First published 1990 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge a division of Routledge, Chapman and Hall, Inc. 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001
© 1990 Peter Hulme and Ludmilla lordanova for editorial material and their own contributions; all other contributions © 1990 the respective contributors Typeset by Scarborough Typesetting Services Printed in Great Britain by T. 1. Press, Padstow, Cornwall All rights reserved. No part of this book may be repn'nted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data The Enlightenment and its shadows. 1. European culture, history I Hulme, Peter, 1948- D. lordanova, L. 1. (Ludmilla I.) 940 ISBN 0-415-04231-3 Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data The Enlightenment and its shadows / edited by Peter Hulme and Ludmilla lordanova. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 0-415-04231-3 1. Europe - Intellectual life - 18th century. 2. Enlightenment. 3. Civilization, Modem 18th century. I Hulme, Peter. D. lordanova, L. 1. 89-24176 CB411.E55 1990 CIP 940.2'53 - dc20
Illustrations
1 Genoese map of the world (1457). 2 Dutch map of the world (Joan Blaeu 1648). 3 BenoIt-Louis Prevost, frontispiece to the Encyclopedie (1772); after an original drawing by Charles-Nicholas Cochin II (1764). 4 The tree of knowledge from the Encyclopedie (detail). 5 Wood-engraving illustrating South American Indians (1505). 6 Title-page of Francis Bacon, Novum organum (1620). 7 J. M. Moreau, Ie jeune, engraved illustration for Rousseau's La Decouverte du nouveau monde, from vol. VIII of the 1774-6 edition of the Oeuvres Completes. 8 Sixteenth-century map of EI Dorado (from L. Hulsius, Travels 1599). British Library. 9 The Universe according to Ptolemy, from Andreas Cellarius, Harmonia Macrocosmica (1660). 10 Louis XIV as Apollo in the Ballet du Roy des Festes du Bacchus (1651), by an unknown artist. Bibliotheque Nationale, Paris. 11 Philibert-Louis Debucourt, Calendrier republicain (Republican Calendar) (1794). Bibliotheque Nationale, Paris. 12 Antoine Watteau, Les Fetes venitiennes (ca. 1718). National Gallery of Scotland, Edinburgh. 13 Jacques-Louis David, The Death of Marat (1793). Musees Royeaux des Beaux-Arts, Brussels. 14 The First Seal of the Republic (1792). Archives Nationales, Paris. 15 The Goddess of Liberty at the Festival of Reason (November 1793). Reproduced from Revolutions de Paris, no. 215. 16 Pierre-Paul Prud'hon, The Republic, with Liberty, Equality and Fraternity (ca. 1792). Private collection.
6 6 13 14 19 21
40 44 51 61 87 125 128 130 131 133
viii Illustrations 17 Auguste Barr, The Second Seal of the Republic (1848). Archives Nationales, Paris. 18 The Statue of Liberty (1886). Aerial view photograph by Jack Boucher. Reproduced by courtesy of the US Department of the Interior, National Park Service. 19 Eugene Delacroix, Liberty at the Barricades (1830). Louvre, Paris. 20 Anonymous, Le Calculateur patriote (The Patriotic Calculator) (1789). Bibliotheque Nationale, Paris. Jacques-Louis Copia, Droits de l'homme et du citoyen (Rights of Jl;Jarz 21 and of the Citizen) (ca. 1793), after Alexandre-Evariste Fragonard. Bibliotheque Nationale, Paris. 22 Anonymous, Declaration des droits de l'homme et du citoyen (Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen) (1793). Bibliotheque Nationale, Paris. 23 James Gillray, Un Petit Souper, ala parisienne; - or - A Family of Sans-Culotts Refreshing, after the Fatigues of the Day (1792). The British Library. 24 Anonymous, L'Heureuse Etoile (The Lucky Star) (1802). Bibliotheque Nationale, Paris.
136
137 139 151
174
175
212 214
1
Introduction PETER HULME AND LUDMILLA JORDANOVA
In a very dark Chamber, at a round Hole, about one third Part of an Inch broad, made in the Shut of a Window, I placed a Glass Prism, whereby the Beam of the Sun's Light, which came in at the Hole, might be refracted upwards toward the opposite Wall of the Chamber, and there form a colour'd Image of the Sun. (Newton, Opticks [17031, book 1, part 1) The Enlightenment was a self-conscious intellectual movement that discussed its own origins and characteristics with passion. Two texts of particular importance which illustrate this are Jean d'Alembert's preliminary discourse to the Encyclopedie (1751) and Immanuel Kant's 1784 essay 'What is Enlightenment?'. D'Alembert recounts a now familiar story in which the Enlightenment is intensifying that 'light of reason', first lit in Greece, which had been 'rekindled' in the fourteenth century after almost a millenium of darkness (in Diderot 1967: 1-41); Kant defines Enlightenment as 'man's emergence from self-incurred immaturity' (Kant 1970: 54; cf. O'Neill, this volume). The frequency with which these two analogies recur serves to define the self-image of the period, although, like all analogies, each has a troubling ambiguity. These two texts can also stand, briefly, for the very different kinds of address encompassed by the Enlightenment. The Encyclopedie, as its name suggests, attempted to speak of the totality of human knowledge. In his preliminary discourse, d'Alembert, a renowned mathematician, emphasizes in high-minded fashion the progressive nature of human knowledge; although the Encyclopedie itself is also full of scurrilously satirical comments on contemporary life. Kant's short, surprising, yet philosophically elegant and precise essay 'What is Enlightenment?' is unexpectedly the more political of the two texts, since he argues, quite directly, that Enlightenment thinking can be fully realized only in the public sphere - of which he offers an original and provocative definition. Yet encyclopaedia and essay are linked by that 'single style of thinking' which Peter Gay sees as connecting a whole 'family of intellectuals' (Gay 1967-70: 1, xii), an extended family that spanned several generations and that had branches in various European and, eventually, American countries. Certainly in the eighteenth
2 Peter Hulme and Ludmilla Jordanova century there was a constant interchange of visits: Voltaire and Rousseau came to England, a strean1 of philosophes, including Hume and Gibbon, visited Voltaire at Ferney. Learned societies burgeoned with their international links and corresponding members. And if the French branch of the family seemed dominant, then full homage was paid to the trio of English 'pioneers': Bacon, Newton, and Locke. But since the Enlightenment was, in many of its aspects, also highly self-critical, it was inevitable that, even as its identity emerged, it was subverted. There can be no more powerful exemplification of this point than the writings of Denis Diderot, who could be solemn and didactic, excited by science, moved by the moral potential of art, yet, at the same time, playful, mischievous, and completely sceptical about settled notions of human nature. There have been basically two approaches to the inevitable questions of definition and periodization. The first is more exclusive; its origins lie in the period immediately after the French Revolution, and it views the Enlightenment as consisting of a group of more or less likeminded individuals, writing mainly in France in the period between the death of Louis XIV (1715) and the onset of the Revolution (1789). The dominant figures are seen as Montesquieu, Voltaire and Rousseau. In this narrow definition the Enlightenment is viewed as a revolutionary movement of ideas that culminated in the events of 1789-94. Standard works also periodize the history· of Europe in this way. In France these boundaries are emphasized through such series as Peuples et Civilisations, whose two volumes entitled Le Sieele des Lumieres deal with the periods 1715-50 and 1750-89 (Soboul et al. 1977). The same periodization is then found in the Norton history, which includes Tradition and Progress, 1715-1789 (Woloch 1982), and in the Pelican Guides to European Literature, which include an 'Age of Enlightenment' running from 1715 to 1789 (Grimsley 1979). Histories of the Enlightenment itself tend to follow suit: Norman Hampson's The Enlightenment (1968) is divided into two parts, 1715-40 and 1740-89, while the chronology in Lester Crocker's anthology, The Age of Enlightenment (1969) is slightly longer, framed by the Revocation of the Edict of Nantes (1685) and the guillotining of Louis XVI (1793). Even leaving aside the flexibility of these conventions, there is a serious problem with this approach. Although the term 'Enlightenment' was quickly adopted asa general historical period, the use of political events to mark the beginning and end of a predominantly intellectual and cultural movement is bound to be not only arbitrary - as all such 'marks' are -but also tendentious. In particular, a dating which ends the Enlightenment in 1793 or 1794 strongly implies that the multiple strands of the Enlightenment culminate in the single event of 'the Terror'. It is easy and tempting to use such political markers because they are discrete events and because we can see (or think we see) the links between political ideas and their effects. In fact we know very little about how ideas move, either across or within societies. Since it seems likely that their passage is often halting and uneven, it is, to say the least, problematic to mark the end of a movement that was essentially concerned with ideas by invoking a political event. Furthermore, there is consider-
Introduction 3 able evidence to suggest that, in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, some of the most ferocious critics of the Enlightenment were, none the less, deeply indebted to it. Their interpretation of the Enlightenment (see Jordanova, this volume) is not necessarily wrong, but it is important to historicize such interpretations, forcing them to argue on the evidence rather than accepting them on the basis of the founding gesture of periodization itself. At the beginning of this century Gustave Lanson and his students began to broaden the understanding of the Enlightenment in decisive ways, studying its 'origins' in the seventeenth and even sixteenth centuries; paying attention to the importance of English writers such as Bacon, Newton, and Locke; and stressing the continuity of its 'philosophical spirit' into the twentieth century (for an account, see Wade 1971: 3-57). The most influential of Lanson's pupils was Paul Hazard, whose crucial works - published in 1935 and 1946 - effectively defined the modern, 'broader' notion of the Enlightenment. His most important moves, which are now widely accepted, were to establish the beginnings of the Enlightenment proper in the seventeenth century; to clarify the contrast between the 'stability' of the classical ideal and the intrinsically 'restless' character of Enlightenment thinking; to realize the genuinely European nature of the phenomenon of the Enlightenment, with due weight given to its Scottish, English, and German components; and - in some ways 1110st crucial of a11- to argue for the importance to the Enlightenment of the way of thinking introduced by Descartes (against the previous argument that the substance of Descartes' thought had been soon rejected so that he was not a significant precursor). This is how Hazard puts it: The pineal gland, in which he deemed the soul was lodged; those robots or mechanical animals insensible alike to pain and pleasure, the plein; the whirlpools; the physics, and even the metaphysics, of Descartes had fallen by the wayside. What, then, of essential significance survived? His spirit; his method - a lasting acquisition, that - his rules for guiding the operations of the mind, so simple, yet withal so powerful, that even if they did not illuminate the whole domain of truth, they at all events caused some of the shadows to recede. (Hazard 1973: 158) Light was a central metaphor for knowledge long before the Enlightenment, but at that period it took on new vitality. The cosmology of Copernicus and Galileo had established the sun at the centre of the universe, and its light had become the subject - in Newton's Opticks (published 1703) - of the greatest scientific investigations of the seventeenth century. In Newton's work the laws of light seemed to have been laid bare, yet still in devout fashion. Even Alexander Pope, often an acerbic commentator on scientific developments, could see such understanding as part of God's plan: 'Nature, and Nature's Laws lay hid in Night.! God said Let Newton Be! and All was Lighf (Epitaph, intended for Sir Isaac Newton 1730). Consequently, there was a whole epistemology behind the use of images of 'light' in the eighteenth century, one that was boosted by the belief that all knowledge came
4 Peter Hulme and Ludmilla Jordanova from the senses and that vision was queen among the senses, with observation at the heart of the acquisition of solid knowledge of the world. Enlightenment was less a state than a process of simultaneous unveiling and observation. To look well and carefully sufficient light is required, and looking in this way was deemed the only route to secure knowledge, although even a priori knowledge could be analogised to vision as the product of inner light. It was against this background that Diderot's prospectus for the Encyclopedie spoke of 'the general enlightenment which has spread throughout society' Des lumieres generales qui se sont repandues dans la societe] (Diderot 1967: 34). The eighteenth century was commonly referred to by the enlighteners as their century, 'Ie siecle des lumieres', and the German term Aufkliirung was common by the 1780s - although its translation as 'Enlightenment' only came into English usage in the nineteenth century. Dispute over the significance of the Enlightenment has remained at the heart of much twentieth-century intellectual debate. One of the most sophisticated and involuted condemnations of the Enlightenment, the Dialectic of Enlightenment, was written between 1944 and 1945 by Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer. This critique 'from the left' has proved an important reference point in the contemporary debate between two increasingly entrenched positions: a 'poststructuralism' which, in its various forms, is indebted to the anti-Enlightenment views associated with Friedrich Nietzsche; and a standpoint within Marxist 'critical theory' defended by Jurgen Habermas as a 'completion' rather than rejection of the Enlightenment project. Since Adorno and Horkheimer are themselves key figures in critical theory, Habermas's discussion of the Dialectic of Enlightenment is of special importance (Habermas 1987: chapter V), as too is the fascinating but tragically incomplete dialogue between Habermas and the late Michel Foucault, which was enjoined precisely over Kant's 'What is Enlightenment?' essay (Foucault 1984, 1986; Habermas 1986). Similar complexities can be observed elsewhere on the political spectrum. The calculations of reason have traditionally been rejected by an English conservatism drawing its language from Burke's reflections on the French Revolution. More recently, elements of the self-styled 'New Right' have associated themselves with a liberalism that supposedly has its roots in Adam Smith and David Hume. A 'New Enlightenment' has even been proclaimed, speaking in the name of 'reason' against what it sees as the transient intellectual fashions of the 'new relativism' (cf. Graham and Clarke 1986; and - for a French parallel- Bruckner 1986). The point here is not to intervene in those complex debates, but to indicate in brief compass that the major issues of our intellectual life today are still implicated, for better or worse, in the shadows cast by the multifaceted enterprise of the Enlightenment project.
If you were to trace onto a map the principal orbits of the Enlightenment writers and their books, traversing the places where their books were written, published and read, you would find that the writers clustered into a ,!?~~~~~I_g~~g!'!PJ1Lc~1
Introduction 5 area: the north and west of France, the low countries, the north-east of Germany, Switzerland, the south of England, the south of Scotland, northern Italy, and that the readership would stretch to the rest of western Europe with a few outposts in eastern Europe and within populations of European descent outside Europe, especially in north and south America. In that sense the Enlightenment was very much a European phenomenon (see Porter and Teich 1981). The map in Figure 1 was drawn in 1457, 200 years before the beginning of the Enlightenment; the map in Figure 2 in 1648, six years after the death of Galileo and two years before the death of Descartes, in other words right at the beginning of the Enlightenment period. Several very broad but important generalizations are illustrated by these maps. To begin with, the maps show the extent of the changes that had taken place in conceptions of the world in the two centuries prior to the Enlightenment. In 1457 Europe's knowledge of the rest of the world was very limited. There is a notional Africa, and a large area to the right that approximates to Asia. But there is no Indian peninsula, no Australia., and - perhaps most important of all- no America, not even a space into which America could fit. By the 1640s the changes are dramatic. This map is at least recognizably of our world. Africa has approximately the right shape, Asia has more definition, and America is very definitely there, in fact occupying almost exactly half of the map. There is no natural division between west and east, so the vertical line on the in the circumstances probably not second map is simply an assertion unreasonable - that the central axis of the northern European world in 1648 lies in the Atlantic (see Davis 1973). America, which was not there at all 200 years previously, is, on the 1648 map, now too big, almost overshadowing the 'old' world to its east. It would be difficult to underestimate the shock to the European intellectual system of that 'discovery' of America, a new world with a whole new fauna and flora and, above all, a human population that was undreamt of by classical antiquity and of which no mention was made in the Bible. The philosophical implications of the existence of America were by the 1640s still in the early stages of their incorporation into the European world-picture. The other striking feature of the 1648 map is that Australia is not there at all: instead there is a massive southern continent running right along the bottom of the map, which is presumed to exist. It says on the map TERRA AUSTRALIS NONDUM COGNITA, the land of the south not yet known. The bringing into knowledge of this 'land of the south' - or, as it turned out, a multitude of islands of the south - was to dominate debates on the state of nature during the second half of the eighteenth century. The 'discovery' of these various 'new worlds' also gave the Enlightenment a metaphor that could be applied far beyond its immediate geographical meaning. Above all it evoked the nature of scientific advance, for which images of marching into new territories, taming what one found there, and giving a coherent account of fresh terrain were especially apt (see Figure 6). Atlases could be collections of maps, but they were also diagrams and illustrations of that other 'terra nondum cognita', the human body.
6 Peter Hulme and Ludmilla Jordanova
Figures 1 and 2 The mid-seventeenth century marks a shift in the balance of European power
from the Mediterranean to northern Europe. Power lies where maps are produced: the top map (1457) was drawn in Genoa, the bottom one (1648) in Amsterdam. It was the northern European countries which were undergoing during those years in the middle of the seventeenth century what we now recognize as the early stages of the development of capitalism, and those countries which now took a decisive initiative in colonial ventures.
Introduction 7 But the second map is also in some respects misleading. Because the shapes are more or less what we expect them to be, we might presume more knowledge than actually existed in the middle of the seventeenth century. 'Discovery', up until the end of the Enlightenment period, generally meant voyages of discovery often linked with trading ventures. So the outlines were known, but not what they contained: the vast expanse of North America had been little travelled by Europeans in 1650, and was not that much better known in 1800. The interior of sub-Saharan Africa was absolutely crucial to the European economies throughout the eighteenth century because it was this area that supplied the black slaves who worked the plantations along the eastern seaboard of continental America. But the slavetraders bought the slaves on the Atlantic coast: Europeans had little knowledge of the complex societies of the interior until the nineteenth century. In some ways most mysterious of all was China and the Far East, still known mainly through the reports of earlier travellers such as Marco Polo. Africa was unknown and despised: China was unknown and admired as the single ancient civilization that had survived into the modern age, respected both for its polity and its aesthetics. Until the Opium Wars of the nineteenth century when Europe was to force its way into China, Europeans would be obliged to trade on Chinese terms, buying Chinese goods made for export at a handful of approved ports on the Chinese coasts. At this stage the only Europeans allowed a closer knowledge of Chinese society were a few Jesuit missionaries (see, for example, Spence 1984). The Enlightenment's self-consciousness was to some extent a geographical consciousness based on the distinctiveness of the part of the world that came to be called 'Europe'. Even the 1648 map shows that the only line separating Europe from the continent of Asia (of which Europe is in fact a peninsula) must have been, as it still is, an ideological line. In the seventeenth century Europe - or more precisely certain people living on the north-west of that landmass - began to define themselves as different in significant respects from the rest of the world. That difference was represented by positing an imaginary continent with a somewhat flexible eastern boundary. Christendom had furnished the banner for the early voyages of discovery. Widespread scepticism about religious institutions, and especially about the temporal power of Rome, weakened the valency of that idea at least in intellectual circles. A geographical self-definition such as 'European' implied identification with secular and progressive values: Gibbon called Europe 'one great republic' (Gibbon 1896-1900: IV, 163). At key moments in the Discourse on Method and the Discourse on the Origins of Inequality, both Descartes and Rousseau contrast the worthlessness of 'the book' with the need to investigate 'the world', by which they understood both the world of nature and the world of the self. From a perceived European'centre' writers began to speculate about the 'peripheral' parts of the world. In that sense Descartes' references to the Chinese and the Cannibals inaugurate an important Enlightenment tradition (see Hulme, this volume). This is the 'comparative project' of the Enlightenment, one of its most fundamental methodologies. It was at this
8 Peter Hulme and Ludmilla lordanova time that writers began to compare their own societies with a variety of contemporary and past societies. For example, an influential exponent of early comparative sociology was Montesquieu, whose Spirit of the Laws (1748) shows how extended comparisons could assist the development of abstract analyses of political, social and economic conditions. The same author's Persian Letters (1721) reveals how the comparative perspective could be turned to subversive ends when cast in a fictional form. Enlightenment writers themselves were not great travellers: even Descartes and Rousseau, probably the r110st peripatetic, limited their travel to Europe. But they were voracious readers. Their footnotes are packed with references to the travel writers of the day, many of them missionaries whose own writings are then1selves worthy of consideration as Enlightenment texts, amongst the founding documents of the later disciplines of anthropology and sociology. They also sent their fictional heroes round the world, some - like Robinson Crusoe and Candide - travelling within the realms of the known world, others -like Gulliver - exploring the edges of that world as a way of dramatizing the crucial questions of the age concerning the nature of human nature. Most important of the collections of travel books for the Enlightenment is the Abbe Prevost's Histoire generale des voyages, a series begun in 1746. This originally purported to be merely a translation of the great English collections of Hakluyt, Purchas, and Churchill; but soon revealed itself as a much more ambitious project whose aim was to give an account of the manners, customs, religions, government, arts, sciences, commerce and manufactures of all the nations of the earth. It was, in its own way, the historical counterpart of the Encyclopedie with which it ran almost in parallel. The philosophical reflection on the nature of political society was often carried out via contrasts between European institutions and the supposed 'state of nature' witnessed by these European travellers to the new worlds of America and, later, the South Seas. Some of the principal works of writers like Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, Ferguson, and Diderot draw on accounts of these travellers in ways both important for their status as key texts of the Enlightenment, and revealing of their implication with the whole process of European exploration and colonization of the nonEuropean world. There were classical precedents for such comparisons in as much as the nature of 'civilized' society had, for the Greeks, been defined by contrast with, for example, the Scythians (see Hartog 1988). But in place of the Hesiodic 'races' or Ovidian 'ages' - which always told of a 'fall' (as too did the Christian schema), the characteristic Enlightenment philosophy of history was the idea of 'progress', initially from 'savagery' to 'civilization', but then through the stages of a more complex developmental model based on distinctions between hunting, pastoralism, and agriculture. Gradually the Biblical narrative was replaced by historical hypotheses of the kind produced by Rousseau in his Discourse on the Origins ofInequality (see Bernstein,
Introduction 9 this volume) in which the species moved, by a series of almost imperceptible shifts, from the original state of nature through to the social and political complexity of eighteenth-century Europe. Eventually a different kind of map became possible in which all the stages of mankind's 'development' could be visible at a glance: the history of the world could be superimposed upon its geography. At the end of the eighteenth century Edmund Burke wrote: we possess at this time very great advantages towards the knowledge of human Nature. We need no longer go to History to trace it in all its stages and periods. History from its comparative youth, is but a poor instructour.... But now the Great Map of Mankind is unrolld at once; and there is no state or Gradation of barbarism, and no mode of refinement which we have not at the same instant under our View. The very different Civility of Europe and of China; The barbarism of Persia and Abyssinia. The erratick manners of Tartary, and of arabia. The Savage State of North America, and of New Zealand. (Burke 1961: 351; cf. Marshall and Williams 1982) The intense and prolonged reflection of Enlightenment writers on the differences and similarities between various peoples was part of their engagement with the physical world as a whole. People mapped natural variety with unprecedented vigour in the eighteenth century - often thinking of themselves as perfect Baconians when they did so. And since natural historians had to find ways of bringing coherence to their voluminous observations and collections, the Enlightenment saw the heyday of taxonomy. To name, label, describe, examine, and indeed possess natural objects became a powerful urge. It was not just that more was known about the natural world, but that the world itself was coming to be thought about in completely new ways. The crucial issue was history. No one had ever thought that the world lacked a past, but it was believed for many centuries that this past was relatively short, and known primarily through the Bible. During the Enlightenment, fossil· evidence in particular acted as a spur to savants to produce plausible accounts of how what were clearly biological relics got to where they were found, and took the forms that they did. It was evident that the majority of fossils had close affinities with living forms, and also that they diverged from those living forms in certain significant respects. A theological explanation was possible through the notion of special creations: God has created new species at various points in the past, and has also allowed some species to become extinct. The only alternative hypothesis entails organic change - the idea that, over long periods of time, living things changed their basic characteristics. This possibility was first entertained in a serious way by eighteenth-century savants, who were fascinated by the relationships between past and present organisms, and among living species across the globe. Here too the comparative method was central, and it found expression in one of the scientific disciplines that flourished during the Enlightenment - comparative anatomy. By comparing skulls and skeletons of different vertebrates, including humans, anatomists built up pictures of the graduations
10 Peter Hulme and Ludmilla lordanova between what they thought of as 'species' and 'races'. Here the comparative method linked what we now call the natural and the social sciences. In comparative anatomy, the study of nature embraced human beings and animals; it treated what we would think of as questions of race and gender in the same way as natural historical questions. Nature was all-embracing, but still ambivalent. It included the earth, plants, animals, and human beings. Nature held authority - it was the lawful system instituted by God. As such, it could be treated as a paradigm, especially of ethical and moral values. Hence, nature was idealized. Enlightenment writers were prone to personify nature as woman, especially as a generous mother. But, for the restless spirits of the period, nature could also display other qualities - it could be wild, unpredictable, destructive, anarchic, subversive. The Lisbon earthquake of 1755 was often invoked as an example of nature's less benign side. To a degree, then, incompatible views of nature developed, although there were people, of whom Diderot is the pre-eminent example, who managed, if not to reconcile them, at least to hold disparate points of view simultaneously. Diderot could, for example, invoke nature as a comfortable moral and aesthetic norm, and yet allow the title character in his dialogue Rameau's Nephew to pour scorn on the idea of nature as any kind of norm. There was much debate about the place of America in this natural world. In the famous phrase of John Locke, 'in the beginning all the world was America' (Locke 1965: 343). But in the eighteenth century the French naturalist Buffon argued that all the mammals of America were smaller and the indigenous people weaker than those of the other continents, a point elaborated at great length in two tirades written by the Dutchman Cornelius de Pauw. De Pauw, who had never set foot in America, was commissioned to write the article on it for the 1776 supplement to the Encyclopedie. Raynal's History of the Two Indies (1770 and reprinted thirty-seven times by 1820) was similarly scathing about the degenerate Indians; and the descendants of European emigrants were commonly supposed to suffer similar degeneration, both physical and moral. The War of Independence that led to the foundation of the USA put an end to this view and tended in its stead to encourage the Enlightenment metaphor by which the 'old' (and corrupt) world of Europe was ready to pass the torch of progress across the Atlantic: a new version of the translatio imperii given concrete form in France's famous gift to its sister Republic of the statue entitled Liberty Enlightening the World (see Iversen, this volume). During the eighteenth century America was replaced as a testing ground for Enlightenment ideas of the natural by the islands of the South Seas. Two travellers sufficiently important to be considered by their contemporaries as Enlightenment heroes were Louis Antoine de Bougainville and James Cook, explorers of the Pacific in the 1760s and 1770s. Both Bougainville and Cook gave accounts of one particular island that had fascinated them - Tahiti, which has had a special place in the European imagination ever since. Tahiti was described as a kind of paradise: its
Introduction 11 climate was perfect, a plentiful supply of food seemed to fall from the trees, nobody seemed to do any work, everyone seemed to live in peace and harmony, and - what impressed the Europeans most of all - there seemed to be a complete absence of sexual taboos. The Europeans also brought back a number of Tahitians. Most of them found the climate difficult to cope with and soon died, but in the 1770s one of these Tahitians, called Omai, was a great social success in London, and had his portrait painted several times, most famously by Sir Joshua Reynolds. At the same time, in France, Denis Diderot was writing what he called a 'supplement' to Bougainville's account of his visit to Tahiti. Diderot used this work to make some of his most trenchant remarks about nature and freedom: The life of savages is so simple, and our societies are such complicated machines! The Tahitian is so close to the origin of the world, while the European is close to its old age. The contrast between them and us is greater than the difference between a newborn baby and a doddering old man. They understand absolutely nothing about our manners or our laws, and they are bound to see in them nothing but shackles disguised in a hundred different ways. Those shackles could only provoke the indignation and scorn of creatures in whom the most profound feeling is a love of liberty. . . How far we have departed from nature and happiness! Yet nature's sovereignty cannot be destroyed; it will persist in spite of all the obstacles raised in its way. Men may write as much as they like on tablets of bronze - to borrow the saying of Marcus Aurelius - that it is criminal to rub two intestines together voluptuously - the human heart will only be torn between the threats contained in the inscription and the violence of its own impulses. (Diderot 1956: 194, 233-4) This Tahiti was obviously a figment of Europe's imagination, and could not survive extended contact. This was not, as the Europeans had thought, an island in the 'state of nature'. For one thing, Tahiti had a political system. When Omai was taken back his main concern was to overthrow some enemies whom he accused of usurping his territory; so the picture of his return to Tahiti has him dressed rather ludicrously in European armour. South Sea hospitality also had its limits and there were violent incidents. The murder of Captain Cook himself on Hawaii in 1779 during his third voyage to the South Seas was instrumental in undermining the stereotype of the 'noble savage' (see Sahlins 1987). But the image of Tahiti as paradise lingered. In 1789 the most famous mutiny in English naval history took place in the South Seas on board HMS Bounty, when the authority of Captain Bligh was challenged by a group of sailors led by Fletcher Christian. The cry of the mutineers was 'Huzza for Tahiti'. Tahiti signified for them the opposite of naval discipline and authoritarian government. As Bligh later said about the mutineers: 'They imagined it in their power to fix themselves in the midst of plenty, on one of the finest islands in the world, where they need not labour, and
12 Peter Hulme and Ludmilla lordanova where the allurements of dissipation are beyond any thing that can be conceived' (quoted in Marshall and Williams 1982: 291). Many Enlightenment writers saw themselves as metaphorical 'travellers', concerned - as real travellers must be - with first-hand experience, scepticism towards written authorities, and the production of knowledge acquired in a rigorously empirical way. This is one facet of the current of radical individualism that has been deemed central to the Enlightenment (Lukes 1973). Conventional figures of this tradition are the political subject armed with rights to property and the autobiographical subject of Rousseau's Confessions. But the period has even stronger and more ambivalent images of such individualism: Descartes in his 'oven', Robinson Crusoe alone and fearful on his Caribbean island, Emile 'alone in the midst of human society', the 'wild boy' studied by Itard and, finally, Victor Frankenstein at work in his corpse-strewn laboratory. Just as we see Descartes as initiating a way of thinking that was central to the Enlightenment project, Mary Shelley's Frankenstein reveals its bankruptcy by the early nineteenth century. Frankenstein himself, like his creator, was a child of the Enlightenment, but he took his passion for the mastery of nature too far, and hence became not a benevolent scientific father, but an egotistical, irresponsible meddler with delusions of grandeur. The monster is more than out of control, he is totally unviable because his repulsive appearance, the consequences of Frankenstein's hubristic attempts to create a human being, make him an outcast. Early nineteenth-century Europeans had seen Napoleon's failed attempts to master vast territories and construct empires; they remained frightened of chaos and revolution, and became sceptical of the power of reason to bring the necessary degree of coherence to human society. Many people lost confidence in or rejected Enlightenment traditions. Yet, the major movements of ideas in the nineteenth century, such as positivism, retained and developed many of its key commitments. The Enlightenment's shadows have played a complex role in nineteenth and twentieth century society, but by the early nineteenth century the easy confidence and optimism that were so integral a part of the Enlightenment proper had evaporated. For nearly twenty years now all students in the humanities at the University of Essex (and many in the social sciences) have taken a course in their first year called 'The Enlightenment'. The fifty lectures on the course each year are given by members of all seven departments in the School of Comparative Studies - Art History and Theory, Government, History, Language and Linguistics, Literature, Philosophy, and Sociology. The approach taken is determinedly interdisciplinary and many students go on to take joint degrees in two of the component disciplines. This book draws upon expertise and enthusiasms developed in teaching that course: the editors and contributors are all members of the School of Comparative Studies.
Introduction 13
Figure 3 Benoit-Louis Prevost, frontispiece to the Encyclopedie (1772); after an original drawing by Charles-Nicholas Cochin II (1764). There is a detailed explanation of the figures in the Encyclopedie, but Diderot's gloss on Cochin's drawing captures the essence: We see at the top Truth between Reason and Imagination: Reason tries to lift her veil; Imagination prepares to adorn her. Below this group, a crowd of speculative philosophers; lower, a number of artists. The philosophers have their eyes fastened on Truth; proud Metaphysics tries to divine her presence rather than see her. Theology turns her back and waits for light from on high. (Diderot 1967: viii)
14 Peter Hulme and Ludmilla Jordanova
Figure 4 The tree of knowledge. 'This detail of the tree of knowledge from the EncyclopMie depicts some of its classifications. As outlined by d'Alembert, understanding in the system of human knowledge falls into three categories: memory, imagination, and reason. Under memory he placed history (both natural history and sacred history), as well as the arts, trades, and manufacturing. Imagination led to poetry, sacred and profane. The central core was reason, where general metaphysics and the "science of God" led to philosophy, the "science of man", and the "science of nature". The science of man embraced ethics and logic, while that of nature led to mathematics and also to "physics", as seen at the lower left. Mathematics was either pure (for instance, arithmetic and geometry) or mixed (comprising mechanics, astronomy, optics, and other branches of ordinary physics). "Particular physics" embraced philology, physical astronomy (and astrology), meteorology, cosmology, botany, zoology, mineralogy, and chemistry. The other branches can be traced on the tree in a similar fashion.' (Cohen 1980: 269).
Introduction 15 The eleven essays that follow present original research on some of the topics covered by the Essex lecture programme. In at least one respect the essays follow a pedagogical imperative of the Essex course: they focus on the written texts of the Enlightenment rather than retailing a more general history of ideas. And neither are the essays addressed to specialists; rather they aim to engage a more general readership interested in approaching the late seventeenth and eighteenth centuries from a conlparative and interdisciplinary perspective. The book does not offer a conventional 'introduction' to the Enlightenment: no attempt is made at coverage of all issues and writers. None the less, the introduction and the editorial passages linking the individual essays convey a general sense of many of the main lines of Enlightenment thinking and the first and last essays offer comments on the 'beginning' and 'end' of the Enlightenment. Although there is no single 'Essex approach' and, indeed, the essays vary widely in their address to the themes, the project has been discussed in detail by all the contributors and the essays read and discussed in draft. The Enlightenment and its Shadows is a collective project. There is no particular line or orthodoxy but, we hope, a style of thinking that owes something to a critical reflection on the legacy of the Enlightenment. A NOTE ON CONVENTIONS References are by means of the author/date system, with a consolidated bibliography at the end of the volume. A run of references may exclude the author/date after the first mention. Translations of foreign texts into English have been used throughout, with the original quoted where appropriate. We have followed Peter Gay's example in using 'philosophe' as an f.:nglish word (Gay 1967-70: II, xv), and have extended the convention to include 'savant'.
2 The spontaneous hand of nature: savagery, colonialism, and the Enlightenment PETER HULME
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION Geoffroy Atkinson's book on the 'new horizons' of the French Renaissance (1955) lists 550 geographical works, treating of all parts of the world, that appeared between 1480 and 1610. Writers like Michel de Montaigne (1533-92) and Rene Descartes (1596-1650) had plenty of evidence of the diversity of customs and manners. Their respective discussions of the significance of this diversity provide the starting point for Peter Hulme's essay. Descartes was educated by the Jesuits, and it was the Jesuit missionaries who were responsible for the most impressive body of ethnographic material produced in this period, sending back massive reports, some of which were edited and rewritten in France and published as The Jesuit Relations (Thwaites 1896-1901). There were Jesuits working among the Chinese and the Cannibals (to use Descartes' examples quoted at the beginning of this essay), although they were perhaps best known for their missions in Paraguay, mercilessly satirized by Voltaire, another Jesuit pupil, in his Candide (1759) - the subject of the following paper. The wealth of ethnographic writing published in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries fuelled all speculation, however purportedly 'hypothetical', about the nature of human beings and human social and political organizations. John Locke, whose Two Treatises of Government (1690) is the eventual focus of Hulme's essay, refers constantly to this growing body of material, much of which he owned (Harrison and Laslett 1971). Even Jean-Jacques Rousseau, the most avowedly speculative of the philosophical historians, would in 1755 rest his case on extensive quotations from such books, none more important than the Dominican father JeanBaptiste du Tertre's General History of the Caribbean Islands Inhabited by the French (1667). Such Enlightenment speculation about 'savagery' has generally been studied from within the framework of the history of ideas. The two major contexts of
The spontaneous hand of nature 17 discussion have been the 'state of nature' debate in the earlier part of the period (where 'savagery' is the absence of 'civilization'), and the later development of a 'stages' theory of history in which 'savagery' assumes the kind of defining characteristics that mark its use by, for example, Adam Ferguson (with the original dualism expanded by the introduction of the median stage 'barbarism') or Lewis Henry Morgan in the mid-nineteenth century (with 'savagery' and 'barbarism' each further subdivided into upper, Iniddle, and lower forms). A primary aim of this essay is to reinstate the Enlightenment discussion of 'savagery' into a colonial history, looking, at least briefly, at the practice associated with these ideas and trying to see just how they formed part of an extended ideological justification for colonial appropriation of non-European territories, particularly in the Americas. No major Enlightenment figure had direct experience of the colonies but several, foremost amongst them John Locke, worked closely with the private and state bodies which were responsible for formulating the colonial policies of European countries during the period.
2
from college days I had learnt that one can imagine nothing so strange and incredible but has been said by some philosopher; and since then, while travelling, I have realised that those whose opinions are quite opposed to ours are not, for all that, without exception barbarians and savages; many of them enjoy as good a share of reason as we do, or better. Again, I considered how a given man with a given mind develops otherwise among Frenchmen or Germans than he would ifhe had always lived among Chinese or Cannibals; how, again, even in the fashion of dress, the very thing that we liked ten years ago... seems to us at present extravagant and ridiculous. Thus it is by custom and example that we are persuaded, much more than by any certain knowledge; at the same time, a majority of votes is worthless as a proof, in regard to truths that are even a little difficult of discovery; for it is much more likely that one man should have hit upon them for himself than that a whole nation should. Accordingly I could choose nobody whose opinions I thought preferable to other men's; and I was as it were forced to become my own guide. (Descartes 1970: 18-19; translation adapted) A phenomenon as complex as the Enlightenment could have no single beginning but, if the matter were pressed, a claim might be staked for these words of Descartes, published in 1637: they certainly manifest that selfless commitment to truth which has always been such an important part of the self-image of the Enlightenment and they mark, in dramatic fashion, the emergence of an individual and uncompromised project from the plethora of mere example and custom. Descartes forced to become his own guide is a graphic image of temporary loss, assuaged by the knowledge that the authorial subject has emerged from the dark forest of intellectual confusion and is dramatizing in retrospect the quest in which he is inscribed as solitary hero. The cultural geography of the passage obviously owes much to the 'age of discovery' in which France was just beginning to participate: Descartes' mental
The spontaneous hand of nature 19
Figure 5 One of the earliest purported illustrations of the inhabitants of the Americas, this wood-engraving, probably produced in Germany, circulated through Europe in the early sixteenth century. It was accompanied by this account, probably culled from the reports based on the letters of Amerigo Vespucci: This figure represents to us the people and island which have been discovered by the Christian King of Portugal or by his subjects. The people are thus naked, handsome, brown, well shaped in body, their hands, necks, arms, private parts, feet of men and women are a little covered with feathers. The men also have many precious stones in their faces and breasts. No one also has anything, but all things are in common. And the men have as wives those who please them, be they mothers, sisters or friends, therein make they no distinction. They also fight with each other. They also eat each other even those who are slain, and hang the flesh of them in the smoke. They become a hundred and fifty years old. And have no government. (Eames 1922: 756) The negatives are a commonplace of classical primitivist writing; and the tone is neutral in the sense that there is no moral outrage (as with later Puritan accounts) and no obvious satirical or even polemical stance adopted. The reference to anthropophagy was a defining characteristic of representations of America during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Robinson Crusoe and Candide are just two of many fictional figures who have to confront American cannibals.
universe contains Chinese and Cannibals as well as Frenchmen and Germans. The mapping here is straightforward enough: Frenchmen and Germans constitute the European centre with the Chinese and Cannibals at the eastern and western extremes of the periphery. For Europe China had represented an ideal of oriental civilization ever since the time of Marco Polo. The West Indian Cannibals - whose
20 Peter Hulme name was given to the area they inhabited as 'Caribbean' - had, from the earliest reports of the New World, occupied the opposite end of that spectrum, their purported anthropophagy so fitting them for the role of archetypal savages that 'cannibalism' soon came to displace the classical word. Yet if a cultural spectrum is implicit, the Cannibals remain, for Descartes, within the pale. They are a nation, Cannibals rather than cannibals; and so the 'given man', the universal subject of Descartes' sentence, can be as easily imagined developing his 'given mind' among the Cannibals as amongst the Germans. The presumption of a common humanity underlies differences of custom and opinion, however severe. From a philosophical point of view, Descartes is usually considered to have been writing within a tradition of sceptical humanism associated with the essayist Michel de Montaigne, which he would - in the course of the Discourse on Method - turn against itself in what has so often been seen as the founding gesture of modern thought. But culturally he also draws on Montaigne in this passage, following the Ciceronian axiom about philosophy, which had been earlier quoted in Montaigne's Apologie de Raymond Sebond ('Nothing may be spoken so absurdly, but that it is spoken by some of the philosophers' (i928: II, 256)) with a paraphrase of Montaigne's own famous axiom that 'chacun appelle barbarie ce qui n'est pas de son usage' ('men call that barbarism which is not common to them'), made in the course of his remarkable essay 'Of the Caniballes' (1928: I, 219). Yet the general thrust of Descartes' paragraph eventually breaks away from such relativism. A different language begins to emerge, in which 'truths' are 'discovered' like new lands, in which the model for the scientist is that of the new explorer sailing beyond the boundaries of the old world of tired shibboleths, across 'strange seas of Thought, alone' (in Wordsworth's later words about Newton) towards the brave world of new knowledges. No voyager sailed the strange seas of the Atlantic or Pacific literally alone, but the metaphor best suits Christopher Columbus, perforce his own guide across the Atlantic and thereby the unspoken model for Descartes' solitary quest in search of a new-found land of certainties in which to sink the foundations of a new city of knowledge. A geographical revolution had indeed preceded and in many ways provided a language for the revolution in thought that constituted the Enlightenment. At around the time that Descartes began his European travels, Francis Bacon published the first outline of his Great Instauration (1620), the most confident statement of the new science. Like Descartes after him, Bacon begins by rejecting what he calls the 'enchantments of antiquity and authority' which have 'so bound up men's powers that they have been made impotent (like persons bewitched) to accompany with the nature of things' (Bacon 1960: 81). The book, traditional symbol of knowledge and authority, is denigrated for its 'endless repetitions' (83). The spell of the library is to be broken through the example of the voyagers: Nor must it go for nothing that by the distant voyages and travels which have beconle frequent in our times many things in nature have been laid open and dis-
The spontaneous hand of nature 21
Figure 6 The classical world had at its centre the Mediterranean sea, the world of Ulysses'
travels, whose western limits were marked by the straits of Gibraltar. Hercules was one of the few to go beyond those limits, and on his return he set up the Pillars of Hercules, usually identified with the rocks of Ceuta and Gibraltar. In the early fourteenth century Dante, in a remarkable variation on the classical story, had Ulysses tell of how he died after persuading his sailors to set a course directly west beyond the Pillars: 'Think of your breed; for brutish ignorance I Your mettle was not made; you were made men, I To follow after knowledge and excellence' (Dante 1949: 236). In this tradition, Bacon's title page shows a ship passing through the Pillars, symbolically breaking clear of the restraints of Old World knowledge.
