention
See also
noticed that lent to {x y) :
implies
"
(x
Some
46.
§
:
>/}
y')' :
which
',
X
is
n
:
>/
:
to
be a variable It will
5 0.
§
the proposition just proved,
(p, :
of
tj)
asserts that
"
All
be
equiva-
is
X
Y"
is
Y."
Most symbolic logicians use the symbol A~< B, or some other equivalent (such as Schroeder's A=£ B), to 74.
A
assert that the class
is
wholly included in the class
B
and they imagine that this is virtually equivalent to my symbol A B, which asserts that the statement A implies That this is an error may be proved the statement B. :
easily
as
equivalent to the statement
A
hold good when the statement
>/
:
statement
the
If
follows.
A
denotes
by
e,
A B
be always
:
-< B, the equivalence
>;,
and
definition,
B
denotes
e.
must Now,
synonymous with
is
which only asserts the truism that the impossibility (For the compound statement yja, an impossibility. whatever a may be, is clearly an impossibility because But by their definition it has an impossible factor tj.) (ye'y, r\e
is
the statement
n -< e
included in the class
asserts that the class e;
that
to say,
is
>?
wholly
is
asserts
it
that
every individual impossibility. v 2 3 &c, of the class e or e &c.) of the is also an individual (either e 3 r or 2 e is a Thus, which is absurd. class of certainties e tj
>/
,
>;
,
,
>j
;
formal certainty, whereas (See 8 18.)
>;
,
y -< e is a
:
formal impossibility.
CLASS INCLUSION
75]
§
75. to
Some
my
drag
AND IMPLICATION
logicians (see § 74)
have
also
79
endeavoured
formula
(A:B)(B:C):(A:C) into their systems
(1)
under some disguise, such as
(A -< B)(B -< C) -< (A -< C)
The meaning
of (1)
is
clear
....
(2).
and unambiguous; but how
can we, without having recourse to some distortion of The symbol language, extract any sense out of (2) ? -< A B (by virtue of their definition) asserts that every individual of the class A is also an individual of the Consistency, therefore, requires that the complex statement (2) shall assert that every individual of the class (A -< B)(B -< C) is also an individual of the
class B.
class
statement class
But how can the double-factor compound C). (A -< B)(B < C) be intelligibly spoken of as a
(A -<
contained in
It is true that the
the single-factor statement (A-
the single statement (A-
implies
implication
(A-
(3);
The two formulae (1) is quite another matter. and (3) are both valid, though not synonymous; whereas their formula (2) cannot, without some arbitrary departure from the accepted conventions of language, be made to convey any meaning whatever. but that
The inability of other systems to express the new ideas xy kxyz &c, may be shown represented by my symbols A This Take the statement A 80 by a single example. T (unlike formal certainties, such as e and AB A, and ,
,
.
:
e
such as 6 and 6 >/) may, in impossibility, or a variable, an certainty, be a system, my our problem or investiof special data the to according
unlike formal
impossibilities,
:
But how could the proposition gation (see §§ 22, 109). 09 In these it could systems ? other in expressed A be
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
80
not be expressed at
hypothesis
with
certain,
consider
for its recognition
all,
the abandonment of
76
[§§ 75,
would involve unworkable is synonymous
erroneous and
their
(assumed always) that true and false with impossible. If they ceased
their
A
equivalent to their
(when
(A=
denotes
it
and
1),
their
a proposition)
A'
(or
to
as
their corre-
sponding symbol for a denial) as equivalent to their (A = 0), and if they employed their symbol (A=l) in the sense of my symbol A and their symbol (A=0) in the sense of my symbol A v they might then express my but the expression statement A ee in their notation long extremely and intricate. would be Using (in accordance with usage) as the denial of (A = B), my statement A e would then be expressed by (A=/=0)(A=/r l), e
,
,
;
A^B
and
my A
80
by
{(A^0)(A^l)^0}{(A^0)(A=/=l)=£l}. This example of the difference of notations speaks for itself.
CHAPTER XI Let
76.
A
denote the premises, and
Then A .\ B (" A is or its synonym B v A (" B is each of which synonyms
B
the conclusion,
of any argument.
true, therefore
true
"),
true because
true
"),
A(AB
/
r ',
)
argument
denotes the asserts,
argument.
firstly,
A
is
That
B
A
equivalent is
to
say,
is is
to
the
that the statement (or collec-
true, and, secondly, that the coupled with the denial of B constitutes an impossibility^ that is to say, a statement that is incomWhen the person patible with our data or definitions. to whom the argument is addressed believes in the truth / of the statements A and (AB )' he considers the argument
tion
of statements)
affirmation of
is
A
)
,
valid
;
if
invalid.
he disbelieves
either,
he considers the argument
This does not necessarily imply that he
dis-
'BECAUSE
§§76,77]
1
AND
THEREFORE'
<
81
A or the conclusion B he be firmly convinced of the truth of both without accepting the validity of the argument. For the truth of believes either the premises
;
may
A
coupled with the truth of B does not necessarily imply the truth of the proposition (AB') though it does that 17
,
The statement (AB')
of (AB')'. (see § 23)
and therefore
A(AB')
A
But
AB T
T .
.-.
B, like
A(AB')\
A'
+
equivalent to (AB')'
is
Hence we have
B.
= A(A' + B) = AB = A B\ T
synonym A(AB / )
its
A(AB
Like
1
to
1
/
1
)
,
asserts that
it
>
',
A
asserts is
more than
true, but, unlike
AB' is false, but that it incompatible with our data or definitions. For example, let k He turned yah, and let B Ife is guilty. Both statements may happen to be true, and then we have A T B T which, as just shown, is equivalent to A(AB') yet the argument A B (" He is
it
asserts not only that
impossible
—
that
is
it
=
=
,
1
.-.
;
turned
therefore he is guilty ") is not valid, though the weaker statement A(AB')' happens on
pale
:
for
this
occasion to be true, the stronger statement A(AB')'' is not true, because of its false second factor (KB'f. I call this factor false,
because
merely (AB') that it is false that he turned pale without being guilty, an assertion which may be true, but also (AB')'', that it is impossible he should turn pale without being guilty, an assertion which is not true. 77.
it
The convention that to A(A:B), and
equivalent
1
asserts not
A
.-.
to
B its
,
shall
be considered
synonym A(AB'y,
us however to accept the argument A ,\ B as even when the only bond connecting A and B is the fact that they are both certainties. For example, let A denote the statement 13 + 5 = 18, and let B denote the statement 4 + = 10. It follows from our symbolic obliges valid,
conventions that in this case A .\ B and B A are both valid. Yet here it is not easy to discover any bond of connexion between the two statements A and B we know the truth of each statement independently of .-.
;
F
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
82 all
We might, it is true, deduction somewhat as
consideration of the other.
follows
logical
appearance of
give the
78
[§§ 77,
:
By our data, 13 + 5 = 18. From each of these equals take away 9. This gives us (subtracting the 9 from the 13) 4 + 5 = 9. To each of We then, finally, get these equals add 1 (adding the 1 to the 5). 4 + G = 10 quod end demonstrandum. ;
the unreality (from a psychoyet much logical point of view) of the above argument demonstrations rigorous mathematical of our so-called
Every one must
feel
;
'
'
A
are on lines not very dissimilar.
striking instance is
Euclid's demonstration of the proposition that any two sides of a triangle are together greater than the third
—
proposition which the Epicureans derided as patent even to asses, who always took the shortest cut to any place
As marking the
they wished to reach.
A
tween
B and
.-.
noticed that though
first
A
false
e
.-.
;
for
though factor
78.
i]
its
7]
is
:
e
>/
difference beB,
it
be
to
is
:
»/ .*.
fails
.: x,
:
The A, can be accepted as valid. and the second is always when A = like its synonym >?(>/ x), is false, because,
and
evidently
A
A are formal certainties and the two other and stronger state-
A
(see § 18), neither of
ments,
implied factor
its
j/,
:
second factor
>j
:
x
is
necessarily true,
its first
necessarily false by definition.
Though
in purely formal or symbolic logic
generally best to avoid,
when
it is
possible, all psychological
considerations, yet these cannot be wholly thrust aside
when we come
of first principles,
to the close discussion
and of the exact meanings of the terms we use. The In ordinary speech, words if and therefore are examples.
when we true,
say, " If
therefore
B
A
is
is
true,"
true,
then
we
B
is
suggest,
true," if
or "
A
is
we do not
knowledge of B depends in upon previous knowledge of A. But
positively affirm, that the
some way
or other
in formal logic, as in mathematics,
absolutely necessary, to
it is
convenient,
if
not
work with symbolic statements
§§ 78,
CAUSE AND EFFECT
79]
83
whose truth or falsehood in no way depends upon the mental condition of the person supposed to make them. Let us take the extreme case of crediting him with absolute omniscience. On this hypothesis, the word therefore, or its symbolic equivalent would, from the .-.
,
subjective or 'psychological standpoint,
be as meaningless, in no matter what argument, as we feel it to be in the argument (7x9 = G3) therefore (2 + 1 = 3); for, to an omniscient mind all true theorems would be equally selfevident or axiomatic, and proofs, arguments, and logic generally would lay
word
have no raison
psychological
aside
'therefore,' or its
d'etre.
considerations,
synonym
.*.
But when we and define the
as in
,
7G,
§
it
ceases
and the seemingly meaningless argu63)/. (2 + 1 = 3), becomes at once clear,
to be meaningless,
ment, (7 x definite,
9
=
and a formal
79. In
order to
certainty.
make our symbolic
formula?
and
operations as far as possible independent of our changing individual
opinions,
we
will
lay
arbitrarily
following definitions of the word
'
cause
'
and
down '
the
explana-
Let A, as a statement, be understood to assert the existence of the circumstance A, or the occurrence of the event A, while asserts the posterior or simultion.'
V
taneous occurrence of the event V and let both the statement A and the implication A V be true. In these circumstances A is called a cause of V V is called ;
:
;
the
effect
A.*. V,
is
of
A
;
and the symbol A(A V), or :
its
synonym
called an explanation of the event or circum-
V. To possess an explanation of any event or phenomenon V, we must therefore be in possession of two pieces of knowledge we must know the existence or occurrence of some cause A, and we must know the law or implication A V. The product or combination of these two factors constitute the argument A/. V, stance
:
:
which call
A
.•.
A
V
an explanation of the event V. We do not the cause of V, nor do we call the argument the explanation of V, because we may have also is
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
84
B
.•.
V,
B would B
which case
in
cause of V, and the argument
be .-.
V
[§§ 79,
another
80
sufficient
another sufficient
explanation of V.
we want
80. Suppose
event or phenomenon or otherwise) that x certain
number
discover the
to
We
x.
cause of an
notice (by experiment
first
each of a
invariably found in
is
circumstances, say A, B,
of
therefore provisionally
(till
We
C.
an exception turns up) regard
each of the circumstances A, B, C as a sufficient cause of that we write (A x)(B x)(C x), or its equivalent A + B + C x. We must examine the different circum-
x, so
:
:
:
:
cumstance
or
account for
C
whether they possess some circommon which might alone Let us suppose that they the phenomena.
stances A, B,
to see
factor
common
do have a
in
We
factor /.
thus get (see
§
28)
•
(A:/)(B:/)(C:/),wmch=A + B + C:/.
We
before possessed the knowledge
A+B+C
:
x,
so that
we have now
A + B + C:/,'. be not posterior to x, we may suspect it to be Our next step should be to alone the real cause of x. seek out some circumstance a which is consistent with that is to say, some circum/, but not with A or B or C stance a which is sometimes found associated with /, but If
/
;
If we find not with the co-factors of / in A or B or C. that is to say, if we that fa is invariably followed by x
—
—
then our suspicion is condiscover the implication fa x firmed that the reason why A, B, C are each a sufficient :
cause of x is to be found in the fact that each contains the factor /, which may therefore be provisionally considered as alone, and independently of its co-factors, a moreover, we discover that If, sufficient cause of x. while on the one hand fa implies x, on the other f'a that is to say, if we discover (fa %){fa x' our suspicion that / alone is the cause of x is confirmed implies x'
;
:
:
:
§
CAUSE AND EFFECT
80]
85
more strongly. To obtain still stronger confirmation we vary the circumstances, and try other factors, (3, y, S, consistent with /, but inconsistent with A, B, C and with If we similarly find the same result for each other. still
these as for a
so that
;
which =/a x :/+ a (//3 x)(fp x'), which = /]8 x :f + /3' (/? x )(f'y x ')> which =fy x :/+ y' (/<M(/'<S: •<•'), which =fS:x:f+S' (fa
x)(f'a
:
:
:
x'),
:
:
:
'•
:
:
our conviction that / alone is a sufficient cause of x reBut by no ceives stronger and stronger confirmation.
we reach absolute certainty that / when (as in the investigation of natural laws and causes) the number of hypotheses or inductive process can
is a sufficient cause of x,
possibilities logically consistent
with
/ are
unlimited
;
for,
eventually, some circumstance q may turn up such that fq does not imply x, as would be proved by the actual Should this comoccurrence of the combination fqx'. and in natural phenomena it is bination ever occur always formally possible, however antecedently improbable the supposed law f:x would be at once disproved.