22 Peter Hulme covered which may let in new light upon philosophy. And surely it would be disgraceful if, while the regions of the material globe - that is, of the earth, of the sea, and of the stars - have been in our times laid widely open and revealed, the intellectual globe should remain shut up within the narrow limits of old discoveries. (81) For this new challenge the existing guides are puzzled and worthless. The ancients were, after all, limited to coasting the shores of the old continent or crossing inland seas like the Mediterranean. Just as the mariner's needle provided a new guide across the .ocean, so a new scientific method will lead out of the 'woods of experience' into 'the open ground of axioms' (12-13; 80). The analogy is perhaps clearest in the book's opening statement, its frontispiece showing the pillars of Hercules bravely traversed by a new Columbus (Figure 6). Some of the earliest accounts of the inhabitants of America had been written from within that same humanist tradition that Descartes was to subvert. Peter Martyr, the Italian humanist resident in Spain at the time of Columbus's return from the Caribbean, disseminated much information about the New World in his letters and other writings, some of which were translated into English by Richard Eden in 1555 as The Decades of the newe worlde. Peter Martyr's first frame of reference was classical: So that if we shall not be ashamed to confesse the truthe, they seem to lyve in the goulden worlde of the which owlde wryters speake so much; wherin luen lyved simplye and innocentlye without inforcement of lawes, without quarrelling ludges and libelles, contente onely to satisfie nature, without further vexation for knowlege of thinges to come. (Eden 1885: 71; cf. Levin 1972) This vision of the simplicity and innocence of the Golden Age drew its essential elements from the opening book of Ovid's JVletamorphoses, not accidentally the very first book translated into English in America, by George Sandys, treasurer of the Virginia Company at the time of the Jamestown settlement in the early seventeenth century: The Golden Age was first; which uncompeld, And without rule, in Faith and Truth exceld. As then, there was no punishment, nor feare; Nor threatning Laws in brasse prescribed were; Nor suppliant crouching pris'ners shooke to see Their angry ludge: but all was safe and free.... (Sandys 1640: 2) But this humanist ideal of a Golden Age uncorrupted by old world vices was applied
The spontaneous hand of nature 23 to America only from the libraries of Europe: it was a perspective whose soft tones required the distancing provided as readily by the Atlantic as by the centuries separating Europe from its pre-history. Such a view might have proved compatible with initial Indian hospitality and with the desire of would-be colonists to raise support for their ventures - so Philip Amadas and George Barlow, who captained Raleigh's expedition to Virginia (as Raleigh called it) in 1584, had described the inhabitants as 'people most gentle, loving, and faithfull, voide of all guile and treason, and such as live after the manner of the golden age' (Amadas and Barlow 1903-5: 305). But this utopian vision did not long survive the complexities of American topography: colonists' demands for land grew more extensive and more violent, exhausting native hospitality and eventually provoking reprisals. Fortunately the 'age without rule' was capable of a different gloss, even from within the Metamorphoses itself, as in Sandys' commentary on the decidedly inhospitable Cyclops: Now the Cyclops (as formerly said) were a salvage people given to spoyle and robbery; unsociable amongst themselves, and inhumane to strangers: And no marvell; when lawlesse, and subject to no government, the bond of society; which gives to every man his owne, suppressing vice, and advancing vertue, the two maine columnes of a Common-wealth, without which it can have no supportance. Besides man is a political and sociable creature: they therefore are to be numbred among beasts who renounce society, whereby they are destitute of lawes, the ordination of civility. (Sandys 1640: 263) The turning-point for English commentators on this matter was undoubtedly March 1622 when a concerted effort by the Powhatan confederacy under the leadership of the formidable Opechancanough narrowly failed to extirpate the English colony at Jamestown. After this event the attitudes and practices of the settlers themselves remained necessarily pragmatic with regard to contact with the native population; but the 'massacre' - as it was called in England - provided a different and in some ways more powerful impulse to the colonizing process. The dangers could no longer be elided but, since the natives were seen by their action to have relinquished any conceivable natural rights they might have had to the land, the potential rewards for colonial enterprise were now much greater, or at least the difficulties in justifying the rewards less considerable. Samuel Purchas, chief ideologist of the Virginia Company, drew out the consequences in his essay 'Virginia's Verger' published in 1625: But when Virginia was violently ravished by her owne ruder Natives, yea her Virgin cheekes dyed with the bloud of three Colonies . . . the stupid Earth seemes distempered with such bloudy potions and cries that shee is ready to spue out her inhabitants. (Purchas 1905-7: 229)
24 Peter Hulme The initial separation of land from inhabitants in the bestowal of the name Virginia pays handsome dividends here. Not only can the 'virgin' land be savagely raped by its own natives, but the blood thereby spilt onto its cheeks is that of the English colonies themselves, which are, in the process, identified with the Virginia that has been ravished. The Indians became satisfactorily 'unnatural Naturalls', forfeiting any rights they may have had under natural law. In other words the 'massacre' has performed a miraculous reversal by which the settlers have become the natural inhabitants - identified with the land and the original inhabitants have been discursively 'spewed out' by their own territories. An even more immediate reaction came in the sermon addressed by John Donne at 8t Paul's to the members of the Virginia Company on 13 November 1622, soon after news of the 'massacre' had reached London. Donne took as his text Acts 1.8: 'But yee shall receive power, after that the Holy Ghost is come upon you, and yee shall be witnesses unto me both in Jerusalem, and in all Judea, and in Samaria, and unto the uttermost part of the earth.' He proceeded to speak not only of the Company's missionary duties, but also of the difficulties of gaining riches in that uttermost part of the earth: 'though you see not your money, though you see not your men, though a Flood, a Flood of bloud have broken in upon them, be not discouraged' (Donne 1959: 271). Among Donne's audience that day was Thomas Hobbes. His 'warre of every man against every man' expounded in Leviathan (1651) comes complete with American references: 'savage people in many places of America' who 'live at this day in that brutish manner'. This pitiless account of the state of nature was not uninfluenced, it might be speculated, by the events of 1622, given Hobbes' own involvement, through Cavendish, his patron, with the affairs of the Virginia Company (1968: 187-8; cf. Malcolm 1981). Montaigne - in keeping with the satirical strand of classical humanism - had, so to speak, brought the cannibals home in one way: at the end of his essay the Tupis are allowed to offer, through Montaigne's admittedly faulty memory, their own damning comments on European society, notably the contrast they make between some men 'full gorged with all sort of commodities' and others who 'bare with need and povertie, begged at their gate' (Montaigne 1928: I, 229). In some ways Hobbes brought 'savagery' home even more tellingly. The savagery of the state of nature is exemplified in Hobbes' writings 'in this present age' by American societies; but currently 'civil and flourishing' nations 'have been in former ages ... fierce, shortlived, poor, nasty, and deprived of all that pleasure and beauty of life, which peace and society are wont to bring with them' (1972: 118). And what they have been, they can become again, very easily. In his 'Tripos' Hobbes lists the benefits of civilization, only to conclude with the question: 'all of which supposed away, what do we differ from the wildest of Indians?' (1840: 72). The 'savages' hold a mirror up to the 'reality' of our human nature; they show a frightening image of a society bereft of those attributes which make it civilized. The traditional negatives of the classical Golden Age - in the resonant French phrase 'sans foi, ni loi, ni roi' (without faith
The spontaneous hand of nature 25 nor law nor king) - are accepted by Hobbes as an accurate description of life in the state of nature; but that state is judged to produce nothing less than 'continuall feare, and the danger of violent death' (1968: 186). At least part of the obloquy heaped upon Hobbes' work is to be explained by the way in which the abstract notion of human corruption thereby takes on a living form so that the 'savage' Americans become for the first time identical in their deepest nature with their European antagonists. In this way savagery is lodged disconcertingly close to the crust of civilization: America is allowed to provide a glimpse into the heart of darkness (Ashcraft 1972: 162). John Locke's argument in the second of his Two Treatises of Government (1690) might seem equally distant from both these traditions, the humanist and the Hobbesian. The 'Golden Age' does feature once in its pages as that time 'before vain Ambition, and amor sceleratus habendi, evil Concupiscence, had corrupted Mens minds into a Mistake of true Power and Honour' (Locke 1965: 387), but Locke's state of nature is as far removed from a land of milk and honey as it is from Hobbes' world of perpetual strife. It is rather a realm of positive achievements sustained in accordance with the Law of Nature, a state of perfect freedom and equality. The only one of the traditional negatives that applies to Locke's state of nature is 'without a common Superior on Earth' (321). And only the danger of the state of nature becoming a state of war explains the eventual acceptance of an ultimate earthly authority 'from which relief can be had by appeal' (323). This danger arises from the failure of a minority of human beings to conduct themselves according to natural law. References to America might seem to bring Locke closer to Hobbes' chilling universalism: after all, 'in the beginning all the World was America' (343). But in Europe those beginnings were long ago and Europeans - or at least some Europeans - were separated from their American cousins by more than the Atlantic. On closer inspection Locke's famous aphorism inserts an historical wedge of some size between the two continents. The implied relationship between Europe and America becomes apparent on that metaphorical map of the world unrolled a century later by Edmund Burke as the very map of mankind's history with all stages and periods of savagery and civility instantly under our view in different parts of that world (quoted above, p.9). The language of development, here coming into being as an Enlightenment theory of history, is still very much with us, allowing our one world to be read through a metaphor of maturation in which some are - when not 'children' - always junior to the European standard. Locke's argument in the Second Treatise can be seen in general terms as a radical attack on absolutism and its accompanying privileges, the most important of which is the control of land. The target of the book is, then, the practice of the unproductive land-owning aristocracy of seventeenth-century England. In the last analysis the book's complex argument, with its play of limitations and justifications, defends the principle of the enclosure of common land into private property and the
26 Peter Hulme accumulation of capital that results from a commitment to the improvement of that land. But private accumulation can, according to Locke, only be justified if its accumulation accrues - eventually - to the public good. Locke's approach is to formulate what one critic has described as 'a statement of universal principle ... completely independent of historical example' (Laslett 1965: 91). In other words, an elaborate hypothesis is constructed based upon extrapolations from a supposed original condition, conventionally called the 'state of nature'; with key terms such as 'property' and 'labour' complexly and abstractly discussed, independent of any particular case that may be cited. Awhole series of readings of the Second Treatise has sought to uncover the revolutionary context in which Locke wrote the work (most recently Ashcraft 1986). Nevertheless the argument itself proceeds determinedly in the direction of general principles couched in the language of natural law. For these reasons the book is often seen as one of the founding texts of modern political philosophy. However, despite the movement towards universal principles, most of the crucial steps in Locke's argument actually depend on references to America. Locke begins by affirming (on Biblical authority) that the state of nature is a state of equality with the earth given to mankind in common (Locke 1965: 309), and the taking of private property from the common stock only therefore warranted 'at least where there is enough, and as good left in common for others' (329). Seventeenth-century England could hardly be thought capable of supplying 'enough, and as good' to those without land, but this threatening limitation is overcome through a form of colonial calculus whereby private improvement of land has far-reaching public benefits: To which let me add, that he who appropriates land to himself by his labour, does not lessen but increase the common stock of mankind. For the provisions serving to the support of humane life, produced by one acre of inclosed and cultivated land, are (to speak much within compasse) ten times more, than those, which are yeilded by an acre of Land, of an equal richnesse, lyeing wast in common. And therefor he, that incloses Land and has a greater plenty of the conveniencys of life from ten acres, than he could have from an hundred left to Nature, may truly be said, to give ninety acres to Mankind. For his labour now supplys him with provisions out of ten acres, which were but the product of an hundred lying in common. I have here rated the improved land very low in making its product but as ten to one, when it is much nearer an hundred to one. For I aske whether in the wild woods and uncultivated wast of America left to Nature, without any improvement, tillage or husbandry, a thousand acres will yeild the needy and wretched inhabitants as many conveniencies of life as ten acres of equally fertile land doe in Devonshire where they are well cultivated. (336) The equality existing under the state of nature was never likely to survive Locke's hypothetical reconstruction of the development of political society, but the result-
The spontaneous hand of nature 27 ant inequalities could still be defended if it were claimed that ev~n the worst-off would have benefited - an argument that has become one of the planks of economic liberalism. The Second Treatise takes the worst case to be a day-labourer forced to sell his only property - his labour - in return for sufficient wages to keep him and his family alive. If the day-labourer were to question the improvement in his condition over what it had been in the state of nature when land was held in common, Locke's answer would again point across the Atlantic: There cannot be a clearer demonstration of any thing, than several Nations of the Americans are of this, who are rich in Land, and poor in all the Comforts of Life; whom Nature having furnished as liberally as any other people, with the materials of Plenty, i.e. a fruitful Soil, apt to produce in abundance, what might serve for food, rayment, and delight; yet for want of improving it by labour, have not one hundredth part of the Conveniences we enjoy: And a King of a large fruitful Territory there feeds, lodges, and is clad worse than a day Labourer in England. (338-9) If the best-off of the Indians is worse off than the worst-off of the English labourers, then Locke's extrapolations from natural law are vindicated. These issues were in no sense abstract in late. seventeenth-century England, the age of enclosure and changing property relations, and of widespread apprehension about the threat from the so-called 'masterless' men. And there is no doubt that the thrust of Locke's argument is towards the defence of a system in which the least well-off can be seen to have benefited from the 'improvements' accruing from a more 'rational' use of land. However, neither can these references to America be without intended substance as is sometimes argued, since the edifice of Locke's argument would fall without the comparison between Indian king and English labourer. (Indeed, the simplest, though infrequently made, challenge to Locke's argument is to say that, with respect to the inconveniences of being an Indian chief, he was ill-informed.) A stronger case could even be made for the American references. To use the example of Devonshire - a peripheral and relatively barren county which had become productive during the sixteenth century through careful husbandry (Wood 1984: 60)as a case of productivity with which to contrast the 'wast of America', demonstrates that the process of improvement as understood by Locke was to all intents and purposes complete in England; leaving the thrust of the argument to apply to the American continent. In the second version of the colonial calculus - in which the proportion of productivity due to labour becomes 99/100ths (Locke 1965: 338) tobacco and sugar, the classic crops of tropical colonialism, weigh at least equally in the example \vith wheat and barley. There is also circumstantial evidence for thinking that Locke's references to America are unlikely to be trivial. Locke himself had intimate connections with the developing project of colonial expansion, especially in North America and the West
28 Peter Hulme Indies. Shaftesbury, his patron and employer, was an active participant in this project - part-owner of slave-ships, leading member of the Committee for Trade and of the board of Lords Proprietors of Carolina; so much the progressive capitalist that his biographer speaks of him being regarded as 'a representative of the rising new capitalistic forces in society' (Haley 1968: 227), and Maurice Cranston says that he 'might almost have been invented by Marx' (1957: 107). Locke worked as secretary for these bodies, was involved in framing the Fundamental Constitutions for the new territory of Carolina, and invested capital in the Royal African Company and the Bahama Adventurers, a merchant company set up by Shaftesbury in 1673. In that year he also became secretary to the Council of Trade and Plantations, which emphasized English interests in tropical and sub-tropical colonies. And in 1697 he wrote about the continuing problems of Virginia for the Board of Trade, discussing the need for land reform (Ashcraft 1969). Indeed the argument of the Second Treatise is implicated with that panoply of natural law theory (mainly Roman in origin) with which European occupation of American land was being justified. In his 1622 sermon, Donne had rooted the 'power' of his text from Acts in the law of nations by which 'if the inhabitants doe not in some measure fill the Land, so as the Land may bring foorth her increase for the use of men', then the land 'becomes theirs that wil possesse it' (Donne 1959: 274). This argument, known as the vacuum domicilium, ·was much elaborated over the course of the seventeenth century, but its point was simple enough. As one European writer put it, with brutal succinctness: 'we rather than they being the prime occupants, and they only Sojourners in the land' (Peter Heylyn, quoted in Berkhofer 1978: 31). During the sixteenth century the key questions for colonial discourse had concerned sovereignty and jurisdiction: Spanish and Portuguese colonists were principally interested in the extraction of natural resources and therefore with controlling the labour-power that made this possible. In the seventeenth century, for the English in North America and the Caribbean, and particularly for the Puritans in New England, the crucial questions involved the exclusive control of land on which to grow their crops: the 'wilderness' had to be reduced through improvement in a move that was both spiritual and physical. As John Winthrop put it in his General Considerations for the Plantation in New-England (i629): the whole earth is the Lord's garden, and he hath given it to the sons of Adam to be tilled and improved by them. Why then should we stand starving here for the places of habitation, (many men spending as much labor and cost to recover or keep sometimes an acre or two of lands as would procure him many many hundreds of acres, as good or better, in another place,) and in the mean time suffer whole countries, as profitable for the use of man, to lie waste without any improvement. (quoted in Pearce 1988: 21; cf. Eisinger 1948; Washburn 1959; Jennings 1976) This is very much Locke's language too:
The spontaneous hand of nature 29 God gave the World to Men in Common; but since he gave it them for their benefit, and the greatest Conveniences of Life they were capable to draw from it, it cannot be supposed he meant it should always remain common and uncultivated. He gave it to the use of the Industrious and Rational, (and Labour was to be his Title to it;) not to the Fancy or Covetousness of the Quarrelsom and Contentious. (Locke 1965: 333) There is a labour theory of value here, which Locke goes on to articulate, but also something close to a theory of humanity, since the industry of those who appropriate land to themselves by their .labour and, consequently, through pursuing their private interests contribute to the public good, also thereby demonstrates (or even gains) their chosenness. The implicit reasoning is Puritan, even Calvinist: 'Work was a test for which men must volunteer; their failure to volunteer was evidence that they had not been called' (Waltzer 1966: 218). Those who did not 'volunteer', the quarrelsome and contentious, or even simply the idle, were at best ignoring God's intentions, at worst failing to demonstrate their rationality and, therefore, since human beings are essentially rational, failing to demonstrate their humanity. So, for Locke, a central distinction within humanity has been established between those who recognize their reason ('writ in the Hearts of all Mankind' (315)) and make use of it, and those who do not. By contrast, the theory of labour is universal, for the simple reason that nobody can eat without, according to Locke's definition, employing their labour. The example is again American: God, who hath given the World to Men in common, hath also given them reason to make use of it to the best advantage of Life, and convenience. The Earth, and all that is therein, is given to Men for the Support and Comfort of their being. And though all the Fruits it naturally produces, and Beasts it feeds, belong to Mankind in common, as they are produced by the spontaneous hand of Nature; and no body has originally a private Dominion, exclusive of the rest of Mankind, in any of them, as they are thus in their natural state: yet being given for the use of Men, there must of necessity be a means to appropriate them some way or other before they can be of any use, or at all beneficial to any particular Man. The Fruit, or Venison, which nourishes the wild Indian, who knows no Inclosure, and is still a Tenant in common, must be his, and so his, i.e. a part of him, that another can no longer have any right to it, before it can do him any good for the support of his Life. (328) Logically, one might suppose that the deployment of the 'reason' given by God to men was responsible for all food production through the development of hunting, pastoralism, and agriculture. But, instead, Locke introduces a further distinction whereby originally - and still in certain kinds of society - food is provided 'by the
30 Peter Hulme spontaneous hand of Nature'; and appropriation out of this 'hand' is the first sign of how 'labour' intervenes in the process. Even the wild Indian - who still lives in a situation where land is held in common - makes a possession of what is to be his food by mixing his labour with it, even if that only involves picking the fruit off the branch. The Indian has used his labour - but not in the productive process, and so without, according to Locke, showing any exercise of reason. What holds this argument together is the intervention of that 'spontaneous hand of Nature', which enables Locke to separate the concepts of labour and reason. Without the spontaneous hand of nature there would be no explanation of how those who had not yet demonstrated their rationality had managed to survive with some degree of success. It is this idea of spontaneous food provision - prior to the exercise of reason - that underwrites the exclusivity of Locke's central category of fully rational human beings. And, incidentally to his argument, explains away, at least within the purview of colonial discourse, the presence in America of cultivated crops such as maize and tobacco refined over many centuries in Mesoamerica, along the Atlantic seaboard and throughout the Caribbean islands, long before Columbus 'discovered' them and brought them back to Europe. So according to Locke humanity is defined by reason, and the exercise of reason demonstrated by improvement of land. The existence of food is not in itself sufficient proof of 'culture': labour sometimes merely 'collects' what nature has provided. Therefore the central division for Locke lies between those who 'improve' and those who merely'collect': only the former are fully rational and therefore fully human. The argument from spontaneity is necessary to explain how the 'not fully rational' can manage to eat: it is this trope that excludes native American agriculture from consideration, and even from recognition. As if in response to the significance of its references to America, Locke's Second Treatise was soon drawn upon to support one of the most extensive and sophisticated of the Puritan justifications for appropriation of Indian land, John Bulkley's long preface to Roger Wolcott's highly political Poetical Meditations, aimed at the group of European colonists called the 'native rights men' after their insistence on buying land from the Indians on the grounds that they did fully own it (Bulkley 1725; cf. Dunn 1969). Bulkley quotes extensively from the Second Treatise, making particular play of Locke's theory of labour, for which he finds support in Genesis: And to this voice of the Law of ~Jature, viz. that Labour in this State shall be the beginning of Property, seems well to agree the voice of God Himself in the Gift or Grant he made of the Earth, the Creatures & productions of it to Mankind, Gen. I. 28. - Where we find that Cultivating and Subduing the Earth, and having Dominion are joyned together: thereby assuring us that as in that Gift he then made of it in common to, men, he did not design it should serve to their benefit & comfort only by its spontaneous Productions, but that it was his will that by Art and Industry in Subduing and Cultivating of it they should draw still more from
The spontaneous hand of nature 31 it, so that this should be their Title to it at least during the continuance of that State of Nature, & till by positive Constitutions of their own, the matter of Property should be otherwise Determined and Settled. (Bulkley 1725: xxv-xxvi) But his second use of that Lockian phrase about the 'spontaneous' provisions of nature makes explicit the literary reference that lies behind the trope: Their way of Living the Poet well describes when accounting for the Golden Age, he tells us of Men then.... And men themselves contented were with plain & simple Food, That on the Earth of natures gift, without their Travel stood, Did live by Respis, Hipps & Haws, by Cornets, Plums & Cherries By Sloes and Apples, Nuts and Pears & Loathsome Bramble berries, And by the Acorns dropt on ground from loves broad tree in field. Certain 'tis Nature the main Materials of their Subsistence without any Art or Labour of theirs; they had but little more to do than to Catch or Gather what they had provided for them. And during this State of things among any Societies of Men, of what Consideration or Value can Land be to them, especially when these spontaneous Provisions of Nature in all Places are in such Abundance that there is no danger of Want, and all means of Communication or Trade with other parts of the World, together with the Use ofMoney, among themselves, (which things might impair their Stock of Provisions and give a Value to them over and above what their own Necessities did) are wholly wanting, as we all know was the case with the Aborigines of the Country? (Bulkley 1725: xxxvii-xxxviii, quoting Arthur Golding's 1563 translation of Ovid's Metamorphoses) Bulkley's enthusiastic explication of Locke highlights a peculiarity about the spontaneous hand of nature which had remained invisible in Locke's exposition. What supports the crucial distinction between universal labour and the more restricted exercise of reason amongst humanity is precisely the humanist language of the Golden Age from which Locke - paradigm of the modern political philosopher - is supposedly so distant. As Ovid has it, here in Sandys' translation, at that time: The yet-free Earth did of her own accord (Vntorne with ploughs) all sorts of fruit afford; and its denizens contented themselves 'with Natures un-enforced food' (Sandys 1640: 2). 'Own accord' and 'un-enforced' are both synonyms for 'spontaneous'; 'sponte sua' is Ovid's second phrase describing the Golden Age - 'uncompeld' in Sandys' translation.
32 Peter Hulme Ovid's 'golden age' is a time of abundance and bounty, part of a narrative of loss that was central to classical (and particularly Roman) self-definitions. That narrative has a long, discontinuous history. It had provided a frame of reference for the humanism of Peter Martyr and Montaigne; it is an ingredient in Diderot's Enlightenment story of the noble Tahitian savage; and it would still, in the next century, be visible in Karl Marx's theory of primitive communism. But the abundance and bounty of a lost Golden Age can have no part to play in a political philosophy based on justifying the rational use of land previously allowed to lie waste. For Locke, bounty has only ever resulted from improvements in food production. Where land has not been improved the inhabitants reliant on the provisions of nature - are 'needy and wretched' (Locke 1965: 336). Or, as he elsewhere has it, if it were not for the practical knowledge of some men in the past, 'we should spend all our time to make a scanty provision for a poor and miserable life', such as that of the inhabitants of the West Indies, who are 'scarce able to subsist' (Ashcraft 1987: 148 n. 3). Bulkley's gloss on 'spontaneous' ('in such Abundance that there is no danger of Wanf) reflects its Ovidian provenance and, indeed, his perception of the realities of Indian culture, but at the same time it serves to undermine the Lockian argument in whose service it is advanced; because if there is 'no danger of Want', there is significantly less advantage to be gained through economies of scale in agriculture and therefore - to put the argument only in its weakest form significantly more difficulty in justifying the accumulation of land into a few hands. The trope of spontaneity itself is a necessary component of Locke's argument, drawn from the repertory of contemporary colonial discourse to hold apart 'labour' and 'reason': but its Ovidian connotations work counter to the picture of deprivation against which the promise of greater 'Conveniences' finds its justification. It took Adam Smith, nearly a hundred years later, to clarify Locke's position for him in a paraphrase on the very first page of The Wealth ofNations which equates the 'civilized and thriving' nations with their technological superiority over 'the savage nations'. In the former the produce of the whole labour of the society is so great, that all are often abundantly supplied, and a workman, even of the lowest and poorest order, if he is frugal and industrious, may enjoy a greater share of the necessaries and conveniences of life than it is possible for any savage to acquire. (Smith 1838: 1) Here 'labour' and 'reason' are unproblematically universal: it is just that the level of skills is very different in 'savage' and 'civilized' societies. The argument now has a satisfying circularity to it, its confident generalizations purged of the contradictions associated with the Ovidian reference to spontaneity. In The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism, C. B. Macpherson demonstrated the importance of what he called the 'differential rationality' by which Locke's theory naturalized the economic differences between the propertied and propertyless (Macpherson 1962: 222-47). In that case, though, reason can in prin-
The spontaneous hand of nature 33 ciple be exercised by all; it is force of circumstance - the absence of available land that prevents the landless majority demonstrating their use of reason by making land productive: unless they plant in those 'in-land, vacant places of America' (Locke 1965: 335). The Indians' lack of displayed reason is - though of less importance to seventeenth-century England - a more serious matter within the terms established by the Second Treatise, since in America the opportunity to 'improve' the land has, according to Locke, gone begging. The Indians' failure to 'volunteer' for labour is consequently a more serious indictment than that levelled at the English labouring poor. After all, reason teaches all 'who will but consult it' (311). Failure to consult reason is clearly in the American case a moral failure in no way mitigated by circumstances. It was only towards the end of the 'age of the Enlightenment' that a scientific racism came to secure the distinctions between different groups of human beings. For Locke - as for Descartes before him - the monogenetic tradition of Christian thought guaranteed the essential unity of the human species, even unto the uttermost part of the earth. But Locke's differential rationality with respect to cultural production, held in place by that trope of the spontaneous hand of nature, still contained within it a powerful set of consequences: the penalty for failing to see reason could be severe. The earth produces fruits and feeds beasts (328). If the Indian merely collects what is provided 'spontaneously' then it is not easy to see how he differs from the beasts that are similarly provided for; except of course that as a human being he is guilty of ignoring the law of nature that is incumbent upon humans but not on animals (see Locke 1958: 188). Here - in an almost Hobbesian way - the boundary between animal and human is distinctly permeable. Certainly those who can be seen as 'having renounced Reason' (Locke 1965: 314) by shedding blood, or even those who have revealed an 'enmity' towards a man of reason, may, under Locke's fiercesome gloss on the law of nature, 'be treated as Beasts of Prey, those dangerous and noxious Creatures', destroyed 'for the same Reason, that he may kill a Wolf or a Lyon' (319-20). This is not the war of all against all, but the war of the righteous against those they perceive as attacking them: the language in which all colonial wars against native Americans have been justified.
There are different narratives available to explain the presence of that 'spontaneous hand of Nature' in the Second Treatise. According to one story it would be an unfortunate 'survival' from the language of classical humanism, with Locke seen as a transitional figure in a gradual movement towards that 'purer' language of calculation only fully articulated in The Wealth of Nations. Such stories of the progressive shedding of earlier rhetorical encumbrances sit comfortably with the Enlightenment's self-image. The story told here has had a different accent: on the implication of two discourses, the political and the colonial, both with their foundations in theories of natural law, but here articulated around a single nodal pointA
34 Peter Hulme the need to deny the existence of American Indian agriculture. The 'Enlightenment' argument of the Second Treatise is shadowed by that unconscious denial which serves to tether Locke's reasoning to historical and ideological circumstances beyond its conscious control. NOTES Relevant work on Locke (not already cited) would include Ashcraft 1968; Batz 1974; Lebovics 1986; Slavin 1976.
For the larger context of colonialism and Enlightenment see: Bitterli 1989; Duchet 1971; Dudley and Novak 1972; Franklin 1979; Hodgen 1971; Hulme 1986; Meek 1976; Solomon 1987; White 1972. For opportunities to discuss earlier versions of this essay, I would like to thank David Murray, Simon Barker, Valerie Fraser, and Anthony Pagden; and for her comments, Gesa Mackenthun.
3 Candide and native America GORDON BROTHERSTON
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION In 1578 Jean de Lery, a Calvinist minister, published an account of his year's stay (in 1556-7) amongst the Tupinamba of Brazil, inaugurating the modern tradition of ethnography that doubles as social criticism. Lery's account of the Tupinamba is scrupulous enough for Claude Levi-Strauss to refer to it as a 'masterpiece of anthropological literature' (1976: 102), yet it is inevitably coloured by the events of the intervening twenty years -which included the Saint Bartholomew Day's massacre of Protestants by French Catholics in 1572. For Lery the cannibalism of the Tupi is more understandable than the symbolic cannibalism of European usurers, and he reminds his readers how Catholic murderers had eaten Protestant hearts on the day of that infamous massacre. As a genuine traveller, Lery had the authority to make these kinds of comparisons, although he puts the strongest words into the mouth of an old Tupi man who is made to cross-question Lery with impressive skill about the reasons for the Europeans' presence in America. Even Montaigne (see above p. 24) allowed the last words of his essay to one of the Tupi he had interviewed in Rouen. The balance between ethnographic description and philosophical dialogue was a delicate one~ The Baron de Lahontan had travelled extensively in North America, yet his dialogue with the Huron Adario (published in 1703) is clearly a fictional representation of opposing viewpoints, a form brought to perfection later in the century by Denis Diderot - in Rameau's Nephew (written 1776-84) and in the Supplement to the Voyage of Bougainville (written 1772), which contains a fictional conversation between a French chaplain and a Tahitian called Orou, one of the most impressive examples of what has been called 'the savage critic' (Pagden 1983). Voltaire's Candide (1759) is a philosophical tale with no particular ethnographic pretensions, yet it is illuminated by setting it in the context of Lery and Lahontan, especially since Gordon Brotherston's essay restores a true sense of the centrality of
36 Gordon Brotherston the American utopia at the heart of Voltaire's story. Despite his one venture into the genre, which has a 'savage from Guiana' as the spokesman for common sense, Voltaire remained suspicious of the enthusiasm for savagery evinced by many of his fellow philosophes, so Cacambo - Candide's Amerindian guide - is not the true equivalent of Adario or Orou. None the less, Voltaire had a keen eye for examples of European infamy abroad, as with the Surinamese slave system anatomized in Candide; or at home, as in the torture and execution of the Protestant Jean Calas for the supposed ritual killing of his son, a verdict Voltaire was instrumental in having overturned. So 'the fourth part of our universe', as Voltaire himself called it, .could certainly provide a space in which to interrogate the prejudices and fixed ideas of eighteenth-century Europe. Of all Enlightenment writers Voltaire (1694-1778) had the most varied and extensive output. Poet, playwright, historian, satirist, author of the influential Lettres philosophiques sur les Anglais (1733), his greatest literary success came with his contes (especially Candide, one of the best-sellers of the period), small fictional crucibles in which Voltaire managed to precipitate almost all the important moral questions of his day, in marked contrast to the more discursive style of Rousseau and Diderot.
3
rrhe most celebrated of Voltaire's contes, Candide ou I'Optimisme [1759-61] has generally been read as what it announces itself to be, that is a satire of certain currents in Enlightenment thought, in particular the supposedly Leibnitzian doctrine of 'all is for the best, in the best of all possible worlds'. In line with this, more attention has on the whole been paid to the wit and sheer pace of the work than to such other literary qualities as structure or even character. It is after all commonplace to account for the eponymous hero and above all his philosophizing mentor Pangloss in the satirist's terms of cartoon or cardboard figure. Thrown out of the Westphalian paradise he shared with his first love Cunegonde he is literally propelled from one disaster to the next as he pursues her through half the known world, before finally coming to some kind of rest at the very end, in his Ottoman estate. Hence, references to the work as a 'relentless, unrelated torrent of mishaps' or 'the extraordinary and impossible piling up of events' (Auerbach 1953: 360, Thacker 1968: 12). If however we recover no more than a rudimentary feel for the landscape of Candide, for its progress through a mappable world, then the narrative comes readily to support a notion of structure, and indeed of definite stages in the hero's character development. For, as the text ceaselessly reminds us, we begin in a garden in north-west Europe, travel west to the New World and back again to the Old, to end up in another garden in south-east Europe. Each of these three parts of Candide's journey occupies more or less a third of the 33-chapter text. Occupying the central third in this scheme, the New World is distinguished by the fact that Candide sails there not pursuing but together with Cunegonde and confident that America may actually prove to be the much-invoked 'best of all possible worlds' ('It is certainly the new world that is the best of possible universes' ,. (Voltaire 1961: 35)). Moreover, before he goes there Candide is the passive object of abuse; after he comes back, his problems are more those of boredom and disillusion. In EI Dorado, at the half-way point or hinge ofthe American journey, which is also that of
38 Gordon Brotherston the journey overall, the relationship between hero and environment is turned on its head, so that he thinks of exploiting others rather than being simply or 'candidly' exploited by them. To this degree, and however unlikely the notion may at first seem, Candide in fact resembles such notorious 'americanos' of the period as Robinson Crusoe; that is, he is a European whose critical life-experience is profiting from America. For both heroes suffer shipwreck and vicissitude, encounter cannibals and other Amerindians of dubious human status, entrust themselves to Providence and get rich thanks to the Americas, and marry and end up with their own little estates back in the Old World. Far from being fortuitous, the parallel points us to an order of Americanism in the Enlightenment which has not always received from us the critical attention it deserves; it invokes a particular sense of that Fourth World of planetary history which Columbus added to the previous three. Voltaire announced his Americanism early on, in Alzire ou les americains (1736), a work which Chinard (1913: 236-8) signalled as one of the first American tragedies to appear in France. By taking themes popularized in the Indes galantes of Fuselier and Rameau and by making spoken drama of them, Voltaire here anticipated such New World monuments of the period as Marmontel's Les Incas (1777); but at no point does he effectively go beyond the parameters of his main source, Destruccion de las Indias (1552) by the Spanish historian and polemicist Fray Bartolome de las Casas. Then, at the other end of his writing career, in the 1760s, he approached America again, in contes like Candide (1759-61) and its sequel L'Ingenu (1767). This last tells how the candid hero with his Huron background sacrifices his freedom and his principles in order to come to terms with the corrupt society of metropolitan France. Between these terms, America preoccupied Voltaire in his vast Essai sur les moeurs et l'esprit des nations, begun in the 1740s, published in 1765 and then again complete with its 'Introduction' in 1769. In particular, this Introduction serves as a useful guide to the contes, in proposing 'the fourth part of our universe' as a fundamentally other term of comparison, the like of which no previous part could provide. From the Essai, too, we can trace how Voltaire grew in ethnographical awareness, despite his abiding hostility to Lafitau; author of the epoch-making Moeurs des sauvages americains (1724), Lafitau was also a Jesuit (Brumfitt 1966: 265). In Candide, the hero's local experience of native America falls, like the text as a whole, into three main stages. Geographically these correspond to a movement from the lowlands of South America into the highlands and back again, as we are taken successively to the Guarani missions, the mountain fastness of EI Dorado, and the estuaries of the Guianas. Historically, the intermediary remoteness of EI Dorado, the outpost in time of the Andean Inca and Chibcha, corresponds to the fact that it never belonged to the lowland realm of La France Antarctique which gave Montaigne so much food for thought, and of which French Guiana is a tiny remnant today. By turns these three stages of the narrative make their ideological points. The
Candide and native America 39 supposed sexual and (no surprise) eating habits of the 'savage' are used negatively to shore up received notions of the 'human'; a working socialism is doubted in principle in just the location where there has been most evidence for it historically; and when finally the question of human rights is raised it is not at all for the benefit of America's first settlers and native population but because of the imposed economy of African slaves. Of course, much of this is presented by Voltaire in the terms of satire and joke. It remains for us to say, at the expense of what and of whom. Over the three stages of his South American journey, Candide comes face to face \-vith a variety of characters who are indigenous to their place, that is, who are native Americans. And he does so in the company of a newly acquired man-servant, Cacambo, who is also a native, or at least three out offour parts of him are. Acitizen of Tucuman, a town in the north of what is now Argentina, and in the south of what was the Inca empire, Cacambo speaks Quechua, the language of that empire which continues to be spoken in northern Argentina today. He can also converse in Guarani which, with Tupi, once constituted the major language group of lowland South America and provided the basis of the lingua geral of Brazil. As a companion he is far more useful than Pangloss, not least because he knows how to talk the local language and hence smooths the path for his employer and defuses the parlous situations through which the narrative leads him. The constant presence of Cacambo, as a skilled guide and intermediary, means that Candide's experience of South America is doubly filtered from the start, not just by his own preconceptions but by the particular origins and formation of his guide. This filtering, a fine token of Voltaire's encyclopaedism, openly sets Candide apart in that line of individualist European explorers of America, stretching from the conquistador to the US pioneer, which, in writing out infrastructure, prefers direct interface between the I and the supposed unknown. In itself it argues for Voltaire's own greater faith in social interplay than in some concept of pure nature. In this respect it is significant that the need for a Cacambo becomes evident at the precise moment when Candide leaves European urban society for the first time. As Candide under threat of death dithers about whetber to quit Buenos Aires and abandon Cunegonde to the clutches of the imperious colonial governor Fernando d'lbaraa y Figueroa y Mascarenes y Lampoudos y Souza, Cacambo is suddenly as it were discovered and brought into the action (being said in retrospect to have travelled with them all from Cadiz): it is he who then finds the means for his master to flee into the American wilds. During the first stage of his journey, travelling north from Buenos Aires, Candide meets the Guarani who still make up the majority of Paraguay's population today. In French literature, these people had a long pedigree as 'savages' before Voltaire, one which is implicitly referred to in Candide. In addition to the then topical question of the Jesuit missions we have Voltaire's contribution to a long-standing French debate about South America and its inhabitants. Not long after Fran~ois I's invention of La France Antarctique, the Tupi-Guarani appeared in Montaigne's essay 'Of
40 Gordon Brotherston
Figure 7 1. M. Moreau. Ie jeune, engraved illustration for Rousseau's La Decouverte du nouveau monde (The Discovery of the New World). Rousseau wrote this opera libretto between 1739 and 1741. American themes were popular with Enlightenment writers: Rousseau. typically. went back to the original encounter, although this early work reads like an apologia for European colonialism. As they land on the island of Guanahan the Spaniards sing: 'Let us triumph, let us triumph on land and wave. I Let us give Laws to the Universe. I Through our daring we have, this day. discovered a new world. I It is made to bear our shackles.' Columbus is impressed by the courage of the Caribbean cacique, who is allowed to keep his throne. The cacique, equally impressed by the dignity and generosity of Columbus, volunteers to become a Spanish subject. Both sides join to sing the final chorus: 'Let us spread throughout the universe lOur treasure and our bounty. I Let us unite through our Alliance I Two worlds separated by the abyss of the seas.' For the text of the libretto. see Rousseau 1959-69. II: 810-41 (ef. Rex 1987: 94-8).
Candide and native America 41 the Caniballes', which was designed to refute the racism of Christian missionaries like Yves d'Evreux, and which praises their bravery and their anacreontic taste in poetry (Brotherston 1979: 48-50). In Voltaire's narrative, dealings with the Guarani fall into two sequences, and focus on those who had been incorporated into the Jesuit missions and then on those who had not. With the former a certain sympathy is shown, on the straight argument of social injustice: that the reverend fathers exploited the Indians for all they were worth. Claims that the missions represented communist bliss, paradise on this earth, are shown to be priestly hypocrisy. While the masters live in the most .splendid luxury, surrounded by colonnades and trellises alive with rare and brilliant birds, the Indian peasants labour in poverty and under the strictest surveillance. Exercising a devilish power over their native hordes, the reverend fathers aspire to rule a kingdom of their own, choosing a certain Nanguiru as the titular monarch: indeed it was just these developments which provided the reason for Candide's coming to America, as a captain in the army sent to crush the missions. In the first instance, this account of Guarani servitude corresponds more to hatred of the Jesuits than to sympathy with the natives, with people encountered in their own place and time. Evident from such details as there being not a word said about the certainly worse rapacity of the slavers who roamed the region, armed and backed by liberal financiers in Europe, this general attitude towards the Guarani is corroborated when we pass on to those members of the nation who have succeeded in retaining some polity and territory of their own. For now that we go beyond the frontier fence of the missions, even the human nature of these creatures is thrown into question, by the depiction of both their sexual and their table manners (the title of chapter 16 is 'What Happened to the Two Travelers with Two Girls, Two Monkeys, and the Savages Called Oreillons'(48)). The women, it is suggested, take monkeys as lovers and, full of natural sentiment and compassion, even cry over them when they are killed, by Candide. As for the men, they are the ones honoured with the lead role as cannibals, devourers of their own species, the dread would-be eaters of human flesh, in this case Candide's. Now both these aspects of 'wild' or untamed Guarani life carry a message that can be readily decoded in terms of the history of Western ideas./The monkey business has normally been understood as a dig at Rousseau and at contemporary arguments based on the 'natural' affections of savages who characteristically were American. In addition, like the cooking-pot into which Candide was to be put, it can be said to echo an exactly eighteenth-century concern with species definition and genetic taxomony, as the Biblical guarantee for man's image began to lose all coherence; in Voltaire, this concern is evidenced elsewhere, in his remarks in the Essai about an Egyptian woman stated by Herodotus to have behaved just as Candide feared the Guarani maidens would. The particular frisson of the cooking-pot of the would-be cannibals (which term, of course, derives etymologically from the American Carib) is perhaps best understood in terms of Christian philosophy and the centrality of the words 'take, eat, this is my flesh ...', a possibility anticipated with horror by early missionaries in America.
42 Gordon Brotherston What remains less clear is how these Guarani monkey-lovers and man-eaters fit into Voltaire's overall satire. They obviously constitute a disillusion for Candide who not so long ago had been sailing to the New World with a Rousseau-esque faith in the likely virtues of its inhabitants, or at least the belief that he was going somewhere else. Yet we are somehow made to feel that this is not the main point, that we ought to have suspected all along that native Americanism of such naivety was bound to be misplaced anyway. And Voltaire's main prop in getting such a view across is the great mediator Cacambo, who here truly comes into his own. Knowing something of the local 'jargon', that is to say Guarani rather than Quechua, Cacambo is able to save Candide's life by appealing to his captors. He appeals specifically to their reason and innate sense of justice, a principle apparently extended here even to the proto-society of the Guarani with its strange manners and different taboos. Then later he explains sardonically to Candide that after all monkeys are one quarter human just as he is one quarter Spanish; and that anthropophagy, being less of a moral problem than murder, should not be divorced from such practical questions as food supply. There is here a veiled irreverence, that effectively takes to new lengths Voltaire's satire of the received morality of Christendom, no less than of Rousseau's faith in purely natural man. At the same time, and as if by sleight of hand, writer and reader are thereby neatly enabled to circumvent the heavier ideological charge implicit in the image of the Guarani. For as quasi-animals these people can no more than roam their 'roadless' land devoid of territorial rights, a point of no less significance in the history of European colonialism than Queen Isabel of Spain's device of dispossessing unwanted American natives by categorizing them as cannibals (on this, see Hulme 1986: 13-44). Yet while Cacambo's world-view doubtless draws on his particular experience as an American, he is made to deny any commitment to his place of origin. No sooner have they escaped from the unsettling company and conversation of the Guarani than Cacambo urges Candide to return to Europe, since 'this hemisphere is no better than the other' (52). In other words, and as if prophylactically before Candide has the chance to acquire further experience of the New World, Voltaire raises the prospect of difference only to withdraw it. These possible dimensions of the text become more sharply defined in Candide's subsequent experience of America, among the descendants of the Inca, whose empire extended throughout most of the Andean highlands at the time of the European invasion. The Inca or EI Dorado sequence in chapters 17 and 18 stands out from the narrative as a whole on several counts. It is the one point where the travellers can be felt to leave the actual landscape, and where the human society they encounter has decidedly fantastic features; and for this reason it has been customarily excised from· geography and assigned to the realm of the fairy-tale. Against this, it should be recalled that right up to Voltaire's day EI Dorado was still being confidently placed on maps, usually in the unsubdued and mysterious common watershed of the Amazon and the Orinoco first explored from the outside
Candide and native America 43 forty years later, by Alexander von Humboldt; and that a direct historical link was perceived between this place and the gold-working populations who inhabited the Andes under Inca rule (Swan 1958: 271-81; Hemming 1978). Moreover, the very notion of later Inca history was one that had considerable resonance for the Enlightenment, and that found military and political expression not just in Tupac Amaru II'S great rising in 1780 but in rhetoric like that of the English Prime Minister Pitt, who in all seriousness proposed the restoration of the Inca monarchy to his fellow parliamentarians. Hence, there was in Voltaire's day at least a notional context for the very old man (172 years of age) who actually remembers how he and fellow Inca fled to the mountain fastness of El Dorado to save what they could of their culture from European greed. In any case what Candide learns about the basic economics of El Dorado, its system of roads, public hostelries, metal working, impeccably tilled fields, and thriving flocks, accords quite well with what can be known about the Inca state from sources that were available to Voltaire, like the Comentanos reales (1617) of Garcilaso de la Vega, previously drawn on in Alzire (known as El Inca, Garcilaso was the son of an Inca princess). Voltaire even picks out, as Marmontel does in Les Incas, the characteristics of actual Inca hymns, that they thank rather than implore, and by invoking the sun as enlightenment vindicate what the Essai calls the 'budding reason' of the Peruvians. Again, he effectively draws attention to the uniqueness of Inca pastoralism within native America, by transforming Inca llamas into very large sheep that travel at immense speed pulling coaches behind them; a possible allusion to Montaigne's other Americanist essay, on coaches, this exaggerated detail of Inca life likewise appears in the Essai. In terms of Candide's own progress or development as a character, the El Dorado chapters stand out of course because here, for the first and only time in the story, evil becomes something not external and environmental, imposed as in the blow of aggression, disease, or upper-class boredom, but internal and psychic, the result of inner prompting and intimate nature. There is nothing wrong with this society of native Americans who hold fast to pre-Hispanic ways. Indeed it exudes the very virtues, of justice, pleasure, and intelligence, that Voltaire spent his life extolling and fighting for. On the planetary scale, and in that initially Enlightenment view of the world 'from China to Peru', it epitomizes a continent whose wealth eclipses that of Asia, Europe, and Africa put together, and whose excellence France and Europe are no match for. For once Candide and Cacambo manage to be termed 'happy'; and they are even said to recognize that they may after all have found the 'best of all possible worlds', the Optimist dream which in principle the narrative is dedicated to satirizing. As Candide says, with the advantage of hindsight: 'Certainly if all is well it is in Eldorado and not in the rest of the world' (63). Yet perversely the pair decide to leave: 'The two happy men resolved to be so no longer' (58). Candide's reasons for going are a murky mixture of imagined yearning for Cunegonde and the desire, incisively diagnosed by Pascal and Rousseau (Cassirer 1951: 135-61), to shine and boast and be seen to be rich among those he
44 Gordon Brotherston -~"
-~OA ole/ DORADO,. -~-
..=
---...
.
Figure 8 Sixteenth-century map of El Dorado.
had left behind; which amounts to a synthesis of medieval plus nascent bourgeois patterns of self-delusion appropriate to Candide's condition as a European. Only later at the end of the tale, in a privately-owned garden rather than as the citizen of an entire state, and at the old Asian or eastern end of Europe rather than in the new western World, will he finally break through that delusion in order to settle, in the sense of resign himself. But what about Cacambo? For Cacambo, in addition to all the good experienced and rejected by Candide, finding El Dorado is like coming home. There, everyone speaks his mother tongue: 'Cacambo ... heard them speaking Peruvian; it was his mother tongue' (54); and they embody a history and ways of behaviour otherwise distorted or suppressed under European rule in America. However, the local understanding which had served to distinguish him from Candide when among the Guarani now entirely vanishes. Apart from the fact that he speaks Quechua, in every response and reaction to El Dorado he becomes indistinguishable from his master: there is the same surprise, the same faux pas, the same radical ignorance. And finally he is just as keen to leave. By giving this particular twist to Cacambo's character, and by giving El Dorado its fairy-tale gloss, Voltaire appears to be making quite sure that no one should confuse his philosophy with the order of Americanism found in such predecessors as Montaigne; and that Europe should remain the only serious arena and term of reference in philosophical debate.
Candide and native America 45 This reading of the American chapters in Candide is amply confirmed by what happens during the last part of the hero's journey. For after stating his binary version of bestial Guarani versus utopian Quechua, Voltaire appears to exhaust whatever interest he may have had in the original inhabitants of the New World. From now on the natives vanish from the landscape altogether, as Candide and Cacambo descend the rivers towards the Guyanas and the northwest coast of South America. Exactly the same thing happens in the Essai, when Voltaire for once chooses to focus specifically on 'America', as opposed to use it sporadically as ammunition in his polemics. Ignoring the 'high' civilizations of the Incas and the . Mexicans,and contradicting what he has previously said about how intelligently the American 'savages' provide for themselves, how deeply they feel for the land made theirs through the presence of their ancestors' bones, and how fiercely they defend their freedom, he ends up telling us testily that America was never populous, has land that was socially inimical and poison-producing, and that 'nature had given the Americans a far less industrious spirit than it had the men of the Old World' (in fact, as Levi-Strauss has pointed out, the record of Americans as generators of food and in turning poisons to good use is unrivalled in human history: see Brotherston 1986). Sparse and lazy, such people could never be expected to hold the attention of a sophisticated European for long. To be exact, in Candide the Indians do not so much vanish as are displaced by another people, the Africans brought to work as sugar slaves. Significantly, the enemy and the source of evil now become again easier to identify. As the pair of travellers listen to the African who has been atrociously abused by Vanderdendur, the whole abhorrent system of European-run oppression is exposed to the reader, in the terms of political and economic oppression applied to the Jesuit missions but here taken to far greater lengths. It is as if Voltaire here gathers all the indignation which might have been (but never was) previously expressed on behalf of the true native Americans of the piece, whose suffering and expropriation began with Columbus and continues today, on a continental scale unparalleled in the history of the planet. In short, Voltaire discovers his Americanism in Black rather than Indian, setting a pattern for such literary successors as Rene Chateaubriand, who though he began Les Natchez as a passionate defence of Lousiana Indians massacred by the French in 1730, soon preferred the African as term of reference, or James Fenimore Cooper, whose Oak Openings actually suggests that oppressed US blacks should be recompensed with Indian land (Brotherston 1985). As Jack Forbes has intimated in his masterful Black Africans andNative Americans (1988), the underlying reason for all this cannot be divorced from the fact that over the centuries the history of Blacks in America has fitted more readily than that of the Indians into western capitalism's scheme of economy and hence morality. In this analysis of Voltaire's Candide, the argument has been made that, once due attention is paid to the location of the narrative, much clearer insight may be gained into the 'character' of the eponymous hero, especially in his relationship with Cacambo. Not just that, but the New World gains in clarity as a notional alternative
46 Gordon Brotherston to the Old, in political and even economic terms. To this extent, the narrative may be said to possess a latent Americanism which critics have taken little notice of. Within this geographical dimension, however, strict limits are imposed: far more explicit in the self-contradictory ethnography of the Essai sur les moeurs, these curtail from the start any notion of the great American Indian revolution taken up in the twentieth century by such writers as D. H. Lawrence and Antonin Artaud. An indispensable means of setting the limits is provided by Candide's guide to America, Cacambo, who both is and is not a child of his continent and culture. Chief among the consequent effects is the psychic displacement of outrage, in matters of territorial displacement and genocide, from the native American victim to the African. In short, rather than functioning as the prime dream which our science is only now beginning to decipher, for Voltaire the fourth world signifies at best only in addition.
4 Music in the Enlightenment JOE ALLARD
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION This paper, in its focus on the early Enlightenment, illustrates a number of important themes that recur throughout the book. It reveals, for example, how music was both embedded in its historical context and intellectually bound to areas such as natural philosophy, mathematics, literature, theology and so on. Understanding this makes it easier to see how changes in musical theory and practice could be so similar to changes in other fields. In fact, Joe Allard's claim goes far further than this. There were, he shows, certain core issues that united aesthetics, natural philosophy and music. The relationships between reason and the passions, between mind and body, between ancients and moderns, between texts and other forms of communication were all central to the lively debates about music in seventeenth-century Europe. The centrality of mathematics for music and the pervasiveness of the macrocosm/microcosm analogy signal the persistence of a shared intellectual framework. Nor should the history of music during the Enlightenment be divorced from its social setting. Music was a field where patronage wgs essential, and, in seventeenthcentury France the art of patronage was practised above all by the state. Louis XIV and his chief ministers, especially Colbert, were keen on state-run academies. These created, perpetuated and rewarded the elites of many fields, they ensured their indebtedness to the crown and they harnessed the interests of elites to those of the state. It is hardly surprising then to find that questions of national identity, indeed of national style, occupied the minds of musicians and politicians in both seventeenthand eighteenth-century France. Nowhere was this more evident than in the case of opera, where the distinctive qualities of the French and Italian languages were as much an issue as musical styles. Music was also entertainment as well as an intellectual and political activity. As such its effects on listeners were a matter of some moment. Thus we can see how
48 Joe Allard music could raise ethical and moral issues. As a result, certain general features of the Enlightenment are pointed up. The concern with the effect of the arts generally, music could raise ethical and moral issues. As a result, certain general features of the Enlightenment are pointed up. The concern with the effect of the arts generally, and especially the theatre, was characteristic of much eighteenth-century thought. One reason is that a movement of ideas that strives to create a new and more rational order has to address the question of social cohesion and social control. In the more mature Enlightenment these questions become more pressing as the corruption and depravity of ancien regimes was increasingly evident. The culmination of all this occurred in the French Revolution, as Margaret Iversen's paper in this volume reveals. The comparison with her paper is also apt because musical theory and art theory shared some important features. In both cases, for example, the relationship with the written language was debated. Indeed, it was because words were so much a part of both music and art that moral and ethical matters could be raised so directly. It is surely significant that in one of the greatest of all Enlightenment texts, Rameau's Nephew, Diderot subversively mixes debates about music, manners, and morality, all of which serve to advance his challenging interrogation of the nature of human identity.
4
It was in seventeenth-century France that all the foundations for Enlightenment music practice, theory, and commentary were laid. The century between the 1580s and 1680s witnessed some of the most revolutionary alterations in musical perception that have ever occurred and these correspond to changes in most other areas of western thought. Although it is probably a popular notio,n that the essence of Enlightenment music can be heard in Mozart, especially, at the end of the eighteenth century, the first real pinnacle, at least of early Enlightenment music, is in the orchestra and operas of Jean Baptiste Lully. In the 1670s and 1680s he produced a series of lyrical tragedies (tragedies-lyriques) which combined the new seventeenthcentury harmonic tonality - the basis of what we call Baroque - new types of song, and elements of both French and Italian styles of music. These works were greeted as great triumphs of 'modern' music, and sound, finally, the death knell of the musical humanist venture of recovering ancient music. They are the endorsement of the modern style of music that would find its final fulfilment in the eighteenth century in the work of J. S. Bach.
HARMONY OF THE SPHERES Until the Enlightenment - and since antiquity - music had had the elevated status of one of the Quadrivium. Its credentials \vere impeccable with such theorists as Pythagoras, Plato, Aristotle, Chrysostum, Augustine and Ficino, and such practitioners as Orpheus, David, Amphion, Timotheus and St Cecilia. Repeated and commented upon time and again over these years was a canon of stories celebrating extravagant claims of music's powerful effects upon all of creation from angels (St Cecilia) to emperors (Alexander and Timotheus) to animals and trees (Orpheus) to stones (Amphion). Wedded to this was an unbroken tradition of theosophic metaphysical music theory.
50 Joe Allard Fundamental to all of these notions was the Ptolemaic universe in which the earth was in the centre of a series of ever-larger crystalline spheres. To these were attached the moon, sun, planets, and fixed stars. They were intelligences for the ancients; angels for such as Dante and Ficino. Finally, beyond all, was the creator, for Plato; or God, for the Christians. Everything above the earth was fixed, eternal, perfect - and harmonious. Musica Mundana was not simply a metaphor, but a conviction that the entire universe was in a state of constant and powerful rllusic. Here, alas, in this sub-lunar realm of corruption and mutability we cannot hear it. In Lorenzo's words from The Merchant of Venice: How sweet the moonlight sleeps upon this bank! Here will we sit and let the sounds of music Creep in our ears; soft stillness and the night Become the touches of sweet harmony. Sit, Jessica. Look how the floor of heaven Is thick inlaid with patens of bright gold. There's not the smallest orb which thou behold'st But in his motion like an angel sings, Still quiring to the young-eyed cherubins; Such harmony is in immortal souls, But whilst this muddy vesture of decay Doth grossly close it in, we cannot hear it. (V.i. 54-65)
Although our 'vesture of decay' renders the harmony of the spheres inaudible to us in this world, thinkers chronologically as far apart as Pythagoras and the young Marin Mersenne doubted neither the profound power of music nor the possibility that we might be able to imitate, in our own terms, on our own instruments, the universal harmony. And with almost incalculable results morally, politically, and socially. What happened to these traditional and quite beautiful theories is that the universe collapsed at the end of the sixteenth century. The element of fire was quite put out. The observation, research, and conjectures of Copernicus, Galileo, and Kepler undermined the principal suppositions and tenets of universal organization and, consequently, everything which was based upon it. My comments are hyperbolic, of course. Such changes in philosophy, science, and the arts are always more complex and more gradual; and those who contribute to such changes can seldom be conscious of large-scale, retrospectively perceived shifts of this nature. The fact remains, however, that the early decades of the seventeenth century, the beginnings of what we call the Enlightenment, saw profound changes in musical theory and practice that correspond with revolutionary changes in other realms of thought and action. The central early Enlightenment thinker about music was humanist and natural philosopher Marin Mersenne. He stood at the crossroads between sixteenth-century
Music in the Enlightenment 51
Figure 9 The universe according to Ptolemy. Ptolemaic cosmology from the Harmonia Macrocosmica of Andreas Cellarius, 1660.
metaphysical musical humanism, to which he gave his blessing in Celebrated Questions About Genesis of 1623, and the gradual acceptance of mechanistic principles, which are increasingly obvious in his correspondence with Descartes, and clearly manifest in his Universal Harmony of 1636. By 1640 hehad rejected metaphysical musical humanism entirely and described the actions and effects of music upon us in terms of empirical principles inspired by Descartes. In the Questions Mersenne described with praise the beliefs and activities of the Academie de Poesie et de Musique, granted a royal charter by Charles IX in 1570. Led by Jean Antoine de Baif and Joachim Thibault de Courville, the group was dedicated to the musical humanist goal of the recovery of ancient music and, with it, the powerful ethical and physical effects described by commentators since antiquity. Writing half a century later, Mersenne could see the hopes and goals of these early academicians clearly - and with sympathy; but he also increasingly came to see the impracticalities, indeed impossibilities, of their pursuit. Baif and Thibault accepted
52 Joe Allard the traditional view that music was a crucial part of the encyclopaedia of knowledge; that is, all of our knowledge considered as an integrally related unity. THE HUMANIST QUEST The members of BaWs Academie, in Mersenne's words, 'did not wish to bring in a new kind of music, unless you call that new when something is restored to wholeness, but wished to recover those effects, which, as we read, were once produced by the Greeks.... For they hoped to exhilarate the depressed spirit, to reduce the over-elated spirit to modesty, and to stir themselves to other feelings by their own music.' The result of recovering ancient Greek music would be to 'drive barbarism from Gaul' and to form 'the manners of youth to everything honourable'. This high moral aim of the Academie had a political side for Charles IX, whose monarchy was threatened by imminent religious civil war. In his Letters Patent for the Academie, the king expressed his awareness of the opinions of many great personages, both ancient legislators and philosophers ... that it is of great importance for the morals of the citizens of a town that the music current and used in the country should be retained under certain laws, for the minds of most men are formed and their behaviour influenced by its character, so that where music is disordered, there morals are also depraved, and where it is well ordered, there men are well disciplined morally. (Yates 1947: 56,64, 78-9) The ideas which inspired the French humanists were ultimately Platonic, although they were tinctured by a Neoplatonism that came to them from Marsilio Ficino, via Pontus de Tyard, who, like Baif, was a member of the ?leiade and, through his knowledge of Ficino, the main spokesman for Platonism and the effects of ancient music in later sixteenth-century France. Four principal assumptions underlay the musical humanist movement. First, proper musical effects were thought to result from the correct relationship between the elements of vocal music: poetry, rhythm, and mode. In France only was dance added to the list. It was believed that it was the subject of the text and the words, with their innate rhythms, that were of prime importance and that dictated the creation of melody and dance. Second, it was felt that man-made music gained its power because the text of the verse spoke directly to the mind, and the rhythm and harmony echoed, or reproduced the harmony of the spheres. Deriving from the same source as the universe, man was a microcosmic image of it. In its most perfect form, music imitated not only the macrocosm but could lead the listener to God. Third, the music created here might form a channel between our own harmony and that of the universe because of fundamental relationships between microcosm and macrocosm. Fourth, since music is potentially so powerful, it is necessary to control its composition and use. Music could be a useful tool for the security of the state. Proof of this was taken to be Plato's description of Egypt in The Laws as a society in
Music in the Enlightenment 53 which music was strictly regulated, and which had known stability for ten thousand years. It was in the interest of the state not just to cultivate music, but to legislate to control it. The three main avenues of research were into the identification of the ancient modes, into vvays to subordinate the music to the verse, and into the character and creation of proper rhythm. Everyone felt that the proper mode, and its accurate employment, were part of the motive force behind any ethical effect. And because the stories had been told for so long and repeated so often, the effect was not necessarily a single nor simple thing. Agood literary example of the sophistication of modal theory is from the 1660s. In Paradise Lost John Milton has Satan's fallen host move towards Pandemonium: In perfect Phalanx to the Dorian mood Of Flutes and soft Recorders; such as rais'd To highth of noblest temper Hero's old Arming to Battel, and in stead of rage Deliberat valour breath'd, firm and unmov'd With dread of death to flight or foul retreat; Nor wanting power to mitigate and swage With solemn touches, troubl'd thoughts, and chase Anguish and doubt and fear and sorrow and pain From mortal or immortal minds. Thus they Breathing united force with fixed thought Mov'd on in silence to soft Pipes that charmd Thir painful steps ore the burnt soile.... (Book I, 550-62) The problem was the proper identification of each ecclesiastical Renaissance mode with its ancient namesake. European opinion was divided: the mode that some believed to be the Dorian was held by others to be the Phrygian, and so on through the modal series. This was a worry because very particular effects were associated with each mode. The danger in error was that if one were to compose a work in the Dorian mode, intending to lead the listener to serene understanding and good citizenship, one might, by mistaking the mode and composing in the Phrygian, arouse warlike and active emotions. The endeavour to subordinate music to verse considered both the expression of the sense of the words and the audibility of the text. The sense of the word always took precedence over more purely musical concerns. This clearly suggests certain values the humanists attached to artistic expression. Their desire was to make music more significant. Pure music, often called 'harmony', was thought to be meaningless; hence the almost universal rejection of sixteenth-century polyphony, which sacrificed verbal meaning to musical sound. The word was the mirror of reason. It could produce significant sound and affect the mind. In this way music becomes a philosophical discipline, rather than an artform for the senses. The only
54 Joe Allard
way music could reach the mind was to imitate the spoken word, to become inseparably attached to language. All innovation would be for nothing, though, if the listener could not make out the words. The dense contrapuntal polyphony of the earlier sixteenth century was anathema, but what to replace it with presented the choice of a single voice with instrumental accompaniment in counterpoint, monody, or homophony. The more purist of the humanists in both France and Italy (Galileo's father was one of these) argued for either the first or second of these as genuinely classical, using a cornbination of ancient sources and a priori reasoning. Everyone agreed that homophony was a modern development. It was on this issue in particular that the great Ancients and Moderns debate of the Enlightenment would focus. Most theorists, and virtually all composers, felt that modern music's exploitation of the possibilities of harmony, even if excessive in the madrigal, was a good thing. They wanted to retain elements of modern harmony, but to reform music for greater audibility of the text. The answer was the homophonic style in which three or four voices could sing different melodies and create pleasing harmonic intervallic relationships but, sounding simultaneously, preserve the integrity of the word. To achieve this, strict rhythmic control was necessary. One of the main efforts of Baif and his colleagues was the search for ways to use rhythm as a means to subordinate music to words. It was through rhythm in particular, they felt, that 'meaning and sound, poetry and music, came together in perfect rapport to work the wonders reported of Amphion, Orpheus, Pythagoras, Timotheus and others. And both poets and musicians thought that it would be through a reformed rhythm that modern music would re-unite sense and sound in order to achieve again the ancient wonders (Mace 1964: 261). In spite of this conviction about the potential power of rhythm, there is surprisingly little detailed discussion about which rhythmic pattern might produce which emotion. One explanation for this silence is the enormity of such a classifying task. To categorize and systematize the rhythmic ethos of each surviving Greek and Latin poem was too vast and complex a job. Another, more helpful answer is that the humanists imagined that the source of all musical effects, both rhythmic and harmonic, resided in number. Hence rhythmic proportions were to be found in the reason rather than in the passions. The same mathematical proportions that produced 'harmony' formed the rational basis of rhythm. In Questions Mersenne discussed metric feet as though they were harmonic intervals. Accordingly the word, like the music, has harmonic proportions. The musician could best achieve his goal of. retrieving ancient ethical effects by re-fusing the proportions inherent in the verse to the proportions of the music. Music successfully composed according to this theory would restore the balance between body and soul, and bring good proportion into the listener's life.
Music in the Enlightenment 55 DESCARTES AND MERSENNE Mersenne maintained his enthusiasm for music throughout his life, including his belief that good music is beneficial to the individual, and that its study ought to be included in academic pursuits. By the 1630s, however, he had decided that musical rhythms correspond to the passions and have little to do with reason. The rational order of effects, central to Renaissance humanism, was abandoned in favour of a study of relations between poetic and musical rhythms and the passions. Between 1629 and 1635 when his Harmonic Questions About the Nature of Sounds appeared, Mersenne was in regular correspondence with Descartes, who had published his youthful Musical Compendium in 1618. The Compendium itself is little more than an ordinary music handbook, much of the theory derived from the Venetian composer and writer Zarlino. However, through his other comments about music, and his ofher works of philosophy, Descartes played an important role in the development of Enlightenment ideas about music. He never produced a complete aesthetic because he believed an internal union between art, history, and philosophy was impossible. Any attempt at a valid system would prove futile. It is possible, however, to piece together a reasonably clear picture of his musical ideas. He felt, first of all, that music had the same qualities as mathematics. The most beautiful music was clear and direct. The simpler the ratios between tones, the more consonant the sound. Aesthetic truth resided in our rational faculties. Beauty resulted from proportion, regularity and symmetry. The most perfect music was the 'truest' (in terms of mathematical perfection). Musical 'truth' was founded in, and judged by, the reason. Judgement about the 'truth' of music might be the business of reason, but music's immediate effect was on the passions. In The Passions of the Soul, the body is described as a machine which responds to the forces of animal spirits upon the pineal gland. The passions and their expressions are like physical reflexes, responding immediately and necessarily to changes in the body. The richness and variety of the passions reside in this immediateness. One important function of music was to give us a pleasurable leisure, an elevated form of amusement. From the inescapable physical passions, stimulated by rhythms, he moved to intellectual passions which can produce intellectual joy - one of the highest forms of our existence. Without this progression from physical passion to intellectual passion and joy, life would be arid and banal. Descartes' theory of the soul's passions was of paramount importance to seventeenth-century music theory and commentary. His other ideas about music were much more fluid and were a good example of the intellectual ferment during the early decades of the century. Throughout his correspondence with Mersenne, he altered or abandoned certain principles he had put forward earlier. For example, he thought, early on, that consonance of sound was the most beautiful because mathematically the simplest. Later, however, he admitted to Mersenne that dissonance might give just as much pleasure. The agreeableness of a musical sound is a matter
56 Joe Allard for the listener's taste; it is subjective. His early view that there might exist universally determinable standards goes by the board. He had also thought, at first, that it might be possible to find correspondence between the passions and particular musical intervals or rhythms, but arrived, finally, at the conclusion that 'it is impossible to determine by any precise method a rapport between acoustic phenomena and phenomena of the mind' (Racek 1930: 297). Like Descartes, Mersenne became less and less interested in the ancients and humanist concerns and, in his later work, came to view the effects of music as result·ing from a relationship between rhythm and human passions. Throughout his Universal Harmony one can detect disillusion with his old faith in the ancients accompanied by an increasing approval of modern music. In the 'Second Book of String Instruments' he discusses a humanist question related to tuning methods described by Ptolemy. He suggests that the reader have confidence in modern methods 'so that the too great respect borne by some of us for the ashes of the Greeks may not throw us into a perpetual distrust of our proficiency and in despair at arriving at as great a perfection of harmony as that which they practised' (Mersenne 1957: 99). In the 'Sixth Book of the Organ' he discusses the question of adding extra keys to the manual in order to capture the entire range of temperament. Although he had said in Questions that the state ought to legislate about musical matters, he seems now to question if music can have such a vast effect: if the observance of the laws should depend on the intervals of music, and if they were to cause the changing of habit and good customs, as it seems the ancients believed, one would have reason to doubt whether it would be expedient or whether it be pern1itted to add some new keys to the organ keyboards, since we read that they banished those who would add new strings to instruments. But experience has not yet shown that this augmentation of strings or keys would be prejudicial to the state or to its mores.... (Mersenne 1636:' III, heading to Proposition XII, my translation) In addition to this new tendency to flavour his readings of classical sources with a few grains of salt, we find discussions of musical rhythm that demonstrate his acceptance of Descartes' theory of the effects of music on the passions. As a priest, Mersenne's aim in his work remained predominantly moral throughout his career, but now he hoped to achieve his goal of religious awakening through a music that, via rhythmic modulation, appealed to the passions, rather than, as he had felt, addressed the reason by modal or harmonic means. In the 'Embellissment' to the 'Second Book of Chants' he included a section concerned with musical accent, which raises questions about the effect of rhythm on the passions. He states that 'each passion and affection of the soul has its proper accent.' Unlike the humanist conception of rhythm, which was mathematically exact and related to reason's awareness of proportion, the rhythm discussed by Mersenne imitates the actual shape of particular passions. The passions respond mechanically and immediately. By 1640 Mersenne can be seen to have abandoned almost entirely all his human-
Music in the Enlightenment 57 ist beliefs about music and to have adopted an aesthetic that was subjective and mechanistic, which looked to music to offer man a little pleasure in a life certain to be tinged with bitterness. In November of that year he defined the role of music to the Dutch poet Constantin Huygens as 'particularly and principally to charm the spirit and the ear, and to help us pass life with a little sweetness amidst the troubles we will encounter.' In reference to the wonderful effects of ancient music he admitted that 'it is difficult to be persuaded of them in the absence of experience of them.' Ancient music probably did not really excite anger or other strong emotions, but was used, as modern music ought to be, to 'refresh the spirit of the listeners, and perhaps lead them to devotion'. The role of music is to lighten somewhat our burden in life, to lead us gently towards devotion, to please us with its harmonies and rhythms. Music exists to 'charmer l'esprit et l'oreille' (Mersenne 1932-72: X, 236-49). ITALIAN AND FRENCH PRACTICE In practical terms the early seventeenth century saw a revolution and a birth. The revolution was a sea-change in the conception of musical space from traditional modality, which was often densely polyphonic, to new harmonic notions that made practical use of the tonic-dominant relationship in the triad and was homophonic and contrapuntal. The birth was of opera. Its creation was directly related to the research of Florentine humanists in their search for an effective declamatory style of singing. The new recitative style was first heard in Jacopo Peri's La Dafne in 1597. His aim, simply, was to reproduce a musical play in the Greek manner as he understood it from traditional sources such as Aristotle. Peri's L'Euridice was performed in Florence in 1600 to celebrate the marriage of Marie de Medici to Henry IV, whence influential reports of this novel form of noble entertainment reached France. From then until the 1660s French monarchs and their ministers, most notably Mazarin, tried with little success to Italianize French culture. They were frustrated largely because of the wide gulf between French and Italian styles of music, and because of a strong bias toward ballet in French court entertainments that would hold sway for two-thirds of the century. Passion, emotional expressiveness, and melody characterized Italian music; rhythm and rational subtlety characterized French. The Italian composer carefully developed his melody which was then lavishly embellished by the performer. Opera provided many opportunities for the expression of violent emotions; a criticism often levelled in France was of unnecessary extravagance. French music, on the contrary, was soft and undemonstrative. Rhythmic subtlety was of most importance. The best song was simple, direct, and graceful; it should please and divert. The exaggerated liveliness of Italian singing, especially when done by the freakish castrati, seemed shocking and crude to the French. Throughout the century there were efforts made to reconcile the two, as when Mersenne enjoined French composers to adopt Italian elements of style to give
58 Joe Allard more buoyancy to their soft, understated air de cour. Such pleas met with increasingly little success, and finally with hostility, socially and politically, as Colbert generated nationalistic fervour at the expense of foreigners in general after 1662. Like Richelieu before him, Mazarin saw the political capital in keeping potentially bored and dangerous aristocrats engaged with large-scale performances of ballet and opera to divert attention from his plots and intrigues. Until his death in 1661 he brought a series of large-scale Italian operas to France. In 1645, for example, Sacrati's Finta Pazza was successfully staged. The success, however, was from neither the music nor the singing of the castrati, but from the fabulous and intricate ·stage machinery designed by Torelli. Time and again Mazarin's lavishly expensive productions were popular for the wrong reasons. His final bid to shore up the Italian faction was a performance of Cavalli's Ercole Amante staged in 1662 to celebrate the marriage of Louis XIV and the Infanta Maria Teresa. Agreat success, ironically it sounded the death knell for Italian opera in France. Inserted between the songs and acts of the six-hour marathon were huge ballets composed and choreographed by Italian-born Jean Baptiste Lully. Ballet had always been closer to the French heart than opera, and the court accepted Ercole Amante as an enormous ballet with dramatic interludes. Mazarin had died in 1661, and so missed this reversal. Colbert, his successor, set out to nationalize French taste; his ambition was towards a genuinely French opera. The man who turned the trick was Lully, who had come to France, at fourteen, in 1646. He entered the service of the young Louis XIV in 1652, then rose inexorably in musical prestige, first as violinist, then as composer, choreographer, and conductor. By 1661 he was superintendent of all the king's music. He ran the king's orchestra like a tyrant until it became the envy of Europe and prototype for all future orchestras. Until 1672 he devoted his energies and innovative orchestral techniques to ballet alone. From the 1650s until the 1680s he produced ballets with Benserade. In 1663 he began his collaboration with Moliere in their new comedieballet. A sensitive political animal, Lully became more closely associated with the French faction in the cultural struggle of the 1660s, although before that, both because of birth and style, he had been associated with the Italian. Even though as late as 1670 he had believed opera impossible to compose inthe French language, it was at his hands, in a subtle fusion of certain Italian and certain French stylistic characteristics, that the immensely popular and influential tragedie-lyrique was first created in 1673. In certain ways this evolved through the idiom of comedie-ballet which Moliere saw as a way to extend the appeal of his plays and to bring ballet closer to dramatic unification. Moliere and Corneille wrote the plots; Lully composed the music and, with Quinault, wrote the lyrics. Through this experience Lully developed the French recitative by Italianizing the air de cour from the ballet. It became more passionate and less rhythmically restricted. His disciplined orchestra was perfect for the rhythmic French style. The songs and choruses of the ballet, however, leaned toward the expressive Italian bel canto. Lully was, in fact, not the first to compose
Music in the Enlightenment 59 opera in French. Robert Cambert and Pierre Perrin had been given a royal charter in 1669 to develop French opera in the newly opened Academie Royale de Musique. Their Pomone was performed in 1671. The ~cademie, however, was disastrously mismanaged and, always one with an eye to the main chance, Lully managed to manipulate a new royal charter to himself in 1672. From then, with Quinault as his usual librettist, he produced a series of tragedies-lyriques, beginning with Cadmus et Hermione in 1673 and continuing at the rate of one a year until 1686. The plots provided by Quinault were consciously in the manner of Corneille and Racine, masters of French tragic classicism. Unlike Italian opera in which a sometimes incoherent and badly organized plot provided an excuse for exuberant arias, the opera of Lully and Quinault depended largely on drama, to which music and dance were added. Quinault was criticized for corrupting the classical formulae of Racine and Corneille by allowing the intervention of ballets and arias, as well as the arrival of gods in machines, but his aim was to maintain simplicity, clarity, and logic. One of the most important elements of both verse and music, and their conjunction, was the rhythm. Like Baif a century before, and Mersenne more recently, Lully was concerned with the lucid projection of the text. Quinault employed Alexandrian couplets of classical tragedy, and copied, as far as possible, the metres, as well. Lully was careful that his musical rhythms conformed with the rhythms of the words. The regulation of rhythms and verse reversed the Italian practice of allowing the singer to regulate the rhythm as he gave most attention to the curve of the melody. Lully used a number of different forms to give colour and variety to his operas. He used large choruses, often juxtaposing large and small choruses to create an antiphonal effect. Lully and his operas are of paramount importance to French seventeenth-century music. In his tragedie-lyrique he had created a style that would dominate French music well into the eighteenth century. The response to his operas was also profoundly important to later writings about music.
TRIUMPH OF THE MODERNS Although there was no music theorist of Mersenne's stature until Rameau began to write in the early eighteenth century, the glories of Louis XIV, of French Classicism, and of Colbert's academies, and the power and popularity of Jean Baptiste Lully's tragedie-lyrique provoked what might be seen as a new genre of music theory - a developed criticism and history. New developments in all the arts produced amateurs and litterateurs who made it their business to keep up with developments. These men wrote commentaries during the 1670s and 1680s that resurrected and popularized older artistic doctrines; in music this was, especially, the language of Neoplatonically-conceived music effects. Language notwithstanding, however, each commentator was a modern and a mechanist. Their general belief was that the function of music was to celebrate and to divert.
60 Joe Allard During the final quarter of the seventeenth century it became the popular notion that Lully had succeeded with his tragedie-lyrique where the musical humanists had failed; that is, he had created a form of musical theatre that captured the effects attributed to the music of the ancients. Although he was not thought to have rediscovered the precise forms and practices of the Greeks, he had discovered a formula through which music, words, rhythm, and dance could be unified with the effect of causing changes in man's behaviour. Since it was generally believed that Lully had succeeded in the old quest for effects, the bulk of the new commentary was devoted to considering the similarities and differences between the musical and balletic practice of the ancients and that of seventeenth-century France. Through these works runs the belief that the Middle Ages were finished, that modernity was triumphant, and that France was a direct and successful descendant of the glory of Alexander's Greece. Of course, developments in all the arts during these years served the political and utilitarian purpose of glorifying the king. The operas of Lully, like the painting by Le Brun, broadcast the image of Louis as the apotheosis of ancient emperor and god. The show and splendour of the productions at the Academie Royale de Musique, like the grand fresco cycles by Le Brun at Versailles, or the entire output of the Gobelins factory, continued at full speed during war and peace with the intention of demonstrating France's inexhaustible wealth. Many of Louis' cultural efforts were consciously intended to divert a potentially bored and dangerous nobility from whom he and Colbert had taken more and more power since the early 1660s. By the 1680s Inany nobles, almost completely stripped of real power, did find delight and diversion through art: dilettantes and amateurs abounded and engaged in the variety of cultural debates about Ancients and Moderns, about the general French superiority to the Italian in most things, about the importance of Line versus Colour, and about the relative ranking of Poussin and Rubens. A few brief examples should suffice to show how the commentators inspired their almost entirely modern and self-congratulatory writing with at least an atmosphere of earlier humanist and metaphysical doctrines. Quinault, Lully's main librettist, and Pure, wrote a history of noble spectacles, which emphasized the political and social utility of performances like ballet. Their basic assumption about the effects of such performance was the metaphysical one that rhythm and melody imitated the harmony of the spheres. Rather than dwell on theory, however, Quinault and Pure traced the development of pageants, chariot races, and so on, to show how such spectacles helped the state: how they increased popular admiration for the ruler, honoured the gods, and diverted a potentially dangerous nobility. They ~iscovered the roots of seventeenth-century French entertainments in classical models, and felt that the political and social functions were the same, but that the modern French had surpassed the ancients. An article in Extraordinaire Mercure Galant in July 1680 discussed the dance in conceptions drawn almost equally from Neoplatonic and mechanist sources. Dance was said to be the oldest of artforms, dating from the creation and deriving from the
Music in the Enlightenment 61
Figure 10 Louis XIV as Apollo, in Ballet du Roy des Festes de Bacchus (1651). Drawing by an unknown artist, watercolour with highlights of gold and silver.
62 Joe Allard harmonious movement of the universe. The rulers of France are compared to those of antiquity in that both recognized the 'utility [of the dance] was necessary to public welfare and preservation of their states.' Nobles received instruction in dance to develop such necessary refinements as good posture, graceful movement, and generally elevated actions. These refinements were meant to make them better warriors. The remainder of the definition of the dance demonstrates contemporary concern with the passions: the dance is described as a 'certain disposition of the body which, by its proportional movements and postures, following the sound of instruments or the voice, is animated and is led to the cadence, and which, according to numbers, the modes and the measures of the art, imitates and expresses the passions of the soul and the actions of the body' (quoted by Isherwood 1973: 38). Charles Perrault, champion of the moderns, discussed music in his Ancient and Modem Parallels in 1688. The effect of modern music was manifold: 'In Music the beautiful sound and the precision of the voice charm the ear, the gay or languishing rhythms of the same voice, according to the different passions expressed, touch the heart, and the harmony of the different parts which are blended with order and admirable economy are a pleasure to the reason' (Perrault 1964: 213-14, my translation). Modern music is superior to ancient for Perrault because the moderns had perfect harmony, which allowed them, through music, to reach man's passions and heart, and, through them, his reason: With all its pomp and ravishing' attire Music today is lacking any rival. This gorgeous art, divine, with marvels sweet, Is not content to charm the ear alone, Not just the heart by its expression's moved But at its pleasure all the passions, too: And last - and best - through beauty that's supreme Reason itself - the highest - feels the charm. (Perrault 1964: 18, my translation) Although there is an aura of mystery in this verse that is reminiscent of the metaphysical explanations of music's power, the description of its effect is purely mechanistic. A final, and usefully comprehensive, example of the popularity of metaphysical theories of music and dance wedded to modern ones is drawn from Moliere's The Bourgeois Gentleman, a comedie-ballet he produced in 1670 with music and choreography by Lully. In an early passage M. Jourdain talks with his Music and Dancing Masters and is, of course, gulled by them:
Music Master:
Well, there is something in philosophy, but music, sir, music Dancing Master: And dancing, music and dancing, what more can one need? Music Master: There's nothing so valuable in the life of the nation as music.
Music in the Enlightenment 63 Dancing Master: Music Master: Dancing Master: Music Master:
And nothing so necessary to mankind as dancing. Without music - the country couldn't go on. Without dancing - one can achieve nothing at all. All the disorders, all the wars, that we see in the world today, come from not learning music. Dancing Master: All the troubles of mankind, all the miseries which make up history, the blunders of politicians, the failures of great captains - they all come from not having learned dancing. M. Jourdain: How d'ye make that out? Music Master: What is war but discord among nations? M Jourdain: True. Music Master: If all men studied music wouldn't it be a means of bringing them to harmony and universal peace? M. Jourdain: That seems sound enough. (Moliere 1953: I, ii) The fact that such musical conceptions could be used in a satiric comedy is an indication that the audience, at least, was familiar enough with the theories to laugh at anyone really taking them seriously. M. Jourdain's wide-eyed credulity indicates just how fully such older musical ideas had permeated the intelligentsia, and how sceptical of metaphysical explanations of pleasure they had become. With the exception of paying lip-service to older theories of music's effects, all such commentaries, at base, seem to hold that the real function of music', beyond the rather vague ones of serving the state and producing good soldiers, was to please and divert the listener, and that the route of such pleasure was through an effect on the passions. The older belief that the function of music was to effect profound moral change, which underlay the research of the humanists, and formed the philosophic core of Mersenne's Questions, had been fully superseded by the Enlightenment belief that the arts found their chief function in giving man, considered in mechanistic terms, some diversion and pleasure during the course of his life.
CONCLUSION Even though our common inclination is to locate 'Enlightenment' music at the end of the eighteenth century, this essay has been concerned to make clear the deep significance of seventeenth-century developments in all aspects of the art. Indeed, the music of Haydn and Mozart announces a radical break from the tradition of Lully, Rameau, and Bach. Mozart, and his younger contemporary Beethoven, are if anything the harbinger and the fulfilment of early Romanticism, and exploit, following Haydn's lead, the potentials in a quite different harmonic space than Bach's. Haydn, Mozart, and Beethoven all explore the universe of harmonic tonality that is
64 Joe Allard vertical in emphasis, growing from the triad, and expressive, emotive, finally hysterical in the nineteenth century. This style has come to be called 'Classical', which is yet another unfortunate use of the word. Bach and his predecessors inhabited a space that, although harmonic (and in structure especially fully exploiting the tonicdominant tonal centres), was linear and contrapuntal, and clearly rational and contemplative in effect. However, to quibble over the greater importance of Bach or Mozart to music in the Enlightenment is to miss the crucial point that most reasonably popular Western music since then grows, directly or indirectly, from roots in the later sixteenth century. It is in the early decades of the seventeenth century that links with the past are broken, that belief in ancient (indeed any) authority is discarded, that knowledge splinters, and that 'modernity' finally wins the argument. There is a telling irony in the musical discourse of the encylopedistes in the mideighteenth century. Central to their aesthetic is the notion that instrumental music that does not intentionally set out to imitate, to 'paint' something, is nonsense. Both d'Alembert and Rousseau interpret M. de Fontenelle's famous remark 'Sonate, que me veux-tu?' ('Sonata, what do you want of me?') as a cry of frustration from a reasonable man who had tried, and failed, to understand what pure music has to offer. They all conclude that it offers nothing - it is noise. In the absence of obvious imitation, music is sent to the back of the artistic queue. It can help other arts; it can ornament language in song or movement in dance. But in itself it is nothing. This might be seen as an example of the weakness of eighteenth-century rationality. Commentators attempt to legislate opinion. Good sense and good taste are defined, however, by people who lack sympathy with, or understanding of their subject matter. That d'Alembert could take such a position about instrumental music within a year of Bach's death is, from a musician's point of view, foolish. Similarly Diderot's attack on Rameau in Rameau's Nephew purports to be criticism of his music when, in fact, it is much more to do with politics and taste. However, one result of 'enlightenment' is an infinite multiplication of points of view. In the absence of any authority or belief, any idea or position can be maintained and defended no matter how absurd or dangerous. The most significant result of developments in the seventeenth century is the fracturing of the Western mind. Once this occurs - and becomes manifest in the academic movement throughout Europe and North America - there is, among other things, a proliferation of arena for debate. Later seventeenth-century Paris saw the birth of a new class of commentator - people like Perrault, who are delighted to weigh into arguments with enthusiasm about tenets of 'modern' taste. What musicians are doing at a practical level becomes subject to their judgement. This split between practice and chatter is the hallmark of what it means to be modern. Of course, the great irony of modernism is that it has no past that it can view with anything other than embarrassment or contempt. The modern lives
Music in the Enlightenment 65 strenuously in the present and for the future, unaware that, in that pose, he or she is already past.
NOTE Further reading includes Anthony 1973, Descartes 1897-1913, Maniates 1969, and'Valker 1942.
5 Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity JAY BERNSTEIN
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION Thinkers of the Enlightenment identified themselves and their times with novelty. They were quite self-conscious about being 'modern'. But they certainly did not agree about what being modern involved, nor whether this was a good thing. Often 'luxury' was the theme through which ambivalence about modernity was explored. When we want to examine this ambivalence more closely, we customarily turn to Rousseau. It is now much more fully appreciated that Rousseau did not in fact advocate a return to a past golden age, as Jay Bernstein's paper makes clear. ; Rousseau used history for a quite particular purpose - it facilitated his thought experiments about what was 'natural' and what was 'original' in the human condition, and, Bernstein reminds us, these two terms do not denote the same thing. Rousseau's interest in the transformations human beings may have undergone alerts us to the significance of change for his thought as a whole. Rousseau is an important figure in the Enlightenment for many reasons, but here it is his energetic enquiries into the nature of nature that are especially striking. Rousseau had a dynamic view of nature; human characteristics can become natural.. ized. Thus, although his rhetoric polarizes nature and society, especially in the Second Discourse, it is in fact the complex interplay between them that preoccupies him. Nowhere is this more evident than in Rousseau's treatment of relations between the sexes. Many scholars have seen his ideas on this subject as exceptionally influential in the second half of the eighteenth century. This is hard to prove, and it seems likely that his direct influence has been exaggerated. But the seriousness of his engagement with gender and its political implications cannot be doubted, providing ample grist for scholars' mills without any need to overstate his influence. Bernstein explores some of the complexities of Rousseau's ideas about male-female relations through the idea of fiction. He points to Rousseau's concern with identity and difference. The latter leads him to see the sexes as complementary
Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity 67
in their attributes, while he is intensely conscious of what Bernstein evocatively calls 'erotic strife'. Emile explores this theme in the final part, where Emile marries, but his wife strays from the straight and narrow path of chaste behaviour that Rousseau prescribed for married women. These themes are linked to Rousseau's treatment of one of the most important concepts of the Enlightenment, that of the citizen. Rousseau envisages the ideal citizen as male, although the stability of the body politic also rests on women's virtue, indeed on women's virtue being publicly visible. By the time of the French Revolution the word 'citizen' was dense with meaning: this single term could evoke an entire political vision, yet at the same time remain ambiguous and contested. It is surely significant that a recent, and highly controversial, book about the French Revolution is entitled, simply, Citizens (Schama 1989). Many commentators have linked Rousseau's writings directly with the Revolution. The actual historical relationship between them is now recognized as exceedingly complex. Bernstein criticizes Hannah Arendt's influential account of this relationship, and then builds on his criticisms to show how we should understand the relationship between particular interests and the general will. The point here is Rousseau's constant concern with changing human nature for political ends. Hence his related concern with education, with the mechanisms whereby human nature is fashioned. Put this way we can appreciate the sense of process that informs Rousseau's thought. For Bernstein we must understand Rousseau's writings as 'fiction'. By this he means nothing pejorative, but seeks to refer us to the rhetorical power of those writings, to their capacity to tell plausible stories that exemplify an ideal political order. Rousseau's writings, with their blend of what we would call stories, philosophy, speculative anthropology, and political theory, opened up important conceptual spaces. But at the same time, their force rendered aspects of them mythic, so that Rousseau cast exceptionally dark shadows. His legacy is a complex, multifaceted one, but it is all the more important because of the subtlety of his ideas and writings. NOTE In chapter 5 the following abbreviations are employed: SO = .second Discourse (Rousseau 1964); E = Emile (Rousseau 1979); SC = The Social Contract (Rousseau 1950).
5
There can be no more vigilant and persistent a critic of enlightened modernity than Rousseau. In his first critical essay, A Discourse on the Arts and Sciences (1751), he offers a genealogical unmasking of the Enlightenment's praise and defence of science and learning: Astronomy was born from superstition; eloquence from ambition, hate, flattery, and falsehood; geometry from avarice, physics from vain curiosity; all, even moral philosophy, from human pride. Thus the sciences and arts owe their birth to our vices; we would be less doubtful of their advantages if they owed it to our virtues. (Rousseau 1964: 48) For Rousseau the arts and sciences are premised on luxury and engender a sublime indifference to moral and political well-being. Rousseau is not opposed to science and learning as such, but their present status is bound up with, and an affirmation of, a world of vice and inequality. The advancement of the sciences and arts has brought about the disappearance of virtue. Of course, it would be an outrageous exaggeration to blame the wholesale corruption of virtue in modernity on the advancements of learning; far more plausible is the claim that they became entangled in a history in which the apparent good they make possible was continually subjected to forces that turned them against their own best possibilities. This is to concede, against the Enlightenment, that there is no intrinsic rational goodness in the advancement of learning. Rousseau's philosophical project, which first reached maturity in his Discourse on the Origin and Foundations ofInequality Among Men (1755), commonly called the Second Discourse, is an historical and theoretical analysis of the corruption of virtue in modernity and a survey of the possibilities for its being restored. At the centre of this enterprise is a reiterated attack on the unsocial sociability of individuals in the modern, liberal state; individuals who 'no longer have a hold on one another except by force and self-interest' (E: 321).
Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity 69
In the Second Discourse Rousseau offers an historical account of the origin of inequality that turns on not projecting back into the state of nature extant psychological dispositions and attitudes, as is done in the works of Hobbes and Locke; they 'spoke about savage man and they describe civil man' (SO: 102). Egoism and instrumental rationality, which together generate the idea of persons as each seeking to maximize their individual happiness, are products of historical development, not natural attributes of persons. The Second Discourse presents the genesis of these attributes as belonging to the 'natural' or ideal type history of the species. As such, Rousseau's account of the development of the soul or psyche must be regarded as less an empirical history of the origins of inequality than an ideal history, a phenomenology of mind, the terms of which are both items of history and analytic and/or theoretical categories through which concrete history can be explained and analysed (on this Hegelian conception, see Gillespie 1984: 1-28). Only on the assumption that this is what Rousseau is doing can we understand his claim that the state of nature, taken as representing man's prehistoric endowments, what is original to our species,· is a state 'which no longer exists, which perhaps never existed, which probably never will exist'; and, hence, the investigation of which can commence 'by setting all the facts aside, for they do not affect the question' (SO: 93, 103). Rousseau's state of nature is not an ideal state of affairs, in the sense of a state of affairs to be sought after and returned to, since in it human beings lack the social and conventional characteristics that are partially constitutive of them as human beings as they are now found in the world. Nor, then, does the state of nature instantiate all our psychological attributes, as is presupposed in empiricist accounts of it. Not everything that is 'natural' to our species is original to it; much of what is intrinsic to us is acquired in history. Rousseau's state of nature marks that moment just prior to the onset of conventionally structured social existence - an existence in which transformation and development become constitutive features of species life. If the state of nature is ideal in any sense, and it is, it is logically and conceptually ideal, like a frictionless surface; Rousseau can thus use it as a standard of measurement, as a critical vantage point from which historical society can be comprehended. Its moral authority as an ideal state of affairs is its neutrality, its being beyond good and evil. Good and evil are moral qualities that adhere to human beings only as fully socialized beings (SO: 128). In the state of nature, human beings are solitary creatures, concerned only with their own self-preservation; they are neither envious nor contemptuous of others because the linguistic terms and routine exchanges between individuals that underlie envy, contempt, hatred, pride, love, honour, and the like do not yet exist. As pure natural beings these individuals are self-sufficient, independent, and peaceful. In order for individuals to oppose their interests to those of others, and thus have grounds for strife with others, those others must be reckoned with as routine objects of concern; and this requires the existence of cognitive and practical forms - like reason, property relations, and the division of labour - binding each individual to its
70
Jay
Bernstein
relevant others. No such forms can be attributed to individuals in the state of nature. Only slowly do people begin to draw together and seek one another's emotional and practical support; only slowly do language and reason appear; only under the pressure and movement of these occurrences does 'civil man' begin to appear. The two central terms of analysis which give this history its critical edge are amour-de-soi and amour-propre. Amour-de-soi or self-love is not equivalent to egoism, pride, or conceit. Originally it involves only simple, unmediated concern for oneself; as such it is best regarded as a form or version of what is usually regarded under the title of the drive for self-preservation. In its first appearance amour-de-soi motivates individuals to action without reflection and deliberation. Reflection, which leads to the weighing and comparing of competing goods, and deliberation, which designs means to ends and draws future goods into present consideration, involve the comparing and linking of ideas, which in turn requires the use of reason and language, neither of which is possessed by savage man. Savage man, the animal that will become civil man, regards 'himself as the sole spectator to observe him, and as the sole judge of his own merit' (SD: 222). For these reasons amour-de-soi is a different passion from amour-propre, which is 'only a relative sentiment, artificial and born in society, [and] which inclines each individual to have a greater esteem for himself than for anyone else' (SD: 222). A good from the perspective of amourde-soi is good for the self irrespective of whether others have or do not have it (or its converse), and irrespective of whether others acknowledge or fail to acknowledge an individual's possession or entitlement to it. Amour-de-soi is taught the nature of these goods through experience; amour-de-soi encourages self-sufficiency and the acknowledgement of natural necessity. As a consequence, for Rousseau amour-desoi, even outside the state of nature, remains a constant norm of action which, when directed by reason and modified by compassion, 'produces humanity and virtue' (SD: 222). The book that best teaches the lessons of amour-de-soi, the first which Rousseau gives to his Everyman, Emile, is Robinson Crusoe (E: 184-8). None the less, the normative authority and motivation provided by amour-de-soi becomes corrupted, repressed, and forgotten when amour-propre comes on the scene. No term within Rousseau's corpus is as difficult to analyse and translate as amour-propre. The usual translations of amour-propre as either 'vanity' or 'egoism' generate a paradox for Rousseau's thinking that is not indigenous to it. Amourpropre certainly marks the way in which individuals gather their practical selfunderstanding and self-identity through the views that others have of them; with the onset of amour-propre self-esteem and self-worth, and their opposites, are mediated through others. Further, in Rousseau's view amour-propre does incline each individual to have a greater esteem for himself than for anyone else; and that inclination has not been resisted throughout history. Amour-propre, then, accounts for the unsocial sociability of individuals in modern states; and it is the psychological precipitates of amour-propre, taken as natural endowments, that govern the actions of 'natural man' in the writings of Hobbes and Locke.
Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity
71
But amour-propre cannot be vanity, egoism, or pride, for were that the case the corrupt and unequal society of the present as described by Rousseau would be unsurpassable; the sociality constitutive of being in society and history would be essentially unsocial; self-worth would be not only always mediated through others but always competitive as well, so that any individual's good would require another's non-possession of that good. If social life were necessarily corrupting of natural virtue, then while amour-de-soi might be brought forward in order to moderate amour-propre, the pernicious effects of that latter passion would remain constant and irremovable elements of social life. Ifthis were so, then the theoretical gain over Hobbes and Locke accomplished by separating amour-de-soi from amour-propre and aligning the latter passion with egoism would be insubstantial; the individualism of their approaches would have been overcome but the consequences of that perspective would remain. In Emile (1762), however, Rousseau makes perfectly clear that amour-propre is not essentially corrupting, and that the passions of envy and contempt, shame and pride that are precipitates of it, to which it inclines, are not intrinsic characteristics. In itself amour-propre is 'good and useful', and 'naturally neutral'; it 'becomes good or bad only by the application made of it and the relations given to it' (E: 92). Rousseau continues this passage by saying that he will not confront Emile with others until his reason is sufficiently developed to allow him to control it. Such a controlling reason was not in place at the historical onset of amour-propre; after a brief moment when conjugal and paternal love dominate, their natural correlates, jealousy, and possessiveness, make their appearance: 'By dint of seeing one another, they can no longer do without seeing one another again. A tender and gentle sentiment is gradually introduced into the soul and at the least obstacle becomes impetuous fury. Jealousy awakens with love; discord triumphs, and the gentlest of the passions receives sacrifices of human blood' (SO: 148-9). It is in this setting of inflamed passions and erotic competitiveness that amour-propre first makes an emphatic appearance. Individuals, gathered together, begin to compare one another's looks and abilities; they begin, insensibly, to seek public esteem and to gather their self-esteem through public acknowledgement of their worth. Natural difference became social worth: that was the 'first step toward inequality and, at the same time, toward vice' (SO: 149). In itself amour-propre is nothing but our being-for-others, it is the form 'our innate concern to be well and do well in and for ourselves takes ... as and when we have regard to ourselves in our standing and place with other people engaged in transactions with them' (Dent 1988: 56). Amour-propre is our desire and claim to recognition by others, one we cannot avoid in so far as we are social beings. Although I shall leave amour-propre untranslated, if pressed I would translate it as simply 'self-consciousness', for its closest analogue within philosophy is Hegel's concept of self-consciousness (amour-de-soi is an analogue of Hegel's conception of 'sentiment of self). Amour-propre is Hegelian self-consciousness in that it specifies the social mediations and relational elements involved in achieving a full awareness
72 Jay Bernstein of oneself. Further, Rousseau's dialectic of dependency, with its contrasting terms of vanity and contempt, shame and envy, anticipates and maps easily onto Hegel's dialectic of master and slave (Hegel 1977: 110-19; cf. Bernstein 1984a). In identifying amour-propre with self-consciousness, the social, and ultimately political, character of the human psyche for Rousseau is implied. Inequality is a product of deformed arnour-propre. And if it is correct to place the onset of amour-propre in a context of erotic strife, and if one recalls Rousseau's acceptance of Locke's axiom that where there is no property, there is no injury (SO: 150), and his insistence that the true founder of civil society was the first person to fence off a plot of ground and say 'this is mine' and find others simple enough to believe him (SO: 141-2), then for Rousseau historical society, inequality, and the degeneration of the species all properly begin with the taking and making of women as property. Women are the 'first' property because erotic strife underwrites the original appearance of amour-propre. For Rousseau the historical dialectic of n1aster and slave, and the historical dialectic of male and female are coterminous (on Rousseau's anticipation of Freud, see Pateman 1988). Once amour-propre is thus introduced, and the possession of women has given men the germ of the idea of property through the affective entanglements of desire and jealousy, then the demise of the state of nature is preordained: the division of labour increases dependency and enjoins the domination of seeming over being; metallurgy and agriculture intensify mutual dependency and the reign of deformed amour-propre until, finally, the introduction of property and positive law come to spell the end of natural existence. The formation of states, a process which turns the right of the stronger into positive right and transforms natural liberty into legal servitude, is coextensive with this last stage of development. This is the state of affairs to which all of Rousseau's writings address themselves: How can the deformation of amour-propre be undone? For Rousseau the establishment of civil liberty and the regeneration of equality presupposes the generation of forms of amour-propre to which the malevolent secondary elaborations of it - pride and contempt, shame and envy - cannot adhere; Are benign forms of amour-propre possible? And what is meant by 'possible' in this context? Is it real, historical possibility that is at issue here; or are we only concerned with logical possibilities, possible worlds in which things might be different? In this question, apart from any answers that might be given to it, lies the central tension in Rousseau's thought. There can be little doubt that Rousseau perceived the society in which he dwelled as so morally corrupt as to make it unsuitable for political regeneration. In this sense, we might say, Rousseau perceived a massive historical blockage cutting off existing society from a more virtuous successor: contemporary society lacked the internal potentialities that would allow it to progress. Alternatively, however, the very terms and literary genres in which Rousseau elaborates the possibility of benign amourpropre raise the concern that the difficulty, the aporia in question, might be as much conceptual as historical, that the very structure of Roussea'u's thought doubles the historical blockage with a conceptual blockage. And while it may well
Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity 73
be the case that Rousseau's, and our, predicament does involve an overlapping of an historical difficulty with a conceptual difficulty, we need none the less to interrogate Rousseau's tense running together of these difficulties. Rousseau elaborates his original state of nature as one which no longer exists, which perhaps never existed, and which probably never will exist; might not the same be said for the ideal state Rousseau outlines in The Social Contract (1762)? Are not both the state of nature and the ideal state fictions? Is not the virtuous family of Julie, or the New Eloise (1761) designedly a fiction? Is not the self created in Rousseau's Confessions (written 1765) a fiction? Fictionality is for Rousseau the consequence of historical failure; in Emile he states: If I have said what must be done, I have said what I ought to have said. It makes very little difference to me if I have written a romance. A fair romance it is indeed, the romance of human nature. If it is to be found only in this writing, is that my fault? This ought to be the history of my species. You who deprave it, it is you who make a romance of my book. (E: 416) Is it Rousseau who fails us, converting historical contingency into logical necessity? Is it his articulation of our problem that prohibits our conceiving of moral progress? Or is it we who have failed Rousseau, who have made his books into fictions, romances, through our depravity? In the space that both connects and separates these two possibilities is lodged the question of political thought and the possibility of political philosophy. The status of fiction in Rousseau's thought is the place where political philosophy and historical reality meet and repulse one another.
Amour-propre is the relating of self and other, identity and difference. Property relations concern what is mine and thine, what belongs to me and is different from you, and hence is equally a relating of self and other, of identity and difference. There is an intimate connection between amour-propre's affective, relational constitution of self-regard, self-consciousness, property relations, and the logic of identity and difference. If there is a conceptual aporia involved in the way in which Rousseau articulates the former, it is derived from the way in which his anthropology and social philosophy are directed by the latter: the logic of identity and difference presses Rousseau's thought into a fictional stance that tendentially turns his immanent critique of modernity into an external critique, his diagnosis of the historical blockage of modernity into a conceptual blockage. To get a better idea of what maybe at issue here let us look again at the Second Discourse. As we have already seen, Rousseau locates the downfall of the species at the moment where deformed amour-propre represses amour-de-soi. If amour-propre were treated as equivalent to vanity, then it would follow straightaway that Rousseau's logic of disintegration was equivalent to the displacement of the simple, unmediated self-identity provided by amour-de-soiby the comparative and reflective
74 Jay Bernstein self-understanding derived from amour-propre. Such a view does receive some support from the rest of Rousseau's argument. The analytic underpinning of the Second Discourse appears to have a tidy and simple dualistic structure. In the first stage of the state of nature, human beings are governed by amour-de-soi, which is moderated in individuals' relations to others by pith?! pity or compassion. Compassion is a 'pure movement of nature prior to all reflection' (SD: 131); through compassion we 'identify' with the suffering of others, we put ourselves in their place (SD: 132). Compassion 'carries us without reflection to the aid of those we see suffer; in the state of nature, it takes the place of laws, morals, and virtue' (SD: 133). For Rousseau, compassion is the true ground of the possibility of virtue, since without it we would lack any but prudential grounds for taking up a moral point of view; but, according to Rousseau, all prudential arguments for moral rules stop short of specifying why I should be virtuous. All they demonstrate is that, optimally, all benefit and none lose from the general adoption of moral rules; but this only shows that it would be a good thing if such rules were generally adopted, and not that I should adopt such rules. My interest will be served best if there are such rules and I can 'free-ride' on their acceptance while continuing to act in ways which disregard their requirements. This is one of Rousseau's central arguments against Hobbes (see Connolly 1988: 54f1). The combination of (deformed) amour-propre and reason is as near fatal to the claims of compassion as it is to the urgings of amour-de-soi. While compassion was obscure and strong in savage man, it has become developed but weak in civilized man; consciousness of difference insistently interrupts our natural capacity for identifying with the sufferings of others, our spontaneous repugnance at the sight of suffering. Now it is evident that this identification must have been infinitely closer in the state of nature than in the state of reasoning. Reason engenders vanity and reflection fortifies it; reason turns man back upon himself, it separates him from all that bothers and afflicts him. Philosophy isolates him; because of it he says in secret, at the sight of a suffering man: perish if you will, I am safe. (SD: 132) Reason engenders and reflection fortifies the psychological precipitates of amourpropre; such a movement weakens the urgings of compassion and represses the natural wisdom of amour-de-soi. Since savage men knew neither vanity, nor consideration, nor esteem, nor contempt; and lacked the slightest notion of 'thine and mine' together with any idea of justice, 'they regarded the violences they might suffer as harm easy to redress and not as an insult which must be punished' (SD: 133-4). In all this Rousseau does appear to make identity a condition of and equivalent to independence" equality and virtue; and to make difference in all its forms the condition for and equivalent to dependence, inequality and vice. Were this to be really the case, then Rousseau's pessimism would be a priori in status, and virtue a property only of ideal, ~ctive states of affairs.
Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity
75
As we have already seen, however, it is only deformed amour-propre that is vicious; and conversely, I now want to suggest, compassion is an essentially social passion, which does not necessarily lack a reflective dimension. For Rousseau, it is our weakness, vulnerability, and non-self-sufficiency that make us social and sociable beings. 'Every attachment,' Rousseau contends, 'is a sign of insufficiency.' As Rousseau continues this thought the ambiguity of his position emerges: If each of us had not need of others, he would hardly think of uniting himself with them. Thus from our very infirmity is born our frail happiness. A truly happy being is a solitary being. God alone enjoys an absolute happiness. But who among us has the idea of it? If some imperfect being could suffice unto himself, what would he enjoy according to us? He would be alone; he would be miserable. I do not conceive how someone who needs nothing can love anything. I do not conceive how someone who loves nothing can be happy. (E: 221) Only a perfectly self-sufficient being could be absolutely happy. Perfect selfsufficiency and absolute happiness are the logical quintessence of amour-de-soi; God exemplifies Rousseau's identitarian logic. However, we are not self-sufficient; our neediness opens us up to the possibility of loving others, a possibility which is a condition for human happiness. Difference is redeemed in love. Hence, either if God is happy we cannot be, or if we can be happy God cannot. 'Frail happiness' appears to be logically anomalous; hence, the alternative conception of happiness implied by the logic of identity comes to hover over and disequilibriate the valencies of finite happiness. Whatever the effects of this disequilibrium, Rousseau perceives us as essentially non-self-sufficient, essentially needy, and hence as essentially drawn into relations with others. Compassion is the affection through which we most feel our identity and common humanity. This thesis is doubly underwritten. First, by the natural logic of the imagination whereby the sight of the suffering other leads us to put ourselves in his place, while the sight of the happy other leads us to want to occupy his place, so displacing him. Imaginative perception tends to lead to compassion at the sight of suffering, and envy at the sight of happiness. Secondly, this logic of the imagination is underwritten by the human condition itself; we are not naturally all 'kings, or lords, or courtiers, or rich men'; rather we are all 'born naked and poor; all are subject to the miseries of life, to sorrows, ills, needs, and pains of every kind ... [and we] are all condemned to death.' This is the human lot, 'what truly belongs to man' (E: 222). Unlike the almost animal version of compassion given in the Second Discourse, in Emile Rousseau accords compassion a fundamentally reflective aspect: the pleasure of compassion derives from our awareness that we are not in the place of the sufferer, even if we could be. Further, our ability to assist a sufferer confirms our freedom and power, while simultaneously underlining our virtuous disposition.
76 Jay Bernstein Virtue is literally its own reward for Rousseau; the pleasures of compassion are both reflective and reflexive. Of course, Emile is a romance, a fiction, because the conditions under which Emile is allowed to keep an appropriate amour-de-soi, to develop an undeformed amour-propre, and permitted to develop a sense of compassIon not drowned by reason and envy, are themselves a fiction, an abstraction from the ordinary processes of education and maturation. The possibility of Emile coming to have a virtuous character is conditioned by his tutor's protection of him from knowledge of other wills in early childhood (something he could not be relieved from were he to have siblings or classmates), from the world of wealth and power, from the sight of woman in puberty, and so forth. The artifice of Emile (the book) is coextensive with the artifice of Emile's (the character) tutor's arrangements, whereby he should not engage any portion of the world actively, cognitively, or affectively until such time as he has the capacity to resist the deforming and vice-engendering features which that portion of the world of experience presents to his development. The artifice of narrative construction and the artifice of pedagogical planning and practice are matched and superimposed upon one another in order to create and construct the virtuous citizen who is Emile. Emile's development is an ideal moral development, in accordance with the logic of Rousseau's moral psychology rather than in accordance with the typical dictates of experience. In this way Emile can become the model, ideal citizen; his personal education is simultaneously a political education. The 'romance' of Emile, however, is a romance because of our historical predicament; it seems natural to conclude that the ideal education of Emile is a surrogate for what would be our political education, a political education that the sway of deformed amour-propre forecloses. Perhaps this is too harsh on Rousseau; perhaps it would be better to say that under conditions of severe historical blockage, under conditions in which the very idea of political education, the idea of a formative politics, is ruled out by the reduction of the state to a means of securing private ends, perhaps under these conditions the only kind of political education possible is through fiction; perhaps we need to say that Rousseau intended Emile's fictional education to be our political education. Since the idea of fiction is an interruption in the historical order, for the truly political to appear only as what it is not, the concept ofthe political would have to have a different range of signification for Rousseau than it does for liberal political philosophers. For them the political world specifies a set of instrumental arrangements, and political philosophy intends the rational legitimation of goods sustainable only through the construction of a political state. But what if the very idea of the political possesses an ineliminable pedagogical and educative component? If political life was, ideally, constructive of the character of citizens, then narrative construction, which had the appearance of a 'romance', would in reality be political education under conditions where political education was historically occluded from the state. And from this it would follow that the meaning of fiction and romance could not be settled a priori, that what it was to be a fiction
Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity
77
would be a function of the historical situation in which narratives were produced and introduced; and equally it would follow that the genres of philosophy, above all political philosophy, would have to be relativized to their historical and political contexts in accordance with their own idea of the political (see Bernstein 1984b). To indict Rousseau for lapsing into fiction or engaging in utopian constructions misses, I am suggesting, Rousseau's indictment of our conception of politics and fiction, our political reduction of his writing to romance. But this would follow only if political education were intrinsic to the idea of the political, if the very possibility of a political world involved the structured education of the passions. If this were so, then not only Emile, but all Rousseau's writings, all his fictions, would have to be regarded in a different, more political light: the fiction of an ideal politics would hence become the politics of fiction, and that latter coextensive with political philosophy in its uniquely modern sense. Rousseau makes it unequivocally clear at the commencement of Emile that his goal is the education of man into a citizen. This will be a difficult teaching for us moderns since it fundamentally contradicts our standing, liberal conception of the correct relation between the individual and the state. Natural man is entirely for himself. He is numerical unity, the abolute whole which is relative only to itself or its kind. Civil man is only a fractional unity dependent on the denominator; his value is determined by his relation to the whole, which is only the social body. Good social institutions are those that best know how to denature man, to take his absolute existence from him in order to give him a relative one and transport the I into the common unity, with the result that each individual believes himself no longer one but a part of the unity and no longer feels except within the whole. (E: 39-40) Good social institutions, and by extension good political institutions, are ones that best denature man, that is, ones that constitute not only the social being of individuals but equally and explicitly their conception of themselves, their selfconsciousnesses as beings belonging to a particular community. Good social institutions are explicitly educative in character; and seek to effect the constitutive affective and reflective self-understanding of the beings who inhabit them. Interests, the very stuff of political debate, negotiation, and conflict, are thereby formed. Only when formed so as not to be in essential conflict, only when formed so that citizens do not perceive their most fundamental interests as conflicting with those of their fellows, is a good state possible. Such a state does not now exist. Indeed, because of the present lack and impossibility of 'public instruction', Rousseau believes that the two words 'fatherland' and 'citizen' should be effaced from modern languages. The harshness of this teaching is brought out in Rousseau's illustrations; for example, of the Spartan woman who had five sons in the army awaiting news of the
78 Jay Bernstein battle. A Helot arrives, and trembling she asks him for news. He tells the woman her five sons have been killed. She replies: '''Base slave, did I ask you that?" "We won the victory." The mother runs to the temple and gives thanks to the gods' (E: 40). Rousseau's vision echoes Machiavelli, who praised the Florentine patriots who dared to defy the Pope, showing thus 'how much higher they placed their city than their souls'; - a thought reiterated by Machiavelli at the end of his life when he wrote 'I love my native city more than my own soul' (quoted in Arendt 1973: 286). To love one's city more than one's immortal soul, to love the world more than one's immortal salvation, specifies perfectly the gap separating absolute individual interest, as represented by the Christian conception of the soul, and political love and solidarity. Rousseau regards the Christian conception of the soul as making'all good polity impossible' (SC: 4, VIII; 132). The worst of all possible states of affairs is one in which the individual's loyalties to self and state, to the civil order and the sentiments of nature, are divided. Such a person, 'floating between his inclinations and his duties', never either 'a man or a citizen', will be good 'neither for himself nor for others'. This is the man of the present day: 'A Frenchman, an Englishman, a bourgeois. He will be nothing' (E: 40). Nota bene, that what we take to be constitutive of our general predicament as moral beings, the very conditions of morality and moral life, namely, the conflict between duties and inclinations, is for Rousseau a historically constructed state with no natural, metaphysical or ontological backing. And further, that the conflict between bourgeois and citizen that makes us 'nothing' repeats and deepens the earlier jurisdictional conflict between church and state. Christianity heightens deformed amour-propre into a theological principle. Amour-propre is now so deformed that the teleological enterprise governing Emile's education, namely his political education from man to citizen, must be construed aporetically since the term 'citizen' is not truly applicable to the inhabitants of modern states. In modernity the two kingdoms have become entrenched in the heart of modern man in the conflict between particular wills and the general will, particular interests and the general interest. In contemporary society we are familiar with the idea that unity of the state or nation is actuated and made manifest when it is threatened by an external enemy; only in the presence of a foreign enemy can such a thing as the nation one and indivisible come to pass. As Hannah Arendt argues, Rousseau's feat was to discover a unifying principle within the nation itself that would be valid for domestic politics as well. This enemy existed within the breast of each citizen, namely, in his particular will and interest; the point of the matter was that this hidden particular enemy could rise to the rank of a common enemy - unifying the nation from within - if one only added up all particular wills and interests. The common enemy within the nation is the sum total of the particular interests of all citizens. (Arendt 1973: 78) Arendt goes on to press this thought by drawing attention to a footnote in The
Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity 79
Social Contract where Rousseau states that the agreement of all interests is formed by opposition to that of each. He continues: 'If there were no different interests, the common interest would be barely felt, as it would encounter no obstacle; all would go on of its own accord, and politics would cease to be an art' (SC: II, iii; 27). This certainly appears to underline Arendt's thesis making the totality of particular interests the common enemy; and to contradict the view that the conflict between particular and general is a merely historically conditioned state of affairs. However, such a view makes the concept of particular interest too homogeneous and univocal. In the footnote following the one just cited, Rousseau quotes Machiavelli to the effect that some divisions are harmful to a republic and some advantageous. Those that stir up sects and parties are harmful; those that do neither of these things are advantageous. Evidently, bourgeois particular interests, as generally conceived, are of the sort that stir up sects and parties. On the other hand, to conceive of divisions that do not entail a conflict of interest in the modern sense is to conceive of a plurality where the fact of separateness permits and encourages individuals to take opposing, differing, positions on the general interest. The concept of particular interest is equivocal between interests of the particular opposing the general, and interests of the general made from a particular position or outlook. When Rousseau states, just where he is conceding the place of particular interests, that 'there should be no partial society within the State, and that each citizen should think only his own thoughts' (SC: II, iii; 27), he is clearly recommending the latter conception of particular interest. The division between the two concepts of particular interest inscribes the pedagogical and educative task facing the Rousseauian legislator. His task is not to generate a general will from the conflicting particular interests of present-day bourgeois; the accomplishment of that task would be the sacrifice and submerging of the individual in the collective. In fact, it is difficult to imagine what such a state of affairs would look like that did not end up equating, quite illegitimately, the general will with some constructed and delimited version of the totality of particular wills. And this reduction could occur if there were a reducing, dissolving element. Poverty is such an element; it conspires to make each one's particular interest the same as everyone else's particular interest; the general will hence becoming the unification of the people through a mutual acknowledgemenfof their shared situation. Such a unification makes not a people, w~ere the separateness of persons is respected, but a mass. Hannah Arendt reads and misreads Rousseau in just this way. For her, the French Revolution, culminating in the Terror, is an historical exemplification of the identification of particular interests with bourgeois interests; and if one accedes to the view that The Social Contract was central to the emergence and unfolding of the Revolution, then the Terror would actually be the fulfilment of Rousseau's doctrine (Arendt 1973: 76-81, 88-91). The task of the Rousseauian legislator, however, is to make a people of the aggregate; and this task should now be construed not as imposing a general will, but rather as generating the conditions under which a general will can become
80 Jay Bernstein manifest. This task is just the task outlined in Emile; the legislator must be capable of changing human nature, of transforming each individual, who is by himself a complete and solitary whole, into part of a great whole from which he in a manner receives his life and b~ing; of altering man's constitution for the purpose of strengthening it; and of substituting a partial and moral existence for the physical and independent existence nature has conferred on us all. He must, in a word, take away from man his own resources and give him instead new ones alien to him, and incapable of being made use of without the help of other men. (SC: II, vii; 38) The task of the legislator is one of political education; it is the denaturing of individuals in order to provide them with a second nature that is wholly social. Now the paradoxical situation faced by the legislator is exactly parallel to the one faced by Rousseau as political thinker: since good laws impose severe privations (for some) when viewed from the perspective of existing particular interests, then the conditions which would make the rationality of those laws perceptible are just the ones they are attempting to institute. Good laws generate and promote conditions under which the goodness of such laws can become manifest. Hence, from the perspective of the legislator, good laws require that the effect become the cause: 'the social spirit, which should be created by these institutions, would have to preside over their very foundation; and men would have to be before the law what they would become by means of the law' (SC: II, vii; 40). The historical blockage of the present is but an extreme manifestation of the situation facing any founding legislator. Rousseau's philosophical and political practice is the one he insists legislators must use: the generating of an authoritative fiction. Because the legislator cannot appeal to either force or reason, the former because its effects are self-defeating and the latter because it is not available, he must appeal to an authority of a different order, one 'capable of constraining without violence and persuading without convincing'. To persuade without convincing is the work of rhetoric; if the persuasion is to constrain, then that rhetoric must appeal to an authority above that of the legislator himself: such a thing is a fiction. Traditionally, legislators credit 'gods with their own wisdom' (SC: II, vii; 40) in order to accomplish this end; Rousseau's philosophical genres, his natural history, the novel of education et al., are surrogates for the gods. They are the fictions that are to raise his legislative activity to authority, persuading without convincing and constraining without violence. Although Rousseau appears in The Social Contract to be interested in theoretical doctrines, the general will, the particular will, the forms of government, and so on, in the same way as great legislators appear to be concerning themselves with particular regulations, in reality he concerns himself 'in secret' with the 'keystone' of .any just state, manners and morals as these are conveyed and circulate in 'public opinion' (SC: II, xii; 53). Only a fiction can accomplish the work of transforming public opinion in a manner that would make a just state possible.
Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity 81
Alas, this historical conception of the relations among history, politics, and fiction cannot be the final word since there remains good cause still to perceive Rousseau's fictions as consequences of a logical rather than an historical demand. And, to repeat, the logical demand derives from the problem of difference. In order to gain a vantage point on this issue, let us return to the status of women in Rousseau. Nowadays Rousseau is often criticized for painting a picture of the ideal woman that matches, almost perfectly, the idealizing distortions of the dominating male tradition: a woman is to be defined by her roles as wife and mother; these require that she be 'modest, attentive, reserved, and that she give evidence of her virtue to the eyes of others as well as to her own conscience' (E: 361). Women must not only act virtuously, as should men, but they must as well be recognized as so doing, unlike men who can better brave public judgement. Indeed, generally, women are for Rousseau the visible manifestation, the icon of public virtue; like the beautiful work that is a symbol of the morally good, the moral beauty of woman is a symbol of the public good. This is why opinion, which is the grave of virtue among men, is its throne among women (E: 364-5). In his analysis of women Rousseau throughout wants to insist on their difference from men, and to reveal how that difference gives them strengths and virtues not available to men. However deplorable Rousseau's patriarchial attitudes, what is damning for his thought generally is that while he insists on sexual difference, he does so in a manner that ends up discounting the differences between men and women as differences that might divide them or render them incapable of achieving perfect unity: 'All the faculties common to the two sexes are not equally distributed between them; but taken together, they balance out' (E: 363). The balancing out of the difference between the sexes is the making of each difference a partial element which, when drawn into relation with the corresponding element from the opposite sex, is made whole. Sexual difference is sublated in the ideal unity of men and women in their assigned roles within the family and the state; the harmonious affections of the ideal family anticipating the harmonious unity of the ideal state. In this way difference becomes an anticipation of non-difference, as part becomes the anticipation of whole. This anticipation of organic unity, a strong concepJion of unity trumping the weak unity of a public sphere in which each enters with his own conception of what the general will should be, reappears in Rousseau's contention that the general will is indestructible. When the social bond weakens, particular interests begin to make themselves felt and oppose themselves to the common interest. Eventually, 'when in every heart the social bond is broken', the meanest interests lay claim to the sacred name of the 'public good'. Does it follow, then, that the generaI will has been exterminated or corrupted? 'Not at all: it is always constant, unalterable, and pure' (SC: IV, i; 103), just like the ideal woman described in Emile (see Connolly 1988: 63). To think of the general will as the equivalent of the patriarchical description of the virtuous woman is not to deny that a great deal of what is at issue in Rousseau's conception of the general will is the attempt fonnally to define a con-
82 Jay Bemstein ception of willing the general or public good compatible with the preservation of individual autonomy and self-determination. To discuss that issue in full would take us far afield. What needs highlighting here is the evident work of idealizing, fictionmaking, present in Rousseau's unitary descriptions of both the virtuous woman and the general will. In both cases serious difference is written out of Rousseau's account to such an extent that, despite himself, Rousseau comes to think of the ideal state as a spontaneous good, an automatic coordination of the individual and the collective; a unity so spontaneous and automatic that the ideal state would require 'very few laws'; and when new ones were required their necessity would be 'universally seen' such that 'the first man to propose them merely says what all have already felt' (SC: IV, i; 102). Under these conditions the art of politics would disappear, virtue replacing the coordinating activity of legislation. The ideal political order would hence become the suppression of the political, and hence the suppression of the question of difference. The obvious conclusion to be drawn from this analysis is that the only way we can satisfy our conception of difference, one that acknowledges the need and necessity for the art of politics, is to accede to the conception of particular interest in its bourgeois sense. But if we go down that path, then we end up negating every aspect of Rousseau's analysis of modernity, legitimating its inequalities and corruptions with a force equal to Rousseau's critical diagnosis of them. Such a reversal is incompatible with the undeniable logical force of Rousseau's critical activity. How then are we to understand our situation, a situation in which we appear to be required to take a stand for or against Rousseau? What the foregoing analysis reveals is that we, and Rousseau, lack an adequate conception of the difference between particular interest in its bourgeois sense and particular interest in a sense that acknowledges separateness but does not reify individual needs and desires into permanent claims against the public good. Serious difference always appears to reduce to bourgeois self-interest, and the general will always appears to congeal into a unifying power opposed to any particularity. The former view legitimates bourgeois self-interest and hence the liberal state, while the latter view images a utopian suppression of political life like that imaged by the Marxian dictum 'From each according to their ability, to each according to the need.' Is not political philosophy for us now precisely a thinking that refuses this eitherl or? And is not the motive of Rousseau's writing the inscriptIon of a space that accedes neither to the liberal legitimation of the present order nor to the utopian suppression of political life as a whole? We do not possess a full account of difference adequate to the demand that it not be one which would lead to the stirring up of sects and parties. But this failure is neither logical (conceptual) nor historical. On the contrary, the logical critique of Rousseau is just the one that would force us into legitimating the liberal order; while the perception of Rousseau as confronting a contingent historical blockage ends up with a utopian suppression of difference, blaming the conflict of interests on the economic arrangements undergirding the
Difficult difference: Rousseau's fictions of identity 83
liberal state. Both liberal and Marxian analyses share the identification of particular interest and bourgeois interest. Whatever the real or apparent lapses in his thought, Rousseau's entwinement of political education and the writing of fiction was meant to identify the place and possibility of political thought. If fiction marks and limits political life as it now is, so separating it from itself, then the demand that would consign Rousseau's writing to either a logical or a historical fiction amounts to the refusal to engage in political thought; a refusal that is equally the refusal to be educated, to be denatured and reformed, through the strenuous activity of reading. We cannot read Rousseau from either where we are or where we think we ought to be, for both where we are, the world of bourgeois particular interests, and where we ought to be, the fully unified world of a virtuous general will, abstract from the aporia of political life: to love one's city more than oneself.
NOTE This paper is an encapsulation of some of the ideas presented to students in the first year Enlightenment course at the University of Essex over the past dozen years or so. In putting them together for this occasion I have not gone back to the numerous secondary sources that aided my first readings of Rousseau, although I am sure much of what I learned from those sources is present in the above pages. The following works certainly influenced my thinking: Charvet 1974, Masters 1969, Shklar 1969, and Starobinski 1988. If there is a sub-text to this essay, it involves the attempt to think differently about the issues of identity and difference in Rousseau that are formulated by Jacques Derrida 1975.
6 Mercier's Enlightenment utopia: progress and social ideals SIMON COLLIER
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION Anumber of the essays in this book take up the question of how exactly to conceive the relationship between the Enlightenment and the French Revolution. LouisSebastien Mercier, a minor but, Simon Collier suggests, entirely typical Enlightenment philosophe, had no doubt about the directness of the connection: as shown by the title of his book on Rousseau; 'considered as one of the first authors of the French Revolution'. Mercier's own earlier contribution to Enlightenment thought had been as a dramatic theorist of rabidly anti-classicist tendencies and as author of the utopian fiction, L'An 2440 (1771), here given one of its very few serious assessments. In 1516 Thomas More's Utopia gave its name to a literary genre. The classical world had produced versions of the ideal society - most famously Plato's Republic and many variants on the traveller's tale, realistic or openly fictional (Lucian was More's favourite author). Europe's 'discovery of America' in 1492 seems to have revived this genre of imaginative constructions. More's Utopia was one of the earliest pieces of writing to base itself on the news of the new world that circulated slowly through Europe in the early sixteenth century, principally in editions (some forged) of the works of the Florentine Amerigo Vespucci. More's supposed informant about Utopia, Raphael Hythlodaeus, had supposedly been left behind during Vespucci's final voyage to America. More's Utopia is therefore a new world society, though it owes its existence to a conqueror from outside, Utopos, and is itself a colonizing country of some ruthlessness. Significantly, it is also an island, Utopos having inaugurated the space for his social experiment by cutting a channel through the fifteen-mile isthmus that had previously connected Utopia with the mainland. The connection between utopia and island has remained close through the Enlightennlent and into the twentieth century: Francis Bacon's New Atlantis (1626) is a significant example from the
Mercier's Enlightenment utopia: progress and social ideals 85 English prelude to the Enlightenment, Aldous Huxley's Island (1962) the most obvious modern version. These alternative worlds, connected with ours only through the suspicious figure of the traveller (embodied for the Enlightenment by Swift's Gulliver) can offer warnings or stimulus, but always with the security given by distance, operating therefore in those 'imaginary spaces' in which even Descartes conducted his revolutionary thinking. So Mercier's L'An 2440 marks a quite crucial turning point in the conception of the perfect society, now located in the future rather than elsewhere, in other words as a goal towards which our society can progress (the key word, as Collier sho\AJs) no longer, in fact, literally a utopia at all, since the place will be here. The corpus of Mercier's work is located very firmly in that 'here', the Paris in which he lived and worked. In the multi-volumed Le Tableau de Paris Mercier set out to record every aspect of what he knew to be the doomed civilization of corrupt Parisian society (Mercier 1781-8; cf. Rex 1987: 167-8). After the Revolution he tried to chronicle the changes in Le Nouveau Paris (Mercier [1797]; cf. Hampson 1983: 263-70). L'An 2440, though written first, is therefore the final panel of an ambitious Parisian triptych representing past, present, and future. Ironically the Revolution itself, highly conscious of questions of time, took an even more radical step than anything Mercier had envisaged. The Revolutionary Calendar aimed 'to structure and name time anew' (see Brotherston 1982). But for Napoleon, L'An 2440 would have become L'An DCXLVIII.
6
Alas! is public happiness to be no more than a vain dream? Must our wishes and our efforts forever remain ineffective? Let us reject this fatal idea, for it strikes deadly cold into all sensitive souls. Louis-Sebastien Mercier, CAn 2440 (1786), Postscript The relationship of the Enlightenment to utopian writing has sometimes been thought problematic. For Lewis Mumford, for instance, there is 'a gap in the utopian tradition between the seventeenth century and the nineteenth' (Mumford 1962: 113). An excellent recent discussion of the utopian genre claims that the tradition as such was 'increasingly marginal to the main intellectual developments of the age' (Kumar 1987: 37). The most magisterial modern survey of the Enlightenment (Gay 1967-70) ignores the theme completely. It has to be agreed that the eighteenth century did not produce a 'classic' utopia in the manner of More, Bacon, or Campanella earlier on, or Bellamy, Morris, or Wells nearer our own time. It is also true that none of the major Enlightenment figures chose to use the utopian form to articulate social ideals, and that the Encyclopedie contains no article on Utopia. One reason for this, it has often been suggested, is that the Enlightenment's strong predilection for specific, concrete reforms and reform campaigns (Gay 1967-70: 11,398-447) was at odds with the sort of comprehensive vision of radical social reorganization implicit (or often implicit) in the utopian form. David Hume's attitude may perhaps be taken as representative. Though quite prepared to sketch the outline for an ideal constitution and even to put in a good word for Harrington's Oceana (in the essay 'Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth'), he pointedly emphasizes that real·life reforms should preferably be undertaken 'by such gentle alterations and innovations as may not give too great a disturbance to society' (Hume 1963: 500). Despite this consideration, there was undoubtedly a sizeable undergrowth of utopian or semi-utopian writing in the eighteenth century (Manuel and Manuel
Mercier's Enlightenment utopia: progress and social ideals 87
Figure 11 'This print represents the republican calendar of Year III (22 September 1794-22 September 1795) and shows the changes in the names of the months that reflect the agricultural emphasis decreed by the Law of 24 November 1795.... From the "great book of nature" Philosophy dictates the principles of the new calendar to her attentive genius. At her side are the book of morals and the triangle of equality resting on a base, the inscription of which proclaims the unity and indivisibility of the French Republic. Supported by the laws of nature, the new calendar is thus shown to be based upon rational principles and the civic virtues espoused by the revolutionary government' (Cuno 1988: 227-8).
88 Simon Collier 1979: 430-5; Rose 1987), some of it partly subsumed by the literature of fantasy, adventure, or pornography, some of it directly or indirectly critical of ancien regime abuses and anomalies, which were indeed often a target for imaginative literature in general (Mornet 1967: 251-8). Fpr much of the eighteenth century, utopian writing conformed to the model invented (we have to say invented, since all precedents are dubious) by Thomas More in 1515-16. More's utopia, it will be recalled, was located on a remote island, but definitely in More's own time. Inaccessibility and contemporaneity were thus the hallmarks of most subsequent utopias. It is precisely in terms of this original model that the impact of the Enlightenment was most decisive, largely owing to the emergence of the idea of progress. It is not necessary here to discuss the ways in which this all-important concept gradually (and somewhat tentatively) entered the Enlightenment (Gay 1967-70: II, 84-125; Bury 1955: 127-216; Pollard 1971: 31-103), especially the later Enlightenment. What is more interesting for our purposes is to note that the symptoms of its arrival included a new fashion for speculating about the future, often in optimistic terms. One of the first known texts to embody this was an anonymous English novel, The Reign ofGeorge It], 1900-1925 (1763), a power-fantasy showing a future British empire repelling a Russian invasion and dominating Europe. Round about 1770, too, the abbe Galiani, that popular philosophe, planned (though did not write) a novel portraying the twentieth century. Speculative forecasts (halffanciful, half-serious) can be found scattered throughout the literature of the period. Well-known English examples include Horace Walpole's aside that travellers from Peru might some day gaze on the ruins of St Paul's Cathedral (Walpole 1937-83: XXIV, 62), and Gibbon's surmise that there would be observatories in the interior of Russia and North America by the twenty-third century (Gibbon 1896-1900: IV, 434). In retrospect it might seem obvious that this futuristic trend would fairly quickly colour utopian literature, that the setting for utopia would undergo a time-shift. The vital step was first taken by Louis-Sebastien Mercier (1740-1814) in his anonymously published L'An deux mille quatre cent quarante, reve s'il en fut jamais (Amsterdam 1771), the first utopia to be located in the future. Quite what impelled Mercier to write it we do not know, but it marked the most significant change in the utopian form since the sixteenth century, and its implications were profound for subsequent utopian writing, not to mention twentiethcentury dystopian writing and science fiction. It is not the purpose of this essay to claim Mercier as a major figure of the Enlightenment. He was none the less very well known in the 1770s and 1780s as a tireless (in fact rather compulsive) homme de lettres of enlightened ideas. His most famous work, Le tableau de Paris (6 volumes, 1781-8), is a rich account of Parisian society still frequently mined by historians. But Mercier, a man of modest bourgeois background, also wrote essays, poems, and novels, and was especially prolific as a dramatist, enjoying a particular influence in Germany. His dramatic theory rejected classical models and favoured the kind of drame bourgeois which Diderot had espoused, though Mercier took it further (Majewski 1971: 159-86). The coming of
Mercier's Enlightenment utopia: progress and social ideals 89 the Revolution gave him new roles as journalist and legislator. As a politician, Mercier was ineffective but courageous, opposing the rising Jacobin dictatorship'You are ignorance personified!' he once shouted at Robespierre (Monselet 1857: I, 71). Not surprisingly he found himself in prison in 1793-4, and might have been guillotined had it not been for Robespierre's fall. His initial admiration for Napoleon did not survive into the Consulate and Empire. By now the 'very funny, witty old man' Tom Paine described in 1801 (Aldridge 1959: 266) was becoming famous for his contrariness and eccentricity. Welcoming the prospect of the Bourbon restoration, Mercier died while Napoleon was on his way to Elba. Mercier regarded himself as a fervent disciple of Rousseau, whose acquaintance he made after 1770 (Beclard 1903: 76-82). He was not an uncritical disciple, however, and by no means deserved the nickname - Ie singe de Jean-Jacques, 'JeanJacques' ape' - given him in the later 1790s. The two-volume treatise Mercier wrote to acclaim his hero as the supreme precursor of the Revolution (Mercier 1791), takes issue with Rousseau's political theory at several points, and misrepresents it at others. Nor was Mercier much influenced by Rousseau's distaste for the city and admiration for 'savage' man. What seems to have impressed him most was Rousseau's general democratic attitude, his sincerity and sensitivity - 'No philosophe ever wrote closer to mankind ...; no writer ever made so serious a concern of our happiness' (Mercier 1791: I, 20). L'An 2440 was Mercier's first success as a writer. The book was banned in France, by the Holy Office, and throughout the Sr anish empire. It inspired a crop of imitations and itself had at least a dozen further editions (several pirated) during the author's lifetime, after which it was not fully reprinted again until the 1970s (Bordeaux, 1971; Paris, 1977; Geneva 1979 (facsimile of the edition of 1799)). An English translation soon appeared, with the date in the title altered to 2500 'for the sake of a round number', as the translator put it, ignoring that for Mercier 2440 was a very round number, his 700th birthday. In 1786 Mercier published a second version of the book, simply expanding the number of chapters from forty-four to eighty-two and adding innumerable footnotes: these offer a running commentary on the main text. The best modern editor ofL'An 2440, Raymond Trousson, plausibly claims this amplification of the book 'ended up by killing it' (Mercier 1971: 73). The additional matter, which includes a gratuitously anti-Semitic chapter (ch. 79), does not greatly enhance the utopia. There are at least two good reasons for taking a closer look at this book. In histories of the utopian genre, it is more often mentioned (albeit honourably) than discussed, and it clearly possesses an intrinsic interest as the first futuristic utopia. More important than this, for our purposes, is the fact thatL'An 2440 is an Enlightenment utopia - one might even say the classic Enlightenment utopia. Adiscussion of its main features gives us an unusual portrayal of Enlightenment social ideals as adumbrated in this fantasized form. As with most utopias, the plot of L'An 2440 does not amount to very much. The basic device, much imitated by writers since Mercier's time, is that of the 'sleeper
90 Simon Collier awakening' in this case, the Narrator has retired to bed after a conversation with an English visitor to Paris who has denounced the horrors of modern urban life: squalor, traffic congestion, 'the horrible disproportion of fortunes' (Mercier 1772: 1,11). The Narrator awakes to discover that he has become immensely old. From an inscription in the street he learns that he is now in 'the year of grace 2440'. Some twenty-fifth century Parisians greet him politely, showing n~ surprise that he comes from the eighteenth century. They escort him to a tailor's, where he is clothed in the very simple, rational attire - 'a sort of vest covered with a cloak' (I, 22) - now apparently in universal use. After this, the Narrator is simply given an extended tour of Paris. Mercier adopts the very conventional utopian scheme of visitor-and-guide; the various guides thus tell the Narrator all he wants to know about the twenty-fifth century. Forty-one (or in the 1786 version, seventy-nine) chapters later, he decides to visit Versailles. He finds a heavily symbolic scene of 'ruins, gaping walls and mutilated statues' (II, 246). An extremely old man is sitting disconsolately among the wreckage. He turns out to be King Louis XIV. But before he can interrogate the monarch, the Narrator is bitten by an adder. At this point both the dream and the book come to a very abrupt end. The Narrator's first impressions of the twenty-fifth century are obviously of the enormously improved state of Paris. The city now has 'grand and beautiful streets ... built in straight lines' (I, 16-17); at night these are brilliantly illuminated, and, most astonishing of all, are not thronged with prostitutes. The scene in the streets is anin1ated but very orderly. The horse-drawn carriages (mostly carrying goods) observe a rule of the road by keeping to the right. The street porters carry only moderate weights. There are no luxury coaches to be seen. 'The nobles of our day', the Narrator is told, 'use their legs, and therefore have more money and less of the gout' (I, 29). Just a few coaches are allowed, for elderly magistrates or public servants, but should one of these injure a pedestrian (Mercier writes with feeling; in real life he was knocked down three times) the owner has to supply the injured party with a carriage for the rest of his life - a democratic modification of the deodand principle (which in England disappeared only in 1846). Rather disappointingly, perhaps, the physical fabric of twenty-fifth century Paris is mostly described in generalities - regular streets, open squares, etc. Our overall impression is of an eighteenth-century Paris tidied up, cleaned, rationalized. Thus a fountain of clear water now stands at every street corner. Private houses are spacious and airy; most rooftops have potted flowers and trellises, giving the city (as seen from above) the appearance of un vaste jardin (Mercier 1971: 114), a vast garden. The Louvre (still unfinished in 1771) has been completed, but is used as a residence for artists, not as a palace. The Bastille has been demolished and replaced by a Temple of Clemency. The oldest bridge in Paris, the Pont Neuf, has been renamed the Pont Henri IV - Mercier shared the French Enlightenment's admiration for Ie bon roi. Beyond such material changes, an immense transformation has come over society. All noble privileges have been suppressed: Mercier's obvious pleasure in
Mercier's Enlightenment utopia: progress and social ideals 91 recounting this is heavily reinforced in the 1786 version (Mercier 1787: III, 98-103). There are still differences of wealth and status, but these derive from merit and service alone. Complete social levelling is regarded in the twenty-fifth century as impossible: 'extreme equality would necessarily produce extreme confusion' (III, 71). The general atmosphere, however, is definitely egalitarian. Servants dine with their masters; peasants are regarded as honourable. Moreover wealth carries social obligations: it is now used to promote scientific experiments or to build 'majestic edifices' for public use. Since there are no taverns in Paris any more, the richest citizens keep open house for strangers or the needy. Obviously this system might be abused; monitors are on hand to investigate, and habitual free-loaders are assigned work or even banished from the city. The position of women has also changed for the better. On this score Mercier has little interest in the sexual experimentation favoured by other utopian writers, such as his great friend Restif de la Bretonne. His vision is one of rational domesticity. Women in 2440 no longer do strenuous jobs (such as street portering) and now devote themselves to the upbringing of their children, not least their early religious instruction. Coquettishness is unknown; women improve their minds. Our wives are what were those of the ancient Gauls, sincere and amiable companions, whom we respect and consult on all occasions.... Our women are wives and mothers, and from these two virtues all others are derived. They would dishonour themselves were they to daub their faces with paint, or stuff their heads with snuff ..., if they were to sit up all night or sing licentious songs, or practise the least indecency with men. (Mercier 1772: I, 254-61) Dowries are unknown in 2440. Marriages are love-matches. Divorce, about which there is an extended discussion in the 1786 version (Mercier 1787: III, 13-20), is permitted, rather in the manner of ancient Rome, but is not much used. Family life appears to be natural and unforced, though wives and children are still rather deferential to the masters of households. The economic basis of twenty-fifth century society is only lightly sketched. Property is still mostly private. Paris obviously contains the fulLrange of crafts and manufactures which a man from 1770 would expect to find; there is, perhaps, a general implication that these have become more sophisticated. Hours of work are much reduced. The countryside is peopled by free peasants (feudal obligations having presumably lapsed), who live a more or less idyllic existence, their numerous 'intervals of repose' being filled with 'sports or rural dances' (Mercier 1772: I, 182). On his way to Versailles, the Narrator drops in on the funeral of a peasant, a model of reason and virtue to judge from the funeral oration (ch. 43/69) - a piece of writing which Herder thought did honour to the human race (Mercier 1971: 67). Trade within France has been liberalized: the vision here is broadly physiocratic. Public granaries (this is rather less physiocratic) even out the grain-supply; there is no inflation.
92 Simon Collier Mercier plainly could not make up his mind about how to handle foreign trade in his utopia. In the 1771 version of L'An 2440 it is limited to no more than 'an exchange of superfluities' between France and the New World, certain commodities like coffee, tea and snuff being banned altogether as poisons (Mercier 1772: II, 185). Overseas trade is strongly disapproved of as (and here we come to one of Mercier's key ideas) a principal cause of luxury. Luxury distorts a truly sound economy; it has therefore been phased out through sumptuary legislation. Thus diamonds in the world of 2440 are dumped into the sea. The 1786 version (without the earlier text being altered in any way) allows a much larger role for foreign trade - we are told of vast fleets distributing French goods to a suitably grateful world (Mercier 1787: II, 201-4) - and even for luxury which, provided that it is not ostentatious or excessive, can be justified on economic grounds. In any case, the emotion of envy is unknown in the world of 2440, since wealth is always used rationally. Rationality certainly strikes the keynote in this utopia. The twenty-fifth century citizen 'attends to the voice of nature only, subject to the law of reason, and reason directs him to happiness' (Mercier 1772: II, 168). Nature is thus a fundamental reference-point, a key term throughout the book. 'The laws of nature are all around us,' adds Mercier in the 1786 version, 'and it is the tumult of the world that prevents us from understanding their lessons' (Mercier, 1787: 11,211). It might be remarked here that Mercier's use of nature as a master-concept reflects the early rather than the later Enlightenment. It does not take into account the tensions and ambiguities of the concept being explored by other writers at the time L'An 2440 appeared (Pilkington 1986). However rational and natural people may have become, some sort of political structure is necessary. This is not an anarchist utopia. The political theories of twenty-fifth-century France are explained succinctly in the 1771 version (ch.36) and more lengthily and vacuously in the 1786 version (Mercier 1787: II, 205-17; III, 70-5) by a professor of politics - professors of politics have evidently not changed much in six centuries. They are liberal, constitutional, and moderate, with a strong emphasis on freedom of thought and expression, for 'the liberty of the press is the true measure of the liberty of the people' (Mercier 1772: I, 60). Forms of government are unimportant in themselves; what matters is that all political systems 'should be based on natural law' (Mercier 1787: II, 211). Since monarchy is 'a necessary part in a well-ordered government, above all when the population is numerous' (III, 182), France in 2440 still has a king - called Louis XXXIV in the 1786 version (II, 223) - but he no longer dazzles his people with Versailles-style grandeur, and he retires at seventy. His audience chamber is open to the public once every week; his throne is a plain chair (albeit of ivory) and his uniform an olive branch and a blue cloak. Indeed, the monarch often walks the streets, for he 'loves to observe that natural equality which ought to reign among men' (Mercier 1772: I, 30). Absolutism, of course, is a thing of the past: Louis XXXIV is a constitutional monarch, governing with the help of a Senate and accountable to the Estates General, which meets every two years. No precise electoral mechanisms are mentioned. The provinces of France enjoy a degree of autonomy. The system of
Mercier's Enlightenment utopia: progress and social ideals 93 taxation is uniform and simple: there is a 2 per cent income tax, from which the less well-off are exempt, supplemented by voluntary contributions (very frequent) from the better-off. The laws in 2440 are mild, humane, and efficiently enforced. A kind of police force settles disputes among the citizens and reports to the magistrates. Lawyers (often excluded altogether from utopias) are incorruptible and act purely as counsel for the defence. Not even utopia, of course, is entirely crime-free. Convicted criminals are exposed for a time in fetters and then sent to labour on public works projects. Three convictions mean banishment from France. Capital punishment (now by firing squad) is optional: a condemned man can choose to live on, in public disgrace. By a happy coincidence, the Narrator witnesses the first execution in thirty years. It is an awesome ceremony (attended by the whole Senate) in which the murderer, having chosen death rather than disgrace, is formally forgiven by society before being shot. While the institutions of 2440 are both rational and 'natural', they do not keep the utopia going by themselves. As the Narrator bluntly suggests to his guides, 'if faut une religion' (Mercier 1971: 172), 'there must be a religion'. This would have seemed self-evident to most of Mercier's readers. However enlightened they were, many philosophes were nervous about discarding religion as an element in social stability (Gay 1967-70: II, 517-28). Mercier, an emotional deist in the manner of Rousseau's Savoyard vicar, is far more interested in this than he is in the economic or even social details of his fantasy-world. The twenty-fifth century has naturally abandoned Christianity. Deism is now the official religion of France and by implication everywhere else, for even the Pope, we learn, nowadays spends his time refining 'a code of rational and affecting morality', and has recently published a Catechism of Human Reason (Mercier 1772: II, 231). The twenty-fifth-century hierarchy is fairly informal. It consists of a 'prelate', who goes around on foot just like the king, and priests - 'wise, experienced and friends to toleration' (I, 123) who sound very like modern social workers. There are even a few deist 'saints': these typically volunteer for jobs such as street-cleaning or fire-fighting, 'animated by the grand and sublime idea of being useful members of society' (I, 126). Over the entrance of the main deist temple in Paris is inscribed a verse which effectively encapsulates twenty-fifth-century theology:
'Loin de rien decider sur cet Etre Supreme, Gardons, en l'adorant, un silence profond; Sa nature est immense, et l'esprit s'y confond, Pour savoir ce qu'il est, il faut etre lui-meme. (I, 130) Far from deciding anything about this Supreme Being Let us adore him in profound silence; His nature is immense, and astounds our spirits. To know what he is, one would have to be him.
94 Simon Collier The great dome surmounting the temple is made of glass, thus enabling worshippers to reflect on God and nature, dark clouds symbolizing life's disagreeable moments, thunderstorms revealing the· power of the divinity, and so on. Mercier also gives us the full text of the daily prayer offered in the temple, part of which runs as follows: thy goodness is equal to thy power; all things declare it, but above all our own hearts. If some transient evils here afflict us, it is doubtless because they are inevitable.... Thou hast deigned to speak to us by the voice of nature only. (1, 138) Certain rituals reinforce this natural religion. First communion, for instance, consists of a youngster being taken to an observatory and made to look through both a telescope and a microscope, so as to 'behold the God of the universe, who reveals himself ... in the midst of his works'. Funerals in 2440 tend to be rather upbeat occasions, since death is clearly a part of nature. Certain beliefs about the afterlife are retained in the twenty-fifth century: it is held that souls are successively reincarnated on different planets, gradually ascending towards final perfection. For inferior spirits, a downward movement is possible: a bad king, for instance, might be reborn as a mole (I, 44). Mercier himself considered this 'system' of metempsychosis to be much better than Pythagoras' and it must be said here that his interest in the spiritual and the supernatural was a strong one (Majewski 1971: 25-77). Mercier was fiercely anti-materialist. For all his anticlericalism he is not someone we would place in the company of La Mettrie, Helvetius, d'Holbach or (let us not forget the northern giant who outshone them all) David Hume. The deist civic religion is more or less universal, and it is a testimony to Mercier's democratic impulse that he makes it so: there is no suggestion of one religion for the elite, one for the masses. Persistent atheism incurs banishment in 2440. Normally, though, atheists are first offered 'an assiduous course of experimental physics' (Mercier 1772: I, 260), which seems to cure all but the most recalcitrant. As in many utopias, the question of education is given a thorough airing in L 'An 2440. The standard elementary-level textbook is now the Encylopedie - '0 what a flight you must have taken towards the higher sciences!' exclaims the Narrator when told this (I, 66). Algebra and physics loom large in the secondary syllabus; modern (but certainly not dead) languages are sometimes taught, but history is not, for 'history is the disgrace of humanity, every page being crowded with crimes and follies' (I, 73). Un tissu de crimes et folies - did Gibbon half-remember this when devising his own more famous phrase? (He had a copy of L'An 2440 in his library.) Very similar principles underlie higher education. The Sorbonne, which now teaches only in French, eschews theology, a pointless subject, and history, a dangerous subject, and concentrates on disc'iplines 'useful to humanity' astronomy, for instance, and medicine. Here we must note that something like a wholesale transformation of medicine has taken place. The Hotel Dieu, Paris's old central hospital, no longer exists; some twenty new hospitals are dotted round the
Mercier's Enlightenment utopia: progress and social ideals 95 city's perimeter; there is also a hospital for inoculation, the merits of which were being hotly debated at the time Mercier was writing. Most astonishing of all, people in 2440 now go to hospital not to die but to be cured (I, 47). The medical profession, no longer venal or status-conscious, goes in for scientific diagnosis. It has been discovered that all 'disorders ... proceed from the coagulation of the blood and humours' (I, 83). (The English translator was a doctor, and added a footnote here, explaining that this was 'not strictly true'.) Preventive medicine also flourishes in the twenty-fifth century: The hygiena especially is so clearly investigated, that each one is able to take care of his own health. We do not depend entirely on the physician, however skillful soever he may be.... Temperance, moreover, that true restorative and conservative elixir, contributes to form bodies healthful and vigorous, and that contain minds pure and strong as their blood. (I, 86) The pronounced aversion to history shown in twenty-fifth-century educational policy is very deliberate. To a large extent the utopia has tried to censor those aspects of the past that might disturb the tranquil present - not altogether successfully, the reader may feel, since the Narrator's guides seem amazingly well informed about the shortcomings of the eighteenth century. At some point in the past an enormous bonfire of discreditable literature has been staged: 'nothing leads the mind further astray than bad books,' the royal librarian explains. 'What remained for us to do but to rebuild the structure of human knowledge?' - reedifier l'edifice des connaissances humaines (Mercier 1971: 248). The books that remain occupy no more than a small cabinet. Among classical authors, Herodotus, Sappho, Aristophanes, and Lucretius have been consigned to the flames; Ovid survives in a censored version, as does Horace; Tacitus is accessible only by special permit. English writers have mostly escaped the bonfire, except for a few 'sceptical philosophers' (unnamed). But much of French literature has gone up in smoke: Descartes, Fenelon and the abbe de Saint Pierre are still there, but only a selection from Voltaire, for, while Voltaire had 'the first ... of the virtues, the love of humanity', he also wrote 'insipid and gross reflections against Jean-Jacques Rousseau' (Mercier 1772: II, 28). Rousseau's works, of course, have survived the holocaust in their entirety. Although the classics of the past may have been fierily censored in this way, a high stress is placed on creativity in 2440. Practically every citizen is a writer. The French Academy, located in an idyllic rural park on Montmartre, is open to all comers. Just occasionally, however, writers incur public censure by expressing 'dangerous principles such as are inconsistent with sound morality, that universal morality which speaks to the heart' (I, 58). Such writers are obliged to wear black masks, which can only be removed when they have mended their ways with the help of two citizens assigned the task of moral rectification. All the arts in 2440 tend to embody correct social principles. When the Narrator goes to the theatre, the play
96 Simon Collier he sees is based on the Calas affair, the affair Voltaire had taken up so forcefully in the early 1760s. Painting, for its part, is 'only employed to inspire sentiments of virtue' (II, 93); certainly the examples described by the Narrator are heavily didactic. Likewise sculpture: the most impressive piece seen by the Narrator is a huge monument to Humanity, with statues personifying the European nations in suitably penitential attitudes: France, on her knees, implored pardon for the horrible night of St Bartholomew, for the cruel Revocation of the Edict of Nantes, and for the persecution of those noble sages that sprang from her bosom ... Germany saw with horror the history of her ... frantic theologic rage ... Spain, still more criminal than her sisters, groaned at the thought of having covered the new continent with thirty-five million carcasses.... The figure of Spain was composed of a marble veined with blood; and those frightful streaks are as indelible as the memory of her crimes. (I, 167-9) The focus of L'An 2440, as we have seen, is Paris. Mercier devotes relatively little space to the world beyond, but there clearly is a world beyond. In the 1771 version, war has more or less disappeared. Should it recur, France would rely on sending her enemy 'pestiferous works' of theology (normally kept under lock and key) as her psychological ultimate weapon. In 1786 Mercier was slightly less eirenic: he allows France a small army of 40,000, though tells us that periods of peace now often last for more than a century (Mercier 1787: 111,119-21). Relations between France and England, however, are permanently amicable: Our learning and arts unite us in a communication equally advantageous. The English ... have improved the French, who abound in levity; and we Frenchmen have dissipated surprisingly the melancholy humour of the English. (Mercier 1772: I, 109) Here the English translator has seriously modified Mercier's sense: in the original it is les Anglaises and nos Franr;aises who are the active agents of this mutual character-modification. Further afield, in the American continent, there has been a vast revolutionary upheaval, led by a black slave - a statue of this liberator stands in Paris - and resulting in two independent empires (one of them ruled by a restored Aztec dynasty) covering North and South America. It is interesting to remember here that the abbe Raynal's great book on European imperialism, which also speculates that there might some day be a black Spartacus in the Caribbean (Raynal 1776: III, 465-6), was published at much the same time as L'An 2440. Mercier offers few details of the American upheaval, though we learn that Pennsylvania continues to flourish, under the benign influence of the Quakers. The Narrator discovers these things by glancing at some newspapers in an episode towards the end of the book. We learn from these that in Spain, for instance, the name Dominic (that of the
Mercier's Enlightenment utopia: progress and social ideals 97 founder of the odious Inquisition) has become prohibited and that Philip II is to be struck off the list of Spanish kings. In Paraguay, the expulsion of the Jesuits (673 years earlier) has recently been commemorated. China now uses French as a second language, and has adopted a western-style alphabet. The Japanese, who have just issued a translation of Montesquieu, have now given up ritual suicide, since this is clearly irrational. States like Russia, Poland, and Turkey (a republic) now enjoy liberal forms of government. England is more or less the leading nation in Europe. London has grown in size by no less than three times. The English continue to bask in 'the ancient glory of having offered to their neighbours the example of that form of government which becomes men jealous of their rights and happiness' (II, 235). As usual, Mercier could not resist adding a few more details about this future world when he prepared the 1786 version of his book. We learn here that France exercises a beneficent imperialism over Greece and Egypt, that Portugal is now part of England, that Africa (with a good deal of French help) is completely civilized, and .that Europeans have refrained from conquering India. There is no international language as such in the twenty-fifth century, but certain languages are used worldwide for specialized purposes: German for science, English for poetry and history, French for politics and novel-writing, etc. There is one clear implication that can be drawn from these scattered hints. Utopia is not confined to Paris or even to France. The Enlightenment has prevailed everywhere by the twenty-fifth century; the world as a whole is now reorganized along utopian lines. It seems arguable that Mercier, in addition to being the first author to locate utopia in the future, is also the first to make the whole planet its setting. Such, in the thematic outline, is Mercier's view of the future. It has at least two general features that can do with further elaboration. The first thing that a late twentieth-century eye notices about L 'An 2440 is the unadventurousness of its technological speculations. In so far as it is described at all, the technology of the twentyfifth century is not much of an advance on that of the eighteenth. Great canals, artificial waterfalls, towers on mountain-tops, flexible glass, improvements in lifting gear - none of these things suggests a striking breakthrough in applied science. More imaginatively, perhaps, Mercier visualizes a kind of sound-reproduction device, but it does not resemble the gramophone invented just over a century after he wrote. A few additional forecasts appear in the 1786 version: a long-distance signalling system is mentioned, and the Narrator sees a large balloon or airship ('une machine immense') descend into a city square, having carried eight mandarins from China in just over a week (Mercier 1787: II, 189). This latter idea was only too obviously an 'update' inspired by the Montgolfiers' exploits, about which Mercier had been enthusiastic. In general, Mercier's technological imagination was not very developed. It is not quite enough to say that he was inevitabty constrained by his pre-industrial world. Other writers of the period were able to intuit technological progress in more ambitious ways. Indeed, the glimpses of scientific potential in L 'An 2440 are much less comprehensive than those in Bacon's New Atlantis.
98 Simon Collier Too much should not be made of this. Daring scientific prophecy is not in any sense obligatory in the utopian genre, nor in fact all that common. (H. G. Wells' A ]\lodem Utopia, for instance, is much less exciting in this respect than his imaginative fiction.) Mercier's cautiousness in these matters does not mean that the idea of progress as such is any the less implicit in L'An 2440. Conventional as the utopia is in many ways, it is distinctly innovative on this score. To take the most obvious point: to locate utopia in a Paris shifted into the future, rather than on a remote island, could not have been done at all without recourse to some such concept. Moreover, unlike its predecessors, this is not a static, fixed utopia; it is not a place where history has stopped; it has its own in-built dynamism. As the Narrator is told, Our century will be surpassed, beyond any doubt. . . . The more we become enlightened, the more we realize how much more there remains to be done. ... Where does the perfectibility of man stop, when he is armed with geometry, chemical knowledge and the mechanical arts? (Mercier 1787: II, 231-3, my emphasis) Progress is thus definitely incorporated into the utopian scheme. Mercier is less satisfactory in identifying the mechanisms of progress, though again this is not strictly necessary for the utopian form. How has France actually achieved its admirable twenty-fifth-century condition? Whatever may have happened across the Atlantic, there has certainly been no French Revolution. At one point, it is true, Mercier makes an aside abo~t the 'horrid remedy' of civil war, inevitable in states that are sunk in stupor (Mercier 1772: II, 119). Daniel Mornet has seen this as the clearest of all the calls for revolution prior to 1789 (Mornet 1967: 239). But Mercier makes the remark in a footnote, and could as easily have been looking backwards as forwards. All that the Narrator is told, when he inquires into the process of change in France, is that sometime in the past a 'philosophic prince' restored all power to the Estates General. No date (or even century) is given for this event, but, as the Narrator is somewhat patronizingly told, even in the eighteenth century 'it was foreseen that reason would one day make great progress' (Mercier 1772: II, 135). In other words, the political and social transformation has been gradual, essentially 'the work of philosophy' (I, 123), aided not least by the printing press which, 'by enlightening mankind, has produced this grand revolution' (I, 209-10). This theme is reinforced in the 1786 version, where we are informed that the revolution happened tres aisement, 'very easily' - all that was needed, apparently, was 'a dominant idea and a point of maturity' (Mercier 1787: III, 79). That the spread of enlightened ideas through 'philosophic' writings would inevitably bring about beneficial changes seems to have been one of Mercier's more consistently held ideas. In 1791, for example, he insisted that the Revolution had been 'entirely prepared by the genius of letters' (Mercier 1791: II, 222, his emphasis). Arecent analysis of his later writings suggests that he even attributed the revolutionary excesses of the 1790s to an inadequate understanding of books (Frantz 1988: 102-3). It would be wrong to see this as an unusual view in the
Mercier's Enlightenment utopia: progress and social ideals 99 context of the emergence of the idea of progress. Both Turgot and Condorcet, the authors of the two classic eighteenth-century statements of the idea, regarded the steady accumulation of ideas and knowledge as the principal key to future improvement (Manuel and Manuel 1979: 461-518). For more explicitly economic or sociological theories (or proto-theories) of progress, we have to turn elsewhere, to the Scottish Enlightenment, whose insights were only fully taken up in the grand nineteenth-century formulations of the idea. A modern scholar has observed that 'most critics concede very little measure of originality to Mercier' (Majewski 1971: 115). Mercier's originality in constructing a utopia that incorporates the idea of progress certainly merits more recognition than it commonly receives. Nor is his writing by any means lacklustre or pedestrian: L 'An 2440 has its entertaining moments as well as its longueurs, which only become really monotonous in the expanded version. In any case, the less prominent writers of a given period are sometimes more representative than its major figures, more likely (for their very lack of originality, even, one might say, their banality) to mirror a wide cluster of conventional attitudes. From the brief description of the utopia given here, it should be easy enough to see that L 'An 2440, building on the familiar nature-reason-happiness trinity of the Enlightenment, represents a projection into the future of virtually every aspect of the Enlightenment programme of reform: equality of rights, political liberalism, administrative simplification, scientific advance, humanitarian justice - they are all there. Mercier naturally adds flourishes of his own, notably in his moralistic decimation of past classics and his emotional approach to natural religion. Where his touch is less assured - in his varying discussions of foreign trade and luxury, for instance - he is often reflecting genuine differences of view within the Enlightenment. Yet considering L'An 2440 as a whole, it can hardly be doubted that by taking the common reform ideas of his own time and actualizing them - trying to guess what they might look like in practice in an imagined future world, Mercier offers an unusually vivid pi~ture of the Enlightenment's social ideals. The very fact that L 'An 2440 is a projection of a specific reform programme marks its essential novelty when set alongside the classic utopias of earlier times. All utopias without exception convey the message that society could be better organized. Thomas More's certainly did, but More never seriously expected his utopia to be realized in practice, and says as much at the end of his book. Mercier, by contrast, presents us with the image of a possible future, perhaps even a probable future. To what extent is the new variant of utopia a call to political action? Parts of Mercier's imagined future came rather more quickly than he thought - even (though Mercier was behind bars at the time) an attempt to set up a deist civic religion. There is no evidence that Mercier expected the collapse of the ancien regime, or that he advocated anything other than the monarchie refondue about which he had fantasized in L'An 2440. But when Enlightenment-inspired reforms did take place, in the Revolution, Mercier responded with evident enthusiasm, and could not refrain from claiming credit for having predicted them in the first place
100 Simon Collier (Mercier 1971: 49-50), even (in the preface to the 1799 edition of his book) asserting that he was the true prophet of the Revolution. L 'An 2440 suffers from many of the inherent limitations of its genre. Its characterization is non-existent - this is something that tends to be feeble even in fully novelized utopias such as Aldous Huxley's Island (1962). Like most utopias, too, it is sometimes self-contradictory and inconsistent. The reiterated emphasis on freedom we find in the book does not square well with the wholesale censorship of the past and the limitations on artistic expression which seem to exist in the twentyfifth century. Should atheists really be banished? It is pointless to pursue this theme very far. Such inconsistencies simply reflect the eternal dilemma of all utopias: how can the inhabitants of utopia (or most of them) be made, and credibly made, to behave in an appropriately utopian fashion? The reign of virtue, as Robespierre discovered to his cost, can only be brought about when everyone is willing to be virtuous. In real life it means guillotining atheists and keeping men like LouisSebastien Mercier in prison. With all its limitations, Mercier's version of the old European dream of the Just City remains a useful testimony to the Enlightenment's essentially humane and optimistic social ideals, and to the hopes beginning to be attached to the embryonic idea of progress. His picture of the world of King Louis XXXIV tells us nothing - how could it? - about the twenty-fifth century; it tells us a good deal about the eighteenth, and how an intelligent, lively Parisian of 1770 imagined the kind of world to which a triumphant Enlightenment might some day lead. As we now know, it did not. NOTE Quotations from Mercier's first version of L'An 2440 (1771) are taken from the 1772 translation, which is usually very accurate. Quotations from the 1786 version (which is identical to the third, 1799 version) are my own translations from the French.
7
Adam Ferguson and the enterprise culture TED BENTON
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION Mercier's commitment to the notion of 'progress' connects him with his more illustrious contemporaries, Turgot and Condorcet, whose respective books on the 'progress of the human spirit' embody the optimistic Enlightenment ideal of the perfectibility of man. But these philosophes - though often taken as representative - in fact stand, as Peter Gay put it, 'at the bright end of the spectrum of enlightenment thought' (Gay 1964-70: I, 271). In many ways more representative of the comparative method through which the foundations of modern historiography, anthropology and sociology were laid, is the tradition of Vico, Montesquieu, and Rousseau, tolerant and speculative, which found its culmination in the works of the Scottish Enlightenment, pre-eminently Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations (1776), John Millar's Observations Concerning the Distinctions of Rank in Society (1771), William Robertson's History ofAmerica (1777), and - the subject of Ted Benton's essay - Adam Ferguson's Essay on the History of Civil Society (1767). Ferguson was particularly well placed to make his enquiry. Rousseau's personal and imaginative odyssey had enabled him to contrast the corrupt manners of urban France with more authentic forms of life - with the Caribs of the West Indies seen as the best example of an existing people 'least of all deviated from the state of nature' (Rousseau 1973: 71). Ferguson, however, grew up on the very frontier of a dramatic confrontation between the burgeoning commercial civilization of lowland Scotland and the clan-based pastoralism of the Highlands. The complexity underlying such confrontations is instructive. The dominant forces were sometimes seen as civilization against barbarism, but also as Protestantism against Catholicism, and commercial urban life against primitive agricuTture. These polarities that were so deeply embedded in the experience of educated eighteenth-century Scots provided an extremely powerful set of categories around which the history of civil society could be built.
102 Ted Benton The cultural cosmopolitanism of that milieu probably explains why the Highlands themselves are not mentioned in Ferguson's Essay, though there is little doubt that they were a formative influence on his thinking. But Ferguson was certainly no Walter Scott, whose Waverley, written right at the end of our period (1814), sentimentalizes the I-Iighlands even as it views the destruction of their culture as an inevitable aspect of the progress of civilization. Ferguson's abstraction from his concrete circumstances - although there are plentiful references to the classics and to travellers such as Charlevoix and Lafitau - allows him a more general reflection on the characteristics of different forms of civil society (though, like Smith and Marx, his primary interest was undoubtedly in understanding the contemporary scene). As Benton points out, Ferguson's distinctive break with writers· like Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau was to abandon as misgUided the search for some 'original' state of nature prior to society. Ferguson quotes Montesquieu's lapidary remark from the' Persian Letters: 'Man is born in society and there he remains' (Letter XCIV). Nor, on the other hand, did Ferguson concern himself too much with the stadial theory of development which found its most sophisticated form in Marx's theory of the modes of production. Rather, he worked with some flexible distinctions between 'savagery', 'barbarism', and 'refinement', and was less interested in formalizing his categories or in seeking explanation for historical change than in analysing the operation of the forces which were beginning to alter the workings of the moral economy of European societies.
7
Under the appellation 'the New Enlightenment', a certain view of human well-being and its institutional preconditions, is currently in vogue. According to this view the liberty and security of the individual are the principal - or exclusive - constituents of the good life. The purpose of government is to preserve this liberty and security, and whatever it attempts to do beyond this purpose is a despotic offence against the liberty of its subjects. Liberty consists in freedom of choice, and this, in turn, is taken to be equivalent to, or strongly dependent upon, the institutionalized market exchanges of private property owners. The defence of property ownership, and the promulgation of the market is, it follows, the principal purpose of government. One of the most appealing features of this view is that, unlike so many other utopian visions, it appears to harbour no unrealistic or elevated requirements of its constituent citizens. The effective participant in market exchanges needs only to possess a desire which requires satisfaction, and sufficient rationality to choose from among the goods on offer that which will satisfy the desire at least cost (we leave aside, for the sake of argument, those desires which cannot be satisfied by any of the goods for sale, and those would-be purchasers who have desires but insufficient means of exchange). Given this view of humans as motivated by self-interest, capable of cognising their interests, and rationally calculating the most efficient means for their pursuit, all that is required is that their activities should be brought into interconnection by the institution of market exchanges. Provided that no external force intervenes to disrupt the spontaneous flow of self-interested action in the market, the consequence, intended or not, will be a harmonious coincidence of the satisfaction of the self-interest of each, and the aggregate interest of all. The happy consequence of a pessimistic realism about human nature is that, allowed to follow its course in an appropriate institutional context, it issues in a mutually supportive harmony of the security, satisfaction, and liberty of the individual with the greatest good of all _
104 Ted Benton In this way are neatly combined together a philosophical psychology, an economic theory, and a political philosophy. The crucial elements of the philosophical psychology are a utilitarian conception of rational action, and a 'self-interest' model of human motivation. The key postulate of the economic theory is a notion of market relations as an 'invisible hand' which mediates the self-interested choices of individuals and in so doing brings about the good of all. The political philosophy advocates the liberty of the individual as constitutive of his or her well-being, and as the primary purpose of any legitimate public policy. All who desire the liberty of the individual will, so long as they accept the advocated view of human nature, necessarily be committed to the promulgation of the market society and the 'minimal' state. Easily the most frequently, if erroneously, invoked authority for this 'enlightened' synthesis of the self-interest view of human nature with advocacy of the market as the embodiment and presupposition of the liberty of the individual is Adam Smith. How paradoxical it must seem, then, that one of the most powerful and sustained critiques of these ideas should have been authored by Adam Ferguson, one of Smith's contemporaries and friends, and a fellow luminary of the Scottish Enlightenment. Ferguson and Snlith, together with David Hume, William Robertson, John Millar, and other less well-known figures, centred on Glasgow and Edinburgh, established a distinctive tradition of social philosophy during the eighteenth century. Arguably their very position as cosmopolitan intellectuals yet whose work was conducted in a provincial capital, in significant respects economically, socially, and politically overshadowed by its more 'advanced' neighbour, induced in them an ambiguous attitude to the rapid changes they witnessed in their lifetimes (see Kettler 1965, esp. chs 1 and 2; and Chitnis 1976, passim). While Hume was undoubtedly the greatest philosopher of the group, and Smith retains his celebrated status as one of the great founders of modern economics, it is Ferguson who provides the most telling sociological insights into the contradictory tendencies and dangers of the newly forming commercial society. Easily Ferguson's most important and original work was his Essay on the History of Civil Society, published in 1767, and the main purpose of what follows is to offer an exposition and qualified defence of Ferguson's sceptical view of the relationship between market society and the liberty of the individual. Necessarily, this will also involve us in an exploration of his rival vision of human nature, happiness and virtue. Ferguson's Essay is ostensibly an account of the progress of human society from the 'rude' to the 'polished' state, a secularized theodicy of a genre already well established in the mid-eighteenth century. But if we understand by 'progress' not merely cumulative and directional change, but also a coincidence of that change with the realization of human well-being, 'perfection' or virtue, then we shall miss Ferguson's central preoccupation. For him there is, indeed, cumulative and directional change in human history, but this brings in its wake the threat of corruption, misery, and despotism, no less than the possibility of virtue, happiness, and liberty.