—
—
For,
since,
by hypothesis, the unexpected combination
fqx' has actually occurred, we may add this fact to our data e e e &c. so that we get ,
2
,
3
;
,
e:fqx' :(fqx'r
This
may
be read,
" It is
:(fx'r
'•(/'*)'.
certain that fqx' has occurred.
The occurrence fqx' implies that fqx is possible. The possibility of fqx' implies the possibility of fx' and the possibility oifx' implies the denial of the implication /: x." ;
The inductive method here described will be found, upon examination, to include all the essential principles of the methods to which Mill and other logicians have given the names of Method of Agreement and Method '
'
'
of Difference
'
(see § 112).
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
86
CHAPTER
We
will
now
[SS 81,
82
XII
give symbolic solutions of a few miscel-
laneous questions mostly taken from recent examination papers. 81. Test the validity of the reasoning, "All fairies are
mermaids, for neither fairies nor mermaids exist." Speaking of anything S taken at random out of our a symbolic universe, let/= It is a fairy" let m = "it is a " mermaid," and let e = it exists." The implication of the argument, in symbolic form, is
(f:e){m :/):(/: m) which = (/: e')(e m') (/: :
:
ra).
Since the conclusion /: m is a "universal" (or implication), the premises of the syllogism, if valid, must (see § 59) be either f:e:m or /: e m. This is not the case, so that :
the syllogism
is
not valid.
Most symbolic
Of
course,
logicians, however,
may
replace
e
.
would consider
this
By
our
syllogism valid, as they would reason thus
:
"
therefore /= m. Hence, all fairies and m = data, /= and mermaids are fairies" (see § 72). mermaids, all are argument " It is not validity the Examine the of 82. and it is incompounds, the case that any metals are it may therecorrect to say that every metal is heavy heavy, and are not fore be inferred that some elements also that some heavy substances are not metals." Lete "it is an element" = " it is not a compound"; " it is a metal " and let h = " it is heavy." let m The above argument, or rather implication (always supposing the word " If " understood before the pre;
:
;
=
=
mises)
;
is
(m e)(m :
Let
A=m
:
e,
let
B=m
K)'
:
:
:
(e
h, let
:
h)\h
C=e
:
:
m)'.
h, let
D — h: m
,
and
§§ 82,
MISCELLANEOUS EXAMPLES
83]
denote the implication of the given argument.
let
We
then get >
= AB' CD' = (AB' C')(AB' since x yz = (x y) (x :
:
:
In
order
AB'
:
87
that
may
C and AB'
:
:
D'),
be valid, the two implications
D' must both be
:
:
z).
Now, we have
valid.
(see § 59)
AB
C = AC
7 :
:
B = (m :e)(e: h) (m .
:
h),
Hence, C, which asserts (e:h)', is valid by § 56. some elements are not heavy " is a legitimate conWe next examine clusion from the premises A and B'.
which
that "
the validity of the implication
AB' D' = (m :
AB
7
We
D'.
:
have
e)(m K)' (h m)'.
:
:
:
:
Now, this is not a syllogism at all, for the middle term m, which appears in the two premises, appears also in Nor is it a valid the conclusion. implication, will
as
figure
Let the eight points in constitute the class m
show.
m
the circle
subjoined
the
;
the twelve points in the circle e and let the constitute the class e let
;
five
points in the circle h constitute
the class
m is
is
h.
not h
"
Here, the premises " Every m is e, and some are both true yet the conclusion, " Some h ;
not m" is false. Hence, though the conclusion
conclusion 83. for
D
r
is
C
r
is
legitimate, the
not.
Examine the argument,
only experience can
"
No young man
give wisdom,
is
wise;
and experience
comes only with age." Lety = "he is young") letw = "he is wise" and let Also, let (p denote the has had experience." e = "he We have implication factor of the given argument. ;
cj>
= (/
:
w'){y
:
e')
:
(y
:
w')
= (y
f :
e
:
w')
:
(y
:
w').
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
88
The given implication
[§§
83-85
therefore valid (see §§ 11, 56,
is
59).
Examine the argument, " His reasoning was but as I knew his conclusion to be false, I was led to see that his premises must be false also." 84.
Let clusion
P=" was
were true," and
his premises
Then P C =
true."
:
implication) was valid."
Let
(p
at once
C = "his
con-
his reasoning (or rather
"
denote the implication of
We
the argument to be examined.
let
correct,
get (see
105)
|
= (P:C)C':P'
<£
= the
Modus
valid form of the
tollendo tollens.
Thus interpreted (p is valid. But suppose the word premises " means P and Q, and not a single compound
"
We
statement P.
then get
<£=(PQ:C)C:P'Q'
;
an interpretation which fails in the case CP'Q1 and also in To prove its failure in the latter case, the case C^P^Q ,
6
.
we
substitute for C, P,
values
e,
t},
r\,
=
Q
exponential
their respective
and thus get (>/e
:
rfirf
:
i/e'
=
(rj
:
?])e
:
et]
= ee
:
>/
=
rj.
in the argument: mistakes are culpable for mistakes are sometimes quite unavoidable." "it is culpable," let Let "it is a mistake," let c u " it is unavoidable," and let
Supply the missing premise
85.
"
Not
all
;
m=
=
we get
=
(see §§ 59, cp
= (m
:
64)
m')'Q
:
(m
x :
c)
= (m
:
c)Q
(m
:
:
u').
For this last implication to be valid (see § 64), we must have its premises (or antecedent) either in the form
m The
first
:
c
:
vf or else in the form ,
m
:
c
:
u
form contains the antecedent premise
.
m
:
c;
the
MISCELLANEOUS EXAMPLES
85-87]
§§
89
The first form is therefore the second form does not. one to be taken, and the complete syllogism is
(m
:
c
:
u) (m :
n),
:
Q being c vf which asserts that The original reasoning nothing culpable is unavoidable." in its complete form should therefore be, " Since mistakes are sometimes unavoidable, and nothing culpable is un-
the missing premise
:
,
"
avoidable,
some mistakes
are not culpable."
Supply the missing promise in the argument, " Comets must consist of heavy matter for otherwise they would not obey the law of gravitation." 86.
;
= "it
=
"it consists of heavy let A obeys the law of gravitation." Putting
Let
c
matter" and
is
let
a comet"
# = "it
= (h':g')Q:(c:h)=:(c:g:h):(c:h), application of §64; for g:h = h':g', so (P
by
the
that
missing minor premise Q understood is c g, which asserts The full that " all comets obey the law of gravitation." :
reasoning
is
therefore (see
§11)
(c:h)\(c:g)(g:h),
§11)
or its equivalent (see (c
the
In
form
first
:
it
g){g :h):(c: h).
may
be
read,
"
Comets consist of
obey the law of gravitation, heavy matter law of gravitation consists the obeys that and everything ;
for
all
comets
of heavy matter."
87.
the "
following
Some
is
Supply the missing proposition which
enthymeme
professional
men
*
into
a
valid
will
make
syllogism:
are not voters, for every voter
a householder."
Let
P = "he *
is
a professional man," let
An enthymeme
is
V = "he
a syllogism incompletely stated.
is
a
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
90
and
voter"
H = " he
let
[§§
a householder."
is
the implication of the argument, and additional premise required to justify
We
have <£
W
87-89
Let
the
(see § 11)
= (P = (P
V)' !(V
:
:
H)W = (V H)W :
V)(V H) :
:
:
(P V)' :
W' = (P V H) W.
:
:
:
:
deducible from P V H is assume P H = W', and conse= (P H)', which is therefore the weakest quently The complete argument is therefore premise required.
The
We
:
this
conclusion
strongest
P H.
W
"
:
voter
Some
:
therefore :
men
professional
a householder, and
is
:
:
are not voters, for every
some professional men are
not householders." 88. Put the following argument into syllogistic form, and examine its validity " The absence of all trace of :
paraffin and matches, the constant accompaniments of arson, proves that the fire under consideration was not
due
to that crime." F " it was the fire
=
Let " it
was due to arson and matches " and
"
We
given argument.
= (¥
:
T')(A
:
T)
let
;
let
;
:
under consideration
T="
" ;
A=
let
it left a trace of paraffin
denote the implication of the
get
(F
= (F T')(T' A (F A = (F:T' :A'):(F: A 7
:
A')
:
:
)
:
:
7
)
7
).
The implication of the given argument is therefore valid. The argument might also be expressed unsyllogistically (in the
Let T = " the let A = " the let
(p
(see §
modus fire
fire
tollendo tollens) as follows (see § 105). left
89. •'
How
;
denote the implication of the argument.
We
get
105) (j)
which
a trace of paraffin and matches " and to the crime of arson "
was due
= T'(A
:
T)
:
A'
the valid form of the Modus tollendo tollens. Put the following argument into syllogistic form can any one maintain that pain is always an evil,
is
:
§§ 89,
TECHNICAL WORDS EXPLAINED
90]
sometimes be a Let
R = " It
E = " it
an the argument. is
is
good
real
remorse "
evil "
and
?
let
;
P = " it
causes pain
is
" ;
let
denote the implication of (f) get (as in Figure 3, Bokardo)
;
let
We <£ = (R:P)(R:E) :(P:E) = (R:P)(P:E):(R:E), ,
which
may
that remorse involves pain, and yet
who admits
91
/
But to reduce we have been obliged to
a syllogism of the Barbara type.
the reasoning to syllogistic form
Remorse may sometimes be a real weaker premise (R E)', which only asserts that " Remorse is not necessarily an evil." As, however, the reasoning is valid when we take the weaker premise, it must remain valid when we substitute consider the premise,
"
good," as equivalent to the
the stronger premise
;
:
only in that case
it
will not
be
strictly syllogistic.
CHAPTER
XIII
be given definitions and explanations of some technical terms often used in treatises on
In this chapter
logic.
90. Sorites.
Barbara.
will
— This
an extension of the
is
syllogism
Thus, we have
Barbara =
(A:B:C):( A: C) C D) (A D) C D E) (A
= (A B (Sorites), = (A B (Sorites)!
:
:
:
:
:
:
:
:
:
:
:
E)
&c, &c.
Taken
we get what may
in the reverse order (see § 11)
be called Inverse
Sorites,
thus
:
Barbara=(A!C)!(A!B!C) (Sorites^ = (A D) (A B C !
&c.
!
!
!
!
D).
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
92 91. Mediate
and Immediate
[§§91-94
When
Inferences.
from a
we infer another proposition \j/(a?, z) in which one or more constituents of the first proposition are left out (or " eliminated "), we call it Mediate Inference. proposition
(p(x, y, z)
If all the constituents
of the first proposition are also
found in the second, none being eliminated, we have For example, in what is called Immediate Inference. Barbara we have mediate inference, since from x y z we infer x z the middle term y being eliminated. On the other hand, when from x y we infer y' x', or ax y, we have immediate inference, since there is no elimination of any constituent. :
:
Law
92.
This is the name given of Excluded Middle. B + A~ B or its equivalent a a. The
the certainty
individual
:
:
:
to
:
;
A
A
+
,
B
either belongs to the class
B
belong to the class a formal certainty. 93. Intension
and
—an
alternative
or
which
Extension, or Connotation
does not
it
is
evidently
and Denota-
Let the symbols (AB), (ABC), &c, with brackets, tion. in as § 100, denote the collection of individuals, (AB)^ (AB) 2 &c, or (ABC) r (ABC) 2 &c, common to the classes (AB) so that S will not be synonymous inside the brackets ABC (ABC) AB With this interwith nor S S (see § 9). with S be any individual pretation of the symbols employed, let S taken at random out of our universe of discourse, and X let S S (AB) be our definition of the term or class X. The term X is said to connote the properties A and B, and to denote the individuals X 1> X 2 &c, or (AB) r (AB) 2 &c, possessing the properties A and B. As a rule the greater the number of properties, A, B, C, &c, ascribed to X, the fewer the individuals possessing them or, in other words, the greater the connotation (or intenIn A a sion), the smaller the denotation (or extension). ,
,
;
,
=
,
,
Aa
the symbol a connotes as predicate, and in
it
denotes
as adjective.
All
The two
Contrary and Contradictory.
94. "
X
is
Y"
(or x
:
y)
and
"
No
X
is
Y"
propositions
(or
x
f :
y
)
are
TECHNICAL WORDS EXPLAINED
94-98]
§§
called
93
each being the contrary of the other.
contraries,
The propositions
X
Y"
X
Some is not Y," respectively represented by the implication x y and its denial (x y)' are called Contradictories, each being the contradictory or denial of the other (see § 50). Similarly "
All
is
"
and
:
:
"No X
Y"
is
and "Some
sented by the implication x
:
X
is
y'
and
Y," respectively repredenial (x
its
y')
:
f
are
,
called Contradictories.
Some
X
X
The propositions "Some
95. Subcoutraries.
and
Y"
is
not Y," respectively represented by the r non-implications (x y') and (x y)' are called Subcontraries. It is easily seen that both may be true, but that both cannot be false (see § 73). "
is
:
The
96. Subalterns.
Y," or x (x
:
y')
f ;
y,
:
',
and the universal
X
Some
"
"
No
"
is
X
X
Some
Y," or x
is
not Y," or (x
y' :
'
f :
y)
is
Y," or
is
implies
,
In each
.
the implication, or universal,
cases
X
universal proposition "All
implies the particular
the particular of these
:
called
is
the Subalternant, and the non-implication, or particular, is called the Subalternate or Subaltern. That x y implies {x:y')' is proved in § 73; and by changing y into y' :
and
proves that x
vice versa, this also
r :
implies (x
y
:
y)'
This is the name given by some logicians to the formula x y ?/ x, which, with the conventions of §§ 46, 50, asserts that the proposition 97.
Contraposition.
=
:
"
All
X
non-Y
is
is
Y"
:
proposition
" All
logicians define the
word
equivalent to
is
But other
non-X."
the
differently.
98.
let
Let
Conversion.
A, E,
I,
\j/(y,
x) denote
implies, the
plication
denote any proposition,
letters
y)
:
§ 50); and any other proposition which the first x and y being interchanged. The im-
implying
x)
is
called
y)
and
y]/(y,
the two implications
each
(p(x, y)
or O, of the traditional logic (see
the
other,
as
(x:y'y = (y:x'y, the conversion version.
When
the proposition
x\y
in
is
(p(x,
When
Conversion.
\|/(y,
x) are equivalent, r
— y:x,
called
and in
Simple
Con-
y) implies but is not
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
94 implied by
\^(v/, x),
conversion
is
In
accidens.
called
the
as in the case of (x
Conversion
called all
these
Convertend
:
y)
:
(y
:
the Per
.«')',
Limitation
by
the antecedent
cases, ;
98-100
[§§
or
y) is
and the consequent ^{y,
x)
is
called the Converse. 99. Modality.
In the traditional logic any proposition
AB
of the first degree is called a pure proposition, while any of my propositions A BC or A BCU &c, of a Mr/her degree ,
would generally be considered a modal proposition ; but upon this point we cannot speak with certainty, as logicians are not agreed as to the meaning of the word For example, let the pure proposition A B modal.' " then A Be might assert that " Alfred will go to Belgium be read " Alfred will certainly go to Belgium" which would Again, the proposition be called a modal proposition. A" B which asserts that " Alfred will not go to Belgium" would be called a pure proposition whereas A B or its synonym (A B )\ which asserts that A B is false, would, by most logicians, be considered a modal proposition (see §§ 21, 22, and note 2, p. 105). 7 100. Dichotomy. Let the symbols (AB), (AB ), (ABC), '
;
,
',
;
1
with brackets, be understood to denote classes (as in 7 Boolian systems) and not the statements AB, AB ABC, &c.
&c.,
,
We
get*
A = A(B + B ) = A(B + B
)(C + C) = &c. = (AB) + (AB = (ABC) + (ABC + (AB = &c. 7
7
7
7
)
A
)
7
C)
7
+ (AB C
7
)
may be mutually exclusive divisions then, by similar subdivision of each of these, into four This process mutually exclusive divisions and so on. of division into two, four, eight, &c, mutually exclusive Thus any divided,
class
first,
in our universe of discourse
into
two
;
*
B
;
The symbol (AB) denotes the
total of individuals
the symbol (AB') denotes the total
so on.
number
in
A
common
A and
to
but not in
B
;
and
§§
TECHNICAL WORDS EXPLAINED
100-10:.]
divisions
The
called Dichotomy.
is
Bamean
Porphyry, or
"
enthusiastically of
of
Tree, affords a picture illustration
Jeremy Bentham wrote
by Dichotomy.
of this division
Tree
celebrated
95
the matchless beauty of the
Ramean
Tree."
101. Simple symbolically,
Dilemma.
Constructive
:
may
either
or
B
:
A
" If
be read,
A
expressed
the implication
is
(A aO(B x)(A It
This,
implies
true, then x
is
+ B)
:
x.
and B implies
x,
x,
and
true."
is
This
102. Complex Constructive Dilemma.
is
the im-
plication
(A:aOCB:yXA + B):s + y. 103. Destructive Dilemma.
(A:;r)(B:
y)(
t
It
may
A
" If
be read,
t
This
is
/ + //):A' + B'.
implies
B
and
x,
implies
y,
and
then either A or B is false." 104. Modus ponendo ponens (see Dr. Keynes's "Formal There are two forms of this, the one valid, the Logic "). other not, namely, either x or y
is false,
(A B)A :
:
B
and (A B)B A. :
:
the second form fails in e e for, denoting the the case A^B"' and in the case A~ B
The
first
form
is
self-evident
;
1
;
second form by
we
Wc£
get (see /
;
the
= A 'B- + A- B r
e
>
e
'
105. Modus tollendo
forms
67—69)
§§
tollens.
.
Of this
also there are
(A B)B' A' and (A B)A' :
:
The case
first
is
A^B"*,
evident
and
in
;
two
the second not, namely,
first valid,
:
the second
the case A~
e
fails,
B
e .
:
B'.
as before, in the
For, denoting the
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
96
[§§
105-108
=
A^B" + A" 6 B £ (See second form by (p, Ave get Wc// 67-69.) §§ This also has two forms; 106. Modus tollendo ponens. They are the first valid, the other not. (A
The
first
may
+ B)A
/
:B and (AB)'B':A.
be proved formally as follows
+ B)A' B = A'B'( A + B)
(A
:
:
= The second
is
.
:>]
>j
=
r,
:
= + (,,
:
A = A'B'(AB)'
= (A + B)
,/
n
:
= A'B'
;
We
denote the given implication. (p
=
(
AB)'B'
:
in the case case, let
(p
get
A = (A + B)
e ,
A + B = 0,
Therefore, putting
as already proved.
n
:
e
which fails both in the case (A + By and (A + B)". To prove its failure in the last
= e* = n
:
not valid, for
(AB)'B'
(p
>,)
e.
we
get
.
107. Modus poncndo
tollens.
This also has a valid and
an invalid form, namely,
(AB)'A B' and (A :
The
+ B)B
:
The second
is
(A
which
n
=1 1= :
e.
not valid, for
+ B)B:A' = AB(A + B):>/ = AB:>,, e
the
=
:
€ both in the case (AB) and in the case (AB) the given implication becomes e first case which and in the second case it becomes 6
fails
which = also
A'.
first is valid, for
(AB)'A B' = AB(AB)'
In
:
.
:
t]
:
;
>;,
>/,
>].
Let x 108. Essential (or Explicative) and Ampliative. be any word or symbol, and let
§§
108-110]
TECHNICAL WORDS EXPLAINED
containing x (see
word
(p(x)
is,
or follows neces-
which explains the meaning of the
of words) x
collection
(or
When
§ 13).
sarily from, a definition
97
;
then the proposition
called an essential, or an explicative, proposition.
is
Formal
certainties
are essential propositions (see §
When we
109).
have a proposition, such as xa or x~ a or a x + vf, which gives information about x not contained in any definition of x such a proposition is called ,
,
;
ampliative.
109. Formal and Material A proposition is called a formal certainty when it follows necessarily from our definitions, or our understood linguistic conventions, without further data and it is called a formal impossi;
when
bility,
it
is
inconsistent
linguistic conventions.
when
it
It is
our
with
follows necessarily from
some
necessarily contained in our definitions. called a material impossibility
definitions or
called a material certainty
when
it
special data not
Similarly,
contradicts
it is
some
datum or data not contained in our definitions. In this book the symbols e and n respectively denote certainties and impossibilities without any necessary implication as to whether formal or material. When no special data are given beyond our definitions, the special
and impossibilities spoken of are understood be formal when special data are given then e and n respectively denote material certainties and impossibilities. 110. Meaningless Symbols. In logical as in mathematical researches, expressions sometimes turn up to certainties to
;
which we cannot,
for
a time, or in
considered, attach any meaning.
the circumstances
Such expressions
are
not on that account to be thrown aside as useless. The meaning and the utility may come later; the symbol
^/
—
1
in
mathematics
is
the fact that a certain
a well-known instance.
simple
or
From
complex symbol x
happens to be meaningless, it does not follow that every statement or expression containing it is also meaningless. For example, the logical statement A^ + A'*, which
G
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
98 asserts that
belong to
A
A
either belongs to the class x or does not
whether A be meanwhether x be meaningless or not. meaningless and x a certainty. We get
it,
a formal certainty
is
ingless or not,
Suppose
[§110
Next, suppose
and
also
+ (P = + e =
A*
+ A" x =
A
a certainty
e
>/
e.
and x meaningless.
A x + A- = e° + t-° = + e = f
We
get
r
>;
Lastly, suppose
A
.
We
and x both meaningless.
A x + A"* = 0° +
0-°
=e+ = >/
get
e.
Let A x denote any function of x, that is, any expression containing the symbol x and let
;
Ax
though intelligible for most happens to be meaningless when x has a particular value a, and also when x has a Suppose also that the statement particular value /3.
now
that
the symbol
values (or meanings) of
,
x,
true (and therefore intelligible) for
all
values of
x except the values a and /3, but that for these two values of x the statement
becomes true (and therefore intelligible) also for = a and x = ft provided we lay
the exceptional cases x
down the convention meaningless symbol
or
Aa
definition
shall
that
the
have a certain
hitherto
intelligible
meaning m., and that, similarly, the hitherto meaningsymbol A^ shall have a certain intelligible meanThen, the hitherto meaningless symbols A a and ing m 2 Ap will henceforth be synonyms of the intelligible symbols m1 and m2 and the general statement or formula
.
,
of x
without exception.
It
is
on
this
principle
that
MEANINGLESS SYMBOLS
§§110,111]
99
mathematicians have been led to give meanings to the meaningless symbols a° and a n the first of which is now synonymous with 1, and the second
originally
,
with
—
an
Suppose we have a formula,
In this case, since
intelligible.
thesis,
meaningless,
we
are
at
by hypoit any with any
is,
(p(?)
liberty
give
to
meaning that does not conflict previous definition or established formula. In order, therefore, that the formula
=
the meaningless value 9), we may legitimately lay down the convention or definition that the hitherto meaningless expression (£(?) shall henceforth be synonymous with the always intelligible expression yf(s). With this convention,
had only a
the formula,
(j)(x)
restricted validity, will
=
y(s(x),
which before
now become
true in
all cases.
=
111. Take, for example, the formula, s/x >/x x in mathematics. This is understood to be true for all positive
values of x; but
the
symbol
^/x,
and conse-
quently also the symbol Jxjx, become meaningless when x is negative, for (unless we lay down further conventions) fractions
the are
square
roots
non-existent.
of negative numbers or Mathematicians, therefore,
have arrived tacitly, and, as it were, unconsciously, at the understanding that when x is negative, then, Avhatever
meaning may be given combination y/x^x, like synonymous with x and, ;
it
may
in future be
that meaning
to its
the symbol
Jx
itself,
synonym {^/xf,
further, that whatever
shall
the
be
meaning
found convenient to give to */— 1, conflict with any previous formula
must not
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
100
Those remarks bear solely on the
or definition.
symbol
*J —
illustration
previously.
by in
1,
which we have given merely
it is
wider
the
of
general
—
algebraic
as a concrete
principles
In geometry the symbol *J
itself a clear
no way
111, 112
[§§
1
discussed
now conveys
and
conflicts
intelligible meaning, and one which with any algebraic formula of which
a constituent.