Adam Ferguson and the enterprise culture 105 Indeed, it is hard to escape the conclusion that for Ferguson this trinity of values is more deeply threatened in the 'polished' commercial states than in earlier conditions of society. Along with many of his contemporaries in the Scottish Enlightenment, Ferguson rejected the concept of 'state of nature' as a foundation for political philosophy. His objections to the idea were, like Hume's, partly epistemological: ex hypothesi, the state of nature was not accessible to observation, and so could not be a proper object of positive knowledge. The state of nature theorists confuse poetry and imagination with science, make 'wild suppositions' about our pre-social state in order to buttress their prejudices, and set out to investigate the human case in a way quite different from the approach of the natural historian to any particular animal species. The only methodologically sound way of arriving at general principles in science is to ground them on 'just observation'. Applied to the human case, this method can yield but one conclusion: 'both the earliest and the latest accounts collected from every quarter of the earth, represent mankind as assembled in troops and companies' (Ferguson 1966: 3). Consequently: His mixed disposition to friendship or enmity, his reason, his use of language and articulate sounds, like the shape and the erect position of his body, are to be considered as so many attributes of his nature: they are to be retained in his description, as the wing and the paw are in that of the eagle and the lion. (3)
Humans are social by nature. It follows that the view of society as an 'artificial' creation, devised by individuals in order to realize purposes conceived independently of and prior to it, is incoherent. All that we do follows from our nature and the conditions in which that nature is exercised; there can be no opposition in human affairs between what is 'natural' and what is 'artificial'. It also follows that moral judgements may not be grounded on an appeal to the difference between the natural and the unnatural. Ferguson follows Montesquieu in acknowledging the great,diversity in human modes of social life and forms of government. The character of individuals, too, is shaped by habituation through 'forbearance or exercise' of their various faculties and dispositions. But this acknowledgement of diversity does not deter Ferguson from seeking the 'general characteristics' which constitute human nature. Indeed, following the Newtonian example, it is necessary first to establish these general characteristics if we are eventually to explain the diversity. Some of our general characteristics we have in common with animals. Like them, we have 'instinctive propensities' or dispositions. These in the human case are of two kinds. One set is directed to the preservation of self and the race, while the other leads to society. Where we differ from animals is in the extent to which these initial dispositions are moulded or directed by our mental capacity for reflection and foresight, which are themselves exercised under varied external conditions of life.
106 Ted Benton Among these conditions of life, Ferguson, unlike Montesquieu, assigns priority to the requirements and impositions of a definite mode of social life, and the values and purposes which prevail within it. Depending upon the condition of the social milieu and the relation of the individual to it, he may aspire to a happy and virtuous life, or fall into a state of extreme corruption. The transition from a 'rude' to a 'polished' state of society entails a clear danger of the latter outcome. It is Ferguson's purpose in the Essay to warn of this danger, to examine its historical causes, and to consider if and how it might be averted. But since social outcomes are products of a common human nature whose faculties and dispositions are exercised under diverse conditions of life, we are returned once again to the question of this common human nature. In addition to our selfpreservative and social instincts, we possess capacities to recollect, and to reflect upon our actions, and a further disposition to evaluate, to judge good or bad, which we exercise primarily in relation to ourselves and other persons. Taken together, this ensemble of natural capacities and dispositions implies a further universal characteristic of humankind; one upon which Ferguson places great emphasis. This is their perpetual restlessness and dissatisfaction with their current state: their desire of improvement. Mankind is an 'active being' forever 'in train of employing his talents' (8). This restlessness and desire of improvement, a universal character of individual humans, produces as its largely unintended and unforeseen consequence a distinguishing feature of the species: namely, its historical progress from a 'rude' to a 'polished' condition. Whereas the individuals of other species exhibit growth and development, in the human case these processes are continued at the level of the whole species. As we shall see, Ferguson recognizes that this phenomenon of historical development is more manifest with respect to the employment of some faculties than others, and herein lies one source of corruption and loss of liberty. But in any event, whatever the moral character of the outcome of human restlessness, its status as a key fact of human nature is unmistakable: 'We may desire to direct this love of improvement to its proper object, we may wish for stability of conduct; but we mistake human nature, if we wish for a termination of labour, or a scene of repose' (7). But we do not understand the true nature of this human disposition restlessly to employ talents in projects of improvement if we think of it as a disposition which will be exhibited by individuals independently of their external conditions. This, along with the other general characteristics of human nature, are only fully expressed in the appropriate milieu, and this milieu is society. To say that humans are by nature social is, for Ferguson, to say that society is the condition or context for which they are formed, and therefore the context in which alone their general and distinctive faculties are acquired and exercised. Individuals are most fully themselves, most fully human the more they are bound together in society, and the more they find within society the medium and the object of their activity. To imagine, or to observe (as in the case of 'wild-men') human individuals independently of their involvement
Adam Ferguson and the enterprise culture 107 in social life as a source of illumination on human nature is a profound mistake. An individual deprived of the proper context for the exercise of the powers of its species could not be representative of its kind. Ferguson supposes that such an individual would even suffer organic imperfections and deformities, so closely is the acquisition of our nature bound up with the social state. As we have seen, Ferguson also assigns to our social disposition the status of an 'instinct', albeit one that is subject to direction and moulding through habituation under varying conditions of social life. But that our attachment to society is one of primary affectivity is an important fact. We are not attached to society as a means of improving our material standard of life. Observation shows, on the contrary, that increase of luxury and 'external conveniences' is often accompanied by a loosening of the ties that bind individuals to society. Nor is it a matter of mere security: in times of national crisis and danger, we are frequently willing to sacrifice our lives in the service of society. Nor can the desire for mere honour and esteem explain the passions unleashed by the attachment to society. We are not, in fact, attached to society for any purpose extrinsic to it, but simply desire the society of others for its own sake, as an end in itself. But the passions which. bind us to social life are not to be reduced to mere 'benevolence' or 'sympathy'. The intensity of our social loyalties also begets and feeds from equally intense hostility and enmity. The willingness to defend by force of arms one's society against its enemies is for Ferguson not only evidence of the power of our social bonds, but also one of the highest expressions of public virtue. With this broad view of human nature in mind, we are now in a position to turn to Ferguson's critique of the 'selfish system' of philosophy, and to his closely related critique of the utilitarian view of happiness and virtue. Although not often named, the main target of Ferguson's criticisms was Hobbes, and certainly not Adam Smith, with whom Ferguson had much in common (see, for example, Smith 1976, Part II, Section III, chs 1 and 11). Ferguson's own critique of the selfish philosophy, or, more specifically, the 'self-interest' view of human motivation, has three main strands. First, the selfish philosophy misrepresents what is really only an innovation in language as a discovery of science. For example, parental care is regarded as 'selfish' since it is the parent's own desire which is gratified in ministering to the well-being of the child, no less than when the parent is taking care of her or himself. Ferguson argues that this is merely to redefine 'benevolence' as a disposition to act from no desires of one's own. The proponents of the selfish philosophy may adopt this revision, of course, but the rest of us will still need to mark the distinction previously made between action arising from a desire for the welfare of oneself and action prompted by a desire for the welfare of others. Second, if the 'selfish' philosopher is reluctant to admit 'benevolence' in this sense in which it is used by 'the vulgar', t~en surely he will at least admit that humans frequently act out of passions such as 'hatred, indignation, and rage' in opposition to their known interest. But the introduction of the term 'interest' here leads us to what is, for our purposes, the core of Ferguson's ~rl!!51~le_~ !h~ J~fjsb
108 Ted Benton philosophy. In what does appear to be a direct reference to Smith, he objects to the term 'self-love', partly because 'love is an affection which carries the attention of the mind beyond itself' (Ferguson 1966: 12), but also because of the degradation of our nature involved in the implicit reduction of the objects of self-regard to mere 'interest'. That humans act out of self-regard is not denied by Ferguson. As we have seen, he assigns to us a self-preservative instinct. But what is objectionable in the selfish philosophy is its limitation of 'this supposed selfish affection to the securing or accumulating the constituents of interest, or the means of mere animal life'. He continues: It is somewhat remarkable, that notwithstanding men value themselves so much on qualities of the mind, on parts, learning and wit, on courage, generosity, and honour, those men are still supposed to be in the highest degree selfish, or attentive to themselves, who are most careful of animal life, and who are least mindful of rendering that life an object worthy of care. It will be difficult, however, to tell why a good understanding, a resolute and generous mind should not, by every man in his senses, be reckoned as much parts of himself, as either his stomach or his palate, and much more than his estate or his dress. (13)
Ferguson's insistence, here, is on the importance of distinguishing between 'interests' as those 'objects of care which refer to our external condition, and the preservation of our animal nature', and the much wider range of faculties and qualities of the person which constitute human well-being, happiness, and virtue. Since these qualities are precisely the ones that are most dependent on our social bonds with others for their acquisition and exercise, then our desire to protect and augment them in ourselves cannot be opposed to our desire for the welfare of others and society itself. Properly understood, there is a natural coincidence of our selfregarding affections with our social dispositions. Of course, this does not rule out the sources of competition, conflict, enmity, and war, since for Ferguson these are rooted in our social dispositions, no less than benevolence and sympathy. It is the interests of the narrower, and, Ferguson clearly thinks, inferior sort which are mistakenly taken to be the sole motive of human action in the selfish philosophy. Here, in his elevated view of the identity of happiness and public virtue, and, indeed, in his refusal to make happiness dependent upon the 'externals' of life, Ferguson acknowledges a debt to the Stoic philosophy. But he is not content to rest his case on luminous classical references: the view of human faculties and dispositions is given a systematic observational grounding. Ferguson's critique of the selfish system of philosophy passes directly into his critique of the utilitarian view of happiness and morality. He admits that the pursuit of pleasures and avoidance of pain may enable us to fulfill the 'purposes of nature' in self-preservation and the continuation of the species. But they are not a solid foundation for human happiness. Pleasure, as an episodic sensation, terminated once the object of gratification has been obtained, is to be contrasted with happiness as
Adam Ferguson and the enterprise culture 109 an enduring quality of the individual. The happy individual is one who, exhilarated by the fullest exercise of his highest faculties, shows contempt for pleasure and indifference to pain. The pursuit of pleasure and avoidance of pain are associated by Ferguson with the much-criticized notion of 'interest', and likewise counterposed to the true fulfilment of our human nature in the active exercise of our faculties in the enhancement of social life: It should seem, therefore, to be the happiness of man, to make his social dispositions the ruling spring of his occupations; to state himself as the member of a community, for whose general good his heart may glow with an ardent zeal, to the suppression of those personal cares which are the foundation of painful anxieties, fear, jealousy, and envy.... (54)
Similarly with our moral sentiments. If the utilitarian view were correct, then man would be classed with the brutes with respect to the objects of our desires, differing only in our capacity of multiplying the means of achieving them. Our passions would be limited to joy of success or grief of disappointment, and our relations to others in society governed by considerations of utility or disutility only. But observation shows that this is not the case. The passions attending a perceived insult, injustice, or wrongdoing, and those kindled in the company of others are far greater than those attaching to 'interest', and so are not reducible to them. The 'self-interest' view of human motivation, and the closely related utilitarian views of happiness and moral virtue stand refuted. Their advocates gain plausibility by unacknowledged revisions of linguistic usage, and by conceptual confusions, but, above all, their theories are unsupported by readily available empirical observation. Ferguson's own account of human nature, happiness, and virtue is not deduced from 'first principles' but is rather presented as a set of inductively grounded empirical generalizations. But the perspectives against which Ferguson's arguments are pitted are not merely the conceptual and empirical errors of speculative intellects. Their persistence and at least superficial plausibility also call for explanation. If human purposes are reduced to the satisfaction of bodily appetites and the preservation of property, if human happiness is confused with the pursuit of pleasure and avoidance of pain, and if morality is equated with utility, then what can have engendered such confusions but a society which comes close to making them true? Ferguson's choice of empirical illustrations is an exemplary use of the comparative method to expose the insularity of his opponents' perceptions. Ferguson, in common with Smith and the other Scottish moral philosophers of the period, not only drew upon the Stoic philosophy (especially for a conception of civic virtue), but also took a deep interest in classical history and civilization. Late in his career, Ferguson wrote a widely regarded history of the Roman Republic and the Essay itself is replete with illus\trations drawn from histories of classical Greece and Rome. He was clearly a keen reader of travellers' tales, and of the histories of non-European peoples. His own I -------------------------------------
110 Ted Benton Highland background, too, no doubt endowed him with a certain sympathy for the positive qualities of social life in its 'rude' state, prior to the changes wrought by commercial society and constitutional government. Although resolutely opposed to the Jacobite cause, Ferguson retained a 'condescending identification' with his highland origins, and was most unusual for someone of his social position in his command of the Gaelic language (see Kettler 1965: 46). In the face of this weight of historical and anthropological evidence, the condition of commercial societies is represented as exceptional. In these societies, the instinctual disposition to sociability is least augmented by habituation, and social bonds are consequently at their most attenuated. In these societies, too, the selfpreservative instinct is most likely to take the form of an exclusive concern with possessions and mere bodily security - with 'interests' in Ferguson's disapprobatory use of the term. In the commercial nations, we have a form of society in which the paradigmatic personality-type, the predominant purpose of action, and the prevailing scale of values most closely approximate those represented in the philosophies to which Ferguson takes greatest exception. There is a clear affinity or complicity between these philosophies and the commercial societies which spawn them. Ferguson's critique of these philosophies, as misrepresenting human nature, happiness and virtue, is, then, at the same time, a critique of those forces at work in the society of his time which distorted, or corrupted human nature, withdrawing from it the conditions of its fulfilment in a happy and virtuous life. But the situation is more complex than this. Exceptional though they are, the commercial societies must continue to be viewed as, like all other forms of society, genuine expressions of human nature. In corrupting or distorting human nature, they nevertheless represent one among the many diverse ways in which it can be moulded or directed by the conditions of social life. If this were not the case, then observations of human life as it is lived in the commercial societies would stand as an empirical refutation of Ferguson's own general account of human nature. Social bonds are attenuated in such societies, and benevolent sentiments less widely or keenly felt, but they are still present. Parental care is a surviving example of the latter which Ferguson frequently cites, and we are reminded of the 'tolerable footing of amity' and restraint observed even in business transactions as an example of the former. Indeed, Ferguson tends to treat the commercial nations as a kind of experimental test situation, or 'worst-case' scenario for his theory of human nature: What must we think of the force of that disposition to compassion, to candour, and goodwill, which, notwithstanding the prevailing opinion that the happiness of a man consists in possessing the greatest possible share of riches, preferments, and honours, still keeps the parties who are in competition for those objects, on a tolerable footing of amity, and leads them to abstain even from their own supposed good, when their seizing it appears in the light of a detriment to others? (Ferguson 1966: 35) Wherever there exist societies that are 'polished' or civilized, and also have attained
Adam Ferguson and the enterprise culture III a high development of the mechanical and commercial arts, then there are attendant dangers of corruption, national ruin, and despotism, or political slavery. But there is no necessity about the 'progress' from civilization to corruption, or, indeed, from corruption to despotism. Both civilization itself and the advance of material wealth and technique bear within them the seeds of corruption but only under definite circumstances do these seeds germinate and flourish. Moreover, different forms of government - democratic, aristocratic, monarchical, and various admixtures - are consistent with the civilized state. A degree of ordered society, liberty, and even virtue may be preserved even in the face of widespread corruption, depending on the form of government and the kind of requirement it makes upon its subjects for virtue and public spiritedness. For Ferguson the designation 'polished' or 'civilized' refers primarily to the achievement of an ordered, law-abiding society, in which internal conflicts are settled peacefully and in which there is security from external invasion. But these conditions of peace and security in the enjoyment of the fruits of labour also foster the development of the mechanical and commercial arts. The discovery is soon made that a division of labour which allows each individual to specialize in a single task makes possible a greater perfection in the goods produced as well as an increase in the efficiency and quantity in which they are produced: there is a steady accumulation of technical powers and of material wealth. In turn, the division of labour and specialization, in severing the immediacy of the connection between production and consumption, requires and stimulates the development of market relations and what Ferguson calls the 'commercial arts'. Finally, the development of the mechanical and commercial arts rests upon 'accidental' inequalities in property, faculties, and dispositions, which it further progressively augments. The societies with which Ferguson is concerned, then, share four intimately connected features. They may be characterized by anyone of a number of possible forms of government, but all possess some form of constitutional government which, at the minimum, legally regulates transactions between individual subjects, provides security from external invasion, and includes a system of checks and balances by means of which the liberties of subjects are protected from possible excesses of the executive power itself. Second, there is a high level of development of technique and material production, manifested in a developed pattern of occupational specialization and differentiation. Third, consumer goods are primarily produced for, and obtained by, market exchange: that is, these are 'commercial nations', in Ferguson's terminology. Fourth, there are marked and entrenched inequalities in the ownership of property. As we have seen, Ferguson thought that notwithstanding the admitted benefits that flow from each of these features, their combination also renders a nation peculiarly liable to specific forms of corruption and to a consequent risk of decline, ruin, and despotic rule. In particular, Ferguson is concerned to demonstrate the actual incompatibility between such societies and a substantively democratic political order as well as to identify a series of threats to the liberty of their citizens. The two features most sharply incompatible with substantive democracy are the
112 Ted Benton advanced division of labour and marked inequalities of property. Some specialized occupations elevate the mind and engage the heart, but many have the opposite effect on those whose life is spent in pursuit of them. Indeed, the increase in efficiency and perfection of production resulting from the division of labour is most marked precisely when the labourers are least required to think or to be creatively involved in their task: Many mechanical arts, indeed, require no capacity; they succeed best under a total suppression of sentiment and reason: and ignorance is the mother of industry as well as of superstition. Retlection and fancy are subject to err; but a habit of moving the hand, or the foot, is independent of either. Manufactures, accordingly, prosper most, where the mind is least consulted, and where the workshop may, without any great effort of imagination, be considered as an engine, the parts of which are men. (Ferguson 1966: 183) This spine-chilling observation is the start of a long line of sociological concern with the social and human implications of modern manufacturing and industrial systems, and Ferguson has with some justification been accorded the status of one of the founding figures of modern sociology (see, for example, Meek 1954; McRae 1969; Swingewood 1970). Ferguson's own principal concern was with the degeneracy and narrowness of vision on the part of the labouring classes which must follow from their place in the division of labour. But if the division of labour alone has these baleful effects on those whose dispositions and faculties are moulded by it, then how much more serious the situation is when the effects of inequality of property are combined with them. Such classes as mechanics, labourers, and beggars are constrained to devote their lives to procuring the means to a mere livelihood. They are necessarily occupied with menial tasks, and preoccupied with the degrading object of material security. Depending upon their diverse characters and situations, members of these classes are liable to become envious, avaricious, criminal, servile, and/or mercenary: We think that the extreme meanness of some classes must arise chiefly from the defect of knowledge ... and we refer to such classes, as to an image of what our species must have been in its rude and uncultivated state. But we forget how many circumstances, especially in populous cities, tend to corrupt the lowest orders of men.... An admiration of wealth unpossessed, becoming a principle of envy, or of servility; a habit of acting perpetually with a view to profit, and under a sense of subjection; the crimes to which they are allured, in order to feed their debauch, or to gratify their avarice, are examples, not of ignorance, but of corruption and baseness. (Ferguson 1966: 186) Now, for Ferguson, democracy is a form of government in which sovereignty rests with the collective body of the whole people, and in which all citizens are eligible for
Adam Ferguson and the enterprise culture 113 public office. For a democracy to thrive, its citizens must love equality, and must be willing to work for the public good without hope of personal profit. In short, the virtue of the citizens is a necessary condition for democratic government. Since this condition, as we have seen, cannot be satisfied in the modern commercial societies, given the necessary preoccupation of the lower classes with mere survival, demeaning tasks, or with material interests, it follows that substantive democracy cannot be sustained in them. All that may remain are mere 'pretensions to equal rights'. Ferguson clearly regards the entrusting of major public office to the corrupted and degenerate lower classes of these societies as the height of folly - at most 'they may be entrusted with the choice of their masters and leaders' (187). But the choice between democracy and the market society presented no great dilemma for Ferguson. While democracy had a certain romantic attraction for him (he regarded the move away from democracy as inevitably involving a degree of corruption), he tended to regard it as an extreme and unsustainable form, as a 'paroxysm' of the political order. In enjoying the benefits of both material advancement and the security that comes from regular government, we must reluctantly accept political forms which fall short of substantive democracy. In practice, Ferguson always kept aloof from the Reform movement, consistently putting his loyalty to the established constitution and the system of class subordination it sustained before any appeal that an extension of the francise might have had for him. In this respect, Ferguson's views were superseded by later socialist writers who were able to make an analytical distinction between the increasingly capitalist commercial ordering of economic life, with its associated deskilling and impoverishment of the working classes, on the one hand, and the increase in material well-being that could come from the cooperative organization of production and the rational application of knowledge in technique, on the other. But even on his own premisses, Ferguson's bleak conclusion does not follow. Economic insecurity and poverty could, and did, just as easily lead to an elevating and invigorating combination among the dispossessed as to their corruption through envy and servility. In the early trade union and socialist movements could be found a social milieu in which the exercise of the highest human capacities and dispositions, such as benevolence, honour, loyalty, and courage was both required and made possible. That these virtues could be acquired and enhanced in a spirit of antagonism and competitive struggle is only to be expected on Ferguson's own view of human nature. If this modest revision of Ferguson's analysis is correct, it suggests that a healthy and vital labour movement is a necessary condition for substantive democracy in the advanced commercial states. For Ferguson himself, however, a degree of liberty, order, and virtue can be sustained in the face of the corrupting effects of the division of labour and economic inequality only if other forms of government (aristocratic, monarchical, or 'mixed') are allowed to prevail. Here, what is necessary is that the worst corruption of human nature should be confined to those classes least relied upon for public office. Even this, unfortunately, cannot be guaranteed, and in so far as the division of labour and
114 Ted Benton specialization of function becomes an all-pervasive principle of social organization it poses a threat not just to democracy, but to liberty itself. Implicit in Ferguson's comments are three features of occupational specialization which are potentially undermining of civil liberties. First, occupational categories are identity-forming in ways that compete with identification with and loyalty to nation. Each occupational group has its own 'carriage', 'point of honour', system of manners and ceremonial through which the character of the individual is formed. The resulting diversity of individuals and ranks 'suppresses' the bonds of similitude which make up the 'national character'. Second, as we have seen, life-long preoccupation with a single activity must narrow the vision. Not participating in the wide diversity of social practices, the individual plays a necessary part in the whole without any comprehension of what that part is, or how it relates to the others: 'society is made to consist of parts, of which none is animated with the spirit of society itself' (Ferguson 1966: 218). This loss of overall vision renders the individual unfit to playa full role in public life. Third, occupational specialization, concentrating the activity and attention of individuals on the sphere of private interest, withdraws them from the public domain: The separation of professions ... seems, in some measure, to break the bands of society, to substitute form in place of ingenuity, and to withdraw individuals from the common scene of occupation, on which the sentiments of the heart, and the mind, are most happily employed. (218) These three pervasive consequences of the division of labour and occupational specialization - individualism, narrowness of vision, and 'privatism' - were, of course, important topics of interest in subsequent sociological analyses of industrial capitalism, most famously, perhaps, in the great French sociologist, Emile Durkheim's Division ofLabour in Society (1933). The Hegelian-Marxist concept of 'alienation', too, includes as- a significant element the effects of the division of labour in detaching and isolating individuals from one another and from the life of society. Ferguson's own concern is with the loss on the part of individual citizens of the motivation and capacities to playa full, active, and disinterested part in public life. The consequence of this is a reduction in the public sphere itself, and a usurpation of power on the part of the executive. Incapable and unwilling to make sacrifices in defence of their liberties, a self-interested and preoccupied citizenry is liable to lose them. When the exercise of public office itself becomes subject to occupational specialization, then the threat to liberty is yet more dire. The functions of warrior and statesman, the paramount public offices, are the ones most decisive for national well-being, as well as for preserving the conditions for the highest development of individual happiness and virtue. Accordingly, for these activities to fall prey to selfinterested functionaries and men of narrow vision spells disaster for both national stability and the liberty of the individual. Ferguson lays greatest emphasis here on
Adam Ferguson and the enterpnse culture 115 the threat to liberty posed by occupational specialization in the military sphere. By employing a professional army, the citizenry is apt to take its security for granted, and to lose the capacity for self-defence. The way is then open for the military machine they have created to be turned against their own liberties. These arguments and others were used by Ferguson in his pamphlets supporting a Scottish militia, advocacy of which was a life-long commitment of his (see Kettler 1965: ch. 4). Earlier in his career he had served as a military chaplain with the notorious 'Black Watch' regiment, a fact no doubt associated with the continuing militarist cast of his notion of civic virtue. Despite the seriousness of all these dangers to national well-being, virtue, and liberty, Ferguson is clearly most exercised by a further threat to which the commercial nations are exposed. This threat is, perhaps, a culmination or synthesis, of each of the others. Secure, regular government, the advancement of the mechanical and commercial arts, and unequal property, are, severally, conditions which pose specific threats of individual corruption and national decline. But none produces such effects of necessity, or in abstraction from the influence of the others. These conditions affecting economic and political life, to produce their most ruinous effects, must further give rise to a wholesale and pervasive shift in values: A change of national manners for the worse, may arise from ... a change in the prevailing opinions relating to the constituents of honours or of happiness. When mere riches or court-favour, are supposed to constitute rank; the mind is misled from the consideration of qualities on which it ought to rely. (Ferguson 1966: 238) Under the influence of these 'prevailing opinions' social honour is assigned on the basis of wealth, or flattery of the powerful, independently of the intrinsic merit or virtue of its recipients. Happiness is confused with mere pleasure, and private interest is treated as the principal purpose of life. Public life, no longer the domain in which the highest purposes of the citizens are concentrated, becomes a mere means for the more successful pursuit of private interest. It is the pervasiveness of this cultural complex, rather than the mere existence of political security, material luxury, the market and economic inequality, which is the 'Achilles heel' of the modern commercial nations. The political and economic features of these societies predispose them towards the value-system and the personality-type which we may without too much difficulty recognize in the 'enterprise culture' of our own time and place. At the same time we may recognize in them the very view of human nature, happiness, and virtue which Ferguson denounced as the 'selfish system' of philosophy. In view of the quite special dangers which Ferguson attached to the enterprise culture, it will be worth spending a little time in exploring both his analysis of the conditions which bring it to prominence, and his reasons for fearing its consequences for the preservation of liberties. The first condition is prolonged peace and security itself. Although the achievement of this might require a great exertion of
116 Ted Benton national effort and virtue, once achieved it makes possible a 'growing indifference to objects of a public nature'. Constitutional government and the security it brings are taken for granted, and 'no engagement remaining on the part of the public, private interest and animal pleasure, become the sovereign objects of care' (Ferguson 1966: 256). Second, the restlessness and desire of perfection which are an intrinsic part of human nature itself tend to promote disproportionate attention to the development of the mechanical arts and the accumulation of wealth: these, compared with other objects of human concern, are capable of limitless augmentation. Third, although the resulting material wealth and 'luxury' is not itself identical with corruption, it certainly predisposes to it: Nations are most exposed to corruption on this quarter, when the mechanical arts, being greatly advanced, furnish nun1berless articles, to be applied in ornament to the person, in furniture, entertainment, or equipage; when such articles as the rich alone can procure are admired; and when consideration, precedence, and rank are accordingly made to depend on fortune. (251) Finally, public policy itself may become concerned only with preserving the security and property - the 'interests' - of the citizenry, without regard to the promotion of their higher faculties and virtues: If to any people it be the avowed object of policy, in all its internal refinements, to secure the person and the property of the subject, without any regard to his political character, the constitution indeed may be free, but its members may likewise become unworthy of the freedom they possess, and unfit to preserve it. (221-2) These, then, are the conditions under which a definite personality-type, a prevailing set of values and opinions, of preoccupations and 'objects of care' comes to pervade all classes in a commercial state. But what is it about these values and preoccupations which makes them 'corrupting' in Ferguson's sense, and how do they lead to a loss of liberty and to national ruin? First,lhe valuation of property over personal qualities such as merit and virtue, and the adoption of wealth as the foundation of the system of class 'subordination' involve a devaluation of the person, and a corresponding transfer of human value to mere material or animal objects and beings: He finds in a provision of wealth, which he is probably never to employ, an object of his greatest solicitude, and the principal idol of his mind. He apprehends a relation between his person and his property, which renders what he calls his own in a manner a part of himself, a constituent of his rank, his condition, and his character, in which, independent of any real enjoyment, he may be fortunate or unhappy; and, independent of any personal merit, he may be an object of
Adam Ferguson and the enterprise culture 117 consideration or neglect; and in which he may be wounded and injured, while his person is safe, and every want of his nature completely supplied. (12)
The 'enterprise culture', then, involves a kind of self-alienation in which regard for 'self is displaced into regard for property and/or mere material well-being, into a preoccupation with 'interest', while concerns properly addressed to the self take as their object mere material possessions. A house, ornaments, clothes, furniture, and so on, are substituted for merit and virtue as objects of esteem and social honour. But this alienation from self and its associated fetishism of commodities also implies an alienation between individuals and the social world, and consequently among individuals themselves. Where self-interest reigns supreme, the community, ceasing to be the object which directly engages the most powerful sentiments, becomes a mere instrument for individual advantage: The individual considers the community so far only as it can be rendered subservient to his personal advancement or profit: he states himself in competition with his fellow creatures; and, urged by the passions of emulation, of fear and jealousy, of envy and malice, he follows the maxims of an animal destined to preserve his separate existence, and to indulge his caprice or his appetite, at the expense of his species. (238-9)
In establishing a merely utilitarian relation between the individual and the community, or species, the preoccupation with 'interest' characteristic of the enterprise culture also reduces the relation between individuals themselves to matters of instrumental calculation, on a level with their relations to their non-human property: 'he has found an object which sets him in competition with his fellow creatures, and he deals with them as he does with his cattle and his soil, for the sake of the profits they bring' (19). Under the combined influence of these material and political conditions, and the shifts in the dominant value-system and practical orientations which they facilitate, human nature itself is corrupted and debased. Two basic character-types become pervasive: those who without moral restraint seek power and wealth on their own account, and those who, equally without moral restraint, make themselves the willing tools of the wealthy and powerful in order to acquire some share of their masters' acquisitions: On this corrupt foundation, men become either rapacious, deceitful, and violent, ready to trespass on the rights of others; or servile, mercenary and base, prepared to relinquish their own. Talents, capacity and force of mind, possessed by a person of the first description, serve to plunge him the deeper in misery, and to sharpen the agony of cruel passions; which lead him to wreak on his fellowcreatures the torments that prey on himself. To a person of the second, imagin-
118 Ted Benton ation, and reason itself, only serve to point out false objects of fear, or desire, and to multiply the subjects of disappointment, and of momentary joy. (239)
Crucially, these corrupting influences affect all classes and conditions of persons, including those classes upon whom devolve the duties of public life: But the higher orders of men if they relinquish the state, if they cease to possess that courage and elevation of mind ... are, in reality ... become the refuse of that society of which they once were the ornament. ... The care of his buildings, his equipage, or his table, is chosen by one; literary amusement, or some frivolous study, by another. The sports of the country, and the diversions of the town; the gaming-table, dogs, horses, and wine, are employed to fill up the blank of a listless and unprofitable life. (259-60)
Ferguson at one point even warns of the possibility of the Hobbesian war of each against each in the absence of the restraint of law. But such a war is not, for Ferguson, the consequence of unaided and unconstrained human nature; it is rather a measure of the corruption and degeneracy of human nature under the combined influence of luxury, economic inequality, the division of labour and the consequential changes in values and practices: Under this influence, they would enter, if not restrained by the laws of civil society, on a scene of violence or meanness, which would exhibit our species, by turns, under an aspect more terrible and odious, or more vile and contemptible, than that of any animal which inherits the earth. (12)
However, once this degree and spread of corruption is approached, even the restraint of law undergoes a transformation in its bearing on the liberties of subjects. The law only serves as a defence of liberty when it continues to be applied in that spirit, and with constant vigilance against abuse and usurpation. When these conditions are absent, 'they serve only to cover, not to restrain, the iniquities of power.' The influence of laws in preserving liberty, Ferguson contends, 'is not any magic power descending from shelves that are loaded with books, but is, in reality, the influence of men resolved to be free' (263-4). So, with pervasive corruption and debasement of human nature, those who hold executive power seek to extend it by overcoming all obstacles to their designs, while those subject to executive power actively connive in the destruction of their own freedoms. Not merely unfit either to exercise or to defend their liberty, they actively seek its annulment. Once the citizenry have connived in the usurpation of the executive power a process is set in motion in which all remaining centres of resistance are identified and eliminated:
Adam Ferguson and the enterprise culture 119 enemy; when his mind is elated, whoever pretends to eminence, and is disposed to act for himself, is a rival. He would leave no dignity in the state, but what is dependent upon himself; no active power, but what carries the expression of his momentary pleasure.... The tendency of his administration is to quiet every restless spirit, and to assume every function of government to himself. (274)
Consequently: Implicit submission to any leader, or the uncontrouled exercise of any power, even when it is intended to operate for the good of mankind, may frequently end in the subversion of legal establishments. This fatal revolution, by whatever means it is accomplished, terminates in military government. (273)
The progression is complete: a privatized, self-interested, and materialistic citizenry collaborate with a rapacious executive power, saturated by the same corruptive values and purposes, to yield despotic rule, political slavery, and national ruin. Ferguson's critique of the 'selfish system' and his analysis of it as a philosophical expression of that form of corruption of human nature to which modern capitalist societies are peculiarly liable is a powerful, and, to my mind, largely convincing one. Nevertheless, in important respects it is limited or defective. I have already noted Ferguson's (understandable, in context) failure to distinguish analytically between progress in human technical powers, on the one hand, and the institutional forms and inequalities of a market society, on the other. Lacking this distinction, Ferguson was unable to separate out the benefits that might come from a more equally shared material well-being from the corrupting combination of wealth and material insecurity in a class-divided market society. It was this analytical failing which also sustained Ferguson's apparent contempt for material well-being itself, as though this were properly the concern only of 'mere animals'. As Marx was to argue almost a century later (and, indeed, as the Stoics had argued centuries before) desires for food, shelter, clothing, and so on are not in themselves demeaning or corrupt, but they only become so in a form of life which abstracts them from their rightful place in a wider context of human and communal purposes, and turns them, in this abstract form, into the sole or primary end of life itself. Finally, there is an unmistakable masculine - even militarist - cast to Ferguson's concept of the virtuous life. He explicitly distances himself from values sometimes associated with civilization, such as gentleness, generosity, and leniency towards one's enemies. He contrasts such values with the bold and warlike virtues of the classical civilizations, and attributes the change to the spread of 'antiquated' notions of chivalry in relation to women into our public life, and even into the conduct of war. He frequently uses the word 'effeminate' to characterize a life-style corrupted by luxury and withdrawal from the exertion of public life. Notwithstanding these reservations, Ferguson's work contains the broad outlines of a quite startlingly prophetic sociological analysis of commercial civilization and
120 Ted Benton the corruptions to which it is susceptible. Ferguson tends to think of advancement in the 'material arts', specialization and the division of labour, and the growth of commercial society as indissolubly intertwined processes. While they lead to greater comfort, security, and luxury, they nevertheless lead to a new system of domination and subordination, a lop-sided development of the individual, a corrupting preoccupation among the lower classes with mere subsistence, and, above all, a dissolution of social bonds. In so far as commercial society assigns status on the basis of material success, and allows its citizens to take their peace, security and luxury for granted (through, for example, allocating the function of national defence to a specialist standing army), then to this extent self-interested motivations are favoured, and the vigour of civic virtue declines. The highest and most worthy exertions of humanity can flourish only where the intensity of social bonds and civic virtue also flourish. The ~ontrary tendency towards self-interested individual competition can only lead to a debasement of the aims and contents of individual action. Though Ferguson sees no inevitability in these negative aspects of the advance of commercial society, his arguments do suggest an interesting inversion of classical liberal (and modern conservative) assumptions about the relationships between individual well-being, commercial society, and political liberty. The enterprise culture, in fragmenting and dissipating social bonds, deprives individuals of the proper medium in which alone the higher goals of humanity and the full vigour of human activity can thrive. The full development of individual potentials, and the acquisition of personal autonomy cannot, as in the 'selfish' view of human nature, be taken as universally 'given' but must rather be understood as conditioned by the availability of an appropriate social milieu. The corruption, selfishness, materialism, class-division attendant upon the advance of commercial society make the citizenry incapable of wisely using their liberty, and unworthy of an active role in determining the policies of the state. In sum, they prepare the way for despotism and tyranny.
NOTE Further reading includes Davies 1981, Durkheim 1964, Ferguson 1975, Robertson 1985 and Swingewood 1984.
8 Imagining the Republic: the sign and sexual politics in France MARGARET IVERSEN
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION The idea of 'enlightenment' has two implications that are central to Margaret Iversen's paper. First, the importance accorded to light as a metaphor for the acquisition of knowledge indicates the general significance of looking, and hence of the visual sign, whether this be in the process of learning, of leisure activities, or of social and political control. Second, obstacles to clear, unimpeded vision had to be removed. Many Enlightenment writers were, like Diderot, concerned about the differences between appearance and reality. For many commentators, thetheatre was the paradigmatic instance of the gap between appearance and reality and they debated not just the moral effects of plays, but many facets of acting, including how actors felt on stage, and whether they actually experienced the emotions they portrayed. Clothes, dissimulations in appearance, behaviour, and in speech were all obstacles to clarity of vision. So, of course, were masks. Yet there were social groups in eighteenth-century Europe that delighted in the masquerade, in the frisson that came from not knowing who was who in a setting charged with erotic excitement. Masks were thus linked with sexuality (Castle 1986), and more particularly with illicit sexuality. Iversen's paper shows some of the complex ways in which these matters were gendered. Most obviously, personifications of abstract issues revealed assumptions about gender in that male and female ones had distinct attributes, implications, and effects. Moreover, the virtues that were personified were themselves gendered. We can see this especially clearly in the case of Rousseau who had two quite different views of virtue for men and for women, and· depicted the two sexes as complementary rather than as politically equal or equivalent (see Bernstein this volume). Outram (1987) has shown how gendered ideas of virtue continued to have a strong grip on participants in the French Revolution, while Bloch (1987) has put a similar case for the American Revolution. We can go a step further than this. In taking the
122 Margaret Iversen story forward to the Statue of Liberty, Iversen shows how by associating Liberty with Progress the gendering becomes even more complicated. Science was often personified as male, nature as female. Or, more loosely, science was associated with the masculine triumph over nature, with the appropriation and deployment of natural forces like electricity. Liberty was ambivalently gendered: liberty as secular, and especially as economic and industrial progress was masculine; liberty as republic and as protective mother was female. Iversen discusses other associations of the idea of light. One of the most telling examples that she uses is the plan to inscribe the word 'light' on the forehead of a gigantic statue of Hercules. Here, the association between light and mental capacities is perfectly explicit. But we can also see in this instance the drive towards legibility that was so strong during the Enlightenment, which was, above all, a movement committed to didacticism, to the instruction of the middle and of the popular classes. A revolutionary situation, with its inevitable power vacuum, placed fresh demands on political language and on the communication of political ideas to the masses. Naturally, neither language nor ideas were stable and, as the revolutionary agenda changed, as different groups struggled for supremacy, symbolism was similarly mobile. Some themes emerged more strongly than others from this fluid situation, and one was that of the unity of the nation. We know from the writings of Rousseau that questions of political unity, of cohesion between citizens, was of great importance. The goal of national unity also had to be given visual form, as Iversen shows. The culture of the French Revolution is fascinating, not just because of its complex relationship to the Enlightenment, but also because here we can see the birth of the recognizably modern notion of a nation state. Visual images of the infant republic, in which the tensions and contradictions of the revolutionary process are so clear, give us access to many aspects of the Enlightenment and its shadows.
8
The French Revolution presents us with an acute case of a crisis of representation. The image of the state before the Revolution had been provided by the body of the king whose figure appeared as a sort of 'sacred centre' of the cultural-political field (Hunt 1984: 87). The authority of the king was affirmed through repeated ceremonies, such as coronations and weddings, and annual festivals. So the Revolution not only abolished monarchy; it also left a gaping hole in the system of representation. The vacuum opened up had to be filled. However, because the monarchy and the church were thought to draw their power partly from the manipulative use of images, spectacles, and emblems, there was a strong current amongst radical thinkers of the Revolutionary period urging the abolition of symbols altogether. Throughout this period, then, there was a tension between an ideal of transparency in the sphere of representation and a need for persuasive symbolization in the political sphere. Another tension related to this is the Revolutionary leaders' demand for didactic clarity and the popular appeal of imagery and icons. Rousseau was the most important theoretical s~urce for the radical ideal of transparency. In the Discourse on the Origins of Inequality (1754) Rousseau attacked display and competitive games as powerful sources of corruption in the original state of nature: They accustomed themselves to assemble before their huts round a large tree; singing and dancing, the true offspring of love and leisure, became the amusement, or rather the occupation, of men and women assembled together with nothing else to do. Each one began to consider the rest, and to wish to be considered in turn; and thus value came to be attached to public esteem. Whoever sang or danced best, whoever was the handsomest, the strongest, the most dexterous, or the most eloquent came to be of most consideration; and this was the first step toward inequality and at the same time toward vice. (Rousseau 1973: 90)
124 Margaret Iversen Because people won favour for how they appeared in other people's eyes, semblance or the fa<;ade of superiority became sufficient tokens. By wearing a mask, bearing emblems or symbols of superiority one could command respect and admiration. Rousseau argued that men should not seem but be a certain way. In other words, they should be perfectly transparent to one another, instead of covered in an accretion of signs. They should not need nor want to compare themselves to others. For Rousseau, masks lead to competition and discord, transparency to collective harmony. The parties and festivities of the old regime might be thought to be prime examples of display and self-regard. In his illuminating book, The Invention of Liberty, Jean Starobinski compares the fetes galantes of the aristocracy to the ideal of revolutionary festivals. During the ancien regime, the round of balls, dinner parties, and spectacles were frequented by pleasure-seekers in masks and disguises. Only a civilization enamoured of shows and pageantry, a civilization stressing primarily the pleasures of the eye, could cultivate this art of disguise and masquerade. The masked Carnival afforded everyone the pleasure of seeing and being seen without revealing his own identity; they revealed only an arbitrary aspect of themselves, which they could vary with time and place as the fancy took them. Released from all entangling circumstances of class and profession, the person behind the mask was no more than the particular image he chose to flaunt. . . . Like an actor, a masked man exists entirely in the present: his freedom is unbounded, and is protected by the recognition that he is only acting, arbitrarily and deceitfully. (Starobinski 1964: 90) The pleasure of these festivities was, according to Starobinski, in their very superficiality and fugitiveness, though they were inevitably followed by blank disillusionment at daybreak. There is another, more political, reading of the masquerade which connects it with the traditional carnival. This is Terry Castle's argument in Masquerade and Civilization. She sees the eighteenth-century masquerade ball as an urbanized and commercialized remnant of the village carnival in which a utopian ideal of freedom is acted out in the transgression of ideological boundaries of rank, race, and gender (Castle 1986: 77). However, the predominantly aristocratic clientele at these occasions and their transgressive character made them a target of moralistic denunciations like those in the Spectator: Addison wrote of the masquerade that it was 'wonderfully contrived for the advancement of Cuckoldom' and that the 'libidinous asserrlbly seems to terminate in assignations and intrigue' (Spectator 8, 9 March 1710). In Hogarth's Marriage a la Mode (1744) a masked ball ends in murder. The situation in early-eighteenth-century France, as described by Thomas Crow, revolved around an aristocratic protest against the high-mindedness of official culture - a 'resistance against state pretensions to monopoly over cultural expression' (Crow 1985: 70). He tells of aristocrats slumming at local fairs in order
Imagining the Republic: the sign and sexual politics in France 125
Figure 12 Antoine Watteau, Les Fetes venitiennes (ca. 1718).
to see the bawdy Italian Comedy and of their bringing this carnivalesque atmosphere into their salons and pleasure gardens. This is the ambiance so wonderfully captured by Watteau in the first two decades of the century (Fig. 12). Rousseau did not explicitly attack the masquerade, but the practice was certainly counter to his ideal of the transparent citizen. He imagined a completely different kind of festival that would unite citizens without making them spectators. If the
126 Margaret Iversen aristocratic fete was a scattered gathering of people indulging in private pleasures behind masks and engaging in mannered dancing, then the truly popular festival would be just the opposite collective, spontaneous, and joyful. Rousseau envisaged a popular festival in which there was no spectacle, only a participatory assembly of people. This is how Starobinski describes it: 'They would celebrate a new transparency: hearts would hide no more secrets, communication would be completely free of obstacles.' Ideally, the festival would have no ornamentation or symbols or decoration: 'The system of fac;ades, screens, fictions, alluring masks which dominated the world of aristocratic culture could no longer be retained: they were condemned to disappear, for they were felt in future to be simply inert elements, harmful obstacles' (Starobinski 1964: 101). Private desires would be sublimated in a unity of minds, the collective subject. Images were to be swept away in a cult of pure presence. In her excellent book, Festivals and the French Revolution, Mona Ozouf says that the ideal involved a divorce between theatre and festival, a de-theatricalized festival - and also observes that the ideal was never realized (Ozouf 1988: 206). In fact, revolutionary festivals were frequently theatrically iconoclastic - burning the symbols and emblems of the ancien regime and religious effigies (Idzerda 1954). Ozouf remarks on the prevalence of transformative scenes: 'Everywhere the cardboard throne concealed the altar of the fatherland, which was then revealed by fire' (Ozouf 1988: 101). The flame of purification and destruction also symbolized light, which banished anything that might 'interrupt the beam of liberty.' This reference to liberty or truth as an unimpeded beam of light is part of the metaphysics of transparency. It can be usefully juxtaposed to Edmund Burke's turning of the metaphor in his attack on the French Revolution and in particular on the doctrine of the Rights of Man: These metaphysic rights entering into common life, like rays of light which pierce into a dense medium, are by the laws of nature refracted from their straight line. Indeed, in the gross and complicated mass of human passions and concerns the primitive rights of men undergo such a variety of refractions and reflections that it becomes absurd to talk of them as if they continued in the simplicity of their original direction. (Burke 1968a: 153) The conservative Burke saw rights as historically evolved and contingent; the philosophers of republicanism saw them as absolute and universal and so endeavoured to jump over the history of France in their pursuit of an ideal for the Republic seeking out the original beam of light rather than its figural refractions. Progressive art theory in mid-eighteenth-century France manifests a similar distrust of the ambiguity of figuration. Diderot, for example, encouraged readable painting and, because of this, his admiration for Chardin is tinged with a certain apprehensiveness about la magie de faire ('the magic of execution'). Diderot was an advocate of the public, didactic function of art and so focused on ideas and
Imagining the Republic: the sign and sexual politics in France 127 expression rather than painterly nuances. Such effects must remain subordinate to the intelligibility of the narrative. In Absorption and Theatricality, Michael Fried notes that Diderot did not contest the hierarchy of the genres of painting, and suggests the reason for this: still life and landscape require such admirable painterly handling to call our attention to them that we become conscious of technique or the artist's virtuoso performance and this militates against any imaginative involvement (Fried 1980: 74-5). But there is another explanation closer to hand, namely, that landscape and still life are not properly discursive or didactic. Diderot insists that 'every work of sculpture or painting must be the expression of a great principle, a lesson for the spectator - otherwise it remains mute' (Eitner 1971: 64). Chardin's still-life painting leaves Diderot doubly dumbfounded. Not only is the subject matter mute, the handling defies explanation. 'This magic is beyond comprehension' (Eitner 1971: 59), he said, and magie has connotations in his writing of preenlightened secrecy and mystery. Diderot's anxiety about the unverbalizable nature of Chardin's painting and its indubitable excellence are brought together in his anecdote about Greuze pausing before an example in the Salon of 1763 and uttering a sigh. Greuze, also championed by Diderot, produced eminently legible paintings (Bryson 1981: 122-53). Unfortunately, Diderot did not live long enough to see his ideal perfectly realized in David's paintings. David's characteristic style, with its preternatural clarity and transparent atmosphere, can be read as a quest for a form of representation that jumps over the history of painting in the modern era to return to an earlier ideal (Fig. 13). His Graeco-Roman austerity served as a counter to the fluency of academic painting. As Thomas Crow observes, it signalled a language of truth and virtue: 'strained, stiff, awkward, obvious' (Crow 1985: 227). This very awkwardness was praised by sympathetic critics who 'disqualified the work of any artist, no matter how accomplished, who remained within the bounds of accepted artistic practice' (Crow 1985: 217). The position taken up by these critics, as summarized by Crow, is worth quoting at some length: The 'correct' drawing and composition perpetuated by the Academy was, for Carmontelle and critics like him, a false perfection of technique which counterfeited real grandeur and truth of expression. The eye, they said, must not be fooled by affected postures, silken textures, or sensually liquid play of the brush. . .. The demand was for an art that would, by the strength of its commanding counter-example, unmask both the deceits of the academicians and the reign of false appearances by which a despotic elite escaped public scrutiny and censure. (Crow 1985: 220-1) A fuller account of the relevant aesthetic-semiotic positions adopted during this period would include, among other topics, Rousseau's attack on the theatre and Diderot's proposed reforms of it, as well as discussions of political rhetoric and of dress reform. However, the intention here is only to provide a framework for under-
128 Margaret Iversen
Figure 13 Jacques-Louis David, The Death of Marat (1793).
standing the debates surrounding images of the Republic. These hinge on a fundamental contradiction: an iconoclastic impulse and an ideal of transparency clashed with the revolutionary government's demand for propaganda. The clash engendered paradoxes like the festival without spectacle, the art of sincere oration, painting which repudiates the painter's metier, or the idea of a costume which is transparent to one's authentic self. Mona Ozouf regards such paradoxes as the effects of mixing two strong intellectual currents. On the one hand, there was the Rousseauian and Platonic distrust of images (no doubt heightened by hostility to Catholic 'idolatry') and, on the other hand, the very influential empiricist psychology of the Abbe de Condillac, whose thesis that all knowledge derives from sense perception tended to privilege sight for purposes of education or social
Imagining the Republic: the sign and sexual politics in France 129 control. The convergence of these two views meant that propagandists and festival organizers were forced into the insuperable contradiction summed up by OZQuf: 'Secure in their belief in the power of images, they had to use them, while remaining distinctly convinced, according to a scheme inherited from classical thought, that everything that is figuration is false' (Ozouf 1988: 205). At the very least, a consequence of these conflicting positions was that the use of simulation, symbol, and allegory had to be carefully monitored. Ozouf argues that allegory seems to have been favoured as a solution to the problem, for allegory is allusion rather than illusion (Ozouf 1988: 211). It maintains a certain distance from reality; it is a visual image (which appeals to the senses), but not a simulation (which is a lie). Yet allegory often has a hermetic quality to it which makes it difficult to decipher - a serious defect for the propagandist. It seems as though the anxiety attaching to the mimetic quality of the visual sign could be allayed in either of two ways. One could aim at sincerity and truth in the hope of producing an image transparent to its object. Alternatively one could avoid the slipperiness of the simulacrum by heightening the conventionality of the image with allegory. The debate in the National Convention of 1792 over the new seal of the Republic is highly instructive in this context (Fig. 14). The State, amorphous, anonymous, and abstract, had to be personalized. Replacing the king as the figure on the insignia of the official seal was to be a woman leaning with one hand on a sheaf of fasces, holding in the other hand a lance topped with a liberty cap, a tiller at her feet, with the legend 'In the name of the French Republic'. Here, the traditional figure of Liberty is officially blended with the idea of the Republic. A minority view during the 'reign of Terror' held that there should be no insignia of the Republic and that moral principles should not be personified. Clear writing and clear speech ought to be enough. As Lynn Hunt succinctly puts it: 'Reason and nature, the foundations of the new regime, needed no representation outside of clear writing and clear speech since they were engraved on the hearts of all men' (Hunt 1983: 97). Even those who defended the use of insignia made a distinction between the type of royal emblems - 'the ridiculous hieroglyghs of heraldry' - and the new republican system of signs based on the principles of Condillac. The following, taken from a speech by the Abbe Gregoire to the convention, assumes an identity between the object perceived and the idea in the mind of the perceiver: When one reconstructs a government anew, it is necessary to republicanize everything. The legislator who ignores the importance of signs will fail at his mission; he should not let escape any occasion for grabbing hold of the senses, for awakening republican ideas. Soon the soul is penetrated by the objects reproduced constantly in front of its eyes; and this combination, this collection of principles, of facts, of emblems which retraces without cease for the citizen his rights and duties, this collection forms, in a manner of speaking, the republican mold which gives him a national character and the demeanor of a free man. (cited in Hunt 1983: 97)
130 Margaret Iversen
Figure 14 The First Seal of the Republic (1792).