112. Induction.
— The reasoning by which
we
infer, or
rather suspect, the existence of a general law by observation of particular cases or instances
is
called Induction.
Let us imagine a little boy, who has but little experience of ordinary natural phenomena, to be sitting close to a clear lake, picking up pebbles one after another, throwing them into the lake, and watching them sink. He might is a stone" (a); "I "It sinks" (7). These
reason inductively as follows: "This
throw
it
into
the water"
(/3)
;
three propositions he repeats, or rather tacitly and as
it
were mechanically thinks, over and over again, until finally he discovers (as he imagines) the universal law a/3 y, that a/3 implies y, that all stones thrown into ivatcr sink. He :
continues the process, and presently, to his astonishment, discovers that the inductive law a/3 true.
An
exception has occurred.
:
y is One
not universally
of the pebbles
which he throws in happens to be a pumice-stone and Should the lake happen to be in the crater of an extinct volcano, the pebbles might be all pumice-stones, and the little boy might then have does not sink.
arrived inductively at the general law, not that all stones sink,
but that
all stones float.
called " law of nature."
So
The whole
it
is
with every so-
collective experience
mankind, even if it embraced millions of ages and extended all round in space beyond the farthest stars that can ever be discovered by the most powerful telescope, must necessarily occupy but an infinitesimal portion of infinite time, and must ever be restricted to a mere Laws founded upon infinitesimal portion of infinite space. data thus confined, as it were, within the limits of an of
§ 1
1
"
2]
LAWS OF NATURE "
infinitesimal can never be regarded (like
and
101
most formulae
in
mathematics) as absolutely certain they should not therefore be extended to the infinite universe of time and space beyond a universe which must necessarily remain for ever beyond our ken. This is a logic
in
;
—
truth which philosophers too often forget (see
Many theorems
in mathematics, like
most
§
80).
of the laws
of nature, were discovered inductively before their validity
could be rigorously deduced from unquestionable premises. In some theorems thus discovered further researches have
shown that
their validity
limits than
was
in
the
is
restricted
at first supposed.
Differential
Calculus
is
within narrower Taylor's
Theorem
a well-known example.
Mathematicians used to speak of the " failure cases " of Taylor's Theorem, until Mr. Homersham Cox at last investigated and accurately determined the exact conditions of its validity. The following example of a theorem discovered inductively by successive experiments may not be very important but as it occurred in the course of my own researches rather more than thirty years ago, I venture to give it by way of illustration. Let C be the centre of a square. From C draw in a ;
random
direction a straight line CP, meeting a side of
the square at P.
What
whose variable radius
is
is
the average area of the circle
CP ?
The question is very easy for any one with an elementary knowledge of the integral calculus and its applications, and I found at once that the average area required is equal to that of the given square. I next took a rectangle instead of a square, and found that the average area required (i.e. that of the random circle) was equal to that of the rectangle. This led me to suspect that the same law would be found to hold good in regard
symmetrical areas, and I tried the ellipse. The was what I had expected taking C as the centre of the ellipse, and CP in a random direction meeting the curve at P, I found that the average area of the variable to all
result
:
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
102
[§112
is CP must be equal to that of the Further trials with other symmetrical figures confirmed my opinion as to the universality of the law. Next came the questions Need the given figure be symmetrical ? and might not the law hold good for any point C in any area, regular or irregular ? Further trials again confirmed my suspicions, and led me to the discovery of the general theorem, that if there be any given areas in the same plane, and we take any point C anywhere in the plane (whether in one of the given areas or not), and draw any random radius CP meeting the
circle
whose radius
ellipse.
:
boundary
of any given area at a variable point P, the average area of the circle whose radius is CP is always
equal to the
sum
of the given areas, provided
when P when P is
sider the variable circle as positive exit
from
any
area,
entrance, and zero
negative
when P
random radius meets none Next came the question theorem be extended
to
is
is
non-existent,
a
we con-
a point of
point
of the given boundaries.
Might not the same general any number of given volumes :
instead of areas, with an average sphere instead of
Experiment again led
of
because the
—
circle
?
an affirmative answer that is to say, to the discovery of the following theorem which (as No. 3486) I proposed in the Educational Times as follows to
:
Some
lie about matter where they be Within such solid, or without,
shapeless solids
No
Let's take a centre C.
From
centre C, in countless hosts,
Let random radii run, And meet a surface each at P, Or,
may
be,
meet with none.
Those shapeless solids, far or near, Their total prove to be The average volume of the sphere Whose radius is CP.
FINITE, INFINITE, ETC.
§§112, 113]
The
sphere, beware,
When
out at
P
positive
they
But, changing sign,
When
is
103
fly
'tis
negative
you spy. One caution more, and I have done entrance there
The sphere
is
naught
when P
there's none.
In proposing the question in verse instead of in plain prose, I merely imitated the example of more dis-
Mathematicians,
contributors.
tinguished folk,
moments
have their
burst forth into song just to relieve their theorem thus discovered inductively was
ductively by Mr. G. clearer
S.
A
Carr.
proof was afterwards
who succeeded Mr.
Miller
like
other
when they The feelings.
exuberance,
of
proved
de-
and therefore
fuller
given by Mr. D. Biddle,
as
mathematical
editor
of
the Educational Times.
Much 113. Infinite and Infinitesimal. is caused by the fact that each of
confusion of
those words used in different senses, especially by mathematicians. Hence arise most of the strange and inadmissible paraTo doxes of the various non- Euclidean geometries. avoid all ambiguities, I will define the words as follows. The symbol a denotes any positive quantity or ratio too large to he expressible in any recognised notation, and any
ideas is
such ratio
is
called a positive infinity.
course of an investigation,
have
to
As we may,
in the
speak of several such
the symbol a denotes a class of ratios called infinities, the respective individuals of which may be designated by a a 2 a g &c. An immensely large number is not
ratios,
,
,
For example, let M denote a million. which denotes the millionth power of a
necessarily infinite. M
The symbol
million,
is
a
M
,
number
so inconceivably large that the ratio
which a million miles has to the millionth part of an inch would be negligible in comparison yet this ratio M M is too small to be reckoned among the infinities a a a y &c, of the class a, because, though inconceivably ;
,
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
104
[§113
in our decimal nota-
large, its exact value is still expressible
tion ; for we have only to substitute 10° or 1,000,000 The for M, and we get the exact expression at once. in— negative any a, denotes synonym its symbol /3, or negative different denote &c, finity ; so that fi v j3 2 /33 ratios, each of which is numerically too large to be Mathematicians expressible in any recognised notation. ,
,
and — co pretty much in the and /3 but unfortunately they
often use the symbols oo to a
sense here given
employ
also
oo
and
1 3 as -, -,
sions such
—
consider oo and
meeting
it
is
They speak a point
at
ratios at
but mire
all,
Mathematicians equivalent when they are employed (see §
class
oo
in this sense; but
equivalent.
indifferently to denote expres-
&c. which are not
non-existences of the
—
;
oo
at
clear
6).
—a
that a and
infinity
but this
;
are not
straight
parallel
of all
lines
only an
is
which &c, or fi v or /33 &c, can never be distinguished by any or /8 and possible instrument from parallel straight lines may, therefore, for all practical purposes, be considered
abbreviated
meet
way
any
at
of saying that all straight lines
av or a 2 or
infinite distance
,
a,,
,
;
parallel.
The symbol any
positive
expressible 7c,
called
h,
called a positive
quantity or ratio
in a
any
negative
quantity or ratio in
any
recognised
any positive
recognised
finite
a ratio neither
to
be
and the symbol denotes any negative
small numerically
Let
notation.
number
denotes
notation;
infinitesimal,
too
infinitesimal,
small numerically
too
or
too large nor
c
ratio
to
be
expressible
temporarily
—
that
too small
is
denote to
say,
be expressymbols of the to
our ordinary notation; and let forms xy, x + y, x — y, &c„ have their customary mathematical meanings. From these conventions we get various self-evident formula?, such as sible in
§
FINITE, INFINITE, ETC.
113]
(2) (ch)\ (ckf
(1) (cay, (c(3f;
105
- c)\
(3) («
;
;
fl
(4) (,±/0
(7)
(10)
The
Q\ of
first
finite
c
:
(5)
;
(£)*;
afar*
;
( 1 1 )
+ cf;
«
a
+ s^
:
2
(/S )";
ar°
;
(|)
;
(9) (aflP;
(12) (M)*.
positive infinite is a positive infinite
neither
if
any
ratio
x
is
;
and a
difference
between
positive
the tenth
a positive
a positive nor a negative infinite.
formula asserts that the infinite
(«Y,
(8)
(f)",
(6)
formula asserts that the product of a
and a
formula asserts that is
((3
finite, it
The
third
a positive
positive finite is a positive infinite.
and the infinieighth article on " Symbolic Reasoning" in Mind. The article will probably appear next April. Note 2.— The four " Modals " of the traditional logic are the four terms f T This proin the product of the two certainties A + A' and A + A' + A".
Note 1.— A
fuller discussion of the finite, the infinite,
tesimal will be found in
my
A^ + A^ + A^A^ + A'A"; it asserts that every statement A is either (A € ), or necessarily false (A''), or true in the case considered but not always (A T A"), or false in the case considered but not always (A'A"). See § 99. duct
is
necessarily true
CALCULUS OF LIMITS CHAPTER XIV
We will begin by applying this calculus to problems in elementary algebra. Let A denote simple ratio, or fraction. A x asserts number, symbol any The the belongs to class that A x, the symbol x denoting as positive, or negative, or zero* or some such word The symbols A*B», A^ + B A* B y A~ x imaginary, &c. &c, are to be understood in the same sense as in §§ 4For example, let Y= positive, let N = negative, and 10. 114.
2
= zero*
let
;
while
numbers
all
',
:
,
,
or ratios not included
in one or other of these three classes are excluded from
our Universe of Discourse out (3
-
3)°,
x
(f),
(3
p
+ N 2)N
— that
(3PJi*
0)°,
,3,
(P 1
+ P2
),
(N 1
,
is
to
Thus we get
consideration.
of
(P^/,
say, left entirely
(6
—
4)
p ,
(W,
(4
—
6)
N ,
(N^f
and many other self-evident
for-
mulas, such as
(AB) P = A P B P
+ AN B N N P P N N (2) (AB) = A B + A B (3)(AB)° = A° + B°.
(1)
(4)
{Ax
- B) p =
.
.
B B Ux - A/J )Y = k{x - ?Y + A*(x A A) \ I
\
V
* In this chapter and after, the symbol 0, representing zero, denotes not simple general non-existence, as in § G, but that particular nonexistence through which a variable passes when it changes from a (See § 113.) positive infinitesimal to a negative infinitesimal, or vice verm.
106
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
§§114, 115]
(5)(A
107
,-B,={4-B)^4-By + 4_By.
(7) (ax
= ah) = (ax - ab)° = { a(x -b)}° = a" + (x - b)°.
greater and less have a wider meaning In algebra, when than in ordinary speech. we have (.« — a) p we say that " x is greater than a," whether a is positive or negative, and whether x is Also, without any regard to the positive or negative. sign of x or a, when we have (x — ctf, we say that " x Thus, in algebra, whether x be positive is less than a!' or negative, and whether a be positive or negative, we have
The words
115.
in algebra
,
(x
From
this (x
— of = (x > a), follows,
it
(x
— «) N = (x < a).
by changing the sign of
+ af = (x > - a), > and <
the symbols
and
and
(x
a,
that
+ af = (x < - a)
;
being used in their customary
algebraic sense.
For example,
a -
let
3.
We
(,r-sy = (x>3), and In other
words,
that
equivalent to asserting that x
is
—
is
assert
that x
that x
is less
Next,
3
than
let a
is
negative
- 3f = (x < 3).
(x
assert
to
get
x
—
greater
3
is
than 3
positive ;
equivalent to asserting
3.
= - 3. We get x - a y = (x + 3) = (x > - 3 N = (x < - 3 (x - af = (x + 3 p
(
)
Let x (x
Let
= 6,
> -
x= 0,
(x
> -
we 3)
p
)
(a certainty).
get
= {x + 3 p = (0 + 3 = e p
3)
).
get
= (x + 3) = (6 + 3 p = e
we
)
is
while to
)
(a certainty).
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
108
[§§
x= — 1, we get p (x > - 3) = (x + 3) = - 1 + 3) = e
115-117
Let
p
(a certainty).
(
= — 4, we get p = (x > - 3) = (x + 3) = - 4 + 3 Let
a?
)''
(
It
is
evident that
between
> —
3)
is
(an impossibility).
a certainty
for all
(e)
and for all negative values of x and — 3 but that x> — 3 is an impossibility negative values of x not comprised between
positive values
(>?)
(,/;
>/
of
x, ;
for all
and —3. With (x< —3) the case is reversed. The statement (x< — 3) is an impossibility (>?) for all positive values of x and for all negative values between and — 3 while (x < — 3 ) is a certainty (e) for all negative values of x not comprised between Suppose, and — 3. for example, that x= — 8 we get ;
;
(x< - 3) = (x + 3) N = - 8 + 3) N = e (a certainty). Next, suppose x= — 1 we get (x< - 3) = - 1 + 3) N = (an impossibility). (
;
(
116.
From
>?
the conventions explained in
§
115,
we
get
the formulas
(A>B) = (-A)<(-B), and (A( -B);
= {(-A)-(-B)} N = (-A + Bf = (A-B) = (A>B), and{(-A)>(-B)} = {(-A)-(-B)} p = (-A + B) p = (A-B) N = (A
P
number
117. Let x be a variable
a
is
a constant of fixed value.
fraction, while
or
When we
have
(x
— «) p
,
synonym (x > a), we say that a is an inferior limit oix\ and when we have (x — cif, or its synonym (x
+ a) p (x + cif (x
asserts that
asserts that
— a is — a is a
an
inferior
limit of x,
superior limit of
x.
and
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
§§118,119] 118. For
example,
let
it
109
be required
to
find
the
superior or inferior limit of x from the given inequality
Sx
—x—
3
x >x+ + 6
2
A
Let
3
denote this given statement of inequality.
We
get
2
\
= i6 3
Hence, —
2«
— —— _
)\
-
3
= (tx—3y=(x —
.
is
an inferior limit of
In other words, the
x.
7
A
given statement of x lower
values of
than
3 -,
impossible for any positive value
is
and
also impossible for all negative
x.
119. Given the statements
A
— — —<—
denotes Sx
and
B, in
which
We
of x.
—
and B denotes
4
2
Find the limits
,
A
3
3x
4'
have
A = Ux-°^- -j = (12x-l() + 2x-lf 1
=(^-n>»4-liy=(*
—
= (6
-3x--j = (24-4x-36x-3)»
= (21-4tor = (4te-2ir' = Hence we 8get
AB =
(
—>x>— 40/
\14
1.
= (.,-^J
a;
(
>|l).
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
110
119, 120
[§§
Thus x may have any value between the superior 11 limit
....
and the
-
limit
inferior
21 --
but any J value of
;
40
14
x not comprised within these limits would be incompatible with our data. For example, suppose x = 1
We
get
*=i - 1Y Ya - 2 - 1 Y- /3 V '\
a -(s
4/
2
\
B
6 :
(
^-
3
4/
'U/
- ij Y| - 30
;
(an •
im ~
» >?
'
possibility).
(a certainty).
e
with
A
Thus, the supposition (x=0) is incompatible with though not with A. 120. Next, suppose our data to be AB, in which
B
Thus the supposition (#=1) though not with B.
A B
^
/ :
:
]
-
—
A
incompatible
get
N
1
(
(
We
x=0.
Next, suppose
is
)
e
:
:
n
denotes ox
(a certainty).
(an impossibility).
— - > 4a; + -. 4
B
denotes Qx
3
— - < 4« + -. 4
2
We
get 3 ^-4-
.
4;/:
IV = / 13\ p / 13 = (^12 (^12 -3J )
/
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
120, 121]
§§
Hence we
get
AB = ->£> — = 13
5
/5
,
t01
In this
denotes
what what
for
and
for
2x-l — x— 6
=
1
T2J
>
13\ :
'
/-
l2J
data AB are mutually A or B, is possible taken combination AB is impossible.
but the
121. Find positive,
/5
(8
our
Each datum,
incompatible. itself;
(an impossibility)
:
therefore
case
>i
13\
>aJ>
\8
by
111
positions
of
F
x the ratio
is
F
when
negative,
positions
28 — x
+ 84
2x2 -29a;
2(x-
4)(x
-
10£)
x(x - 3)
x(x-3)
in § 113, let a denote positive infinity, and let /3 Also let the symbol (to, n) denote 'negative infinity. assert as a statement that x lies between the superior limit m and the inferior limit n, so that the three
As
symbols (to, synonyms.
(m>x>ri), and
n),
We
have
consider
to
(m six
— x)\x — nf limits,
are
namely,
in descending order, and the five to the five statements corresponding intervening spaces 10i), Since x must lie (a, (10J, 4), (4, 3), (3, 0), (0, (3). a,
in
10i, 4,
3,
0,
(3,
one or other of these e
= (a,
10£)
five spaces,
+ (10l,
4)
+ (4,
3)
Taking these statements separately,
1
Oh
4)
(4, 3) (3,
+ (3,
0)
+ (0,
(3).
Ave get
- 1 0|)> - 4)> - 3) V F p p - 3) FK (z - 1 Offix - 4) (x 1 0|-)> 4) N N ¥ - 3)V F p (x - 10i) (fl - 4) (x - ±)"(x - S) N 0) (x - 3)V (x - 10|)> - ±f(x - 3)V F N N Fp /3) x" x\x - 3 f{x - 4) (sc - 1 0i) ( 0+)
(a, 1 (
we have
:
-
(x
p
p
1
0|)
:
(x
:
:
:
Thus, these
(.v
:
five
:
:
:
:
:
:
,
V
(;v
:
:
.
:
statements respectively imply
F
p ,
FN Fp ,
,
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
112
F N Fp
[§§
121, 122
the ratio or fraction F changing its sign four times as x passes downwards through the limits 1 Oi, 4, ,
,
Hence we get
3, 0.
F p = («, 10*)+(4, 3) + (O,0); F N = (10i 4) + (3, 0). That
is
and
or between 4
ment that F that x 3
and
3,
is
either between
is
equiva-
is 'positive is
and 10 \,
either between a
is
or between
negative
is
F
statement that
to say, the
lent to the statement that x
and
ft
;
and the
state-
equivalent to the statement
10i and 4 or
between
else
0.
2«-l_28 122. Given that
values of It is
—
—
x
the value or
find
to
,
x
3
x.
evident by inspection that there are two values of
x which do not satisfy this equation
m When x=0, n
.
we get 6
2a;
-1 = -1
x-3
;
...
while
and
they are
—x = — 28
28
3'
.
and
;
3. .
evi-
dently a real ratio - cannot be equal to a meaningless o
— 28
ratio or unreality
2re-l
.
get 6
— = —5 x-S -
be equal to
28 —
...
while
,
— = 28 —
28
x
.
Excluding
denote our data, and
let
5
.,
,
;
3
(x=0) and (x=o) from our
A
Again when x=3, we
(see § 113).
fl and evidently J -
therefore
cannot
the suppositions
universe of possibilities, let
F=
—x —— - —x
.
We
get
3
A Fo .
.
/ 2a-
_
\x-3 :
28\°.
f
2(x-
xj'l
- 4)(^-10i)} {(X
:(x
=
4:)
+ (x=10i).
x(x-'S) :
J
(x- 4f + (x-10if
§§
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
122-124]
From our
we conclude
data, therefore,
113
must be
that x
either 4 or 10i.
„ 123. Suppose
„^ n
.
,
we nave given
13j;
3
8
4
>
3«
6
4
— 7% 8
to find the limits of x.
Let
A= .
A
/13a;
3x
3
-
G
4
\ 8
4
=
'
we
,13a;
3
ment that
,
=
N
than
— 7x
6
4
—
the statement that
is
—
Q
7x
TT
Hence
.
4
whatever value we give
is
—
,
13x
3
8
4'
sign
=
,
which,
for
all
values
given If in the b for the sign
> we ,
,
so that, in this case,
the value of
124. Let the limits of
A
is
G
—
7a? ,
4 8 evident from the fact
is
to its
simplest form, r
of
is
x,
equivalent
is
to
shall get
G-7,y =
8/
4
4
8
ox
J
statement we substitute the
/13a_3_3. \
than
equal to *
8
6
less
'
This
to x.
when reduced
.
4
\2x
7x
6
2,x
,
must be
4
8
8
that --
3
13a;
.
nnposl
4
8
3%
.
is
8 Q
'tQ,--,
and so
sible,
for
Thus, the state-
>/.
3x
,i
,
greater
<
substitute the sign
4
8
_ XPp 7«)
v.
A=
.
is
=
we
shall get
.
1Q - B6 - 6x B = (13# + ,
l
If in the given statement
the sign >,
have
1'
7.A
8/
|
,,
We
denote the given statement.
()0
=
a formal certainty, whatever be
x.
A x.
denote the statement
We
A = (x2 -
x}
+ 3>2>x\
have
= { (x - 2x + = {{x- l) + 2}" =
2x + 3) p
2
1
)
+ 2 }p
2
e.
H
to find
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
114
Here
A
is
124-128
a formal certainty whatever be the value of
no
so that there are If
[§§
we put the
sign
=
x,
limits of x (see § 113). for the sign > we shall get
real
finite
A={(,e-l)°
+ 2}° =
>
h
Here A is a formal impossibility, so that no real value of 2 It will be remem2x. x satisfies the equation x + 3 bered that, by § 114, imaginary ratios are excluded from our universe of discourse. 125. Let it be required to find the value or values of
=
We get (x -Jx=2) = (x - Jx - 2)° = (x + x* + x°) _ J x _ 2 )° = x\x - Jx - 2)° = x {(x - 2)(xi + 1)}° = A (^ - 2)° = (x = 4) N for (x = 4) implies x and x° and « are incompatible the datum (x - Jx - 2)°.
x from the datum x
— s/x= 2.
v
;>J
(
p
h
'
P
v
,
126. Let
with
be required to find the limits of x from
it
datum (x— Jx>2).
the
(x-Jx>2) = (x-Jx-2y = (c '+x"+x°)(x-Jx-2y i
= x (x-Jx-2y -2)(x + 1)}^ = ,^- 2) = p
=
p cc
{(x
i
p
i
F
for
(v>4) implies x and datum (x — Jx — 2) ,
the
1
127. Let the
(x-
it
x°
and
N re
(.> ;
>4)
;
are incompatible with
'.
be required to find the limits of x from
datum (x— Jx<2).
Jx<2) = (x- Jx- 2) N = (.^+^-M')<>- Jx= (x + x°)(x - Jx - 2) N = of(x - Jx - 2) N + x° = x {^ - 2)(x$ + 1)} N + x°=x*(xi - 2f+x° = x\x* < 2) + x° = x\x < 4) + x° = (4>^>0) + O=0).
2)
N
v
¥
Here, therefore, x
may have any
value between 4 and
zero, including zero, but not including 4.
128. The symbol
gm
denotes any
number
or
ratio
§§
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
128, 129]
115
than m, while Im denotes any number or ratio less The symbols gx m g2m, g3m, &c., than m (see § 115). denote a series of different numbers or ratios, each greater Similarly, than vi, and collectively-forming the class gm. the symbols l-{m, l2 m, l3m, &c, denote a series of different numbers or ratios, each less than m, and collectively forming the class Im. The symbol xgm asserts that the number or ratio x belongs to the class gm, while x '" asserts that x belongs to the class Im (see § 4). The symbol xgm gn is short for xgm z gn the symbol xP mln is short iorxgm x ln ; and so on (see § 9, footnote). These symbolic conventions give us the formulae
greater
}
1
'
;
m = (x>m) = (x-my.
(1) x^
x
(2) (
129. Let
We
lm
3) x
m
= (x<m) = (x- mf. = x° mx = (x > m)(x < n) = (x — mY(x — iif = (n> x > m).
gm
ln
ln
and n be two
different
numbers
or ratios.
get the formula (
To prove numbers) af
1
this
m.gn
)
,,:<""
•
9*
V
= X^V + Xa n = (x > m > n) + (x > n > m). 71
we have
(since
m
and n are different
_ ^m.gn^jn + ^m^ for ^jn + ngm _ g = xgmx*nm9n + xgmx n9m = {x9mm9W)x + nnam)x°m = xgmmgn + x9 ngm = (x > m > n) + (x > u > m ffn
<)n
{,:»P
for
term the outside
in each
factor
may
),
be omitted,
compound statement in the bracket, since x>m>n implies x>n, and x>n>m implies x>m. Similarly, we get and prove the formula because
it
lm ln
(2) x
implied in the
is
= J mm + aV = (x < m < n) + (x < n < m).