The choice of a female allegory of Liberty for the seal of the Republic transformed the image into an allegory of the Republic itself (Fig. 14). Hunt remarks on how stately the image is, how far removed from the turbulence of the revolutionary days, and she tries to account for that appearance: 'Like a Counter-Reformation saint, she represented the virtues so desired by the new order: the transcendence of localism, superstition, and particularity in the name of a more disciplined and universalistic worship' (Hunt 1984: 62). If Liberty as the Republic is a secular saint, then David's painting of the death of Marat (1793) (Fig. 13) is surely a contemporary PiE~ta (Paulson 1983: 14). This superimposition of the ideals of the Republic onto the traditional sites of culture and religion is well illustrated by the case of the infamous Fete de fa Raison celebrated in Notre Dame (renamed the Temple of Reason) in November 1793 (Brumaire of the year II) (Fig. 15). In place of an altar there was a throne of Liberty upon which was seated a living female allegory of Reason or Liberty (Agulhon 1981: 28). Evidently a new form of worship was being encouraged. And in the spirit of abolishing dead images or simulacra, a living being was presented as the goddess. Still the goddess was not, of course, a real presence but another form of representation, probably an actress from the Opera. Counter-revolutionaries rumoured that she was a half-naked whore, just as hostile caricatures of the new Republic showed Liberty prostituting herself.
Imagining the Republic: the sign and sexual politics in France 131
Figure 15 The Goddess of Liberty at the Festival of Reason (November 1793).
The slurs on the virtue of the impersonator of Liberty and attacks on the Republic as a whore raise the issue of the feminine gender of the allegory of the Republic in a particularly acute way. Of course, there is a long history of representing abstract qualities or ideas with feminine allegories, and to this extent her gender needs no explanation. But it would seem that a certain sexual politics, together with theories of the sign prevalent during the revolutionary period, inflected the image of the Republic in particular ways. A strong case can be made for this by turning to the writing of Rousseau in which the theory of the sign is crossed with sexual politics. It turns out that the ideal of transparency he promulgated applied to men only. The abolition of distance pertained only as between citizens. What then is the role of women? Rousseau was concerned that his citizens needed bonding with some kind of social glue and spurred to action. Just as the allegorical figure of Truth on the frontispiece of the Encyclopedie (Fig. 3) and elsewhere is thinly veiled so as to entice male initiative to seek the naked truth (Jordanova 1989: 87-110), so Rousseau thought that women in the Republic should wear a veil of pudeur or modesty in order to excite male initiative that would spill over into the public domain. This idea is expressed most clearly in Emile (1762), and in the Lettre ad'Alemberl sur les Spectacles (1758). Commentators on these texts have made similar observations. Patrick Coleman writes that, for Rousseau, feminine modesty 'stimulates masculine initiative in the public sphere' (Coleman 1984: 116) and Joel Schwartz, in his book on Rousseau's sexual politics, notes that male desire must be inflamed by imagination - men truly desire an ideal that does not exist (Schwartz 1984). To create a sense of initiative in excess of material requirements, Rousseau recom-
132 Margaret Iversen mended a programme of education for boys and girls designed to increase sexual differentiation (Coleman 1984: 116). In Emile he suggested that Sophie's 'natural gift' of cunning ,should be cultivated so that she would know how to dissemble, to conceal her own feelings and to lie, for if she told the truth 'she would not long attract him' (Rousseau 1974: 348). He counselled that 'to say no is to say yes in the most effective way' (348). Rousseau was aware that the 'productive illusion' of idealized femininity which inspires sublime love and promotes the sort of selfmastery necessary for men to transcend 'the baseness of our human nature', is essentially chivalric: 'we scoff at the knights of old; they knew the meaning of love' (354). The 'meaning of love' is unrealizable desire, which produces a surfeit of masculine initiative, or sublimated violence, that can be manipulated and redirected by the wise legislator. It is surprising to observe the degree of harmony on this point between Rousseau and Edmund Burke. Burke castigated the revolutionaries for rudely tearing off 'the decent drapery of life' and for regarding 'homage paid to the sex' as folly. Here, too, respect for woman is regarded as a lynchpin of social cohesion and as a guarantee of political order without which society descends into barbarism (Burke 1968a: 171). The dissolution of hierarchy implied an abolition of distance and consequent loss of aura. Under the new dispensation, as Marx observed in the Communist Manifesto (1848), men formerly looked up to with awe are stripped of their haloes but, for Rousseau, haloes are not to be abolished, just displaced onto the heads of women. When the traditional social hierarchy is levelled and nothing is sacred, something must be invented to compensate for the loss so that naked self-interest does not have free rein. To this end, Rousseau raises the chaste wife to an icon of virtue, clothed in a veil of modesty and an aura of remoteness. The allegory of the Republic also represents an ideal, and is intended to inspire social cohesion. It is clear from what has been said why the image has the remote character described earlier. The Republic as Liberty is not, as Hunt claims, simply disciplined and universalistic. She has a very particular status, that is, one that is neither outside the social order like the wild, virginal Diana or Amazon, nor within it as a maternalistic protective figure. Rather she is the image of a chaste, mature woman who simultaneously inspires desire and commands respect. Maurice Agulhon's excellent Marianne into Battle presents the history of the image of the Republic in France. Although there were established iconographical attributes of Liberty, there was no iconographical tradition for the idea of the Republic apart from historical cases such as Rome. There was an allegory of Monarchy - a woman seated on a throne, crowned with the rays of the sun, holding a sceptre and leaning on a lion, and one of Anarchy - a woman with a vehement expression holding a dagger and a flaming torch. The image of the Republic, however, had to be fashioned anew and made intelligible to the broad mass of people. Liberty was the essence of the Republic and she had always had a prominent place in the allegories, sometimes accompanied by the other virtues, Equality and Fraternity. In some group allegories, the Republic has a separate existence and is
Imagining the Republic: the sign and sexual politics in France 133
Figure 16 Pierre-Paul Prud'hon, The Republic, with Liberty, Equality and Fraternity (ca. 1792).
surrounded by the three virtues. Agulhon describes the complicated group allegory devised by Prud'hon (Fig. 16) which shows the Republic seated, wearing helmet and breastplate like a Minerva. Her right arm rests on the shoulder of Liberty (standing, in a short tunic, the cap on the end of her pike and shattered chains about her ankles, and with a cat sitting beside her). Her left hand is on the shoulder of Fraternity (who stands holding a stick with a cock on the top of it and is followed by two children leading a lamb and a lion harnessed together. Liberty herself holds out her hand to an Equality who is half-naked and is followed by three more children bearing the symbols of the social ranks. (Agulhon 1981: 21) Yet the Republic is usually represented as a single female figure, perhaps in the interest of national unity, together with the symbols of other attributes such as the mason's level for equality and the fasces for unity, but most notably, the cap of liberty or bonnet rouge which formed a very clear contrast to the crown of monarchical authority. The early allegories of the Republic as Liberty were erected on the sites formerly occupied by statues of the king. For example, a plaster statue of Liberty was erected in the Place Louis Quinze, which became the Place de la Revolution, site of the
134 Margaret Iversen guillotine, and which is now Place de la Concorde. The images of young women representing France were derided with the common name of Marianne by counterrevolutionaries, but it soon became an affectionate term. Agulhon suggests that in Catholic France people may have been particularly receptive to a feminine goddess and Marianne was a name close to Mary, the mother of Jesus. The personification had the virtue of being a concrete symbol, while avoiding the pitfalls of real-life revolutionary heroes who could fall out of favour. For a brief time, during the 'Terror', the female allegory herself fell out of favour. In 1793-4, a more radical image was sought. David proposed that the Convention should order the erection of a giant statue in the form of Hercules to represent the French people, and soon thereafter they voted to make the Hercules the subject of the seal of state (Hunt 1983). It was a precarious time for the fledgling Republic, which had to defend itself from foreign invasion and regional counter-revolution the angry and hungry workers were demanding action, moderates were being executed, and the process of de-Christianization was in train (this was the moment of the Festival of Reason). David devised a statue that would render heroic and monumental the people's triumph over despotism and superstition. Its base was to be constructed of the debris of kings' heads knocked off the porticos of Notre Dame. At forty-six feet high it was to have 'force and simplicity', the virtues of the people. In one of its hands it was to hold little figures of Liberty and Equality, which showed how both depended on the people. During this period the distant and rather demure figure of Liberty was repudiated. No doubt her replacement with a masculine figure was also desirable for an image representing the sovereignty of working people. Yet David was evidently doubtful that the people would recognize themselves in the image he invented for them, so he called for the engraving of key words on the body of the colossus. On his brow would be inscribed 'light'; 'nature' and 'truth' were to appear on his chest; 'force' and 'courage' on his arms; and 'work' on his hands. The value of the giant statue as propaganda had to be overlaid by verbal didactic clarity. After the fall of Robespierre, the plan for the statue was abandoned, but the image of Hercules continued to circulate, intermittently resurfacing on coins during later republics. During the nineteenth century the image played a prominent role in socialist and proletarian iconography (Hobsbawm 1978). The contrast between civic Liberty and the awesome Hercules is in fact played out within the history of images of Liberty herself. She has a moderate and a radical image, as Linda Nochlin notes: there is 'the youthful, vigorous, combative tomboy sort of figure who wore a short skirt and was represented in an animated pose and the calm, serene, mature Liberty, shown fully draped and often seated. Right from the beginning ... there seems to have been a kind of opposition between a more dynamic, combative, and popular conception of Revolutionary imagery and a more serene, institutionalized and conciliatory one' (Nochlin 1981: 63). Marina Warner points to the same dual semantic value of the figure of Liberty in the chapter called 'The slipped chiton' of her Monuments and Maidens. She refers to an array of statues representing Justice or Liberty or Wisdom, all of whom are armed and serving as guardians of virtue. Warner argues that these figures, related
Imagining the Republic: the sign and sexual politics in France 135 to Athena or Minerva, stand for a kind of civilizing castration: they 'obey naturally and simply certain prescriptive metaphors which associate sexual control by women and the suppression of erotic desire with moral worth, or, in Freudian terms, with the formation of the social human being and his super-ego' (Warner 1985: 55). Clearly, some images of the Republic conform to this violent conception of the demands of civilization: the statue over-looking the guillotine seems to have been of this type. Yet the omnipresence of the red Phrygian cap during the Revolutionary period indicates quite a different reading of the images. The cap has a complicated iconographical derivation. It seems to derive partly from the floppy cap worn by t~agi and others designated as coming from the east or from afar, that is, as denoting an outsider. It also has associations with the cap worn by a freed Roman slave (Warner 1985: 277). Warner also suggests that the cap relates to the shape of an animal skin worn on the head of hunters or people associated with the wild. The connotations of 'outsiderness' and otherness are reinforced by another attribute of Liberty, the slipped chiton or bared breast. In Greek art Artemis, the 'fierce virgin' who dwells in the woods and is worshipped by the Amazons, is shown with slipped chiton (Warner 1985: 279). There would seem then to have been a radical image of Liberty, partly appropriated by official images of the Republic, which referred to a domain outside the law. She was positioned beyond the sYITlbolic order, and was therefore in a powerful position to subvert it. On this account, the second seal of the Republic (1848) must be seen as a tamed image of Liberty (Fig. 17). She is shown seated instead of standing, fully draped and surrounded by a hoard of obscure attributes. The most striking feature is the sun diadem instead of a Phrygian cap, which had by then become associated with radicalism. It is suggested that the sun emblem has masonic origin and has to do with Enlightenment and with political progress. Agulhon points to a split in the Republican camp during the Second and Third Republics, basically along the lines of bourgeois and working class, and a corresponding split in imagery. One unusual case is Daumier's sketch of the Republic, which was produced in 1848 for a competition to find a moderate image of the Republic. The figure manages to be both enthroned and maternal, and yet also a dynamic image of radical republicanism. The contest, incidently, ended in universal derisiop and with no winner. As T. J. Clark and Albert Boime both point out, this indicates the impossibility of state art during the second Republic (Clark 1973: 71; Boime 1971). Agulhon speculates about why there was no real equivalent in the United States for the Republic/Liberty/Marianne figure. Perhaps it was because in 1776 there was no real threat of counter-revolution as there was in France. A female allegorical figure may not have been so welcome in a country without a Catholic tradition. And tinally, the United States played up the cult of the US presidents, something that was more problematic in France where there was a history of Republican leaders betraying the Republic - most prominently the two Bonapartes. An eagle was chosen for the state seal and the country was personified by an Indian Princess, a figure adapted from the emblem of the whole continent, although later Columbia
136 Margaret Iversen
Figure 17 Auguste Barr, The Second Seal of the Republic (1848).
became a more popular image. Yet there is little doubt that the famous Statue of Liberty in New York Harbour is now considered the personification of the United States (Fig. 18). Liberty Enlightening the World, her original name, was a gift from the people of France to the USA in celebration of the centennial ofthat nation. It was inaugurated and the veil lifted from her face in 1886. A great deal of literature appeared about the statue on the occasion of the Bicentennial when it was carefully refurbished. The press coverage alluded to the fact that the statue was designed to articulate a particular concept of Liberty. The sculptor, Bartholdi, himself wrote: 'revolutionary Liberty cannot evoke American Liberty, which, after a hundred years of uninterrupted existence, should appear not as an intrepid young girl but as a woman of mature years, calm, advancing with the light but sure step of progress' (Bernstein 1986: 68). The 'revolutionary Liberty' to which Bartholdi alludes is perhaps most famously embodied in Delacroix's Liberty Leading the People at the Barricades (1830) (Fig. 19) which represents a bare-breasted young woman on the corpse-strewn barricades of the July Revolution in that year. The image, and variations on it, had a great deal of currency in 1848 and came to be associated with popular uprisings. The antimonarchist but conservative bourgeoisie wanted nothing to do with this image, especially in the wake of the Paris Commune (1871), and so their brainchild Liberty
Imagining the Republic: the sign and sexual politics in France 137
Figure 18 Auguste Bartholdi, The Statue of Liberty (1886).
Enlightening the World is fashioned after the calm, sedate forms of Liberty. While
Delacroix's Liberty is erotically charged, wearing the Phrygian cap, and carrying a rifle and a tricolour as she leads a revolutionary insurrection (Pointon 1986); Bartholdi's is a static, classicized, bourgeois matron, chastely clad and with a coiffure of neat ringlets. The statue has next to no attributes of Liberty at all, which
138 Margaret Iversen are the cap, slipped chiton, and dishevelled hair (she does have broken chains at her feet but these are practically invisible). Instead, her attributes are the sun diadem, a torch, and the Tables of the Constitution. The devisors of the statue wanted it to signify Liberty as enlightenment, prosperity, progress, self-discipline, and political stability. The original idea of having electric lights in the crown was particularly appropriate, since electricity was regarded at the time as the prime example of a natural force tamed by man. The construction of the colossal statue was also a technological tour de force. The extended arm is rigid, the body erect (an earlier version showed a more relaxed pose), her eyes stare straight ahead as Progress (her real name) advances one measured step in a trajectory which will disregard all natural irregularities. The ideology of the statue is echoed in an unintentionally humorous painting by Bartholdi, Fauns and Nymphs Surprised by a Locomotive (n.d., illustrated in Liberty 1986). The publicity material accompanying the Bicentennial did acknowledge the original function of the statue as a beacon beaming political messages back to Europe, but markedly accentuated its later interpretation as Mother of Exiles greeting immigrants from Europe during the first half of this century. A poem by Emma Lazarus, 'The New Colossus' (1883), affixed to the pedestal in 1903, stressed this aspect, contrasting this Liberty to the 'brazen giant of Greek fame with conquering limbs astride from land to land' - a reference to the colossus of Rhodes which dominated that port in Antiquity. The new colossus is a welcoming woman with 'mild eyes'. She is a strong and generous Mother prepared to adopt her own poor and helpless children from abroad: Not like the brazen giant of Greek fame, With conquering limbs astride from land to land, Here on our sea-washed, sun-set gates shall stand A mighty woman with a torch, whose flame Is the imprisoned lightening, and her name Mother of Exiles. From her beacon-hand Glows world-wide welcome, her mild eyes command The air-bridged harbour that twin-cities frame. 'Keep, ancient lands, your storied pomp!' cries she, With silent lips. 'Give me your tired, your poor, Your huddled masses yearning to breathe free, The wretched refuse of your teeming shore, Send these, the homeless, tempest-tost to me, I lift my lamp beside the golden door!' Lazarus's poem is an extreme case of imaginative projection. As Marina Warner and others have pointed out, the statue has a stern face, masculine features, and an implacable stare. In fact, during the two world wars, representations of her emphasized those features. Yet the desired Mother image has stuck in the nation's imagination. And so a compassionate face and a comfortable body have been super-
Imagining the Republic: the sign and sexual politics in France 139
Figure 19 Eugene Delacroix, Liberty at the Barricades (1830).
imposed on a female allegory designed to represent phallic mastery and control. No doubt this is what makes the Statue of Liberty such a powerful icon. It sums up an irresolvable contradiction in the nation's psyche - the ambition to dominate the world economically, politically, and even culturally, on the one hand, and the desire to give oneself to a protective Mother country on the other. If myth is 'an imaginary reconciliation of a real contradiction', as Levi-Strauss claims, then the Statue of Liberty is a very potent myth (see Liberty 1986 and Trachtenberg 1976). We have seen that the Enlightenment ideals of social and political transparency were already, perhaps necessarily, compromised during the Revolutionary period. The fledgling Republic needed a means of re-educating the public and it was thought that effective propaganda demanded spectacle and images to impress new ideals and virtues onto the minds of the people. The ideal of an open political forum quickly decayed into an opportunity for surveillance, control, and manipulation. The ideal of transparency is perhaps even more radically compromised when half the human race was condemned to inauthenticity and masquerade for the purposes of inciting masculine initiative in the public sphere. Finally, even the great metaphor of the transparency of reason - an undeflected, unimpeded beam of light - is compromised. Liberty Enlightening the World holds a torch over New York Harbor guiding vessels, electric beams in her crown symbolizing man's technological mastery of nature. The ideals of Liberty and Reason are more than ever harnessed to ideals of Commerce, Industry, and Enterprise.
9 Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 DAVID MUSSELWHITE
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION The bicentenary of the French Revolution is followed by the bicentenary of the responses to it. The English timetable is well known. The dissenting preacher Richard Price delivered his sermon 'Discourse on the love of our country' in November 1789. It was published by the Revolution Society (founded the previous year to commemorate the English Revolution of 1688), and provided the immediate stimulus for Edmund Burke's Reflections on the Revolution in France, whose full title continues And on the Proceedings in Certain Societies in London Relating to that Event. The Reflections were written during the first half of 1790 and published in November of that year. They provoked many replies by defenders of the Revolution, of which the best known are Mary Wollstonecraft's Vindication of the Rights of Men (1790) and Tom Paine's The Rights of Man (1791). That debate between Burke and Paine has often been seen as establishing the terms of modern political discussion in England, one defending the principles of a conservative inheritance, the other restating, in the new language of universal rights, the radical positions of the revolutionary English tradition. Given the changes to political language in this country since the late 1970s, it is hardly surprising that the debate over the significance of the French Revolution should have something of the passion of its original. For the left, Paine - and in some ways even more so Mary Wollstonecraft (whose Vindication of the Rights of Woman followed in 1792) - are reminders of fundamental statements made at times of crisis. To recall and to celebrate them is to refresh the weapons of language at a moment when, finally, the tide seems to be on the turn. David Musselwhite's essay fully confirms the relevance of the discussion of the French Revolution to today's circumstances; but it argues the unusual case that what is to be found in some of the lesser-q~oted sections of Burke's Reflectionsis a stinging indictment of what has been euphemistically called enterprise culture.
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 141 Given Margaret Thatcher's less than glowing assessment of the French Revolution, delivered with matchless insensitivity during her visit to Paris in July 1989, it would no doubt come as an unwelcome shock to her to read how Burke - father of conservatism - had castigated the Revolutionary Assembly precisely for its Thatcherite economic policies. In Burke's procedures Musselwhite finds confirmation of contemporary discourse theory. The views quoted - those of Laclau and Mouffe - are in themselves controversial, not least on the left; but the crucial importance of language to the political scene has been brought honle by the Thatcherite success in disarticulating .radical vocabulary, a notable coup in 1988 being the appropriation for the 'enterprise culture' of the notion of 'active citizenship', no doubt a pre-emptive strike against the Revolutionary celebrations. Burke's Reflections demonstrates this 'surface of emergence' on which we can see the terms of an (older) conservatism in the process of articulation. But he also more surprisingly - proves to be the theorist of this process, in his early Enquiry into the Sublime and the Beautiful (1756), through the pages of which Musselwhite's essay approaches the Reflections.
9
Burke addressed many audiences - his constituents, his fellow Members of Parliament, the young enthusiast for revolution, the decadent aristocrat, the American colonist, the 'nabob' exploiter - and any commentary on his work can only do justice to that work if it, in turn, keeps a variety of audiences in mind. In what follows, therefore, I shall endeavour, in my turn, to 'rotate' my audiences as Burke rotated his. I hope, in this way, to provide an introduction to Burke's work for those who are not yet familiar with it while at the same time to offer adjustments to established interpretations of that same work which might be of interest to those for whom Burke is already a familiar figure. Finally, to perhaps the most important audience of all, I would like to present a Burke who speaks to us now in 1990 - that is, to an audience, to a public even, bemused and disturbed by the political phenomenon of 'Thatcherism'. No less than the number of audiences he addressed is the number of 'Burkes' who addressed them. Few writers can have assumed so many contradictory and diametrically opposed positions at once. Burke was for and against just about everything the Crown, the aristocracy, the poor, the bourgeoisie, religion, and the Church, even the jacobins - and always with the same compelling intensity. Indeed there is something manic, even schizoid, in Burke's endless shifts of moods and positj0ns. Just at the very moment when one thinks one has located him, Burke slips away and reappears somewhere else - the effect being that 'where Burke is, you cannot be', or that game of 'scissors, paper, stone', where each discrete element either caps or is capped by one of the others. Even when - perhaps especially when - Burke is advocating a position with (apparently) his utmost conviction there is always the chance that he will reverse field on himself and in a blink the opposite is being said. It is impossible to find any consistency in Burke and it is this which makes him both a readily available and an equally treacherous ally. Seeking support from Burke today, in the very act of launching what seems to be a most thrusting indictment of many recent government policies: 'To tell the people that they are relieved by the dilapidation of their public estate, is a cruel and insolent imposition' (Burke
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 143 1968a: 371) one trips over some other pronouncement equally supportive of those policies: 'To provide for us in our necessities is not in the power of government. ... The laboring people are only poor because they are numerous' (Burke n.d.: 133-4). What is important in Burke and makes his work peculiarly relevant today is not so much what he says - which, as I have argued, can easily be shown as selfcontradictory - but the logic or purpose that lies behind this very dispersal of his subject positions. The notion of 'the dispersal of subject positions' comes from current discourse theory, briefly discussed at the end of this essay. It is a notion that Burke would have grasped quite easily, for the whole of his political and rhetorical practice was based upon it and its basic operating system, so to speak, is to be found explained with some clarity in his early Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful (1756). The Philosophical Enquiry is of major importance for understanding Burke's work as a whole but it can be seen to be of particular significance for an understanding of his later Reflections on the Revolution in France (1790). The Enquiry begins by establishing that Most of the ideas which are capable of making a powerful impression on the mind, whether simply of Pain or Pleasure, or of the modification of those, may be reduced very nearly to these two heads, self-preservation and society. (Burke 1958: 38) On the basis of this simple dichotomy (and one cannot but note its contemporary significance) Burke constructs his theory of the sublime and the beautiful. Beauty is generally conducive to the well-being and reproduction of society and is characterized by smallness, smoothness, sweetness, and so forth - an assemblage of generally 'feminine' (and, it must be said, rather uninteresting) attributes. The sublime, on the other hand, is very much the opposite, distinctly 'masculine' in tenor. It is what causes pity and fear and threatens life itself: Whatever is fitted in any sort to excite the ideas of pain, and danger, that is to say, whatever is in any sort terrible, or is conversant aoout terrible objects, or operates in a manner analogous to terror, is a source of the sublime; that is, it is productive of the strongest emotion which the mind is capable of feeling. (39) 'Later this is amplified in a passage which will be of considerable interest to us: The passion caused by the great and sublime in nature, when those causes operate most powerfully, is Astonishment; and astonishment is that state of the soul, in which all its motions are suspended, with some degree of horror. In this case the mind is so entirely filled with its object, that it cannot entertain any other, nor by consequence reason on that object which employs it. Hence arises the great power of the sublime, that far from being produced it ":lInt"lrU"\":lIf"I':)C'
144 David Musselwhite our reasonings, and hurries us on by an irresistible force. Astonishment, as I have said, is the effect of the sublime in the highest degree; the inferior effects are admiration, reverence and respect. (57) The very last phrase is particularly important. Part of the significance of the Enquiry resides in the attention Burke pays to the psychology and the physiology of the subject who experiences the sublime or the beautiful - that is, for Burke the sublime and the beautiful are no longer simply characteristics of the object but are in large part determined by the experiences of the subject him- or herself. This was perhaps the most radical aspect of the Enquiry. The subject's capacity for associations and sympathy will playa large part in determining what he or she feels. In pursuing his argument, and in examining the relationship between 'terror' and 'pain' as components of the sublime experience, Burke observes how body and mind react on each other - the body in pain becomes contorted as it does with terror: the only difference being that pain affects the mind through the body whereas terror affects the body through the mind (132). It follows from this, then, that the body itself, as common denominator, can be used as a kind of 'trigger' to provoke that terror and fear which is part and parcel of the experience of the sublime. In other words, by simulating body postures - by adopting contortions and grimaces - one gains, through a kind of associative sympathy, some access to the emotions that would normally cause such postures. Burke cites the case of one Campanella: this man, it seems, had not only made very accurate observations on human faces, but was very expert in mimicking such, as were any way remarkable. When he had a mind to penetrate into the inclinations of those he had to deal with, he composed his face, his gesture, his whole body, as nearly as he could into the exact similitude of the person he intended to examine; and then carefully observed what turn of mind he seemed to acquire by this change. So that ... he was able to enter into the disposition and thoughts of people, as effectually as if he had been changed into the very men. (133) This anecdote from early in his career helps greatly in understanding Burke's later rhetorical strategy and goes some way to explaining what is meant by a 'dispersal of subject positions'. In fact, of course, Burke had already used this rhetorical ploy in his Vindication of Natural Society (1756) which he wrote in the style of Bolingbroke as a satire on that rationalism that asserted the values of a natural society as against the vices and corruption of society itself. It is notorious that Burke's parody of Bolingbroke was too successful and that Burke was seen by Godwin, among many, as having 'displayed the evils of existing political institutions with incomparable force of reasoning (quoted in Burke 1968b: 41). One can sympathize with Godwin's
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 145 misreading - for the following does read like a bitter and reasoned indictment of class society: The most obvious division of society is into rich and poor; and it is not less obvious, that the number of the former bear a great disproportion to those of the latter. The whole business of the poor is to administer to the idleness, folly, and luxury of the rich; and that of the rich, in return, is to find the best methods of confirming the slavery and increasing the burdens of the poor. In a state of nature, it is an invariable law, that a man's acquisitions are in proportion to his labours. In a state of artificial society, it is a,law as constant and as invariable, that those who labour most enjoy the fewest things; and that those who labour not at all have the greatest number of enjoyments. (1968b: 59)
It might be worthwhile comparing this briefly with the following passage from the late essay on Scarcity: To provide for us in our necessities is not in the power of government. It would be a vain presumption in statesmen to think they can do it. The people maintain them, and not they the people. It is in the power of government to prevent much evil; it can do very little positive good in this, or perhaps in anything else. It is not only so of the state and statesmen, but of all the classes and descriptions of the rich: they are the pensioners of the poor, and are maintained by their superfluity. They are under an absolute, hereditary, and indefeasible dependence on those who labour and are miscalled the poor. (Burke n.d.: 133-4) Most readers if asked to say which of these passages was ironic or satiric would say the second - and, such is the volatility of Burke's thought, they might well be right. These are probably two good and comparable instances of Burke's tendency to reverse field on himself. Furthermore, the inherent instability of these passages should remind us that the 'dispersed subject' is not quite as simple as the Campanella example suggests. This would imply that an already constituted subject adopts various positions one at a time, whereas 'dispersal' means that there is never any fixed subject ontologically prior to the dispersal itself and that this dispersal never stops. What keeps the subject as an identity is not a point of arrest but its speed round the track. Like a gyro, the faster it spins the stiffer it is; there are moments, indeed, when Burke reminds one of a whirling dervish. The third important contribution of the Enquiry to an understanding of Burke's later work - after the introduction of the substantive notions of the sublime and the beautiful themselves and the model of Campanella - is to be found in the brief discussion of language in the last section. Here Burke distinguishes between what he calls 'simple aggregate words' like 'man, horse, tree, castle, etc.', 'simple abstract words' like 'red, blue, round, square, and the like' and what he terms 'compounded
146 David Musselwhite abstract words' such as 'virtue, honour, persuasion, docility' (1958: 164). It is these last which interest Burke most. He remarks of them: Of these I am convinced, that whatever power they may have on the passions, they do not derive it from any representation in the mind of the things for which they stand.... Such words are in reality but mere sounds; but they are sounds, which being used on particular occasions, wherein we receive some good, or suffer some evil, or see others affected with good or evil ... they produce in the mind, whenever they are afterwards mentioned, effects similar to those of their occasions. (164-5) The compound abstract words, then, have no reference and represent nothing, but they have accumulated great emotional power through associations and their mere utterance can re-evoke huge areas of meaning and experience. In this sense these words have less a reference than a referential, or even in Burke's case very often, a 'reverential', power of conjuring up those great multi-layered complexes that Voloshinov would probably term a 'theme' and Barthes a 'myth' - like 'Englishness', or 'inheritance', or 'chivalrousness' - the examples abound, as we shall see. Not that the use of this language is without its risks as Burke acknowledges, supplying in the process the very critical term that his own excesses often invite:
Wise, valiant, generous, good and great. These words, by having no application, ought to be unoperative; but when words commonly sacred to great occasions are used, we are affected by them even without the occasions. When words which have been generally.so applied without any rational view, or in such a manner that they do not rightly agree with each other, the stile is called bombast. (166) What we derive from the Enquiry is therefore a powerful binary paradigm - the sublime and the beautiful, a method of achieving intuition into even alien modes of thought, and a recognition of the essential arbitrariness and capriciousness of language effects - all of which help us to understand better the nature of Burke's rhetorical strategies in his later works generally, and particularly in the Reflections. But the Enquiry offers us even more. A comparison of the Enquiry with the Reflections illustrates Burke's knack of unfixing and disarticulating the elements of one discursive practice in order to reconstitute them as moments of another, quite different, paradigm. We have seen how, in the Enquiry, the sublime is regarded as strong and male and alluring, whereas the beautiful comes across as something essentially weak and 'feminine'. Part of Burke's problem in the Reflections is that, in spite of himself, he finds the French Revolution to be a primarily sublime event: 'All circumstances taken
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 147 together, the French revolution is the most astonishing that has hitherto happened in the world' (1968a: 92). 'Astonishment', as remarked above, was the most distinctive characteristic of the experience of the sublime and it is this very fascination exercised by the revolution which threatens to undermine Burke's ostensive project to defend the English constitution, the aristocracy, the Church, etc. Simply to be able to appeal to the principle of beauty - as he does, for example in the description of the French Queen (see below p. 149) - is not in the end good enough, for beauty alone remains too weak and effete. What we find Burke doing in a large part of the Reflections is systematically disconnecting many of the most powerful secondary aspects of the sublime - 'admiration', 'reverence', 'respect' as well as 'obscurity', 'awe', 'magnificence', even 'disorder' - from the Revolution and deploying them instead as part of the repertoire of what will become the classic statement of modern conservatism. What is important to note about this is that this 'statement' is here being pieced together for the first time: it does not represent positions or interests already 'fixed' elsewhere - the 'aristocracy', the 'Crown', or, even, the 'bourgeoisie'. The Reflections is the discursive surface where these elements emerge in their modern sense for the very first time. The process of disarticulation and rearticulation which makes possible this new discursive surface is possibly Burke's most effective and consistent strategy. It also explains, once again, why his positions can sometimes seem to be so precarious. Finally, there is an amusing illustration of just this precariousness of subject position in the Reflections, involving one last reference to the Enquiry. Burke inserts a footnote at a moment of spluttering indignation: Another of these reverend gentlemen, who was witness to some of the spectacles which Paris has lately exhibited - expresses himself thus: 'A King dragged in submissive triumph by his conquering subjects, is one of those appearances of grandeur which seldom rise in the prospect of human affairs, and which, during the remainder of my life, I shall think of with wonder and gratification.' (1968a: 157) The resort to the footnote is itself interesting in that it suggests another text, another subject position, another scene. The footnote is itself footnoted by Conor Cruise O'Brien to the effect that the 'reverend' gentleman referred to in the note was unknown. There is, of course, every chance that the reverend gentleman is no other than Burke himself wearing another hat, so to speak - for the appreciation of the aesthetic appeal of 'the ruin of monarchs, and the revolutions of kingdoms' comes straight out of the Enquiry (1958: 62). To use an expression I am sure MarieAntoinette would not thank me for, Burke here is gleefully having his cake and eating it. Burke is the great founding ideologue of modern liberal conservatism and his critique of the French Revolution in his Reflections has been seen as the model of all conservative critiques of radicalism. In the Reflections Burke presents himself as
148 David Musselwhite the great champion of the English Constitution, the defender of aristocracy, the Crown, the English parliamentary system, the Church of England, religion, and property. What he was against in the French Revolution is the threat to all these institutions presented by a democratic radicalism and egalitarianism based upon some abstract theory of the universal rights of man. For Burke the French Revolution was a catastrophe, a crisis for the whole of European civilization, for he saw that what it would lead to was atheism, greedy and parasitic speculation, and anarchy. Let us look at some of the more resounding passages. First on the English Constitution: We have an inheritable crown; an inheritable peerage; and an house of commons and a people inheriting privileges, franchises, and liberties, from a long line of ancestors. This policy appears to me to be the result of profound reflection; or rather the happy effect of following nature, which is wisdom without reflection, and above it. A spirit of innovation is generally the result of a selfish temper and confined views. People will not look forward to posterity, who never look backward to their ancestors. Besides, the people of England well know, that the idea of inheritance furnishes a sure principle of conservation, and a sure principle of transmission; without at all excluding a principle of improvement. . . . By a constitutional policy, working after the pattern of nature, we receive, we hold, we transmit our government and our privileges, in the same manner in which we enjoy and transmit our property and our lives. The institutions of policy, the goods of fortune, the gifts of Providence, are handed down, to us and from us, in the same course and order. Our political system is placed in a just correspondence and symmetry with the order of the world, and with the mode of existence decreed to a permanent body composed of transitory parts; wherein, by the disposition of a stupendous wisdom, moulding together the great mysterious incorporation of the human race, the whole, at one time, is never old, or middle-aged, or young, but in a condition of unchangeable constancy, moves on through the varied tenour of perpetual decay, fall, renovation, and progression. Thus, by preserving the method of nature in the conduct of the state, in what we improve we are never wholly new; in what we retain we are never wholly obsolete. By adhering in this manner and on those principles to our forefathers, we are guided not by the superstition of antiquarians, but by the spirit of philosophic analogy. In this choice of inheritance we have given to our frame of polity the image of a relation in blood; binding up the constitution of our country with our dearest· domestic ties; adopting our fundamental laws into the bosom of our family affections; keeping inseparable, and cherishing with the warmth of all their combined and mutually reflected charities, our state, our hearths, our sepulchres, and our altars. (Burke 1968a: 119-20) This passage offers us much of what is remembered as the typical tone and position
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 149 of the Reflections - the formal sonorousness that reminds us of Royal Weddings and the Last Night of the Proms, the defiant celebration of the notion of inheritance and heritage, the boasting of an access to a 'wisdom without reflection' founded on natural intuitions that resists the 'innovation' of 'confined views' (Burke's dismissive term for abstract theory), the celebration of the essential unity of past, present, and future, of a system that ensures continuity without excluding moderate change, and that models itself on a 'pattern of nature' which cuts across nature, society, and family and which is sanctioned by a divine 'Providence' disposing 'stupendous wisdom'. Burke's style does not invite close analysis, for all too often one is left wondering exactly what certain phrases really mean - what is 'wisdom without reflection'; whose is the disposition of a stupendous wisdom'? - but we must recall that 'reference' and 'representation' are not, for Burke, integral to the significance of language at this level of abstraction. What matters is the mood, the resonance, the affective bond that he creates - the mood, in a sense, of a certain 'Englishness'. Burke's defence of the aristocracy reaches its climax in his famous, even notorious, apostrophe to the French Queen: It is now sixteen or seventeen years since I saw the queen of France, then dauphiness, at Versailles; and surely never lighted on this orb, which she hardly seemed to touch, a more delightful vision. I saw her just above the horizon, decorating and cheering the elevated sphere she just began to move in glittering like the morning-star, full of life, and splendor, and joy. Oh! What a revolution! and what an heart must I have, to contemplate without emotion that elevation and that fall! Little did I dream when she added titles of veneration to those of enthusiastic, distant, respectful love, that she should ever be obliged to carry the sharp antidote against disgrace concealed in that bosom; little did I dream that I should have lived to see such disasters fallen upon her in a nation of gallant men, in a nation of men of honour and of cavaliers. I thought ten thousand swords must have leaped from their scabbards to avenge even a look that threatened her with insult. - But the age of chivalry is gone. - That of sophisters, oeconomists, and calculators, has succeeded; and the glory of Europe is extinguished for ever. Never, never ~rmore, shall we behold that generous loyalty to rank and sex, that proud submission, that dignified obedience, that subordination of the heart, which kept alive, even in servitude itself, the spirit of an exalted freedom. The unbought grace of life, the cheap defence of nations, the nurse of manly sentiment and heroic enterprize is gone! It is gone, that sensibility of principle, that chastity of honour, which felt a stain like a wound, which inspired courage whilst it mitigated ferocity, which ennobled whatever it touched, and under which vice itself lost half its evil, by losing all its grossness. (169-70)
The important point to be made is that this is not a 'defence of the aristocracy' in the sense of an already existing order (this, it seems to me is the basic mistake of
150 David Musselwhite almost every reading of Burke: that he 'stands for' or 'represents' the 'aristocracy' or the 'bourgeoisie'). Burke not only knew as ,,,,ell as any man of the many shortcomings of a decadent and idle landed aristocracy, he was also outspoken in his utter contempt of such an order (200-1; and cf. his Letter to a Noble Lord in Burke n.d.). Burke's 'defence', in other words, is more of the order of a rhetorical evocation or, better and probably more accurate, an arriviste's fantasy montagelike the tabloid construction of the royals: it is here, in effect, that the modern iconology of the Crown emerges for the first time. Nevertheless, it should not be overlooked that this passage also provides us with the central argument of the Reflections in that one key moment: 'But the age of chivalry is gone. - That of sophisters, oeconomists, and calculators, has succeeded; and the glory of Europe is extinguished forever.' That this passage embarrassed even Burke's friends - as well as offering Thomas Paine the target for his best shaft: 'He [Burke] pities the plumage but forgets the dying bird' (Paine 1969: 73) - is well known, but set alongside it one noted Marxist historian, E. P. Thompson, quoting another noted Marxist thinker, Christopher Caudwell, sounding very much like the arch-conservative Burke on the relationship between 'tenderness and cash': It is as if love and economic relations have gathered at two opposite poles. All the unused tenderness of man's instincts gather at one pole and at the other are economic relations, reduced to bare coercive rights to commodities. (Thompson 1978: 84) For all the sugar coating the principal insight is as hard as steel. Perhaps if one had to choose one passage from the Reflections to represent Burke's style at the peak of its powers it would be the following celebrated account of the nature of the social contract - indeed of the nature of society - that thing of which there is no such, according to one of Margaret Thatcher's most quoted pronouncements: Society is indeed a contract. Subordinate contracts for objects of mere occasional interest may be dissolved at pleasure - but the state ought not to be considered as nothing better than a partnership agreement in a trade of pepper and coffee, callico or tobacco, or some other such low concern, to be taken up for a little temporary interest, and to be dissolved by the fancy of the parties. It is to be looked on with other reverence; because it is not a partnership in things subservient only to the gross animal existence of a temporary and perishable nature. It is a partnership in all science; a partnership in all art; a partnership in every virtue and all perfection. As the ends of such a partnership cannot be obtained in many generations, it becomes a partnership not only between those . who are living, but between those who are living, those who are dead, and those who are to be born. Each contract of each particular state is but a clause in the great primaeval contract of eternal society, linking the lower with the higher natures, connecting the visible and the invisible w~~~, _~c~o!~i!1~ !~ ~ }i~~q _
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 151
( ' ((rlrulr/II'lff' /)I/II'/~,II',
Figure 20 Le Calculateur patriote (1789). One of the anonymous group of prints that were well-known through numerous copies and versions; they take a grim view of the Revolution, whose patriotic accountant is shown keeping a record of the heads that have been taken in payment and those that are still due (Cuno 1988: 154).
152 David Musselwhite compact sanctioned by the inviolable oath which holds all physical and all moral natures, each in their appointed place. This law is not subject to the will of those, who by an obligation above them, and infinitely superior, are bound to submit their will to that law. The municipal corporations of that universal kingdom are not morally at liberty at their pleasure, and on the speculations of a contingent improvement, wholly to separate and tear asunder the bands of their subordinate community, and to dissolve it into an unsocial, uncivil, unconnected chaos of elementary principles. It is the first and supreme necessity only, a necessity that is not chosen but chooses, a necessity paramount to deliberation, that admits of no discussion, and demands no evidence, which alone can justify a resort to anarchy. This necessity is no exception to the rule; because this necessity itself is a part too of that moral and physical disposition of things to which man must be obedient by consent or force; but if that which is only submission to necessity should be made the object of choice, the law is broken, nature is disobeyed, and the rebellious are outlawed, cast forth, and exiled, from this world of reason, and order, and peace, and virtue, and fruitful penitence, into the antagonistic world of madness, discord, vice, confusion, and unavailing sorrow. (Burke 1968a: 194-5) From Paine to Macpherson the 'partnership ... between those who are living ... those who are dead ... and those who are to be born' has been held up to a derision that is by no means helped by the mumbo-jumbo of that 'great primaeval contract of eternal society' - but the passage still works, effectively and affectively. Moreover, for all the illogicality, there may be some validity in this notion of a cooperation between generations whereby the past does not have a stranglehold on the future as Paine read Burke - but, on the contrary, the future is expected to make its own distinctive contribution (281). Indeed, what fixes the power of this passage is that it is precisely here, operating at full blast on the conservative stop, that Burke provides the philosophical space in the let-out justification of 'necessity' - for the very thing he anathematizes: 'a resort to anarchy', that is, to revolution itself. This, in fact, is perhaps the most flagrant instance of Burke 'reversing field' on himself and it is perhaps the most disturbing index of the way in which Burke is capable of self-destructing, of involving himself in a kind of catastrophic logic warp, of holding seemingly incompatible positions at once. It is the impossibilism of these fuzzy sets which makes Burke seem curiously post-modern. Finally, as the passage comes to a close, there is the marvellous eschatological vision of the final judgement which evokes the apocalyptic dimension of the revolutionary act and which repeats, as if in a coda, the argument of the passage as a whole and of the Reflections itself. Burke's 'defence' of religion and the Church is probably the site of most complexity in the Reflections. That Burke's attitude towards the Church and religion is profoundly ambiguous has frequently been noted, but less attention has been paid
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1.990 153 to the actual textual disturbances associated with this area of Burke's thought. Take the following, which begins with so much defiance: We know, and what is better we feel inwardly, that religion is the basis of civil society, and the source of all good and comfort. In England we are so convinced of this, that there is no rust of superstition, with which the accumulated absurdity of the human mind might have crusted it over in the course of ages, that ninetynine in a hundred of the people of England would not prefer to, impiety. (186-7)
After the initial velocity the argument suddenly stumbles on that phrase 'the rust of superstition' and one is left wondering what kind of double bind we are being presented with in the choice between 'the accumulated absurdity of the human mind' and 'impiety'. We sense, in short, that Burke is blathering. Again, listen to the following: For, taking ground on that religious system, of which we are now in possession, we continue to act on the early received, and uniformly continued sense of mankind. That sense not only, like a wise architect, hath built up the august fabric of states, but like a provident proprietor, to preserve the structure from prophanation and ruin, as a sacred temple, purged from all impurities of fraud, and violence, and injustice, and tyranny, hath solerrlnly and for ever consecrated the commonwealth, and all that officiate in it. This consecration is made, that all who administer to the government of men, in which they stand in the person of God himself, should have high and worthy notions of their function and destination; that their hope should be full of immortality; that they should not look to the paltry pelf of the moment, nor to the temporary praise of the vulgar, but to a solid, permanent existence, in the permanent part of their nature, and to a permanent fame and glory, in the example they leave as a rich inheritance to the world. (189)
The bewildering accumulation of explosives recalls that gibe about Burke's rhetoric smelling of whisky and potatoes. And, when disentangled, for all the zest of the urging we have an unequivocally secular argument. To use a most telling phrase from later in the Reflections what is present here is a secular state apparatus 'construed in the service of God' (272), that is, it is a discursive articulation. The old barb that the Church of England is the Tory Party at prayer is no more and no less than the necessary correlative of Burke's rhetorical achievement, for by the time Burke was writing the Church itself as a political force had already become marginalized. What Burke brings back is not so much 'religion' as 'religiosity', a matter of style rather than of substance. Practically all of Burke's references to religion have this perplexing ambiguity. The following is the most notorious example:
154 David Musselwhite The monks are lazy. Be it so. Suppose them no otherwise employed than by singing in the choir. They are as usefully employed as those who neither sing nor say. As usefully even as those who sing upon the stage. They are as usefully employed as if they worked from dawn to dark in the unnumerable servile, degrading, unseemly, unmanly, and often unwholesome and pestiferous occupations, to which by the social oeconomy so many wretches are inevitably doomed. If it were not generally pernicious to disturb the natural course of things, and to impede, in any degree, the great wheel of circulation which is turned by the strangely directed labour of these unhappy people, I should be infinitely more inclined forcibly to rescue them from their miserable industry, than violently to disturb the repose of monastic quietude. Humanity, and perhaps policy, might better justify me in the one than in the other. It is a subject on which I have often reflected, and never reflected without feeling from it. I am sure that no consideration, except the necessity of submitting to the yoke of luxury, and the despotism of fancy, who in their own imperious way will distribute the surplus product of the soil, can justify the toleration of such trades and employments in a well-regulated state. But, for this purpose of distribution, it seems to me, that the idle expences of monks are quite as well directed as the idle expences of us layloiterers. (271)
This is, of course, a hopelessly confused passage: it is, on the one hand, an entirely unconvincing defence of the clergy, who emerge here as unequivocally parasitic, while the invocation of the 'necessity of submitting to the yoke of luxury, and the despotism of fancy', (gilded a little with 'their own imperious way') is totally specious. On the other hand, there is that terrible glimpse of the plight of the poor and oppressed condemned to work in the most appalling conditions (surely here we have the first glimpse of an industrial proletariat not a rural peasantry) which almost provokes Burke to one of his field reversals - we are close here, surely, to the voice of the earlier Vindication of Natural Society. There may be genuine confusion in Burke's position as to the relative roles of distribution and production in the working of an economy. But the greater confusion comes from Burke's not knowing quite how to define the role of the Church in a new historical context. For the Church Burke is seeking to defend is, again, not the institution that exists, but one that he wants to produce as some kind of bastion against the unbridled materialism which he sees coming into being with the French Revolution: Why should the expenditure of a great landed property, which is a dispersion of the surplus product of the soil, appear intolerable to you or to me, when it takes its course through the a~cumulation of vast libraries, which are the history of the force and weakness of the human mind; through great collections of ancient records, medals, and coins, which attest and explain laws and customs; through paintings and statues, that, by imitating nature, seem to extend the limits of creation; through grand monuments of the dead, which continue the regards
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 155 and connexions of life beyond the grave; through collections of the specimens of nature, which become a representative asserrlbly of all the classes and families of the world, that by disposition facilitate, and, by exciting curiosity, open the avenues of science? If, by great permanent establishments, all these objects of expence are better secured from the inconstant sport of personal caprice and personal extravagance, are they worse than if the same tastes prevailed in scattered individuals. (272)
Burke is here constructing what Coleridge in his On the Constitution ofthe Church and State (1829-30) will be very shortly calling the Idea of the Church (cf. Burke in the Reflections: 'Church and state are ideas ...' (198)) which he distinguishes quite clearly from the actual established Church and which he sees as a kind of superior educational and cultural institution separate from the state and funded by its own resources, what he terms the 'Nationalty' (Coleridge 1976). In a way Burke's Church, while having some of the trappings of the medievalism that appealed to Carlyle, is more like a model of the great municipal libraries and art galleries and archives of the Victorian heyday, great public institutions and endowments, centres of higher education. In other words the 'Church' that Burke defends is not one that already exists, but, once again, the notion, the Idea - to use Coleridge's distinctive word again - of a kind of civic institution responsible for welfare and learning, and immune from the depredations of the market. So much for what the Reflections affects to defend - inheritance, property, the Crown, the aristocracy, and the Church. We have seen that neither Burke's style nor his argument is quite as limpidly clear and unambiguous as might be expected of the committed polemic the Reflections purports to be. On the whole, however, this is what might be called the 'familiar' Burke, the Burke who would not be out of place in the shires and the Conservative Party Conference - 'one of us', so to speak. We have just glimpsed now and again the underlying tensions in this particular Burke. Much of what Burke attacks in the Reflections is wholly consistent with this 'conservative' element - there is the impatience with theory and abstraction, the distrust of egalitarian 'levelling', the disapproval of all radical change. But it is when we come to see more closely just exactly what - or rather whom - Burke was attacking that the conventional recall of Burke starts to become troubled. By 'the conventional recall' I mean that view of Burke as the champion of conservatism against radicalism, or of the Crown against the jacobins, those poles that elide so easily with the polarities of aristocracy and people, of right and left, of rich and poor, and so on. Even, indeed, the more accurate view of Burke as the champion of the aristocracy against the bourgeoisie. Perhaps the coolest and at the same time the most complex of Burke's accounts of the social structure of the Revolution is to be found in the Letters on the Regicide Peace (1796): The chain of subordination ... was broken in its most important links. It was no
156 David Musselwhite longer the great and the populace. Other interests were formed, other dependencies, other connections, other communications. The middle classes had swelled far beyond their former proportion. Like whatever is the most effectively rich and great in society, these classes became the seat of all the active politics, and the preponderating weight to decide upon them. There were all the energies by which fortune is acquired; there the consequences of their success. There were all the talents which assert their pretensions, and are impatient of the place which settled society prescribes to them. These descriptions had got between the great and the populace; and the influence on the lower classes was with them. The spirit of ambition had taken possession of this class as violently as ever it had done any other. They felt the importance of this situation. The correspondence of the moneyed and the mercantile world, the literary intercourse of academies, but above all the press, of which they had in a manner entire possession, made a kind of electric communication everywhere. (Burke n.d.: 380) Burke has clearly broken with the kind of binary pattern offered in the early PhilosophicalEnquiry. What Burke fears is an amalgam of forces for which he coins the term 'middle classes', an amalgam that fractures the binarism of 'the great and the populace', and substitutes for it a whole ensemble of heterogeneous interests and groupings - for Burke, quite monstrous combinations, but powerful withal, as the passage clearly reveals. This realization that it is the 'middle classes' rather than some scythe-swinging mob that are the object of his attack can come as a great surprise. And with this surprise comes a dawning sense of the vertiginousness of time, as Burke lambasts what he conceives to be those interests that spearhead the Revolution. By the vast debt of France a great monied interest had insensibly grown up, and with it a great power ... a monied interest originating from the authority of the crown ... an extensive, discontented money interest. (1968a: 209, 214, 264) For Burke the Revolution was primarily a case of warfare between the ancient landed interest, and the new monied interest, [and] the greatest because the most applicable strength was in the hands of the latter. The monied interest is in its nature more ready for any adventure; and its possessors more disposed to new enterprizes of any kind. (211) The Revolution was principally the result of the frustration of this new monied interest (what Burke sometimes terms 'ability') faced by the entrenched power of the land-owning aristocracy (the short-hand term for which in Burke is 'property'). The single most decisive act of the Revolution was the device whereby money achieved
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 157 its purchase on property, that is on land: the confiscation of Church lands. With this single act the Revolution became irreversible, for with the issue of a paper currency backed only by the security of the confiscated estates of the Church everyone who held such currency had a 'guilty interest' (225) in the new order. Burke's account of the process by means of which Church property was first confiscated and then fed into the market is by far the most sophisticated piece of economic analysis in the whole of the Reflections (223-4). The land could not be released all at once as this would lower its price by glutting the market. The first alternative was to issue stock to the major financial institutions but this also failed - largely because many provincial municipalities did not want to see so much money centred in the large stockholders in Paris. Moreover, there was a need for some kind of currency as gold and silver were in short supply. And so a new national debt was incurred, backed by the Church lands. Finally, the lands were sold off piecemeal but because of the nonavailability of ready money, purchasers could enter the market with a small deposit, the balance to be paid over longer periods of time, of ten years and more. What followed was only to be expected - an explosion of short-term speculation, assetstripping, and massive inflation. This is what appalled Burke, the eruption onto the historical scene of a resentful and ambitious rentier class, parasitic and unproductive; not an entrepreneurial grand-bourgeoisie but a selfish, philistine, petit-bourgeoisie of small-time lawyers, assignat holders and brokers, and bankers ~ or, as he puts it, 'sophisters, oeconomists and calculators'. And with his indictment of this parasitic force that has effectively 'volatilized' property, Burke, in a sense, leaps towards us. For him this selling off of the Church estates and the consequent loss of what he terms a massive institutional 'power' was like the squandering of a natural resource such as 'the power of steam, or of electricity' (1968a: 268). The result was an economy of 'hot' money. It is difficult, indeed even irresponsible, to ignore the pertinence of Burke's indignation and outrage to today. Your legislators, in every thing new, are the very first who have founded a commonwealth upon gaming, and infused this spirit into it as its vital breath. The great object in these politics is to metamorphose France, from a great kingdom into one great play-table; to turn its inhabitants into a nation of gamesters; to make speculation as extensive as life; to mix it with all its concerns; and to divert the whole of the hopes and fear of the people from their usual channels, into impulses, passions, and superstitions of those who live on chances.... The truly melancholy part of the policy of systematically making a nation of gamesters is this: that tho' all are forced to play, few can understand the game; and fewer still are in a condition to avail themselves of the knowledge. The many must be the dupes of the few who conduct the machine of these speculations. (309-11)
158 David Musselwhite Elsewhere Burke sketched one of the most lurid images of the Revolution: out of the tomb of the murdered monarchy in France has arisen a vast, tremendous, unformed spectre, in a far more terrifying guise than any which ever yet have overpowered the imagination and subdued the fortitude of man. Going straight forward to its end, unappalled by peril, unchecked by remorse, despising all common maxims and all con1ffion means, that hideous phantom overpowered those who could not believe it was possible she could at all exist, except on the principle which habit rather than Nature had persuaded them were necessary to their own particular welfare and to their own ordinary modes of action. But the constitution of and political being, as well as that of any physical being, ought to be known, before one can say what is fit for its conservation, or what is the proper means of its power. The poison of other states is the food of the new Republic. That bankruptcy, the very apprehension of which is one of the causes assigned for the fall of the monarchy, was the capital on which she opened her traffic with the world. (Burke n.d.: 237-8) If the apostrophe to the French Queen reminds us of the tabloid image of Princess Diana, this monstrous female personification of the Revolution must remind us of none other than Mrs Thatcher herself: the remorseless determination, the pitilessness ('Moderation will be stigmatized as the virtue of cowards'; (Burke 1968a: 374)), the unnaturalness. That sentence 'The poison of other states is the food of the new Republic' - which for Burke was metaphorical, has become astonishingly literal in the context of a country offering itself as an unregulated dump for toxic waste, while his perception that bankruptcy has become the very principle of international finance is all too accurate an account of the current hysterical ebb and flow of hot capital through the City driven by a monstrous balance of payments deficit. Burke's nightmare is upon us. The real Burke problem is not so much to explain how he saw her coming, but to account for why there was a 200-year hiatus between the prophecy and the eventwhich makes his anticipation of Napoleon seem a very <modest achievement indeed. This hiatus, I would claim, is itself Burke's most remarkable achievement. Of course there were political, economic, geographical, and many other factors that made possible Britain's great epoch of, first, industrial and, then, financial world domination - though this domination was never as solid as it often seemed, nor as long-lived. But without Burke's wonderfully blusterous rhetoric where could there have been found the encompassing world vision that welded together so many disparate parties and elements? Burke's reputation has oscillated rather than wavered - this piece itself could hardly have been written five or six years ago - but we may at last be approaching a time when some kind of definitive assessment might be possible - largely because the hiatus, the breathing space, that Burke gave us between the advent and the nemesis of capitalism (at least as far as England is concerned) has finally been exhausted.