This formula
ln
may
be obtained from (1) by simply sub-
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
116 stituting
for g
I
and the proof
;
is
129-131
[§§
obtained by the same
substitution.
130. Let m,
We
ratios.
aT m rf
fi -
1)
(
(
2)
be the three different numbers or
r
n,
get the formulae
= m n Jr + — Jm ni m + x
gn gr ln
lr
,
7>iP
in
ln
lr
,/;?
W'" + aWV*. lm
n nlr + J r r lm r ln
ln
.
These two formulae are almost self-evident but they may be formally proved in the same way as the two for since m, n, r are, by hypothesis, formulas of § 129 or ratios, we have numbers different ;
;
mgn or + ngm gr + ^m gn _ ^ m + nlm.lr + rlm.ln = €^ jf n -9n.gr = x gm.gn.gr e ^ by fas formula .
.
ln.lr
while
x
im.in.i r=.
x
multiplied
o:°
m
e^ 9n -'jr
implied factors, as in
§
-
ln
-
lr
omitted implied factors, as in r, s,
and
131.
principle evidently applies to four ratios, m, n,
so If,
on
to
any number.
we suppose m, n, r to be inferior terms of the alternative ev namely,
in § 130,
limits of x, the three
mgn-ir
i
When get Formula (1). by the alternative e 2) and § 129, we get Formula (2).
we
129,
we have multiplied xlm The same
= ae,
and ^q same formula. When we have by the alternative ev and omitted a
^
im.in.ir
ngm -° r
gm an
r
,
-
,
respectively assert that <m
nearest inferior limit, that n
is
is
the
the nearest inferior limit,
And if we suppose be superior limits of x, the three terms of the ln lr n lmAr r lmAn respectively alternative e2 namely, m assert that m is the nearest superior limit, that n is the that r
m,
is
the nearest inferior limit.
n, r to
-
,
,
nearest superior limit, that r
For of any number of
is
the nearest superior limit.
inferior limits
nearest to x is the greatest; whereas,
superior limits, the nearest to x
,
,
is
the
of a variable
of least.
x,
the
any number of
And
since in
each case one or other of the limits m, n, r must be the nearest, we have the certain alternative e1 in the former case, and the certain alternative e2 in the latter.
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
131-133]
§§
It is evident that
m may ln
that
mPn may be replaced by (m—n) v
be replaced by (m
replaced by (m
117
— n)"(m — r)
N ;
— ?i) N
and
,
that
mlnAr may
be
so on.
CHAPTER XV When
we have to speak often of several limits, &c, of a variable x, it greatly simplifies and shortens our reasoning to register them, one after another, as they present themselves, in a tabic of reference. The * symbol ®m>, n asserts that xm is a si^erior limit, and x n an inferior limit, of x. The* symbol xm n rs asserts that xm and xn are superior limits of x, while x r and xs 132.
x x x2 x3 ,
,
,
,
are inferior limits of
aW.n means xm'.n'.r.
and
Thus
x.
(x
means
,
- m f{x - n J or (xm >x>xn - mf(x - xn f{x - r) p(x -
),
(x
s
f,
so on.
The symbol
(with an acute accent on the osm m) always denotes a proposition, and is synonymous with (x — xm y, which is synonymous with
133.
numerical
.
suffix
It affirms that the mth limit of x our table of reference is a superior limit. xm (with no accent on the numerical suffix), a proposition, asserts that the mth limit of x
(x<xm ).
our table of reference xm means (x-xm ) p
is
an
registered in
The symbol when used
as
registered in
Thus
inferior limit of x.
.
my memoir
* In
on La Logique Symbulique et ses applications in the du Congres International de Philosophic, I adopted the symbol x™ (suggested by Monsieur L. Couturat) instead of iy„, and .vm " instead ofxm n rs The student may employ whichever he finds the more conBibliotheque
r
>
t
.
From long habit I find the notation of the text easier but the other occupies rather less space, and has certain other advantages in the process of finding the limits. When, however, the limits have been venient.
;
found and the multiple integrals have to be evaluated, the notation of the text is preferable, as the other might occasionally lead to ambiguity (see §§ 151, 150).
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
118
134, 135
[§§
134. The employment of the symbol xm sometimes to denote the proposition (x — x,m) v and sometimes to denote the simple number or ratio xm never leads to any ,
,
ambiguity
for the context always
;
—I
X
it
is
which
fraction -,
of
reference
outside the
z)
supposed
is
3,
bracket denotes the
the
be marked in the table
to
the third limit of x; whereas the x3
as
bracket,
is
— x3 Y,
statement
(x
Similarly,
when we
A=
— \x — x — x
the xs inside
that
clear
makes the meaning
For example, when we write
perfectly evident.
,
affirmed to be equivalent to the
and
is
therefore
statement
a
also.
write
+ 8 4 > 2 9x) = (x - 1 0|) + (x - 4)N = {x — x^f + (x — x2 Y = x + Xg, p
2
( 2,,;
l
we
assert that the statement
+ x^,
native statement x l (as a statement)
A
equivalent to the alter-
is
of which the
first
term x1
that the limit x1 (denoting
and the second term
inferior limit of x,
10|)
asserts
an
is
asserts that
»_,
Thus, the limit x 2 (denoting 4) is a superior limit of x. the alternative statement x -\-x2 asserts that "either xl >
is
an
inferior limit
of
x,
or else x 2
is
a superior limit
x.
135. The
operations of
calculus
this
of
limits
are
mainly founded on the following three formula? (see
§§
129-131): (
In the /„,./„,
/
xm
.
n
= xm ~ x n) xn\xn ~ xm) = xm \xm xn + xn \xn — xm
xm n
\° )
x m'.n
first
and
1
(Z)
,
""
''m\
>
)
''-
m' .n\'
vi
''
n)
)
.
'
symbol xm n means and xn are both inferior limits
of the above formulae, the
asserts that xm
•
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
135, 136]
§§
119
The statement (xm - xn f asserts that Xm is greater x. than xn and therefore a nearer inferior limit of x while the statement (xn -xmY asserts, on the contrary, that xn and not xm is the nearer inferior limit (see §§ 129, In the second formula, the symbol xm n asserts 131). The statethat xm and xn are both superior limits of x. ment (xm - xj" asserts that xm is less than xn and therewhile the statement fore a nearer superior limit of x K — that xn and not xm is contrary, on the asserts, x (x m) of
;
>
.
;
n
The
the nearer superior limit.
third formula
is
equiva-
lent to '
and
of
§
.n
•
\
xm
xn)
>
a superior limit, and xn an inferior
xm then xm must be greater than xw
asserts that
if
is
When we
have
limit, of x,
13G.
m
three inferior limits,
Formula
(1)
135 becomes %m .n.r = xm «
in which a asserts that xm inferior limits,
ft
xr
is
asserts that
+ Xnfi + X y, r
the nearest of the three
is
asserts that xn is the nearest, In other words, the nearest.
and y
— xm ~ xn) xm ~ X p = {xn xm (xn — xr y=(xr -xmf(xr -xny. a
\
r)
\
)
)
When we
have
Formula
three superior limits,
(2) of §
135
becomes xm'. W. ?
= xm' a + x
n'ft
+ xr'7>
in which, this time, a asserts that xm
the nearest of the
is
ft asserts that x n is the nearest, In other words, is the nearest.
three superior limits,
y
asserts that
xr
= (xm
and
xr ) xn \Xm ft=(xn- Xmf(xn- xrY a
)
y = (xr — xm f(xr — xn ) Evidently the same principle
number
may
of inferior or superior limits.
s .
be extended to any
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
120
[§§
137, 138
137. There are certain limits which present themselves so often that (to save the trouble of consulting the Table of Limits) it is convenient to represent them by special
These are positive infinity, negative infinity, and Thus, when we have zero (or rather an infinitesimal). any variable x, in addition to the limits x v x 2 x 3 &c, registered in the table, we may have always understood symbols.
,
,
the superior limit xa which will denote positive infinity, the limit xQ which will denote zero (or rather, in strict logic, a positive or negative infinitesimal), and the always ,
,
understood inferior limit xp infinity (see § 113).
variable
y,
,
which
will
denote negative
Similarly with regard to any other
we may have the
three understood limits ya
,
&c. y yp in addition to the registered limits yv y 2 y 3 Thus, when we are speaking of the limits of x and y, we ,
,
,
,
= =
- a. x (or dx or dy) x yp y the other hand, the statement xa m asserts that x lies between positive infinity xa and the limit xm registered in the table of reference; whereas xm p asserts that x lies
have xa — y a = a
;
= =
;
fi
On
,_
,
,
Simibetween the limit xm and the negative infinity xp larly, xm tQ asserts that x lies between the superior limit while ;% n asserts that x lies xm and the inferior limit and the inferior limit xn limit superior the between that x is positive, and implies statement « Thus, the m the statement xQ is Also, negative. is that x xff n implies s the statement x is and X statement synonymous with the p shown in § 134, As x statement synonymous with the to denote a sometimes symbol x the employment of the Q not lead need statement, a limit, and sometimes to denote .
,
;
.
,.
,
;
.
any ambiguity.
to
138. Just as in finding the limits of statements in pure logic (see §§ 33-40) we may supply the superior limit n when no other superior limit is given, and the inferior limit
e
when no other
inferior limit is given, so in find-
ing the limits of variable ratios in mathematics, we may supply the positive infinity a (represented by xa or y a or z &c, according to the variable in question) when no ,
§§
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
138, 139]
other superior limit
and the negative
given,
is
121 infinity
(3
(represented by .^ or yp or zp &c.) when no other inferior Thus, when xm denotes a statement, limit is given. ,
namely, the statement (x — x^f, it may be written xa m and, in like manner, for the statement xn which denotes (x — xn y, we may write xn tP (see § 137). 139. Though the formulae of § 135 may generally be dispensed with in easy problems with only one or two variables, we will nevertheless apply them first to such ,
;
>,
,
make
problems, in order to
meaning and object
their
apply them afterwards to more complicated problems which cannot dispense with their aid. Given that 7a?— 53 is positive, and 67 — 9a; negative;
clearer
when we come
required the limits of
Let
A
denote the
to
x.
datum, and
first
B
the second.
We
get TABLE
A = (7x-5Sy = (x-~X=x1 =xa
,,
1
B = (67-9*) N = (9,:-G7) p = (^-y
)
Hence, we get
AB = av. By Formula
(1) of § 135,
xa
x
,,
2
=x
a ._
j
we get
= Xjlfa — x + x (x — x^f p
a5j _
2
2
2)
2
53_67
Y
,67
53V
9~
= r (477-469) + r (469-477) p ,forQ = (63Q) = x1e + aw = x (see § 11, Formula? 22, 23). From tne aata AB thereThus we get AB = a 12 = p
p
p
t
t
2
1
1
,i'
fore
we
infer
that
between positive greater than
53
—
-
.r
-
x
infinity ,_4
or 7-.
.i-
between xa and ,i\ that 53 In other words, x and
lies
;
—
is.
is
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
122
[§§
139, 140
Now, here evidently the formula of § 135 was not for it is evident by mere inspection that u\ is
wanted
;
greater than
,r 2
,
that a\ being therefore the nearest
so
inferior limit, the limit
out of account.
AB = A =
,r aU 140. Given
positive
Let
;
A
,r
2
is
In fact
A
—
53
superseded and
may
implies B, so that
be
left
we get
.
7x
that
is
required the limits of
denote the
first
negative
datum, and
B
get—
A = (7£-53) N = (x-
53
x x,
and
07
—
9*
x.
-—
the second.
We
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
141]
123
CHAPTER XVI 141. We will now consider the limits of two variables, and first with only numerical constants (see § 156). Suppose we have given that the variables x and y are both positive, while the expressions 2y — 3# — 2 and 3^ + 2^ — 6 are both negative; and that from these data we are required to find the limits of y and x in the order
Table op Limits.
y, x.
A denote We have
Let data.
our whole o 2/i
A=y
r
x p (2y
-
3x
-
-6) Beginning bracket
with
factor,
(2y
-
3x
we
N
2) (3?/
+ 2x
=^+ l
N .
the
first
get*
N -2Y = (y-^x-lJ = (y- A ) = Vv
Then, taking the second bracket
?
factor,
we get
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
124
Substituting this alternative for y v A, we get
2
.
[§141
in the expression for
A = (y rx v + y^\)y^. o = (yv. 0% + feiftK-.o
= VV. VC
V
a.
+
.
y
==
C a'. 1.