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 159 There is no space here to summarize Burke's achievement in the required detail; what follows is no more than a schematic description under the three headings of ideology, narrative, and hegemony. The Reflections was spoken of earlier as providing a 'surface of emergence' for our modern notions of aristocracy, Crown, Church, etc. What reinforces this notion of a surface of emergence is that Burke does in fact produce indispensable terms for the understanding of the bourgeois order - terms such as 'middle classes' and 'party', for example, in the modern sense. Modern-day theorists often speak disdainfully of Burke's 'traditionalism' and 'empiricism', making him largely responsible for an allegedly 'English' 'mystagogy' towards institutions and 'philistinism' towards ideas. These allegations are only possible within the narrowest conception of what a theoretical operation might be. Burke is in fact a major political theorist to the extent that he produces concepts that have a performative rather than a logical consistency, concepts which produce the behavioural reality. Even more important, though, is the fact that Burke also makes possible the creation of concepts that he himself never uses. The two most important are 'tradition' and 'ideology'. The Reflections cries out again and again for the notion of 'ideology' which, alas for Burke, did not come into the language until six years after the Reflections were completed. Instead, we find Burke throughout the text resorting to all sorts of alternatives: cement, prejudice, sentiment, superstition, manners. Burke was in no doubt that the old order was over and done with and that the old institutions no longer offered secure anchorages of power. Something more was required - a set of beliefs, a mode of consensus, an instilled sense of collective identity - something like the 'Englishness' mentioned earlier. He writes - and again the contenlporary relevance cannot but move us: Where trade and manufactures are wanting to a people, and the spirit of nobility and religion remains, sentiment supplies, and not always ill supplies their place; but if commerce and the arts should be lost in an experiment to try how well a state may stand without these old fundamental principles, what sort of thing must be a nation of gross, stupid, ferocious, and at the same time, poor sordid barbarians, destitute of religion, honour, or manly pride, possessing nothing at present, and hoping for nothing hereafter? (1968a: 174) Burke knew, moreover, just how precarious, how insubstantial, how unbacked, was this massive bluff of 'sentiment' and the energy required to maintain its 'ever-origination' (to borrow and modify one of Coleridge's brilliant insights into the nature of the processes of legitimation). 'Sentiment', 'superstition', 'prejudice' never have specific roots (or references, recalling here Burke's theory of language) and are ever in a state of perpetual supplementarity: 'These public affections, combined with manners, are required sometimes as supplements, sometimes as correctives, always as aids to law' (172). We can recall here that odd phrase 'the rust of superstition': Burke awaits his Derrida. There is always something corrosive and double-edged
160 David Musselwhite about Burke's prose even while it is being adamant and brilliant. Typically, Burke describes this effect well in characterizing the sophistries of the jacobins addressed to the fallen king (much of Burke's insight into the jacobin mind hinges on the principle that ''it takes one to know one'): The anodyne draught of oblivion, thus drugged, is well calculated to preserve a galling wakefulness, and to feed the living"ulcer of a corroding memory. Thus to administer the opiate potion of amnesty, powdered with all the ingredients of scorn and contempt, is to hold to his lips, instead of the 'balm of hurt minds', the cup of human misery to the brim, and to force him to drink it to the dregs. (163) There is, in fact, little comfort to be found for the ancien regime in the Reflections if it is read with anything like proper attention. This is why Perry Anderson's claim that Burke's 'Traditionalism - veneration for the monarchy, the Church, the Peerage, the City, etc. was the natural ideological idiom of the landed class' is quite \",rong (Anderson 1966: 31). We have seen how this idiom is being constructed to offer a characteristically bourgeois symbology - 'the spirit of a gentleman, and the spirit of religion' (Burke 1968a: 173) - while at the same time slapping that same bourgeoisie's face with it. What makes the Reflections compelling reading is the way Burke works his volatile symbology into a coherent narrative. It has not been remarked, so far as I know, just how much like, say, a Scott novel the Reflections are: the vituperative close focus on the Revolutionary Society, the stirring account of the events in France leading up to the climactic apostrophe to the French Queen; and then the ruthless dissection of the contradictions and graft inherent in the new order which is to culminate in the eruption onto the historical scene of Napoleon. The Reflections present us with the archetypal bourgeois narrative. In this sense Burke offers what Lyotard has characterized as one of the two 'great narratives' of the bourgeois order - the narrative of 'mind' or of 'spirit', as opposed to the narrative of emancipation and freedom. (It is perhaps worth noting that the great protagonist of the narrative of emancipation was Burke's most powerful adversary, Paine. It is typical that while Burke looks forward, as I have suggested, to centres of higher education, Paine concentrates on the development of universal secondary education for all.) I said earlier that Burke brings words into existence - or, more precisely, redeploys available words in a new discourse. No word is more powerfully transformed by Burke than the word 'mind' when he speaks of the mind of a country (137). It is this conjuring up of a specific 'mind' or 'cultural ethos' or 'national identity' which was, perhaps, the most significant achievement of this specific period of English history, and Burke's contribution to it was massive. As Corrigan and Sayer put it, in their book on English state formation: The dignified, 'irrational', 'pomp and circumstance' features - such a sore trial to the systematizing mind, and so constantly bemoaned as 'feudal relics' - enabled
Reflections on Burke's Reflections, 1790-1990 161 the sponsored unification of the ruling classes, old and new, as a historic bloc, establishing a particular form of civilization, politics, culture, nationality Englishness, in short. (Corrigan and Sayer 1985: 105) Later in the same book they point to the moment when this particular narrative began to fall apart: in between times, from the 1760s until the 19605 (being crude again in order to be clear) political economy provided a moral rhetoric, a theatrical repertoire, a secular equivalent for religion that linked the facts of commerce to the promise of liberty. Progress, it was frequently said, would deliver the goods. Now fiscal policing and a language of necessity remain supreme. (107) For Lyotard, too, the time of the 'great narratives' is past, both that of mind and that of freedom, as we move into a 'post-modern condition' of instabilities, catastrophe, paralogism, and panic: a fractal world of impending implosion (cf. Lyotard 1984). But is this not precisely the world Burke himself addressed in 1790? Who knew more intimately instabilities, catastrophe, panic? Much as we may lament their demise, there is no point indulging a nostalgia either for the ideology of liberalism or for the great narratives -. both are traceable to Burke, as we have seen. What we need to rediscover is a Burke working at a more basic, more archaeological level, a Burke elaborating and demonstrating a discursive practice (a rhetoric - it must no longer be held against him as some kind of slight) that in many ways anticipates the most 'modern' and 'sophisticated' explorations of hegemonic strategies. Again I must be brief. In their Hegemony and Socialist Strategy (1985) Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe's version of the end of the 'great narratives' argues the need to abandon what they term the 'jacobin/Marxist imaginary' based as it is on a certain classic model of revolution entailing a struggle between fixed and pre-given classes and resulting in the triumph of a new class and a new social order. Implicit in this older model is a certain economic determinism and historicist teleology. For Laclau and Mouffe this model is far too rigid, for the relations of difference and equivalence do not correlate in any literal or straightforward way between groups and interests, advanced and reactionary sectors - there is no way of 'reading off one from the other. There is no way in other words of knowing whether a popular movement will be progressive or reactionary, whether a minority interest will be a spur or an obstacle to social change for the better or worse. To cite as an example perhaps the most important case today: there is no pre-given guarantee that the Green movement will move in a 'left' rather than a 'right' direction - and this argument can apply to all social groupings. This also means - and it is one of the problems facing the left in the 1990s - that not all that Thatcherism has to say is always necessarily wrong. The force of her critique of the corporatist state/union alliance bears that
162 David Musselwhite out. What is required in such a condition of crisis is an endless process of discursive scrutinizations, of disaggregations, unfixings, appropriations, and disappropriations of discursive elements which can never cohere in any specific social unity here Laclau and Mouffe come dangerously close to the famous Thatcherite axiom 'There's no such thing as society' - but it is precisely the need endlessly to rethink and re-imagine this absent totality that makes the impossibility of society possible. There is no security here but only the endless watchfulness of a 'war of position'. 'Society' exists only to the extent that it continually re-originates itself, constituting and reconstituting the frontier effects of its Otherness, its constitutive antagonisms, 'the first of political problems' (Laclau and Mouffe 1985: 134). All this Burke fully recognized and practised. We have seen how he never allowed himself to be fooled into any simple binary model of the Revolution. We have seen how he never speaks from or for any previously established class positions. We have seen him constantly on the move in a manic 'war of position'. We have seen his articulations and disarticulations of discursive elements. We have seen his constant creation and recreation of 'frontier effects' - most powerfully the constitution of 'France' as the 'Other' to a new 'Englishness' - but also the way in which he elbows a space between 'aristocracy' and 'bourgeoisie', 'Crown' and 'people', 'Church' and 'theorists'. Above all we have seen how he creates that impossible heterotopia of 'society' itself, a Library of Babel that is inconceivable but infinite. NOTE Further reading includes Boulton 1963; Freeman 1980; Hall 1988; Reid 1985.
10
Human rights and the corruption of governments, 1789-·1989 MICHAEL FREEMAN
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION The persistence of the notion of basic human rights is an excellent example of the enduring legacy of the Enlightenment. Although it sounds clear and simple, Michael Freeman shows how complex the idea of rights is. Three kinds of complexity are alluded to in his paper; philosophical, political, and historical. It is evident that all discussions of rights are rooted in the particular historical context of those discussions. As a result, the social experiences which lie behind demands for and negotiations over rights will differ, as will the precise nature of the rights themselves. At a political level too, Freeman reveals, rights are never self-evident. Exactly who is included in the group that has rights, and by virtue of what, and the mechanisms whereby rights are acquired and defended are all contested matters. The philosophical discourse around 'rights' as a concept is equally elaborate; innumerable arguments for and against its validity have been put forward, arguments that go in and out of fashion, and that are more or less plausible in any particular context. Freeman finds the historical and political aspects of rights more important than the philosophical ones. He forcefully argues that rights are about defending against tyrannical uses of power, that they have a real life in the political experience of people. Thus he links debates about rights since the Second World War, generated by the rise of Fascism, with those that took place during the Enlightenment, that is during a period of arbitrary, absolutist government. By moving between these two episodes, Freeman can both show how rights must be understood in context and defend the idea that general notions about rights are not only perfectly valid but also essential from a human point of view. In the Enlightenment rights were part of a larger political and social discourse that included discussions about the relationship between individuals and society, about citizenship, about duties, obligations, and the virtuous life. Of course, the Enlightenment hardly invented these debates, which have their origins both in
164 Michael Freeman Christian traditions and in classical thought. But the Enlightenment did have new ways of thinking about them. The novelty derived from the kind of society that eighteenth-century Europe then was. It was an increasingly urban society, in which print culture played a significant role. It was a commercially successful society, that was highly conscious about economic relationships between persons, classes, and nations. It was a society beconling increasingly geographically sophisticated: it knew where more places were, and something about the physical and social characteristics of distant lands. All of this helps to explain how Defoe came to write Robinson Crusoe and how the book came to embody an Enlightenment myth about 'individualism' (see Watt 1963). Furthermore, the importance of these facets of eighteenth-century society for the development of the modern world helps to account for the long-lived inspirational powers of Robinson Crusoe, that made possible the story Freeman tells about its being evoked in United Nations debates. This illustrates how integral stories and myths are to thinking through concrete political problems. A persistent theme in Freeman's paper is the relationship between people's lives and abstract discourse. There is a certain need for the latter, he suggests, not least because we require a reference point in talking about rights that transcends local conditions. At the same time abstract discourses should never become divorced from rights as they are experienced. When that happens, it becomes possible to enter into debate as if nothing hung on it. What hangs on rights, in the eighteenth century as now, can be measured with the very bodies of those who suffer, like the Peruvian prisoner Freeman mentions. This is why the fall of the Bastille, the place where people could be arbitrarily confined, became such a potent symbol of the destruction of the ancien regime in France. Participants in the Revolution both felt the sting of injustices and worked to conceptualize the nature of basic justice. Their Rights ofMan and of the Citizen acted as both a manifesto and a precaution. It proclaimed their basic ideas about rights, and by formulating these in general terms, it sought to prevent abuse. It was a kind of yardstick against which different practices could be measured. While it was designed to be applied to particular cases, its abstract qualities enabled it to transcend individual instances. For Freeman, the United Nations declaration has, necessarily, these same qualities. By reading these two 'declarations against each other we arrive at a much better understanding of the intentions behind each one. The legacy of the Enlightenment is quite palpable here. Despite the dramatic differences in the historical circumstances under which these two declarations were written, they share an essential feature. Both declarations speak generally about the rights of individuals in a social context, and do so in such a way that any particular citizen's life could potentially be materially improved as a result.
10
ROBINSON CRUSOE Air THE UN The discourse of natural rights and of the rights of man was one of the distinctive elements of the eighteenth-century Enlightenment, culminating in the various declarations of rights promulgated during the French Revolution. After, and in no small measure as a result of the Revolution, this discourse was replaced by various alternatives, such as utilitarianism, historicism (including Marxism), positivism, nihilism, and so on. Paradoxically, it took another great trauma of European history, the advent and defeat of Fascism, to bring back the discourse of rights. In 1948 the United Nations adopted its Universal Declaration of Human Rights. In recent years the rhetoric of human rights has been used both by governments to score diplomatic points against their opponents and by political dissidents and national and international pressure groups to protest against the cruel and unjust practices of oppressive regimes. This revival of political practice with regard to human rights has not exactly reflected, nor been reflected in, the domain of political theory. It is true that a thriving academic human rights industry has developed, and that some philosophers have strenuously endeavoured to persuade us to take rights seriously (Dworkin 1977). However, this endeavour has be~n equally strenuously resisted and debated, with the result that, while the status of human rights as a standard to which appeal may be made is at present relatively secure in international politics, its status in philosophy is much more uncertain (Gauchet 1980; Paul et al., 1984; O'Neill 1986; Jones 1989). There is consequently a disjunction between practice and theory. At the level of political practice there appears to be a certain obviousness about the evil of human rights violations such as, for example, political murders by governments, while at the level of theory the status of human rights is extremely problematic. Can theory show practice to be misguided? Can practice show theory to be inadequate? Does the disjunction itself require some kind of rectification, and, if so, what kind?
166 Michael Freeman On one question there is consensus: the contemporary human rights doctrine is a direct descendant of that favoured by thinkers of the Enlightenment. Those who took the lead in drafting the UN Declaration were well aware of their eighteenthcentury predecessors (Best 1988a). This can be illustrated by a charming episode which took place when the Third Committee of the United Nations was discussing, in June 1948, the draft declaration of the Commission of Human Rights. After settling twenty-eight articles defining the rights which individuals should have against the state, the Committee came to article 29. The Commission had proposed that article 29 should declare that everyone has 'duties to the community which enables him freely to develop his personality'. The Australian delegate suggested an amendment which would substitute for the words after 'community' the phrase 'in which alone the free and full development of his personality is possible'. The Belgian delegate objected to the word 'alone' on the ground that it implied falsely that the individual could develop his personality only within the framework of society. It was, he said, necessary only to recall Robinson Crusoe to find proof of the falsity of this implication. The delegate of the USSR, however, supported the Australian amendment, and especially the word 'alone', because he held that it rightly emphasized the fact that the individual could not fully develop his personality outside society. The Belgian delegate had quite misread Robinson Crusoe, for the book showed that man could not live and develop his personality without the aid of society. Crusoe had, in fact, had at his disposal the products of human industry and culture, namely, the tools and books he had found on the wreck of his ship (Morsink 1984: 316-20). The Soviet reading of Defoe won the day: the word 'alone' appears in article 29 of the Universal Declaration of I-Iuman Rights (Brownlie 1981: 26). Thus did a fictional character of the early eighteenth-century Enlightenment make his modest contribution to the philosophy, sociology, and international law of the second half of the twentieth century. THE REAL WORLD OF HUMAN RIGHTS While many people now believe that human rights constitute a fundamental and vitally important moral possession, claim, or entitlement of every human individual, the human rights doctrine has been attacked on the following grounds, among others. 1. Human rights do not exist: they are fictions (MacIntyre 1981). Since the French still speak of 'the Rights of Man' (les droits de l'homme), there is a version of this objection which is more readily made in French: 'Man' is a fiction; 'natural rights' are fictions; the (natural) rights of Man are therefore doubly fictional. 2. The idea of human rights is too abstract: human rights claims depend upon
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
}{uman rights and the co"uption of governments, 1789-1989 167
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
an account of human beings and/or prescribe their supposed entitlements without regard for the real, complex social relations, experiences, and problems of human life. The abstractness of human rights is a typical objection of Utilitarians, who insist that the goodness of rights must be judged, not 'in the abstract' (Le. not as pure ideas) but by reference to the consequences of recognizing them (Bentham 1962; Allison 1984). The human rights doctrine is too individualistic: it accords moral priority to the value of the individual over that of the social, whereas the latter is the foundation of the former and should therefore have the priority (Gauchet 1980). Human rights theorists treat human beings as isolated atoms, as units disconnected from, or at best externally connected to each other; but no man is an island, entire of itself ..' . (Taylor 1979). The human rights doctrine endorses individual egoism: it constitutes a set of selfish demands subversive of human community (Marx 1978; Lefort 1981; Lukes 1985). Human rights are anarchic: they are derived from non-social sources and consequently have anti-social implications (Rousseau 1968; Burke 1968a; Bentham 1962). Human rights should be subject to the common good; to give priority to the rights of individuals over the interests of the majority or of society is morally perverse (Bentham 1962). The human rights doctrine and the human rights movement neglect human obligations: they thereby neglect what is fundamental to morality and to social life (O'Neill 1986). The human rights doctrine and human rights declarations are unfitted to protect the human interests they proclaim because they fail to specify who has what obligation to take what action to defend the rights declared and they fail to institutionalize and render effective the necessary obligations (O'Neill 1986). Human rights are supposedly universal and human rights claims presuppose universal moral truths. In fact, morality can exist only as part of the fabric of particular social forms of life. Rights, therefore, if they exist at all, are social and relative to particular cultures (Sandel 1984; Milne 1986).
This is not all that can be said against human rights (it does not, for example, deal with problems arising from conflicting human rights) but it does constitute a formidable and plausible list of objections. These objections themselves suffer, however, from a problem of abstraction. They stand logically at a considerable distance from the subjective experiences and empirical observations that form the basis of human rights political practice. There is a large gulf between street-level human rights problems and philosophical disputation about human rights which has to be bridged before we can assess whether the latter is adequate to the former. It is said
168 Michael Freeman that human rights are fictions and that they are abstract (objections 1 and 2). But human rights politics addresses real, concrete problems. We must understand what these problems are before we can theorize them adequately. This is not to say that there are primitive human rights 'facts' with which we can begin. Any identification of a human rights problem presupposes theoretical assumptions of some kind. But, in order to understand the practice-theory gap, we need to understand the practice and the problems to which it is addressed. I shall attempt to begin with a naive or common-sense description of the kind of experienced problem that gives rise to human rights discourse prior to systematic theorization. A true story may help us to start our journey down the road from practice to theory. Carlos Taype was working for the Peruvian Confederation of Peasants when he was arrested on 17 March 1984, taken to the barracks of the Civil Guard in the provincial capital, Huancayo, and charged with 'terrorism'. Huancayo is high and cold. Carlos Taype was given no food, water, or protection against the cold. He was kept blindfolded, systematically beaten, and forced to stand for long periods, spending one whole night handcuffed to a concrete pillar. After he was forced to sign a statement that he had not been ill-treated, he was transferred to a local prison. He was released on 26 January 1985. More than 500 letters had been sent from twentynine countries to President Belaunde protesting at his treatment and demanding his release (Amnesty International 1986). The agents of the Peruvian government violated several rights of Carlos Taype as these are proclaimed in the UN Declaration. In particular, they acted in violation of article 20, which declares that everyone has the right to freedom of association, and article 5, which states that no one shall be subjected to torture or to cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment. What are the theoretical implications of this episode? Were those who appealed to the principles of human rights in their protest against the actions of the Peruvian officials committing a theoretical error? If we should judge the protesters to have been right to act as they did, what follows for the philosophical theory of human rights and for the objections of its critics? Whatever the philosophical difficulties of constructing and defending an adequate conception of 'truth', I shall pre-philosophically assume that there is an important sense in which the story of Carlos Taype is truth rather than fiction. It is certainly not fictional in the same sense that 'the social contract' may be said to be a fictional device of political theory. Whether or not the 'human rights' allegedly violated were fictitious, the claim that human rights were violated refers us to real and morally problematic events. In this important sense human rights problems are real. Carlos Taype himself wrote from prison that he had measured with his very body the value of the campaign for human rights. Whatever may be wrong with the idea of human rights, it does not (to borrow an image from Karl Marx) exist in the clouds but in the streets, or, rather, in the prisons and in the torture chambers of the world. In this sense human rights problems are far from being abstract.
Human rights and the corruption ofgovernments, 1789-1989 169 The rights of Carlos Taype that were violated were not 'individualistic' in the sense that they concerned only an isolated human individual, for he was persecuted for being a class activist. The collective rights of groups or classes consist of individual rights in that the interests of those groups or classes can be attacked through the violation of the human rights (in the UN sense) of their individual members. Thus, those who favour collectivistic and solidaristic forms of political action should support some individual human rights. A similar observation may be made about the objection that the human rights doctrine is 'atomistic'. When Carlos Taype wrote to thank those who had campaigned for his release, he used the word 'we' more often than the word'!'; the cause was 'our' cause, not 'my' cause. It is an error to conceive of individual human rights as precluding strong solidaristic sentiments and obligations. This last point almost covers the next: the defence of human rights is not necessarily the defence of egoism. Neither the campaigners nor the person on whose behalf they were campaigning were motivated by egoism. The article 20 right to freedom of association is frequently invoked when altruistic action is punished by governments. The argument that certain claims to 'inalienable' rights are 'anarchic' and incompatible with a settled and civilized social order - much favoured by Edmund Burke and Jeremy Bentham - may have some force against seventeenth- and eighteenthcentury formulations of 'natural' rights which invoke a pre-governmental 'state of nature', but do not apply to the UN conception. The Preamble to the UN Declaration affirms that human rights should be protected by the rule of law, thereby presupposing, not negating, a settled social order. The 'anarchy' argument seems to have no merit against the supporters of Carlos Taype. What if the protection of human rights has harmful social consequences? Is it possible that the claims of human rights may be incompatible with the good of social utility? In so far as the protection of human rights is in the interest of society, can the doctrine of human rights be more coherently and plausibly formulated by the theory of utilitarianism? It is not possible to adjudicate here the long-standing dispute between deontological moral theories, which emphasize the inviolability of human rights with little or no regard to the social cost of such protection, and utilitarian theories,\vhich would subject all moral claims to a cost-benefit assessment. Historically, the UN Declaration was a manifesto against Nazi atrocities and an expression of the will of the UN powers that such things should not happen again. They chose the eighteenth-century discourse of rights to express that political will. It is possible, of course, that Nazism would not get a good score on the felicific calculus and that the UN could have based its aspirations on the principle of utility. However, critics of utilitarianism have pointed out its unsuitability for such a purpose. The principle of utility requires us to calculate the costs and benefits of an action, practice, policy, or institution for all those who experience costs and/or benefits from the action, practice, policy, or institution. It seems morally implausible (to put it no more
170 Michael Freeman strongly) to weigh the pleasures of the mass murderers in the Nazi extermination centres against the sufferings of their victims, and to reach a negative moral judgement on Nazi genocide by concluding that the latter outscore the former. (The fact that such scoring is impossible is another problem for utilitarians.) The article 3 declaration that everyone has the right to life, liberty, and security of person, and article 5's prohibition of torture and cruel, inhuman, or degrading treatment seem, at least prima facie, to get a firmer grip on what was morally objectionable about Nazism, Le. its violation of the basic human rights of its victims. Paradoxically, the discourse of human rights seems to be more useful than that of social utility when confronting problems such as those of Carlos Taype. Is the doctrine of human rights vulnerable to the objection that it neglects human obligations and that this is a morally serious defect? It is true, as noted above, that the UN Declaration appears to devote twenty-eight articles to rights and only one to duties. But the text is none the less a declaration, not only of the rights of individuals, but equally of the obligations of governments. 'Member States have pledged themselves to achieve ... the promotion of universal respect for and observance of human rights and fundamental freedoms.' The protester outside the torture cell expresses solidarity with the victim by appealing to his or her rights but he also appeals to the obligations of the state authorities and those of their agents. This last point addresses the objection that the emphasis on rights can neglect to indicate who is obliged to do what. The human rights of Carlos Taype, when violated, activated two sets of obligations. Those who campaigned on his behalf felt some obligation to act to defend his rights. The morally and legally appropriate way to do this was to remind the Peruvian government of its obligations under international law to respect the human rights of all human beings under its power. The two sets of obligations are clearly of different types. The first are imperfect obligations. No individual can act to protect all the threatened or violated human rights of every other individual in the world. But a government is perfectly obliged to respect the human rights of those under its power (except, perhaps, when the consequences of so doing would probably be disastrous). The last of the listed objections to the idea of human rights refers to its claim to universal validity, which is opposed by ethical relativism. This also raises complex issues which cannot be dealt with adequately in this brief space. None the less, two points are worth making. First, claims that a certain practice is justified because it forms part of a particular culture often obscure the fact that it is part of the oppression of one part of a society by another. Torture may be quite common in a particular polity, but it may be misleading to say that it is part of the culture of that society, if this implies that it is generally supported. Second, although cultural diversity does pose problems for the universalism of the human rights doctrine, it does not follow from this, as Rousseau insisted, that we are logically obliged simply to establish right by fact (Rousseau 1968:51). That anti-Semitism was part of the European way of life for many centuries does not render it morally unproblematic. The UN Declaration of 1948, I have suggested, was a political-legal manifesto
Human rights and the corruption of governments, 1789-1989 171 prompted by the crimes of Nazism and intended to minimize the repetition of such crimes. It was cast in the most appropriate available philosophical-legal rhetoric, which reached back, as all commentators agree, to several eighteenth-century declarations of rights, above all to the declarations of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen proclaimed by the French Revolution. The willingness of governments of diverse ideological colours and levels of economic development to subscribe to the Declaration (admittedly, with varying degrees of sincerity and enthusiasm) casts doubt on the claim that is often made that the rights it contains are only relevant to economically advanced, liberal-democratic societies (Milne 1986: 2-3). The thesis that the 'imposition' of human rights on non-Western societies is an act of Western neo-imperialism is shared by some Western intellectuals and non-Western tyrants but not by all non-Western people, as the events of May-June 1989 in China testify. What has caused much philosophical debate in recent times is the fact that the philosophy of natural rights upon which the UN drew had been strongly criticized from the late eighteenth to the middle of the twentieth century and was much out of fashion among philosophers when the Universal Declaration was adopted. What has kept the debate going is the fact that the philosophies that have replaced that of natural rights - for example, utilitarianism, Marxism, positivism, relativism, nihilism, post-structuralism -seem ill at ease (to putit mildly) in the face ofthe real moral world of Auschwitz. The current stand-off in moral philosophy arises from the facts that theorists of human rights have not convinced their opponents that they have overcome all the problems that beset the eighteenth-century theory of natural rights, while the various alternatives proposed have not convinced those seeking solutions to the practical problems of human rights violations that they provide an adequate theoretical underpinning for this enterprise. One exit from this apparent impasse is to deny the problem. Those who believe that Nazism or the treatment of Carlos Taype were morally unproblematic, or easily justified, should stop reading at the end ofthis paragraph. To such people it remains only to say that such a position requires a supporting ethical (or meta-ethical) theory as much as its opposite. The rest of this paper is an exploration of what theory would best help those who supported Carlos Taype and who support others in similar plights. Its method is to return to the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries in order to examine how serious were the philosophical problems which the theory of natural rights bequeathed to those who drafted the UN Declaration and who have later tried to uphold its principles. THE RIGHTS OF MAN AND OF THE CITIZEN The Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen was adopted on 26 August 1789. It proclaims that it was made by the 'representatives of the French People constituted in National Assembly' (Waldron 1987: 26; Godechot 1964: 115). Thus, like the UN Declaration of 1948, it does not appeal to a fictitious state of nature, but, on the contrary, presupposes an historically specific institution. Like the UN Declaration, too, it was a political declaration, a compromise between parties of
172 Michael Freeman different ideological inclinations: the famous (or notorious) ringing phrases of the Declaration were adopted after vigorous debates, by votes, sometimes by small majorities (Thompson 1952: 22-36; Godechot 1968: 27-40; Doyle 1989: ch.5). This is how democratic politics typically works. It is not how philosophy is usually done. The first point to note about the text of the Declaration is its name. It is often known by its shortened title, The Declaration of the Rights of Man. Its authors did indeed begin by resolving to 'expound in a solemn declaration the natural, inalienable and sacred rights of man'. None the less, the concept of 'the citizen' is as important in the Declaration as that of the rights of man. Immediately after the passage just quoted, the Declaration states its aim to be constantly to remind all members of 'the social body' of their rights and duties. Thus, in its opening words, the 1789 Declaration combines ideas we associate with both Locke and Rousseau: 'Man' has 'natural, inalienable and sacred rights', but men are also citizens, members of social bodies, to which they owe duties. The charge that the French Declaration ignores 'the social nature of Man' or his social duties is unfounded. If, as a political manifesto, the Declaration combines the Lockean emphasis on individual rights with the Rousseauist commitment to the duties of citizens, critics may argue that this has been achieved at the cost of theoretical inconsistency: Lockean rights (it is said) are literally anti-social (they are rights individuals may claim against society) while the social contract of Rousseau requires each citizen to alienate all his natural rights to the community (Rousseau 1968: 60). But the Declaration was not an ill-judged attempt to reconcile the political theories of Locke and Rousseau, but rather a proclamation of the rights and duties of citizens to achieve a particular political objective, namely a liberal, constitutional, monarchical state. The critique of the Declaration may not burden it with political theories with which its framers were not concerned but should look to its practical ends and the appropriateness of the means chosen to those ends. The Declaration does make the Lockian assumption that all political institutions have an end and that this end is the preservation of the 'natural and imprescriptible' rights of man. Article 2 summarizes the rights of man as those to 'liberty, property, security, and resistance to oppression'. The purpose of the Declaration is to enable all citizens to compare the acts of the legislative and executive powers with the assumed end of all political institutions so that the claims of the citizens should thenceforth always tend to the support of the Constitution and the happiness of all. Following Locke, therefore, the Declaration treats natural rights as both ends and means. Article 2 explicitly declares the preservation of natural rights to be the end of every political association, but the respect for natural rights by government has a purpose, which is to strengthen the respect for the government by the citizens. The Declaration, therefore, far from being 'anarchic' in intention, seeks to present natural rights as necessary to political order and constitutional government as necessary to the protection of natural rights (Raynaud 1988: 139-49). Article 1 of the Declaration states that men are born and remain free and equal in
Human rights and the corruption ofgovernments, 1789-1989 173 rights. Social distinctions may be based only on common utility. The introduction of this utilitarian criterion clearly opens the way to (and was intended to legitimate) social inequality. It is worth contrasting with the 1789 formulation the corresponding passages from the UN Declaration (articles 1 and 2): All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights. Everyone is entitled to all the rights and freedoms set forth in t.his Declaration, without distinction of any kind, such as race, colour, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth or other status. The 'UN follows the French Revolution in combiniIJg equality of rights with permission for inequality of property and status, although its emphasis is more egalitarian and it specifically mentions equality of race and sex. The inclusion of the connection between 'rights' and 'dignity' is by no means redundant and is itself linked to the emphasis on equality of race, colour, sex, etc., as well as to the 'welfare' rights which the UN added to the eighteenth-century list. The UN conception of human dignity is precisely not 'atomistic', although dignity may inhere in an individual, but invokes an obligation individuals, groups, and states ow~ to each other. This interpretation is supported by the anti-colonial, anti-racist history of the UN and expresses not only a different historical situation from that of 1789 but a more developed conception of the point of human rights. The 1789 Declaration, having set forth the principle of rights in its first two articles, goes on, in article 3, to proclaim the sovereignty of the nation. Thus 'Rousseau' follows hard on the heels of 'Locke'. The supposed 'individualism' of the rights of man is immediately qualified by the'collectivist' affirmation that no individual may exercise any authority that is not expressly derived from the nation. The importance of article 3 lies not only in the familiar fact that it asserts the claim of popular democracy but also that it claims sovereignty for the nation, that is to say that it is a nationalistic at the same time as it is a populistic claim. The Declaration, therefore, far from being simply the apotheosis of the individual, is a manifesto of the nation-state. With respect to human rights article 3 is both logically and historically problematic. Logically, it has been argued that the na!ural rights of the first two articles are contradicted by the national sovereignty of article 3 (Domenach 1989: 21). However, read in relation to their historical context, the three articles can be understood to have a coherent set of goals: to protect individuals/citizens from oppressive government and to subject government to democratic control. There is none the less an evil seed in article 3, for if the nation is sovereign, anyone defined as outside the nation, whether on political or ethnic grounds, may be deemed not to be entitled to the rights of man. The end of that road is genocide; the fate of the Armenians of Anatolia in 1915 at the hands of a Young Turk government influenced by French political theory (Hovannisian 1986; Libaridian 1985; O'Brien 1988). In addition, the collectivism of the sovereign nation complements the individualism of rights in that, as in the theory of Rousseau, there is no room for collectivities between the individual and the nation. This, too, has dangerous
174 Michael Freeman
UJW.": .)\0; J: IIO~l.n: 1<'1"
J)
('II'U 1':"
~
Figures 21 (above) and 22 (opposite) The Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen,
which was made law in France on 26 August 1789, affirmed the sovereignty of the people as the basis of the new order. Figure 21 shows the original version of the Declaration as it appeared in the 1791 Constitution; Figure 22 shows the more radical version that appeared in the Jacobin Constitution of 1793. In 1795 the Declaration was shortened and modified to conform to the more moderate constitution of a bourgeois republic. Figure 21 was designed
Human rights and the corruption ofgovernments, 1789-1989 175
~i~~, .nxz:DrKZZ
M
M
.-
:"~M#UUCIM
M
J
by Alexandre-Evariste Fragonard, the son of Jean-Honore Fragonard, and includes allegorical representations of the three civic virtues - Liberty, Equality, and Fraternity - and of the Republic, who is flanked by a Gallic cock and a sphere and is shown receiving pledges of allegiance from Roman warriors. The anonymous engraving of the 1793 Declaration (Figure 22) employs a fasces topped by a Phrygian cap, a Jacobin emblem of unity appropriate to the more radical constitution of that year. (Adapted from Cuno 1988: 228-9.)
176 Michael Freeman implications. Consider this characteristic comment on the Jews of France by a liberal noble, made in 1789: The Jews as a nation must be denied everything. But as individuals they must receive everything. They must become citizens.... Some say that they do not wish to be French citizens. If that is so, they must be banished. There can be no nation within the nation. (quoted in Higonnet 1988: 226) A leading criticism of the theory of natural/human rights, from Burke's attack on the Revolution to the present, has been that absolute rights are (to use Bentham's phrase) not only 'nonsense upon stilts' but dangerous nonsense, because any apparent good (such as liberty), if carried to the extreme, may create intolerable social harm, and indeed the absolute use of one person's right may impair the rights of others. But, although the Declaration speaks of the rights of man being 'inalienable' and 'imprescriptible', it denies that they are absolute. Article 2 makes 'liberty' one of the 'natural and imprescriptible' rights of man, but article 4 defines 'liberty' as consisting in being able to do everything that does not harm others. Consequently, articles 4 and 5 make clear, the individual's exercise of his natural rights may (indeed should) be limited in order to ensure other individuals' enjoyment of the same rights. The law is entitled and obliged to forbid any actions harmful to society. No one, for example, may be persecuted for his opinions, provided that the manifestation of these does not disturb public order established by law. The free communication of thoughts and opinions is 'one of the most precious rights of man'; hence every citizen may speak, write, and publish freely, save that he must answer for any abuse ofsuch freedom in cases determined by the law. Libertarians may indeed find these concessions to utilitarianism excessive, as Robespierre did during the debates (Godechot 1968: 36). If any harm to society (where 'harm' is undefined) may be forbidden (and, presumably, punished), then the 'imprescriptible' right to liberty is indeed not at all what at first sight it seems to be. The men of 1789, the men of property, were (like Locke) also, and consequently, men of law and men of order. The rights of man were to be protected by the rule of law. The Declaration of 1789 was, pace Burke and Bentham, a declaration of duties of obedience as well as of rights. Without the obedience there could be no protection for the rights. The enemy against which the Declaration was directed was not order but despotism. The law that is to govern the rights of man has a rather Rousseauist character, although it is to take place in a society and in a manner which fail to meet Rousseau's conditions for the establishment of social freedom. The law, says article 6, is the expression of the general will. All citizens have the right to participate in shaping it, either in person or through their representatives. (The permissibility of legislation by representatives is quite contrary to the requirements of Rousseau's theory; on the revolutionary conceptions of citizenship and representation, see Sewell 1988: 105-23). The law must be the same for all. All citizens are equal before the law and all are equally eligible for public office in accordance with their talents and virtues. No one may be punished except through due process of law. Law may not be
Human rights and the corruption of governments, 1789-1989 177 arbitrary and may establish only those punishments that are 'strictly and obviously necessary'. Obedience to the due process of law is a strict obligation of all citizens. In order to guarantee the rights of man and the citizen, a police force is necessary. The Declaration, therefore, has no qualms about forcing people to be free. Finally, the Declaration proclaims that property is 'an inviolable and sacred right'. No individual may be deprived of it 'unless some public necessity, legally certified as such, clearly requires it; and subject always to a just and previously determined compensation.' Since more than 150 years of socialist theory and practice, including the Bolshevik Revolution, separate 1948 from 1789, it is worth comparing this provision with the UN Declaration's view of property rights. Article 17 states that everyone has the right to own property alone as well as in association with others. No one shall be arbitrarily deprived of his property. The UN Declaration also, famously/notoriously, includes a number of 'welfare' rights. Article 25, for example, accords to everyone 'the right to a standard of living adequate for the health and well-being of himself and of his family, including food, clothing, housing and medical care, and necessary social services, and the right to security in the event of unemployment, sickness, disability, widowhood, old age, or other lack of livelihood in circumstances beyond his control.' The right to property proclaimed by the 1789 Declaration follows its general approach to rights: sacred and inviolable, yet subject to public utility determined through the rule of law. The inclusion of welfare rights in the UN Declaration of 1948 is generally regarded as the most significant difference between its conception of human rights and that of the French Revolution. It is worth noting, however, that the Jacobin version of the Declaration, adopted on 23 June 1793, affirmed that society owed subsistance to its unfortunate citizens either by finding them work or by ensuring the means of existence to those unable to work, and that 'society should promote with all its power the progress of public reason and afford an education to all citizens' (Godechot 1964: 214). The Declaration of Rights of the French Revolution did not suffer from some of the defects that have been attributed to it by such important early critics as Burke, Bentham and Marx, and many of their successors (Waldron 1987). It did not presuppose a fictional social contract. It was not 'abstract' in that it required that rights be institutionalized in law and agencies of law enforcement~ It was not individualistic, atomistic, egoistic, or anarchic in that it strongly emphasized the rights and duties of citizenship. The Marxist criticism that the liberal conception of rights divides the private individual from the citizen, whatever its merit in other contexts, does not clearly strike home at the revolutionary Declaration. The exact wording of article 11 on freedom of speech is worth noting in this connection. 'The free communication of thoughts and opinions is one of the most precious rights of man; hence every citizen may speak, write and publish freely.' Contrary to the BurkeBentham view that the rights of man were pre-social and anti-social, it is clear that the framers of the Declaration conceived of the 'rights of man' as being rights of citizens. Although the Declaration does not say so, it assumes that the right to be a citizen is one of the fundamental rights of man (see Sewell 1988). This strong 'Rousseauist' element of the text makes it much less vulnerable to the criticism of
178 Michael Freeman atomistic individualism than is often thought. Indeed, although it was obviously no part of the intention of the framers of the Declaration to establish and justify a socialist society - and the right to private property is strongly defended - the Declaration may be seen as a basis for a form of liberal socialism in so far as it associates closely the rights of individuals with the duties of citizens: it is a combination of the traditions both of individual natural rights and of civic republicanism, which permeated the eighteenth century on both sides of the Atlantic and which live on in political theory today (Waldron 1988: 182-3, 184-5). The 'Rousseauist' features of the 1789 Declaration are somewhat weaker in the UN text of 1948, although the latter does include the right to a nationality (article 15), the right to take part in the government of one's country (article 21), the right freely to participate in the cultural life of the community (article 27), the aforementioned welfare rights (articles 23-26), and the (unspecified) duties to the community (article 29). Was the French Declaration of Rights, as Bentham claimed in his famous critique of 1795-6, 'nonsense upon stilts' (Bentham 1962)? Let us return to the UN Declaration and its point. Let us assume that what the Nuremberg Tribunal termed Nazi 'crimes against humanity' were morally wrong. The UN Declaration of Human Rights was, among other things, an attempt to set out systematically the principled basis for judging them to be morally wrong. Crimes against humanity are violations of human rights. The UN Declaration sets out the most important of these rights. In doing so, it draws on the natural rights discourse of the French Revolution. Bentham found this discourse nonsensical. We have moved from a moral truism (Nazism was evil) to nonsense. Either there is a concealed philosophical mine along this road or Bentham was wrong. Bentham argued that the doctrine of natural rights implied two propositions: 1. there are rights anterior to government: natural rights are distinguishable from/opposed to legal rights; 2. natural rights cannot be abrogated by government. (Bentham also believed that natural rights implied that' governments were established by social contracts, but I think this does not have to be imputed to the Declaration and therefore will not discuss Bentham's refutation of it.) How stands the truth of things, acording to Bentham? There are no natural rights anterior to the establishment of governments, no rights in contradistinction to legal rights. We know what it is for men to live without government: it is to live without rights, without security, without property, without liberty, without happiness. In proportion to the want of happiness resulting from the want of rights, a reason exists for wishing there were such things as rights. But reasons for wishing there were such things as rights, are not rights; ... want is not supply - hunger is not bread. (Bentham 1962: 501)
Human rights and the corruption of governments, 1789-1989 179 That which has no existence cannot be destroyed. That which cannot be destroyed cannot require anything to preserve it from destruction. So much for the nonsense. What says reason? That in proportion as it is right, i.e. advantageous to society, that a particular right be established and maintained, it is wrong that it should be abrogated, and that in proportion as it is advantageous to society that a right be abrogated, that right should be abrogated (Bentham 1962). Hunger is not bread. Want is not supply. Analogously, arbitrary detention is not release. The 1789 Declaration does not say (or -imply) that it is. It does not even say that there is a natural right not to be arbitrarily detained. It does not therefore say that there is a right not to be arbitrarily detained anterior to the establishment of governments. It does say that no one can be (ne peut etre) - perhaps it would have better said should be (ne doit etre) - arbitrarily detained. It also says, in article 2, that there is a natural and imprescriptible right of liberty. It does not say what a natural right is. Since this philosophical space is empty, Bentham puts a straw man in it and proceeds to savage it. (He says article 2 is meaningless, but, if it had a meaning, it would be the one he attacks.) In its place he champions the principle of utility. Embarrassed by the fact that the Declaration qualified natural rights by the principle of utility, he denies that the qualification can be taken seriously because it contradicts the assertion of 'imprescriptible right'. But if, as I have argued, the 'imprescriptible right' is to liberty under law for the common good, there is no contradiction, though the bounds of liberty are certainly indeterminate. However, Bentham's alternative formula that it is right that there be such rights as are advantageous to society is quite as indeterminate. And Bentham's idea that what is advantageous to society is right is at least as confusing as the idea of natural rights, since it conceals the question as to who is to get the advantage and at what cost to whom. Bentham called the language of natural rights 'terrorist language'. Ironically, utilitarianism has recently been questioned precisely because it fails to provide a secure philosophical defence against ideological justifications of (state) terrorism and the idea of human rights has been invoked because it has been thought to do the job better. I have emphasized the importance of distinguishing the political from the philosophical aspects of both the 1948 and 1789 declarations. From a pbilosophical point of view, the most problematic component of the~1789 Declaration is the natural rights axiom. Many of its most famous critics have, in attacking the natural rights doctrine of the French Revolution, had in mind not only the text of the Declaration but also the actions of the revolutionaries. Burke, for example, linked the proclamation of rights with the destruction of institutions, Bentham with 'terrorism' (as Burke also did), Marx with the promotion of bourgeois society. I have sought to show that the text itself is less vulnerable to these criticisms. None the less it does leave the validity of the natural rights philosophical underpinning of political practice rationally unsupported. The point of this approach can none the less be illuminated if we consider what is common to the political contexts of John Locke's Two Treatises of Government (1690) the most famous theoretical exposition of natural rights - and the 1789
180 Michael Freeman and the 1948 declarations. Each was addressed to the problem of absolute and oppressive government. If this is your problem, the discourse of rights ('keep your hands off') seems more apt than the discourse of utility ('I wonder whether your using torture against this person in this situation might or might not, all things considered, be for the good of society') (Allison 1984: 96-7). Locke and the revolutionaries of 1789 believed that they faced a clear and present danger of oppressive absolutism. This is why the right of resistance features prominently in their thinking. The Declaration of 1948 was framed by governments which had just defeated oppression and were arrlbivalent towards encouraging revolution. This is why the right of resistance is less emphasized in the UN Declaration (Morsink 1984: 322-5). Burke criticized the French revolutionaries not for seeking to protect rights (which he often did himself) but for believing that rights were best protected by declarations and constitutions (Le. words and bits of paper) while they were bent on destroying those established social institutions which, he held, were the true bulwarks of freedom. In this view of social institutions, Burke was a disciple of Montesquieu. Ironically, Montesquieu was the hero of at least some of those who drew up the 1789 Declaration and the doctrine of the separation of powers is accordingly enshrined in article 16. The separation of powers was intended to be precisely an institutional protection against absolutism. Yet there is also in the Declaration, as we have already seen, the Rousseauist suspicion of secondary associations intervening between the citizen-subject and the sovereign nation: article 3 specifies that no corporation may exercise any authority not expressly derived from the nation. The UN Declaration of 1948 is much more favourable towards independent organization: article 20 proclaims the right to freedom of association and article 23 the right to form and to join trade unions. Yet·the UN approach to association is rather individualistic and less collectivistic or 'structural': article 20 also announces the right not to belong to an association, and even the right to join a trade union (set out in article 23) is phrased in terms of the protection of individual interests rather than of class struggle. Article 23 expresses welfare liberalism rather than either Marxism or a Montesquieu-Burke concern with absolute and oppressive government. It is difficult to commit to memory systems of moral philosophy. Manifestos are designed to be memorable. This explains why the latter are simpler than the former. The 1789 Declaration states that 'ignorance, forgetfulness or contempt of the rights of man' are the sole causes of public misfortunes and the corruption of governments. The National Assembly had, therefore, resolved to expound the 'natural, inalienable and sacred rights of man' in a solemn declaration, so that it should be a constant reminder to all members of the social body of their rights and duties. On this point the UN Declaration of 1948 echoes its French revolutionary predecessor quite faithfully: Whereas disregard and contempt for human rights have resulted in barbarous acts which have outraged the conscience of mankind. . . . Whereas Member States have pledged themselves to achieve ... the promotion of universal
Human rights and the corruption ofgovernments, 1789-1989 181 respect for and observance of human rights and fundamental freedoms, Whereas a common understanding of these rights and freedoms is of the greatest importance for the full realization of this pledge, Now, Therefore, the General Assembly proclaims this universal declaration of human rights as a common standard of achievement for all peoples and all nations, to the end that every individual and every organ of society, keeping this Declaration constantly in mind, shall strive by teaching and education to promote respect for these rights and freedoms. In a well-known passage that argues against human rights, Alasdair MacIntyre has written: 'In the United Nations declaration on human rights of 1949 what has since become the normal UN practice of not giving good reasons for any assertions whatsoever is followed with great rigour' (MacIntyre 1981: 67). This epitomizes the philosophical errors against which I have been arguing. (It also gets the date wrong and puzzlingly suggests that the UN followed a practice which developed later.) It is, first, mistaken to assert that in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights the UN gives no good reasons. The UN gives as a reason for proclaiming a declaration of human rights the fact that disregard for human rights has resulted in barbarous acts - which is a good reason. Second, it misreads the UN Declaration as a piece of bad moral philosophy (the cited passage comes immediately after a critique of eighteenth- and twentieth-century philosophers), whereas (I have argued) it was not intended "as a piece of philosophy at all. Alasdair MacIntyre's book may be good philosophy, full of good reasons, but it would certainly be less useful for protesting against the treatment of Carlos Taype than the UN Declaration. All political manifestos are soft targets for philosophical snipers. But, pace Bentham, they may none the less be useful in roughly the utilitarian sense, Le. more beneficent than otherwise. The doctrine of human rights has often been attacked as an ideological expression of liberal individualism. I have attempted to show that this view is mistaken, that the Declaration of 1789 is strongly inclined towards a Rousseauist civic republicanism tinted (or tainted) with a somewhat authoritarian utilitarianism, and that the UN Declaration of 1948 is an expression of welfare liberalism, in which rights are also (rather obscurely) subjected, by article 29, to 'the just requirements of morality, public order and the general welfare in a democratic society'. Both defend, in declaratory rather than discursive form, a conception of individual liberty, democratic citizenship and human dignity against oppressive governments which would deny all three. Obviously, the content of any such declaration is open to challenge. But challenges will be more cogent for taking into account the historical purpose of the declaration and the purposes of those who continue to invoke it as relevant to contemporary political problems. My reading of the 1789 and 1948 human rights declarations as liberal political manifestos intended to mobilize peoples against absolutist oppression helps to illuminate another puzzling problem raised by philosophical objectors to the human rights doctrine. Why, they ask, ifthese rights inhere in all human beings, did human beings become aware of them only in the seventeenth and eighteenth
182 Michael Freeman centuries? Does not the historical specificity of this ideology refute its claim to universal validity? There is, in fact, some disagreement about the modernity of the concept of human rights. Alasdair MacIntyre claims that there is no expression in any ancient or medieval language correctly translated by our expression 'a right' until near the close of the Middle Ages. This claim can be checked only by those with a knowledge of all ancient and medieval languages, but Christian Daubie maintains that Cyrus the Great acknowledged the human rights of his subjects some 2000 years ago (MacIntyre 1981: 67; Daubie 1972: 293-304). Oppressive government is certainly not modern. Nor is resistance to oppression. The sovereign nation-state is modern (Giddens 1985). So, perhaps, is the individual citizen, although the idea of the citizen and the idea of the individual have deep roots (to speak only of the Western tradition) in Graeco-Roman and JudaeoChristian thought. Oppressive government is therefore a perennial problem, although its forms vary throughout history as does the discourse of resistance. Human rights orators may make metaphysical claims that cannot be rationally sustained. But human rights discourse should be understood as making sense and having some cogency for its purpose in its historical context. Thus there may be a certain relativity in the idea of human rights, which cuts across the grain of its rhetoric, in so far as it is especially apt to the era of the modern nation-state. Other times, other discourses, perhaps. But to say this is not to say that the appeal to human rights has the same moral force, no more, no less, as any other moral or ideological doctrine. It has arisen in the era of highly concentrated political power. This power poses serious moral problems. Theories and declarations of human rights are attempts to confront these problems and articulate a complex conception of a common life worth living in an increasingly integrated world on the presumption that all human being have, at least prima facie the right to such a life. Alasdair MacIntyre, in the passage already cited, says that the best reason for asserting that there are no human rights is of precisely the same type as the best reason for asserting that there are no witches and the best reason for asserting that there are no unicorns: every attempt to give good reasons for believing that there are such rights has failed (MacIntyre 1981: 67). But Hie reasons that have been given for believing that there are unicorns are quite different from the reasons that have been given for believing that there are witches, and both are quite different from the reasons for believing that there are human rights. MacIntyre, who is sometimes very sensitive to the historical specificity of moral arguments, is remarkably unhistorical about unicorns, witches, and human rights. There is no common ontological problem of the failure of three putative entities to exist. There is a shorthand term which can be unpacked to give an account of human flourishing and of human evil which can thwart it. 'Unicorns' do not (so far as I know) raise moral problems; 'witches' do. 'Human rights' pose political challenges. They raise metaphilosophical questions about what philosophy is for. They ask you whose side you are on (and do not allow you to be neutral in comfort). This question is not always
Human rights and the corruption of governments, 1789-1989 183 easy to answer. Human rights discourse can be simplistic, too self-confident, and question-begging. The concept of 'human rights' is obviously philosophically contestable. But unlike unicorn discourse, it does not refer to nothingness. It refers to real human experiences. It implies, at least in outline, particular political institutions. Meanwhile the problem of the abuse of political power - which was central to the rights theory of John Locke has become more, not less serious in our own era. Human rights declarations are not self-implementing: they feed no one who is starving, they liberate no one who is imprisoned unjustly. But they do provide a framework for thinking and acting appropriately in the face of these sorts of evil. Because they are political documents, they are philosophically flawed. But philosophy, too, feeds no one and liberates no one from prison. And philosophy presupposes certain rights (e.g. the right to do philosophy). The critics of rights could not criticize rights without exercising certain rights. Some conception of rights, therefore, seems to be a precondition both of debating about rights and of thinking about and taking action against evil and oppression. All particular declarations of rights will be contestable. But taking rights seriously does still seem to be an inescapable moral requirement of our time. This is why the French Declaration of 1789, encapsulating many of the most important political themes of the Enlightenment, has survived the formidable attacks of its critics, and why it is good that it has done so. NOTE Five passages quoted in translation from the Declaration of the Rights of Man are given here in the original French. 'Les representants du peuple fran~ais, constitues en Assemblee nationale, considerant que l'ignorance, l'oubli ou Ie mepris des droits de l'homme sont les seules causes des malheurs publics et de la corruption des gouvernements, ont resolu d'exposer, dans une Declaration solennelle, les droits naturels, inalienables et sacres de l'homme afin que cette Declaration, constamment presente tous les membres du corps social, leur rappelle sans cesse leurs droits and leurs devoirs.' (p. 172) 'Le but de toute association politique est la conservation des droits naturels et imprescriptibles de l'homme. Ces droits sont la'liberte, la propriete, la surete et la resistance l'oppression.' (p. 172) . 'Les hommes naissent et demeurent libres et egaux en droits. Les distinctions sociales ne peuvent etre fondees que sur l'utilite commune.' (p. 173) 'Le principle de toute souverainete, reside essentiellement dans la Nation. Nul corps, nul individu ne peut exercer d'autorite qui n'en emane expressement.' (p. 173) 'La libre communication des pensees et des opinions est un des droits les plus precieux de l'homme: tout citoyen peut done parler, ecrire, imprimer librement, sauf repondre de l'abus de cette liberte dans les cas determines par la loL' '(po 176)
a
a
a
11 Enlightenment as automony: Kant' 5 vindication of reason ONORA O'NEIL
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION Descartes, 'forced to become his own guide', served as one of our starting points (see above p. 18). A century and a half later Immanuel Kant defined Enlightenment as 'man's emergence from self-incurred immaturity', with immaturity defined as 'the inability to use one's own understanding without the guidance of another' (Kant 1970: 54). Kant engages with Descartes on the most basic assumption of the Enlightenment: he challenges the claim that we know what the standards of reason are, so stand on firm ground when we use them to guide our inquiry and our actions. Kant calls his enterprise 'Critique of Reason'; he claims that we construct rather than discover the standards of reason. Any thinking that simply invokes arbitrary Kant says'alien' - standards, or the mythical authority of'clear and distinct ideas', simply abrogates reason. Scepticism about reason, the supposed basis of the Enlightenment, has to be taken seriously. On Kant's view the individualistic approach taken by Descartes does not permit a convincing response to scepticism about reason. Authoritative standards for assessing thought and action can only be conceived of as standards that are developed by 'an entire public'. However, reason is not simply disclosed or revealed to an entire public either. Kant's daring thought is that reason has both a natural and a cultural history, that it first emerges and is then constructed as we gradually move towards the still unachieved stage of Enlightenment. In constructing the principles that we view as having the authority of standards of reason, we can do no more than adopt the policy of refusing to act or think on principles that cannot be followed by others. 1~his, rather than wilful self-assertion, is what he views as autonomy in thought and in action, and this is why he characterizes the Enlightenment as based on autonomy, rather than on the illusions of self-certifying disclosures of the method of reason. What is most basic to reason is not the bedrock of method, but living by . strategies that can be followed by all.