2/l'.
0^1'.
2/2'.
'
'1
O^a'.
1
first term the superior limit xa because it the nearer superior limit x x and omitby is superseded term the limit x because it is supersecond ting in the The next step is to apply limit x v nearer seded by the We ^-factors the Formula (3) of § 135 to yvo and yz
omitting in the
;
,
.
get
= Vv.
yv.
0(2/1
- y<>Y = yv. 0(2/1)* = yv. d
= yv.o(3x + 2) = yvJx + ^ =
-®
+
l
1
(*
'
yi'.
- x^f
J
—
2/1'.
0^2 P
2 - -x = = = J = y (6 - 2^ = ^,0(3 -xf = y^ Q(x- 3) N = 2/2'.0<%P
y%.
2/2'.
2
0(2/2
2/2'.
?7o)
o(2/ 2 )
for
}Jx. cftv.
evidently
o(
,
Substituting these equivalents of
A=
2/2'.
x
2.0
is
"J~ 2/2'.
O^a'.
3'.
1
?y
=
r
2/l'.
and 0^1'.
?/ 2
2/2'.
1
O'^V. 1
a nearer inferior limit than
therefore supersedes
,v
2
;
x3
while
is
we get
in A,
.
a nearer
>
,r
2
,
and
superior
xa (which denotes positive infinity), and theresupersedes fore xa We have now done with the ?/-stateonly remains to apply Formula (3) of § 135 ments, and it It is evident, however, to the ^'-statements xvo and xsi this is needless, as table, that of the by mere inspection nor any inconfactor, discover it would introduce no new than is, than greater that x sistency, since x x is evidently process The zero, and x3 is evidently greater than xx limit than
.
.
,
.
therefore here terminates, and the limits are fully deter-
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
§141]
1
25
We
have found that either x varies between xx and zero, and y between y1 and zero or else x varies between xB and xv and y between y2 and zero. The figure below will illustrate the preceding process The symbol x denotes the and table of reference. mined.
;
distance of any point
P
(taken at random out of those in line x and the symbol y
the shaded figure) from the
,
denotes the distance of the point The first equivalent of the data
P from
A
is
the line y
.
the statement
xz xo x
r
ox o>
asserts that y1 and y 2 are superior limits (or zero) is an inferior limit of y, and that
which
llv
2-
of
y,
x
(or zero) is
this
that y
an
inferior limit of x.
compound statement
A
is
It is evident that
true for every point
the shaded portion of the figure, and that it for any point outside the shaded portion. equivalent
+ Vv. o
of
the
A
data
is
the
is
P
in
not true
The
final
y v% x r true for every point alternative
_
term of which is P in the quadrilateral contained by the lines yv y x v xQ and the second term of which is true for the triangle contained by the lines y 2 y0) xv tl
V.
i>
the
first
,
,
;
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
126
[§142
2 2x — 4 y — 4./.' is negative and y required the limits of y and x. positive get Let A denote our data. Table of Limits. p r)-\y 2,,;-4) (v/-4 A +
142. Given
+
tliat
;
We = = -4 N (y-yi)"; tf - ±xy = {(y-2 JxXy + 2 Jx)Y = {y-2 s/xr(y+2 sfxy t
2
tt-)
(7/
—
for (y
2
s/^YiV
+ 2 x/^) N
We
impossible.
*s
therefore
get
a= By Formula 2/ 3 i .
2/2'.
(1) of
3(2/
§
- 2/i) p =
2/2'. s2/i
=
y-2.3. i
135 we get
- Vif + y/yi - 7hY = - 4) + Vl{2x -2jx- 4)* = y (2tf - 2 = y (# - x/« - 2 + y^a? - s/x - 2 N (see §§
^
2/3(2/3
3
p
p
126,
)
)
3
127)
^X ~~l)
slx-l
~i*
Y
-"((•"-D-lM^-i)-!}' = (.j-4) +2/i(*-4) n - N = 2/3^i + 2/r*r= y (# ~ «i)P + p
^
?/3
3
^'i)
Therefore
A = 2/2'.3^1+//2'.l^l'-
We !h.
now apply Formula
3
2/2'. 1
= =
2/2'.
2/2'.
(3) of § 135, thus
- VsY = Ik. s( 2 */« + 2 xA')'' = y*. 3 e P r 1(2/2 - 2/i) = i(2# + 2 V'/' - 4) 3(2/2
2/2'.
= yr. i(* + «/* - -)" = V*. i{( V* + 2J (2) } x ~ = = i(« 1 = h: M' -zY i#2r
2/2'.
)
2/2'.
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
142, 143]
§§
127
Thus the application of Formula (3) of § 135 to y2 3 introduces no new factor, but its application to the other compound statement y2 introduces the new statement Hence we x2 and at the same time the new limit x 2 finally get (since Form 3 of § 135 applied to xa and Xy 2 makes no change) ,
,
1
.
,
.
a
A^y.,.3^+^1%.2
(see
§§137, 138).
" either x lies between x a and x., and y between the superior
This result informs us that (positive
infinity)
oc
jcz
and the inferior limit y 3 or else x lies beand x2 and y between y2 and y v The above figure will show the position of the limits. With this geometrical interpretation of the symbols x, y, &c., all limit y2
tween
;
£&,
,
the points marked will satisfy the conditions expressed by the statement A, and so will all other points
bounded by the upper and lower branches of the parablank area cut off by the
bole, with the exception of the
line
yv 2 143. Given that y — ±x is negative, and y also negative required the limits of y and x.
+ 2x — 4
;
Here the required
limits (though they
may
be found
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
128
independently as before) the diagram this
in
may
problem and that of
case y
+ 2x — 4
143-145
be obtained at once from difference between
The only
142.
§
[§§
142
§
is
that in the present
negative, instead of being, as before,
is
Since y 2 — 4a; is, as before, negative, y.2 will be, as before, a superior limit, and y 3 an inferior limit of y so that, as before, all the points will be restricted within But since y + 2x — 4 the two branches of the parabola. positive.
;
has now changed sign, all the admissible points, while still keeping between the two branches of the parabola, The result will be that the only will cross the line y v now be restricted to the blank will points admissible portion of the parabola cut off by the line y v instead of being, as before, restricted to the shaded portion
and extending indefinitely A positive infinity. towards in the positive direction that the show will glance at the diagram of § 142 within
the
two
required result
branches
now
is
1J-2'.
with, of course, the
3'%.
same
'
V\'. 3^1'. 2>
table of limits.
CHAPTER XVII 144.
The symbol
A —
,
when
the
numerator and denomi-
nator denote statements, expresses the chance that A is true on the assumption that B is true; B being some state-
ment compatible with the data
of our problem, but not
necessarily implied by the data.
145.
The symbol
A
denotes the chance that
A
is
true
e
when nothing is assumed but the data of our 'problem. This is what is usually meant when we simply speak of the "
chance of A."
§
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
146, 147]
The symbol^—,
146.
A ——A —
A
or
B
and
;
upon
S(A, B), denotes
this is called the dependence* of the statement
the statement
(when negative) the
— when
chance
synonym
its
129
B.
It
decrease,
indicates
the
increase,
or
undergone by the absolute
B
the supposition
is
added
to our data.
€
The symbol
<5°
D B
or
,
A
dependence of
synonym
its
upon B
Fig.
1.
A
said
is
which implies, is
to
be independent
-,
€
symbols
a!',
— — — ,
,
e
,
I/,
c
',
the
on
statement
B
(see S 149), that
€
,
&c. (see
S
145); and the
€
&c, respectively denote the chances
&c, so that we get
e
1
*
oj
3.
&c. (small italics) respectively
b, c,
ABC— chances—,
represent the
Fig.
2.
as will be seen further
independent of A. The symbols a,
147.
e
E
E
Fig.
B
In this case the state-
is zero.
E
ment
S°(A, B), asserts that the
Obscure
= n + a' = b + b' = c + c' = &c.
dependence and independence in prosome writers (including Boole) into serious errors. The
ideas about
bability have led
'
definitions here proposed are,
'
'
I
believe, original.
'
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
130
[§148
148. The diagrams on p. 129 will illustrate the preceding conventions and definitions.
Let the symbols A,
B
that a point P, taken at
assert respectively as propositions
random out
of the total
number
of points in the circle E, will be in the circle A, that
it
be in the circle B. Then AB will assert that P will be in both circles A and B AB' will assert that P will be in the circle A, but not in the circle B and similarly will
;
;
for the statements
In Fig.
1
A'B and
we have
A'B'.
§§
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
149, 150]
The following formulae
149.
133
are easily verified
:—
*-}&
<•>£-*-?£(•>
The second of the above eight formulae shows that if any statement A is independent of another statement B,
B
independent of A for, by Formula (2), it is B) implies S°(B, A). To the preceding eight formulae may be added the following then
is
;
clear that <S°(A,
:
AB = A B B A = e
"
e
e"B
*A
B A B (11)^± = + _ AB
AB_A B _B A Q^~Q'AQ~QBQ
(10)
;
.
(12)
A+B
150. Let A be any statement, and proper fraction; then A x is short
A—
=%), which
\ €
that
asserts
= A + B _^?
x be any positive the statement
let
for
chance
the
of
A
is
x.
/
(AB)* means
Similarly,
convention gives us a and
the
—=
AB
\
x);
following
A b (as
before) are short for
e
(1)
A^:^=^- A V
(3)
(AB)x(A + By>:(x + y = a + b);
(5) (AB)"
= (A + B)
(2)
a+& ;
and so
on.
This
in
which
formulae,
— and
;
B -. e
A-B^AB/^A + B)-*-; (4) S°(A, B)
= (AB)
f
'»;
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
132
<6
>(s4)=(s=f)=*( A /A B\ /A = [B = A) \B
„ (7)
\
[§§150,151
B >;
-
+ {a = b):(AB)V + (a = h)
:
!
-
It is easy to
may
prove all these formulae, of which the last be proved as follows
A_B\
/A_Z> A\ /K_b A\° (A/ 6\)° B~Ay' \B~a'B/ \B a'B/ \ B\ X ~ a/ ;
:
:
J
\
:
A
V
/A
jjj(a-&)|
:(
The following chapter
B
\
=
+ («-^)°:(ABr+(a = &).
0J
some knowledge
requires
of the
integral calculus.
CHAPTER XVIII 151. In applying the Calculus of Limits to multiple integrals,
will
it
be
convenient
to
the
use
following
which I employed for the first time rather more than twenty years ago in a paper on the " Limits of notation,
Multiple Integrals " in the Proc. of the Math.
The symbols
^>{x)xm!n
and x m
-
meaning. tion
The symbol
(p(x)dx,
xn
commonly expressed '
'
™
vm\n to the
>.
n
differ
differ
,
in
also in
>.
taken between the superior limit xm and
the inferior limit
fX
xm
n is short for the integra-
m
<J>(%)%
which
n (p(x),
the relative positions of
Society.
\
an integration which would be
The symbol xm
.
left, is
short for
n
m)—
(j>(x
For example, suppose we have
j
I
so
dx(p(x) or
the
symbol
= ^(x).
Then,
l
m<
^
') (
=
p{x)x m n
(
xn p{ that we can thus ,
J\
v
'
with
by substitution of notation, we get
= #m.»' K#) = ^GO - ^G''»)
ex m
the form
either in
l
'
,
entirely
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
151-153]
§§
133
with the symbol of integration,
dispense
the
as in
/,
following concrete example.
Let
be required to evaluate the integral
it
Table op Limits.
'
Cz
C' 1
C'¥
dy
"'-I
I
JVi
J«a
dx,
I
J-'o
=
za
=X V2 = h
«!
=«
h'o
=0
Vl
c
the limits being as in the given table. The full process is as follows, the order of variation being z, y, x.
= (z - z )yv x r = - c)y v xv = (k - ^/>% = { (hA -cy-d- (hvl ~ cy } xv = { (I.* - «b) - (W - cb) x v = (h^ - ex - \tf + bc)x r = #i\ o(^^ — ikr — 2# + &«') = £a — lea — \b + bca.
Integral zr
.
2
yv
&.
.
2
1
.
2
.
(//
.
.
9
,
2
?/r 2
.
.
o
2)
2
,
2
}
.
2
3
3
2
The
152.
evident (
ci
\
'
'.
n
.
;
.
J
.
^'
(5)
6
self-
= - %n' m (2) #«>*V „ = ~ <£OX'. m *W. „<£(») = -Xn'.rn
(3)
(
following formulae of integration are
:
*W
1)
.
//?»'
''
/
m'
n'
.
71
.
r'
'
~r"
(xm „
(9)
.
.
.
+ xr
153.
.
, .
.
"m'
s
.
s
rnfir'
.
)(p(x)
mt
.
r
J
I
.
s
2/m'
s
.
"
J >
•
r
.
n
.
s)
.
.
2/«'
>•
.
,
,
.
stated, the
.
mP^s' r .
5
'
= (xm + ^ n )(p(x) = 0(#)(#m< +
+ *V
As already
,
<.
.
i/n'
"V
r
.
a?
r
s
>
r)
.
.
.
/
.
%
iH>
;
„)•
.
symbol
,
when
A
and
B
A is true on the x and y be any
are propositions, denotes the chance that
assumption that
numbers
B
or ratios.
is
Now,
true.
The symbol
let
-
means
3/B
when
either of these two
suppose the number PU Ihus,
r
1
numbers
-
y is
x
— B
missing, Ave
understood.
x A xA - means - x — B
IB
;
and
—A means x x —AB 1
-
xB
;
and
may
V34>
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
xx
=l
[§§
154, 155
§
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
155]
135
Substituting these results in our expression for Q, shall
we
have
Multiplying by the given certainty xv -0 (see table), we get
XV. oH == lV i\ Applying Formulae 137)
+ -'V.
0^2'
1'. 3.
r. 2.02/-2-
and (2) of
(1)
we
135,
§
get (see
§
#3. _
X2.
(3C
'<0 )"
f
?,
•
o(''
,
expression for x v
results in our
Q,,
get #r. oQ
= %(%2/3 + AW3')y2' + == X2'
We
s
3)
^
3
Substituting these
we
^ V
= ^3 + •% = XlX + *oK = xs - xj* + ar^ - x n = X^e + xv n = x + = X2* + ^ = «* = ff«te Z
t% r
.
31/2'
.
"r ^2' 0^3'
3
.
now apply Formula
"*2\ 3' ^2'.o'
''3'. 2'
.
•'3'
2^/2
.
#3
2' "•"
135
(3) of §
2^2'
'.
to the
statements
**nUS '2' .
3
*2' .0 "^3'
.
2
=V
-l' .
== ^2'
=%
= r $%' X ^0) = ''V e — = XS 2V^3 Xi)
3(^2
'
.
Q\
<
-2'
.
2
.
,?,
.
2)
.
iVl-
This shows that the application of § 135, Form 3, introduces no new statement in y so that we have finished with the limits of x, and must now apply the formulas of §135 to find the limits of y. Multiplying the expres;
sion found for #i'.o 7/i'
By applying
tr ro
==, ''2 .
= y20
by the datum yv
s/Ar. r. 3.0
+
the formulae of
tion of the table, y.2
Q
we get y%
'''2 .
§
v=
0//3
.
2'.r.
<'V.2yi\oQ
we *
get
x3. 2?/i'.2.
o-
135, or by simple inspec-
y3 and substituting these results
side of the last equivalence,
Q,
y.y
;
.
=y
z
;
=
Vz' y$ 2 r right-hand
in the
we get
= ''V.3y2'.3 + <>2\oy3\o + <'V.2/'r.2
<
.
.
'>
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
136
The
application of
Form
135,
§
155, 156
[§§
to the y-statements
3,
no fresh statements in z, nor destroy any that it contains an impossible factor showing term by found the nearest limits of y and it therefore We have Multiplying the last find the limits of z. to only remains get z we datum the expression by ro
will introduce
tj.
;
QA = Q,?v The
_
Q
yv
.
oZ r
application of
effect
= Ov
.
§
.
easy,
3
+ dfe
is
Int
.
o2/ 3
3, to
+%
o
-
.
.
s#r 2>r .
the factor
therefore over
We
;
zr
and
.
o-
will _
The
p is a certainty. )
to evaluate the integrals.
it
pro-
only
get
^
A
= Int(/e.r. $2 + x* ys + %? =l. The A = Int xv ,&v .
Int
.
{z — z x
no change, since
A
for
.
Form
135,
cess of finding the limits
remains
3y 2
3
.
.
o
.
Hl\-
.
2K'
.
integrations
fs l..
are
. f
and the
result
log 2 (Naperian base),
is
which
is
-±
5
a little above -. 9
156. Given that a is positive, that n is a positive whole number, and that the variables x and y are each taken at random between a and — a, what is the chance that n+1
- «} positive ? {(x + y'T - a} is negative and {{x + y) let Q deTable); (see x Let A denote our data y Y 2 r#2 s n the denote R let and -a} note the proposition {(x+y) p n+1 N exponent the in which a} proposition {(.?• + y) positive. P denotes negative, and the exponent _
,
,
We
have
„ , , to find the
.
chance
QR —^-,
which = ,
.
,
Int
QRA .
In this problem we have only to find the limits of integration (or variation) for the numerator from the
compound statement QRA,
the limits of integration for ?/ 1 .2^1.2. the denominator being already known, since A
=
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
156]
Table of Limits
=
y1 a ~a y2 = i
y3 = a
n
—X 1
yi
= — an — x i
=a n + —x 1
7i •J
5
1
y,
= - « n+l - x
Vtf
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
138 #5
3 .
=
«'
s
when a> a"+i (
—a
We
=1
<'V. 5
;
(
an impossibili ty)
we have
1
]
x6
so that
Tl ;
must now apply
We
— an
2a
(
—
a;
§
135,
.
5
Form
y.
.
Q%1'. 2 = VS. 26\ 5
=
For
.r 3 ,
we have
1
the statements
3, to
=
z get ys 2 y&. \ yz>. 5 =yv.5 ai> Substituting these results, we get
in
-
always positive.
is
3
and Xg
;
and when ct<
,
]
[§156
+ y&. 5%. 3«1 + y V
— yv.^n-
Vv.^
5%. 7-
.
Having found the limits of the variable y, we must apply the three formulae of § 135 to the statements in x. Multiplying by the datum xVti we get ,
Q%V. g»l'. = 3fa. 2
for
We
xx
i
5
= =
2''
2/3'.
»/
V.
6'
ajj/ 5
;
.
+
=
-
+
5. 2
5^1'. 3 ft l
2/ 3 '.
B®1'.
ajji
;
Z'.
3
5'.
X V. 7 xZm 2 =
llv. b
.
+
2«1
?/l'.
5'?V.
1'.
7
.
2
I
'''3
=
#7.
!
^7*
,:
these results immediately by simple in-
obtain
spection of the Table of Limits, without having recourse Applying the formulae of to the formulae of § 13 5. §
x which remain, we get
to the statements in
135
xVm v = ./v",, •%.
7
=
+ xr a
iV 3'. n
Substituting these values,
Q%r
2 Xy. 2
.
= QRA = ==
// 3
-
5
\
.
;
iV i'
I
l'.3
.
= «i = a2.i3
This limits,
QRA
is
limit of
Vi 3 a.2
'''v.
;
a 3-
al
"I"
yv.sfls'. 7/
> ?
.
1
"1
#1'.
?"*. 3>
VM.ffiv.'flr\
— (Vb'.S^V. + an an( %.3 = i
7«2
//r. 5 (#3'.
(
(6
l
J
impossibility).
the final step in the process of finding the
and the
is
7
+
2
3
for ai.2
.
3
get
3 «. !
?,
=x =
#r
,
2
we
XV
?/3'.5'
.
a
result informs us that,
a.
greater than
when n
is
even,
when a x which =1) is an inferior In other words, when n is even and a is not
only possible
1,
chance when n
(
the chance of is
even and a
QR
is
is zero.
To
greater than
1,
find the
we have
§
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
L56]
139
only to evaluate the integrals, employing the abbreviated notation of
Thus
151.
§
yv r = (y — y )^v. — = x v {2ax) = 2cuc — 2ax = 4a QRA = yw # + y # = - y^ v + (Vi - y )'%.7
A = Int
Integral
2
,?;
2
2
x
2
,
2
Integral
=
= ®V. =
an
—a
a Tl
(
- a**
1
=
1l
+ l W,_ 3
5
+
~ aH + F + 1
a?l 3
- ^3 ) +
(^j
(
'
a
a
(
— ««+i+
r3'-7
*"
- aw +*
an — a n + l Y 2a
'(
3,. 7
v. 3
(y-s
2
2
1
Vm 6
r< 3
5
2a)#r> 2
(
]
,i
W
7
~ an+1 V + i^ )(a? 8
- x7 ) + £(#?, - ^)
- £a" - |a™+
1
QR = Int QRA _ Int QRA A 7w« A 4a 2
=— We
have now
_ a^+i Y 4a - a - a"* 1
a"
(
Tl
QR A = (y
,/'
,
3
5
when %
the chance
to find
the same process as before r- 3
we
+ yv
.
is
odd.
By
get
%. 7
5(
K +y
& &&. 2«3.
namely, a x and a3
Here we have £wo
inferior limits of a,
so that the
To separate the not yet over. cases, we must multiply the result
process
different possible
obtained by the certainty
reduces to a x
+a v + %, 3
For shortness sake
+a r )(a + a$),
(a 1
3
since a x let
M
x
is
which here
greater than ay
denote
the
bracket co-
a x in the result already obtained denote yc 2 <% 2. tne coefficient of
efficient (or co-factor) of
for
QRA;
a3
We
.
and
let
,
is
M
3
«.
.
get
QRA = (M A + M 3a3 )(a1 + av + %) = (M + M 3 )a + M 3ar>3 .
1
1
3
;
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
140
156, 157
[§§
Hence, (an impossibility). and a9tl = is an odd when n cases there are only two possible which here a>a to say, number, the case a 1 (that is v For the latter, a r -3 means a>l) and the case a r 3 a 13
for
= ar
rj
.
we
,
get Lit M, 1 /_ OR ?= — jL_ = J 2a — ira* A 8a' \ A
N
4, n+1
2
For the
a>
namely, the case
first case,
QR_ 7^(M + M [
1
A ~
7w*
1,
we
get
8)
A
When will
the integrals in this case are worked out, the result be found to be
—
9? = _L( o» - a«+i Y 2a - a" + a^ - a^+i A 8a\ / A 4a \ )
2
\2
1
+ _ The expression
for the
the expression for give the
same
it
(
2a
— a»+
easily seen to be the
1
chance——in the
in the case a
result
1
(
<1
a>l
case
and
evidently ought to
when we suppose a=l. This is fact; for when we put a=l, each
expression gives - as the value of the chance 8
157. The great advantage of this
"
——
A
Calculus of Limits
"
that it is independent of all diagrams, and can therefore be applied not only to expressions of two or three variables, but also to expressions of four or several variables. Graphic methods are often more expeditious when they
is
only require
known curves
straight ;
lines or easily traced
of integration are, in general, difficult
three
variables,
representation
and
well-
but graphic methods of finding the limits
of
because
this
involves
when
there are
the perspective
the intersections of curved
surfaces.
CALCULUS OF LIMITS
§157]
When
there are four or
cannot be employed at
141
variables, graphic methods For other examples in pro-
more all.
my sixth paper in Society (June Mathematical London the Proceedings of the Mathematical volumes of and to recent 10th, 1897), bability I
Questions
may
may
and
interest
refer the student to
Solutions
some
from
Educational
the
Times.
It
readers to learn that as regards the
155, 150, I submitted my results to the test of actual experiment, making 100 trials 1 and in each case, and in the latter case taking a The theoretical chances (to two figures) are re3. 7i spectively -56 and -43, while the experiments gave the
problems worked in
§§
=
=
close approximations of *53
and 41 -
respectively.
THE END
Printed by Ballantyne,
Hanson
Edinburgh &* London
&
Co.
1-IZ-61
lut
rufc'-jjj
Wf.
Hi?
SOUTHERN hw,!°.
NAL
L| 8RAfiy
f^OOO 807 764
/:
^
"r
*-
•.•:.::;:•
;v
.-
-^
'.:-''-'
•.''-'..•-• .'<'':<..'' '.• '' ''
'
.
::;
'
'
'
I
I
'
"-'
:
"••
"
'
M
''-•" •'.-. 3J '' '
'
*
;:
'
^
| ;'..•-
"
'"
:
:
•
.
:"--
Pi
''•
'•.-•
+-
|S Bf
-'
':•... '"''' '
' .;,--•--...-' "
•
v
V.
-\
E»i --'•;'-
Ry '
•
^"
:
'
B»k
BOH
wfife&S
.',-:'..-;-.•• -
',-
'-'-•'-*rnHC~sj&i :
I
,.'...'
>
.
FACIUTV