Enlightenment as autonomy 185 Kant also rejects the Humean view that 'reason is and ought only to be the slave of the passions': far from viewing the practical use of reason as subordinate and merely instrumental, he thinks that the cognitive use of reason is itself grounded in practice. The status of reason is not just a philosopher's problem, but a problem for all of us. It is because we do not have preinscribed standards of reason, but on the contrary a freedom that could lead to anarchy in thought and in action, that we have to find and to follow sharable ways of disciplining thought and action. Appropriately Kant discusses some of his most radical and revisionary claims about reason and its supposed authority not in metaphysical treatises but in political essays. The two that are mainly discussed here by Onora O'Neill are the well-known What is Enlightenment? and the less-known What is Orientation in Thinking? Both are central to Kant's revisionary view of the authority of reason - and of its limits. Foucault has recently aptly characterized the first of these essays as marking the moment at which the Enlightenment 'came to self-awareness through the act of naming itself, situating itself in relation to its past and its future, and prescribing the operation \vhich it was itself required to effect within its own present' (Foucault 1986: 90). Despite the fundamental introspection of the Cartesian gesture, Descartes was deeply if problematically concerned with the accessibility of his method 'of rightly directing one's Reason', hence the unusual decisions to write in the vernacular and to use the autobiographical form. Those opening moves were distinctly egalitarian in tendency. Kant's position on reason may be less confident and more circumscribed, more prone to see it as a set of negative instructions, yet the keynote remains that its fundamental principles must be able to be followed by all, thus assuring open-ended interaction and communication. For Kant, the individual Cartesian path is now closed. Enlightenment is autonomy in thinking among 'an entire public'. The theory of reason is to be vindicated only by its practice. Kant's unusual distinction between public and private comes in 'What is Enlightenment?', published as a response to that question which had been posed by the German periodical, Berlinische Monatschrift. Kant's essay is then, it should be noted, a piece of philosophical journalism, deeply in keeping with the Enlightenment determination to grapple with the most difficult issues in an accessible public space.
11
We live with two incompatible pictures of the European Enlightenment. The first represents the Enlightenment In terms that echo its own manifestos, as a triumph of reason over superstition, as subjecting supposed authorities to reasoned criticism, as a movement towards human liberty and equality, knowledge and progress. In this golden picture reason and science are the progenitors, and justice, peace, and democracy the children of the Enlightenment. The second picture is sombre. It portrays the very ideals of the Enlightenment as symptoms of spurious rationalism and heedless anthropocentrism, and as heralds of a Godless and disenchanted world where only subjective values are left, and which is ruled by modes of social domination more complete and intrusive than those of the old despotisms. In this dark picture, the triumph of reason and science has destroyed not only religion but morality, not only tradition but human bonds. The legacy of the Enlightenment is a world of isolated and alienated individuals who find to their horror that nihilism, terror, domination, and the destruction of the natural world are the true offspring of the Enlightenment. Looking back on their optimistic predecessors they recognize the triumph of theoretical reason and science as the destruction of intelligibility and reason in human lives. The dark picture is not a new one. Many of its elements were discerned in varying forms by Burke and by Hegel, by Goethe and by Mary Shelley, by Marx and by Nietzsche. At the end of the twentieth century the merits of the bright and of the sonlbre images of the Enlightenment are still disputed in a vast range of debates and polemics. Here I shall look only at one fundamental matter, the status of the supposedly reasoned claims advanced in defence of reason itself by the protagonists of the Enlightenment. I shall address the fundamental suspicion that the protagonists of reason not merely underestimated the importance of non-rational sources of intelligibility and value, but invoked an illusory authority when they appealed to reason. The darkest fear that taints the second picture of the Enlightenment is scepticism about reason itself. Why should we take the Enlightenment seriously if
Enlightenment as autonomy 187 its protagonists failed to vindicate the standing of the rational principles to which they appealed? Scepticism about reason is a ticklish matter. In one mood we may think that lack of a vindication of reason cannot count as failure, because any demand for vindication is paradoxical. How could the demands of reason be vindicated? If the vindication was reasoned, it would be circular; if it was not it would not vindicate. It seems that no vindication of reason could meet reason's own standards. The unsatisfactory character of such a demand for vindication is revealed in Descartes' attempts to meet it. In his Discourse on Method (1637) Descartes had claimed that reason had authority because it 'exists whole and complete in each of us' (Descartes 1985: 112; and cf. 7-78). Its methods are discernible by introspection and beyond doubt; they provide axioms on which to found the new edifice of human knowledge. In this account we find a still influential view of what standards of reason should be. If the standards of reason are the foundation, they must be procedures for forming and transforming the elements of thought. Reasoned thinking begins with method. We should expect the methods of reason to include fundamental principles of syntax, procedures of formal logic, modes of (conceptual) analysis, and the mathematical reasoning. We would think of the standards of reason as formal algorithms 'for the direction of the mind', whatever the content of its thoughts. Many critics of Descartes' account of reason accept his view of the sorts of thing we should expect the standards of reason to be, but query his approach to their vindication. They claim that he leaves the introspective and autobiographical procedures that discern reason's standards unvindicated. Why should we think that introspection discloses axioms of reason? Does not Descartes' approach assume both a philosophy of the subject and a tacit theism, which we have reason to query? (cf. Rorty 1986; Kosman 1986 and Ree 1987). If the house of reason lacks Cartesian (or similar) foundations, the Enlightenment project surely has to be reconsidered. What would be the point of subjecting Church and state, beliefs and morals to the standards of reason if those standards had no authority? Wouldn't the Enlightenment project then be no more than a ludicrous philosophical hubris that seeks to call God to account by deifying inherently arbitrary standards and calling them 'reason'? One response to these thoughts might be to look at those critics of the Enlightenment, and more generally of rationalism, who were most aware of them. Many of them saw clearly that if reason is a universal mode of criticism it can be turned on itself. The supposed authority rationalists ascribed to reason was challenged by Pascal, probed repeatedly (if incompletely) by empiricists and relentlessly by Hume. However, no thinker of the Enlightenment was more deeply aware that reason might be an illusory and self-destroYing authority than Immanuel Kant. Here I shall try to bring together Kant's scattered but profound commentary on the possibility that our supposed standards of reasoning are illusory. As we might expect, Kant is a severe critic of groundless modes of thought. His position is complex, and despite
188 Onora O'Neill his well-known enthusiasm for the Enlightenment, some of his admirers doubt whether he is a true friend of reason. One who doubted Kant's commitment to reason was the poet Heinrich Heine, who called Kant the 'all-destroyer' and depicted him as a worse terrorist than Robespierre (Heine 1978: 110). Robespierre killed only a king, but Kant, with his relentless critique of rational theology, killed God. Heine made this charge in a gently mocking rather than a savage spirit. He points to the apparent disparity between Kant's destructive critique of deism and his sober and consoling reiteration of the principles of morality and the hopes of religion. The accusation of terrorism can be pushed further than Heine chose to. For Kant not only criticized rationalist metaphysics and deist religion: he wrote critique of reason. May not the upshot of a sustained attempt to criticize reason indeed be nihilism? If reason is taken as the sole authority for thought and action, will not all authority be destroyed? For if reason destroys authorities, will it not be self-destructive? If it is, then the Enlightenment project disintegrates, and Kant's philosophy leads into darkness. It is well known that Kant did not draw this conclusion. He depicts reason as just and peaceful: it is no dictator; it settles disputes by lawful standards; it leads to a lasting peace. Can these eirenic claims be vindicated? Did Kant offer any vindication of the standards of reason which does not ultimately rest on (some version ot) Cartesian intuition or rationalist hubris? These questions lead to the heart of Kant's enterprise, to the account that he gives of reason's authority. I shall approach them by way of a broad sketch of the central move of Kant's work, and then focus on his central writings on reason's authority, in particular the 'Transcendental Doctrine of Method' at the end of the Critique ofPure Reason (1781; second edn 1787) and two essays of the same decade. What is Orientation in Thinking? (1786?) and What is Enlightenment? (1784). I shall suggest that the account that Kant gives of the authority of reason supports a brighter rather than a darker view of the Enlightenment's character and legacy, but that he too thinks that the loftiest ambitions of the Enlightenment end in horror. THE KANTIAN ENTERPRISE If Kant had died in 1779, at the ripe age of fifty-five, we would know him only as a minor eighteenth-century figure, whose galactic hypothesis about the milky way turned out to be correct. The voluminous writings for which he is in fact known began to appear only in the 1780s, beginning with the Critique of Pure Reason in 1781; they continued almost until his death in 1804. His philosophy is labelled, both by him and today, the critical philosophy. Criticism was to be taken all the way and applied to reason itself: hence the famous titles Critique of Pure Reason, Critique of Practical Reason. Kant took this view of the tasks of philosophy because he realized that the rationalist tradition failed by its own standards. His first Critique begins with the radical suspicion that our cognitive capacities are inadequate to their task:
Enlightenment as autonomy 189 Human reason has this peculiar fate that in one species of its knowledge it is burdened by questions which, as prescribed by the very nature of reason itself, it is not able to ignore, but which, as transcending all its powers, it is not able to answer. (Kant 1933: Avii) The seemingly fatal insufficiency of human reason had left its mark across the full range of inquiry. Would-be rationalism was shot through with internal contradictions: it proposed conceptions of God, cosmology, knowledge and freedom that were incoherent. Kant diagnosed these contradictions as symptoms of an incoherent and excessive conception of the relation between knower and known. For rationalists the object of knowledge is reality itself. Although human knowers cannot know reality to the full, the standard by which their failure is measured is that of a complete, God's eye view of reality. Human cognitive finitude is measured .by the standards of divine omniscience. Kant noted that these standards presupposed that the very knowledge said to elude us was available. In denying that we know a transcendent reality, rationalists assume that we can judge this deficiency by standards we lack. Rationalist philosophy makes the incoherent fundamental assumption that our minds are able to attain (some part of) the truth about a reality that transcends the human mind. The mind is a mirror of nature, and of God; and if it is an imperfect mirror, still philosophy can put together an outline of reality as it is in itself. If these standards elude us, and the transcendent metaphysics to which rationalists aspired cannot be rationally vindicated, what is left? The deist project of salvaging a rational core of religious belief must be abandoned; so must the claim that what passes for scientific knowledge is true of reality as it is in itself. We cannot take it for granted that 'all our knowledge must conform to objects', for we have no vantage point from which to judge such conformity. Kant proposes that we explore a reduced view of knowledge. His famous 'Copernican' hypothesis is that we can count as objects of knowledge only what conforms to our cognitive capacities: 'We must therefore make trial whether we may not have more success in the tasks of metaphysics if we suppose that objects must conform to our knowledge' (Kant 1933: Bxiii). Kant's first move is not to present an account of reason and its authority, but to conduct a trial (Versuch) or experiment. He chooses the experiment of rejecting the move which had led rationalism into self-contradictory, selfdefeating antinomies. Kant's experiment has two aspects. First, it allows us to account for the possibility of some a priori knowledge. If objects must conform to our cognitive capacities, then we can know a priori that the structure of our cognitive abilities is a guide to the structure of our world. Anything that lacked this structure could not be an object for us. Second, the experiment robs us of reasons for thinking that the reality we know - this merely empirical reality of the experienced world - is all there is. Kant thereby rejects both rationalism and empiricism. He rejects rationalism in
190 Onora O'Neill pointing out that we have no reason to think that we know reality as it is in itself. He rejects empiricism in pointing out that we can have some non-trivial a priori knowledge of the world we experience - namely knowledge of its conformity to the structure of our cognitive capacities. The rationalist vision of human knowledge is illusory: 'It is not that ... we cannot know the nature of things in themselves in any save a confused fashion; we do not apprehend them in any fashion whatsoever' (Kant 1933: A441B62).1t is fantasy to imagine that human reason can be vindicated as a partial version of an infinite reason. This, however, is a merely negative point. It does not show us what human reason is, or why any principles for guiding thinking or acting can have the sort of authority that would lead us to call them principles of reason. This surely should be the central task of a philosophy that undertakes a critique of reason. REASON AND AUTHORITY IN THINKING Yet little of the voluminous discussion of Kant's work discusses his approach to this fundamental task. What is his account of reason? Why does he think that any standards have authority in guiding thought and action, or can count as the standards of reason? Is there any non-question-begging way in which to show that some principles have that sort of unrestricted authority without presupposing, so failing to show, that reason has authority? What sort of thing could a vindication of reason be? The initial moves of the Critique of Pure Reason offer no answer. Nothing systematic emerges until the beginning of the 'Transcendental Doctrine of Method', when (after 700 pages!) Kant has the temerity to tell his readers that the whole long 'Transcendental Doctrine of Elements' has been no more than an 'inventory' of the 'materials' of human cognition, and that nothing has yet been established about the 'plan' according to which we should deploy these materials to construct even a modest, less-than-Cartesian edifice of knowledge (Kant 1933: A7071B735). If no one plan is inscribed 'in each of us', coordination is indeed problematic. Intersubjectivity as well as objective knowledge will have to be constructed rather than discovered. Unlike Descartes, who 'guarantees' the intersubjectivity of reason by having God install its principles in each of us, Kant has to account for its possibility. Here is a first and central clue to Kant's aecount of the authority of reason: he takes it that reason's principles must meet conditions for constructing intersubjectivity. Indeed, it is not only intersubjectivity and objective knowledge, but the very principles on which these are based that Kant thinks must be 'constructed'. Yet will not any shared process of construction itself presuppose standards and procedures, so leaving it unclear why the product should have any authority in guiding either thought or action? What could it be to 'construct' the very plan or principles of reason? Kant approaches this delicate matter by way of a series of negative claims. He tells his readers that reason is only a 'discipline' or 'negative instruction'
Enlightenment as autonomy 191 (A709-11/B737-9). He acknowledges that 'reason, whose proper duty it is to prescribe a discipline for all other endeavours should itself stand in need of a such discipline may indeed seem strange' (A710/B738). He informs us that this negative discipline, by which anarchic thinking is restrained, is all there is to reason: 'the whole philosophy of pure reason has no other than this strictly negative utility' (A711/B739). He insists that the principles of reason are not to be equated with the mathematical method of his rationalist predecessors: 'in philosophy the geometrician can by his method build only so many houses of cards' (A727/B755). He disputes analogies between reason and force or coercion: 'there can, properly speaking, be no polemic of pure reason' (A750/B778). He claims that 'reason has no dictatorial authority; its verdict is always simply the agreement of free citizens' (A739/B707).
A first reading of these passages deepens the mystery. Kant has only told us what reason is not, and to compare its authority with that of 'citizens' in open-ended debate may just suggest that it has no authority. Yet this is not Kant's conclusion. He not merely denies that reason is a set of transcendent algorithms implanted in us by some external authority who guarantees their validity: he maintains that the famed authority of reason rests on just two points. The first is the repudiation of 'alien authorities' (dogmatism and force, Church and state); the second is the very strategy of not making intersubjectivity impossible. Yet surely, we may feel, reason must amount to more than the rejection of any 'argument' from authority and adoption of the strategy of not making intersubjectivity impossible. ORIENTATION AND AUTONOMY IN THINKING
Many aspects of this approach may seem implausible. One difficulty is that we perhaps start with a quasi-Cartesian view about sorts of things that standards of reason ought to be. We perhaps think immediately the rules of logical inference, rules of syntax, or aspects of mathematical reasoning, and conclude that principles of reason must be formal algorithms - recipes which guide us precisely through any process of thinking or acting. Yet Kant does not discuss formal procedures - which he calls 'general logic' - in his account of the authority of reason. He makes it clear that reason is to be identified neither with general ~ logic nor with mathematical method. If there are principles that deserve to be thought of as principles of reason, they must guide not just our formation and manipulation of formulae, but our judging, and 'generallogi,c can supply no rules for judgment' (A135/B174). Formal rules and procedures are never sufficient to guide either thought or action. All that follows is that if there are ways of thinking that deserve to be called reasoned, this is not because they meet formal standards (though no doubt they do), but because the standards they meet are not arbitrary. Critique of reason must be taken broadly as asking whether there are fundamental strategies for guiding non-arbitrary thought and action. The second reason why this approach to the vindication of reason may seem
192 Onora O'Neill implausible may be that we expect standards of reason to place substantial constraints on thought and action. If reason requires only rejection of 'alien authorities' and a strategy of meeting conditions for intersubjectivity, wouldn't the most chaotic, structureless thought and action count as reasoned? Kant thinks they will not because he holds that to follow a strategy of not making intersubjectivity impossible is a substantial constraint. Principles can regulate the communication and interaction of a plurality only if sharable by all members of the plurality; they will be sharable (not necessarily shared!) only if they are law-like. He .concludes that to accept or practise 'lawlessness', either in thought or in action, is as unreasoned as subservience to 'alien' laws or principles. It follows that the fundamental principles that have authority in thinking or acting can be neither heteronomous nor lawless. They may neither invoke ungrounded authorities nor preclude the possibility that others with whom we might communicate or interact follow them. The supreme principle of both practical and theoretical uses of reason is a strategy of adherence to principles that we can in principle will others to adhere to. Reason on Kant's account is then simply autonomy in thinking and in action. The most remarkable feature of Kant's vindication of reason is that he does not appeal to reason to explain the importance of autonomy: he invokes autonomy to explain why we should think that some standards in thinking and acting deserve an unrestricted authority, and that we are warranted in calling them principles of reason. This thought is more familiar in a restricted version that Kant formulates for the case of action and morality. In the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), Kant identifies the supreme principle of practical reasoning, the Categorical Imperative, as the principle of autonomy. To follow it is to reject both subservience to 'alien causes' and lawlessness in action; hence it is a matter of acting only on principles that could also be chosen by all, that is, on maxims which can be willed as universal laws. Kant's generalization of the terms of Rousseau's social contract identifies autonomy with acting on one's own principles, on condition those principles are ones that others too can follow (Kant 1953). The centrality of autonomy in Kant's thought is often forgotten or diluted because contemporary interpretations of autonomy, which assume a different account of freedom and action, are radically different. Typically they depict rational action as the instrumentally efficient pursuit of preferred options, and autonomous action as the pursuit of our deeper or more substantial preferences (e.g. Frankfurt 1971; Lindley 1986; Young 1986). In such pictures there is no coordination between the principles of different autonomous beings, so autonomy is portrayed as intrinsically individualistic and self-centred. Iris Murdoch offers a vivid indictment of this reduced modern conception of autonomy, which draws a sharp contrast between reason and autonomy - and attributes it to Kant: We are still living in the age of the Kantian man, or Kantian man-god. Kant's conclusive exposure of the so-called proofs of the existence of God, his analysis
Enlightenment as autonomy 193 of the limitations of speculative reason, together with his eloquent portrayal of the dignity of rational man, has had results which might possibly dismay him. How recognizable, how familiar to us, is the man so beautifully portrayed in the Grundlegung, who confronted even with Christ turns away to consider the voice of his own conscience and to hear the voice of his own reason. Stripped of the exiguous metaphysical background which Kant was prepared to allow him, this man is with us still, free, independent, lonely, powerful, rational, responsible, brave, the hero of so many novels and books of moral philosophy.... He is the ideal citizen of the liberal state, a warning held up to tyrants. He has the virtue which the age requires and admires, courage. It is not such a very long step from Kant to Nietzsche, and from Nietzsche to existentialism and the Anglo-Saxon ethical doctrines which in some ways closely resemble it. In fact Kant's man had already received a glorious incarnation nearly a century earlier in the work of Milton: his proper name is Lucifer. (Murdoch 1970: 80) Murdoch is right that this remains the conception of autonomy of our age. Although existentialists and analytic philosophers placed varying weight on the role of mere, sheer choice and of efficient pursuit of preference, both of them separated autonomy from reason. The autonomous man or woman so conceived needs (at most) capacities for instrumental reasoning. Kant's account of the matter is radically different: to act autonomously is to act on principles that are law-like, yet not subservient. This is the most fundamental principle for guiding practice - the supreme principle of practical reason. Kant's discussions of what counts as autonomy in thinking are less familiar, but follow the same pattern. In What is Orientation in Thinking? he contrasts thinking that submits to arbitrary, alien authorities or attempts an illusory lawless freedom with autonomous thinking, and insists that: if reason will not subject itself to the law it gives itself, it will have to bow under the yoke of the law which others impose on it, for without any law whatsoever nothing, not even the greatest nonsense, can play its hand for very long. Thus the inevitable consequence of declared lawlessness in thinking (an emancipation from restrictions of reason) is that freedom t9 think is finally lost. (Kant 1949: 304) He also insists that: To make use of one's own reason means nothing more than to ask oneself with regard to everything that is to be assumed, whether he finds it practicable to make the ground of the assumption a universal principle of the use of reason. (305n) The parallels between Kant's account of the fundamental strategies of practical and theoretical uses of reason are clear. Yet the claim that this 'merely negative
194 Onora O'Neill instruction' vindicates the authority of reason is still obscure. For in both cases all that we are told is that reasoned thinking or acting rejects both subservience and lawlessness. If we retain the rationalist image of a transcendent vindication of reason, this will seem a wholly inadequate account of the authority of reason. Yet if we accept Kant's critique of rationalist metaphysics we cannot very well hang on to the foundations of those metaphysics. If we abandon rationalism, we must look for another strategy for avoiding arbitrariness. Once we have liberated ourselves from rationalist thinking we can see readily why rejecting unvindicated 'authorities' is an indispensable strategy of reason. Thinking or acting that invokes such authorities will always have an arbitrary element: it relies on unvindicated premisses. Yet we can also see that thinking or acting that acknowledged no authoritative standards will be infested with arbitrariness, superstition, caprice, and ultimately with the very disorientation of thought from which we seek escape. So we can understand the point of both aspects of Kant's negative instruction that constitutes his vindication of the authority of reason. But how can this be all that there is to the authority of reason? To understand this it may help to think over the conception of autonomy that is invoked. If autonomy is not a matter of mere wilfulness, but of following principles that are neither arbitrary nor imposed, it will demand thinking and acting, whose fundamental principles can be followed by all. To flout such principles would be to succumb either to subservience or to disoriented patterns of thought and action. Subservient and disoriented modes of thought and action risk unintelligibility to others, and the collapse of intersubjectivity. In so far as intelligibility is sustained, it may depend on securing (perhaps imposing) subservience to some shared but unvindicated 'authority'. At this point we can see further into Kant's insistence that the construction of principles of reason is a collective and not a solitary task. Nothing will count as a principle of reason if it demands submission to some unvindicated authority; anything that does count as a principle of reason must be one that all can follow. The principles of reason are those that can secure the possibility of intersubjectivity. Kant does not ground reason in actual consensus, or in the agreement and standards of any historical community; he grounds it in the repudiation of principles that preclude the possibility of open-ended interaction and communication. This is a radical reinterpretation of the project of the Enlightenment. Kant does not depict theory as impeccably grounded in reason, and the rationality of practices as derivative. His account of reason is in the first place an account of constraints on practices of thinking and acting among any plurality for whom interaction and communication are possible. If practical reason is fundamental, then the dark vision of the Enlightenment, which depicts theoretical reason as failing to sustain an account of intelligible and reasoned practice, may be unthreatening.
Enlightenment as autonomy 195 ENLIGHTENMENT AND POLITICS This account of the construction of reason out of the requirements of autonomy provides a way of understanding Kant's famous, and still controversial, essay of 1784, What is Enlightenment? The essay begins with a highly unusual account of the principle and the process of Enlightenment: Enlightenment is man's emergence from self-incurred immaturity. Immaturity is the inability to use one's own understanding without the guidance of another. The immaturity is self-incurred if its cause is not lack of understanding, but lack of resolution and courage to use it without the guidance of another. The motto of enlightenment is therefore: sapere aude! Have the courage to use your own understanding. (Kant 1970: 54) In this strange passage we are told that Enlightenment is not to be thought of as a matter of following reason, whose authority in thinking and acting is given by some quite other source. We are told that it is a matter of rejecting spurious authorities and thinking for ourselves. Enlightenment is the practice of autonomy in thinking. The conventional motto is reinterpreted. Weare called not to clear and distinct ideas but to courageous action: 'the maxim of always thinking for oneself is enlightenment' (Kant 1949: 305n; cf. Kant 1978: 152). Kant reminds us that laziness and cowardice readily lull us into accepting alien authorities: 'It is so convenient to be immature! If I have a book to have understanding in place of me, a spiritual adviser to have a conscience for me, a doctor to judge my diet for me, and so on I need not make any efforts' (Kant 1970: 54). He then promptly repudiates any individualist interpretation of autonomy. Asolitary individual cannot expect to escape 'immaturity' and achieve autonomy, 'a people' may do so. Enlightenment is autonomy in thinking among 'an entire public'. Kant claims that this process of enlightenment can happen only if 'the public use of man's reason' is freely permitted, but that 'the private use of reason may quite often be very narrowly restricted ... without undue hindrance to the progress of enlightenment'. These claims are often dismissed gs a timid defence of freedom, which endorses 'enlightened' despotism. Kant lends support to this reading by complimenting Frederick the Great as the one ruler in the world who says, 'Argue as much as you like, but obey!' (55). Kant's defence of political freedom is indeed qualified. However, to dismiss the essay on this account is to overlook its most striking feature, which is the extraordinary way in which Kant distinguishes 'public' from 'private' uses of reason, and to neglect his reasons for thinking the 'public' use of reason more vital. His account of progress towards enlightenment by the emergence of 'an entire public' into autonomy are closely linked with his vindication of reason (O'Neill 1989: Part I). Kant here takes it for granted that much of our thinking and of our acting is in
196 Onora O'Neill fact premissed, and unavoidably premissed, on accepting 'alien' authorities. We accept that doctors can tell us what to eat, that officers can command their troops, and governments their citizens. The peculiar thing about Kant's discussion of these cases is that he calls all of them 'private' uses of reason: 'What I term a private use of reason is that which a person may make of it in a particular civil post or office' (Kant 1970: 55). Such uses of reason are not 'private' because confined to private life, but because premissed in part upon the acceptance of some'alien authority'. 'Private' uses of reason are privatus, deprived or partial. They rely on at least one unjustified premiss. What we today would term 'public service' is on Kant's account subservience to 'alien authority': it is not an adequate model of autonomy, reason or of their social embodiment in 'an enlightened age'. To act in a role is always in part to submit to relations of authority, so incompletely reasoned. When we interpret such action it is on the assumption that the officer had authority to command, the preacher to expound scripture and the state to levy taxes. Action in a role cannot be fully reasoned. Its underlying principles cannot be universally adopted: officers, preachers, and tax collectors assume authority over others, who cannot assume like authority; taxpayers acknowledge authority which they do not themselves assume. These principles could not be adopted as fundamental by all members of any plurality. Kant does not believe that we can do without roles and institutions; he does maintain that we have better models of reason in practice. More fully 'public' uses of reason would be those that do not invoke unvindicated authorities. In this essay and elsewhere Kant offers as images of 'public' uses of reason the communication of 'men of learning' who communicate with 'the true public, the world at large' and of citizens (Kant 1970: 56,57). His point is not to restrict the freedom to reason to any community of scholars. The very officers, preachers, and civil servants who must bow to constituted authority when acting in their roles must be free to make public, unrestricted use of their reason when not acting in those roles. The officer may comment freely on 'errors in the military service'; clergy on doctrine and on church affairs; citizens on fiscal policy. Kant is clearly convinced that this 'most innocuous(!) freedom' to make public use of one's reason is IT10re important for the development of an enlightened public than any merely political reform (55,56). The freedom to think and criticize beyond the demands of role and obedience, a freedom that is modelled by the communication of scholars or in debate among citizens is the social practice which constitutes the matrix of autonomy, and of a flourishing development of practices of reason. This is the way to move from' an age of enlightenment' to an achieved 'enlightened age' (58). The abstract considerations that identify principles of reason require the appropriate social embodiment in practices of communication. Kant warns that: A revolution may well put an end to autocratic depotism and to rapacious powerseeking oppression, but it will never produce true reform in ways of thinking.
Enlightenment as autonomy 197 Instead, new prejudices, like the ones they replaced, will serve as a leash to control the great unthinking mass. (55)
Whether glasnost is more effective than revolution, or indeed than perestroika, and how far they can be dissociated, are large, unsettled questions that arise within the brighter picture of the Enlightenment and its legacy. Kant's answers to them may be inadequate, and I neither have pursued nor shall pursue the matter here. The question that I have pursued is whether Kant's approach to the authority of reason dispels or reduces fears that reason itself is a spurious authority. His answer does not - how could it? - take the form of a reasoned proof of axioms of reason. Nor does he appeal to claims of self-evidence. Like any argument, Kant's needs premisses. What is distinctive is that the premisses are ones that we cannot easily dismiss. Kant's thought is basically that if we hold that any modes of thought and action can communicate with (and possibly convince) others, then we must rely on basic principles of thought and action that do not preclude others from following them. If we simply settle for the contingently shared principles of some actual plurality, we may find that they are not sharable by all, and that our supposed capacities to reason fail and falter at the first boundary. (Communitarians and relativists may retort that this is fine, and ask why any principles should have universal scope: Kant might answer that we indeed cannot vindicate totalizing principles (referring to the totality of possible agents), but that our practices already commit us to communicating and interacting VJith others who differ from us. To claim that reason (and no doubt justice!) stops at frontiers that we in fact cross, simultaneously asserts and denies that intersubjectivity can be open-ended.) A plurality of beings whose action is not antecedently coordinated - in whom reason is not inscribed by divine fiat - cannot appeal to transcendent standards of reason. They can only achieve reasoned communication and intersubjectivity by settling for basic principles all of them can hold. They are not forced to choose such principles, but can opt (at least in part and on occasion) for the contingencies of shared conviction (even for the brutalities of imposed'agreement') and acquiesce in lack of procedures for securing or extending limited agreement. (Heteronomy, imperialism, and madness are all possibilities.) Those who repudiate principles that all could share settle (at least in part) for brute violence or mute solitude. Those who make the principle of autonomy fundamental to their thinking and acting may not have procedures for seeking others' reasoned conviction on all matters, let alone a guarantee that their procedures will always work. Just as practical reasoning provides no more than side constraints for action, so theoretical reasoning may greatly underdetermine what we may reasonably believe. The principle of acting only on maxims, through which one can at the same time will that they be universal laws, can identify principles of obligation, but offers no algorithm for moral action. The principle of thinking using only fundamental principles which
198 Onora O'Neill can be held universally may well constrain but not fully determine the categories of thought, procedures of judgement and inference that we can rationally adopt. Kant offers no algorithm for reasoned belief. Both for practical and for theoretical use he identifies reason as the strategy of adopting principles that will not prevent unrestricted intersubjectivity, yet do not invoke arbitrary premises. This approach may vindicate certain formal aspects of reasoning without God having to inscribe them in us. The rejection of elementary principles of consistency in syntax and inference, and the patterns of formal contradiction this rejection will generate, would impede the very possibility of intersubjectivity. In Kant's vindication of reason, however, the principles of 'general logic' are not the foundations of reason. What is most basic to reasoning is a strategy (embodied in an array of social practices) of leaving open the possibility of interaction and communication, hence of avoiding modes of thought that obstruct them. The only vindication we can offer for general logic and cognate formalisms is that these are crucial tactics for those who follow strategies of reason. Kant's vindication of the practices of reason reverses the traditional agenda of the Enlightenment: theory is to be vindicated by practice rather than practice by theory. Up to a point Kant endorses the dark picture of the Enlightenment: if we try to begin with theoretical uses of reason, then indeed morality, justice, and the practices of life will remain ungrounded. If we do not try to give priority to theory, if we realize that it is the public use of reason that is fundamental, we can recuperate most of the elements of the bright picture. We can distinguish reasoned from unreasoned practices in morality and politics. What we cannot recover is the limitless theoretical ambitions of rationalism; for these, on Kant's diagnosis, are indeed sources of nihilism and despair. At the end of the Critique of Practical Reason he wrote that if we had 'that power of insight or enlightenment which we would like to possess' then God and eternity in their awful majesty would stand unceasingly before our eyes (for that which we can completely prove is as certain as that which we can ascertain by sight). Transgression of the law would indeed be shunned, and the commanded would be performed ... most actions conforming to the law would be done from fear, few would be done from hope, none from duty.... The conduct of man, so long as his nature remained as it is now, would be changed into mere mechanism, where, as in a puppet show, everything would gesticulate well but no life would be found in the figures. (Kant 1977: 152-3) The crippled vision of human life and morality which the dark vision of the Enlightenment emphasizes was in large measure Kant's vision of the fate of practice within the rationalist enterprise. His aim was to avert the melancholy implications of that vision by showing that we have no reason to endorse the rationalist assumption that theoretical reason is fundamental. Rather we should acknowledge 'the utter insufficiency of speculative reason to solve the most weighty problems which are
Enlightenment as autonomy 199 presented to it' (Kant 1977: 152). I-Iis aim was also to retain many elements of the bright picture by showing how practices of autonomy can orient thought and action among a plurality of beings in whom no preestablished harmony has inscribed guarantees of intersubjectivity or principles of reason.
12
The authoritarian response LUDMILLA JORDANOVA
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION In the Introduction (see above pp. 2-3) we raised the question of periodization, suggesting that the conventional dating of the 'age of Enlightenment' should be questioned and the teleological connection between Enlightenment and Revolution sufficiently loosened to allow us to see, from our twentieth-century perspective, the manner in which that connection was first made, in the years after 1789, and the notions that underlay its making. This final essay takes on that task, looking in the process at the work of three transitional figures Maine de Biran, Chateaubriand, and Joseph de Maistre - who in some sense belong both to the Enlightenment itself and to the first period of reaction. These writers were able therefore - according to their own lights - to categorize and make judgements on the phenomenon of 'the Enlightenment', from whose shadow they saw themselves as emerging. The position from which these judgements were made was, in Ludmilla Jordanova's carefully defined word, authoritarian. The central political metaphor of European political thought has always been, that of the body politic. Traditionally the metaphor has validated a separation of functions at the same time as giving a valuable role to all parts: a body needs 'hands' as much as a 'head'. 'Honour and shame from no Condition rise', according to Alexander Pope in An Essay on Man (1733-4); but with the conservative corollary, 'Act well your part, there all the honour lies' (Epistle IV, lines 193-4). The political philosophy of the Enlightenment generally sought to redefine if not to replace the metaphor. Even the famous title-page of Hobbes' Leviathan (1651) shows the body of the sovereign as constituted by his individual subjects, a relationship of interdependence that was formalized through the varieties of Enlightenment contractual theory, culminating in Rousseau's sophisticated notion of the 'general will'. The metaphor was given a new lease of life, so to speak, by the practices of the French Revolution, and in particular by the beheading of Louis XVI, which symboli-
The authoritarian response 201 cally removed the idea of a single person as the 'head' of the body politic. Yet discursively it was not easy to find an alternative metaphor: what image, for example, could embody Rousseau's general will? The body politic, as metaphor, proved resistant, and became, in new forms, one of the staple weapons of the authoritarian response to the French Revolution. The body politic is evoked in the pathos of Burke's description of the assault on the royal family at Versailles, with the body of Marie Antoinette standing for Burke's idea of the old, chivalric France. The Gothic version of the metaphor also proved powerful, with the Revolutionary state personified as a new body politic that is either out of control (like the monster created by Frankenstein) or gorged on the blood of its victims: the vampire or spectre that continued to haunt the nightmares of the privileged throughout the nineteenth century. The strongest use of the metaphor, though, was the one which depicts the Revolutionary body politic as feeding directly on the older 'body' of tradition. Commentators like Burke, Gillray, and Chateaubriand grasped the image of Revolution as cannibal as the metaphor most adequate to their anxieties. Commentators hostile to the Revolution focused on the abuse or excesses of 'Reason' as a cause of monstrosity. They were particularly sensitive to the overreaching that they found in the Enlightenment. Both Frankenstein and Faust were guilty of the particular kind of hubris associated with a thirst for scientific knowledge. The figures 10rdanova discusses found this type of transgression to be particularly offensive, not least because they detected there a spiritual aridity. The slave uprising that eventually created the state of Haiti drew inspiration from news of the Parisian events of 1789-93. That the slaves ('hands') in France's most important colony in the Caribbean should - with the slogans of the Revolution on their lips - overthrow their masters ('head') amid tales of carnage and brutality, was only final confirmation of the connection between cannibalism and Revolution. 'Cannibalism', in its new Enlightenment clothes, had returned to the Caribbean, from whence it had come.
12
The end of the Enlightenment is my concern here. How, when, and why it ended are formidably complex questions, but end it did. And its demise can be linked to a specific event, or rather a series of interrelated processes, that marks a major point of transition in European, and possibly, in world history - the French Revolution. Even at the time, perhaps we should say especially at the time, the Revolution was linked with the Enlightenment, and thus disenchantment with the Revolution often went hand in hand with disenchantment with the Enlightenment. Some commentators went further and suggested that the Enlightenment caused the Revolution (Church 1964). They were able to do so by linking the Terror, which was in reality only one phase of the long and complex revolutionary process, with the values of Enlightenment. By taking the Terror as emblematic of '1789', commentators were able to depict in fearsome terms the darkest, the most threatening shadows of the Enlightenment. In the 1790s and early 1800s a version of the Enlightenment was constructed. It is important not to confuse this with the historical phenomena we now study, although these too are, of course, constructs - ones for other times, other places. An understanding of the Enlightenment as perceived through the terrifying chaos of Revolution has much to teach us. Commentators concerned to reimpose authority saw the shadows of the Enlightenment only too clearly. Shadows cast gloom, they invite those who live under them to account for their darkness. A monstrous Enlightenment was fabricated in order to achieve precisely this. The exact form the monstrosity took tells us much about the worst fears of those who stood in shadow. The relationships between objects and their shadows are complex - the latter· bear a resemblance to the former, but there is always an element of distortion. The authoritarian response reveals some of the Enlightenment's most menacing shadows, and by that token permits a more rounded view of the complex movement of ideas that cast them~ I shall not be concerned here with establishing either the causes or the origins of
The authoritarian response 203 '1789', but with the links assumed to exist between the Enlightenment and the Revolution, links that encouraged the formulation in the early nineteenth century of an authoritarian response that sought to supersede both the Revolution and its associated worldview. Naturally, when such associations were made they served, rhetorically, clear political ends. The case of Burke is certainly the best-known example of this phenomenon and it is discussed elsewhere in the book (cf. Reedy 1981). In 'fact, the Enlightenment was invoked both by those who deemed themselves 'revolutionary', as well as by those who presented themselves as 'counterrevolutionary'. Hence ideas and political events stood in manifestly close, if sometimes fraught, relation to one another. The end of the Enlightenment was bound up with the rise to power of Napoleon Bonaparte (1769-1821). Obviously, he did not single-handedly cause the end of an intellectual and cultural movement. Rather he embodied the gradual, and general withdrawal of confidence in some of the most cherished ideas associated with the Enlightenment. His life exemplifies the shift all the more elegantly because he was educated in an Enlightenment manner, and initially presented himself to the French people as the saviour of the true Revolution. Indeed, many groups, especially outside France, continued for some time to idolize him as a liberator. But as he acquired more political power, disillusion with him spread, while he became ever more vigilant to control not only French society but the images of him that were present in it. He encouraged movements, institutions, and individuals who represented an altogether distinct, and more authoritarian, perspective and discouraged those who embodied Enlightenment values. The mere fact of his existence as Emperor, his Concordat with the Pope, and his elaboration of a matching symbolic order indicated publicly a change of major proportions. This change, although it took place in France, and responded to a whole range of issues and problems that were distinctively French, was noted and had a profound impact far beyond the geographical boundaries of 'France'. There are three main reasons for this. First, French writings and ideas were widely disseminated in Europe and North America, and they were used in very different contexts to canvas the major philosophical, political, and cultural questions of the day. It was inevitable, therefore, that events that openly bore on the fate and standing of such ideas were watched with interest elsewhere. Second, the French Revolution, following rather closely on the American Revolution, became an example, a paradigm of revolution. Its fate was thus of general interest; it allowed people to speculate about the nature of revolutions, about deep change, about new and old orders. Third, the Revolution itself was not confined to France, but directly involved, once war was declared, the rest of Europe, including Russia. Naturally, threats had been felt elsewhere long before that, but these were made tangible by the subsequent long military engagement, and the appalling suffering that it brought to many areas. While we have a name for the revolutionary turmoil, we do not have a term for the reaction against it. To call it counter-revolution would be seriously misleading,
204 Ludmilla lordanova since this suggests movements dedicated to counteracting the Revolution directly (cf. Beik 1970; Best 1988b: 129-53). What I am describing was less focused politically yet more extensive culturally. I shall designate it 'the authoritarian response'. Clearly, a key issue here is the complexity of 'authority' as an idea. Deriving as it does from the cluster of concepts around 'author', authority, according to the dictionary, refers back to a source, an originator, instigator, actor, or begetter. In the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries it generally implied a single source of legitimated power. Authoritative power can be both over the conduct and actions of others and over their beliefs and opinions. This power can be general, as . in the case of government, or more focused and knowledge-based, as it is when particular books or persons are endowed with the power to give authoritative testimony. In the social sciences as they have developed since the nineteenth century, authority is primarily construed in political terms, and we now have a range of theoretical vantage points from which authority may be viewed - inspired by more recent political experiences - none of which were available to observers of the end of the Enlightenment (Michels 1948; Peabody 1968). In this context the crucial point about the idea is that it is exceptionally rich metaphorically. I use the notion of authority deliberately. Because it has been applied to a wide range of phenomena, it enables us to draw out the shared qualities of apparently disparate aspects of a single society. In early nineteenth-century France, for example, it is possible to discern a shift towards an authoritarian mode in literature, art, religion, politics, philosophy, and science, to name only the more obvious areas. The changes these fields experienced, in the wake of distaste for revolutionary excess and Enlightenment assumptions, have much in common with one another. To see the authoritarian response in a fuller context, we need to return to the Enlightenment itself, indeed to its early stages. Before doing so, however, it is necessary to establish a general point about authority. Authority is, as I have already indicated, a metaphor; it has a long history and a capacity to reach the enormously varied and quite palpable experiences of power that lie at the heart of most societies. At the centre of these lie the power of gods and the power of rulers. These have commonly been translated into other forms such as the power of the husband, father, or head of the household. Such apparently diverse forms of authority were both spoken about and experienced in related ways. There are places and periods when these relationships are made perfectly explicit. The legal formulation in England that a wife killing her husband is petty treason, the patriarchalist apologia of Robert Filmer, the complex discourses and symbolism of absolutism, and in particular the endowment of Louis XIV with divine powers are all obvious examples of this point (Wolf 1968; Schochet 1975; Butler 1978; Marin 1988). The intertwining in language, symbol, and experience of these forms of authority requires us to be aware of the ways in which areas like religion, politics, and philosophy were, at many different levels, bound together. And, more specifically, it alerts us to the fact that eighteenth-century societies were the inheritors of rich religious,
The authoritarian response 205 political, and philosophical traditions for which authority was a central term. These traditions were deeply troubling to many eighteenth-century people. Locke's liberal refutation of Filmer's defence of patriarchal authority is a well-known example of this reaction against over-arching authority. There are innumerable other examples of a struggle away from the multiplicity of crushing authorities that 'absolutism' in all its forms represented. I mean to refer here both to the historically-specific political formation generally called absolutism, and, by extension, to general assumptions that power of any kind could be 'absolute'. It is important to stress that absolutism embodies models of power - the extent to which it was successful in actually achieving its ends must remain a moot point (cf. Bonney 1987). Let us take, for example, the authority of God. It is, I think, quite wrong to place exclusive emphasis on the rejection of God's authority during the Enlightenment, although there were, to be sure, a few people who took this route. Rather, there was a loosening of the bonds of that authority. Natural religion, a term that can be used to characterize the beliefsystems of many radical thinkers of the day, represents the desire for a certain distance between the deity and the earthly world - a distance that leaves considerable room for manoeuvre. The tightness present in Filmer's patriarchalism or Louis XIV'S absolutism was altogether too constricting. Binding together the ideas of God, monarch, sun, and father led to a sense of suffocation; the weight of hierarchy was crushing. Of course, it was more than this that people reacted against. Rigid ideas of hierarchy came to seem outmoded, inappropriate, repugnant to a sense of natural justice. This can be linked with the development of 'individualism', which, although a problematic term, refers to a very real sense that most categories of people were endowed with worth and with definable rights. Such assertions were about the value of individual persons, in and of themselves. There was no need to refer upwards, as it were, in search of transferred properties since the key qualities were inherent in human beings themselves. There was another central characteristic of the Enlightenment that was integral to the reaction against absolutism, but less often remarked upon. The absolutist model assumes foci of power. After all, the image of a sun king implies just such a focus. The main foci were thought of as overlapping; they were conceptualized in similar terms. This has implications not only for the nature of rulers (seen as active), but especially for the ruled (seen as passive). Accordingly, the ruled seem relatively inert; they bask in the sun, they worship and adore it, they bow down before it, they are awed by it. By the middle of the seventeenth century, the sun was the acknowledged centre of the universe. The sun is generative, a single dynamic source. In this mind-set it is difficult to imagine order, coherence, and responsibility emanating from the people themselves, without imposition from above. These qualities come, in the absolutist framework, from a different order of being that is beyond, apart from society. Authority was thus associated with a qualitatively distinct level, and with a central source of power. Much Enlightenment thinking, in a whole range of domains, was dedicated to challenging this model. Order could, it was argued, derive from people/believersl
206 Ludmilla lordanova citizens themselves, or, in the case of the physical world, it derived from nature's own laws, even if these were, ultimately, the product of God's will. God's will was distant, nature was immediate; it was there, to be seen, touched, used as a material and an intellectual resource. Similarly, if people came together and made a contract, and then governed themselves in a consensual manner, the kinds of authority involved were immediate and man-made, quite different from the absolutist intention where a single, remote, divinely-sanctioned will was the unique source of authority. Far from emanating from a single, distant, and higher source, authority could be conceptualized by participants in the Enlightenment as arising from below, from the very same level in which it was exercised. I do not mean to . imply that the political participation of the masses was taken as unproblematic, far from it, but it was conceivable that citizens - and much hung on how that term was defined - could govern themselves. For authority to come from among people rather than from beyond them seemed perfectly plausible. There is a further implication contained within the Enlightenment distrust of authority that is central to the themes of this paper. If authority can be located \vithin society, that is, within human beings rather than in gods or in semi-divine monarchs, then people themselves as sources of power become enormously more interesting. One major way of pursuing such questions was through the study of our mental faculties. Accordingly, the study of human nature was central to the Enlightenment project. If ideas like free will, soul, and spirit are under siege, fresh approaches to human nature take on a new importance. A naturalist approach was developed to supersede an overtly theological one. And because terms like 'will' have such a wide range of referents, including to the faculties of the understanding, rethinking such categories becomes a matter of the widest interest. I have already noted how there were overlapping vocabularies for speaking about power in the period. Thus, if one of the cornerstones of a traditional approach to authority was challenged, we would expect a related adjustment in the whole range of discourses. If will as an expression of political and divine action is invalidated, how could it be deployed in the same way to describe mental acts? There were, therefore, quite particular reasons for changes in ways of thinking and talking about human beings, and especially their mental lives, during the Enlightenment. But the shift was more extensive than this. After all, one of the most powerful impulses that lay behind that phenomenon we call the Enlightenment was the drive to explain all aspects of the physical world, including living nature, in naturalistic terms; to find scientific explanations for natural and social phenomena. This included human beings as a matter of course, hence the development of the new discipline known as 'the science of man' (Moravia 1980). The science of man had many aspects in the eighteenth century - it was closely allied to medicine and natural history and to what is now termed anthropology. It also enjoyed a special relationship to speculations about how the human mind worked and the ways in which it was linked to bodily phenomena. This last interest was nurtured by the widespread interest in the brain as the presumed physical location of thought,
The authoritarian response 207 experience, and the soul, by the philosophical concern with building plausible models of mental action and more especially by sensualism - the assumption that all knowledge derives ultimately from the senses. In fact, the philosophical issues here were exceedingly complex. But a simplified version of the sensualist position was widely disseminated in the eighteenth century (e.g. Baxandall 1985: 74-104). As a result, debate about how the senses worked, about how the mind functioned, about whether the soul existed, and, if it did, whether it could be located in a specific anatomical place, was enjoined by a great variety of people (Figlio 1975). What role willing might play in human life was thus an obvious candidate for discussion, both because much hung on it and because of the general curiosity about human nature. The will was a major concept through which concerns about the uniqueness of humanity could be canvassed. The Enlightenment began with a struggle with established authorities; it sought to create alternative sources of validation, above all from nature and from human nature, and it ended in the wake of a renewed political, theological, and philosophical authoritarianism, and even a revival of absolutism. The conflicts between the Enlightenment and the authoritarian response of the early nineteenth century found one of their most powerful expressions in 'psychology'. This word is, of course, somewhat anachronistic if used of periods before the mid-nineteenth century, but I deploy it here as shorthand for the concern with the nature of mental life that attempts to explain the processes of thinking naturalistically, and hence is allied with philosophy, and especially with epistemology, on the one hand, and with the natural and medical sciences, particularly physiology, on the other. Psychology was at the centre of the science of man, a project of the Enlightenment - but it was also at the centre of the authoritarian response. An exemplification of these points may be found in the fate of 'ideology', the science of ideas, a new area of study that emerged at the end of the eighteenth century (Gusdorf 1978). Its students were followers of Condillac and they grouped themselves around Destutt de Tracy (1754-1836), around the salon of Madame Helvetius at Auteuil, and from 1795 around the Second Class of the Insfitut National, which was devoted to the moral and political sciences. Although the intellectual interests of the ideologues were very broad, their shared commitments both to a science of human nature and to an understanding of the phenomena of consciousness were of paramount importance. They were indeed heirs of the Enlightenment, striving to produce ever more sophisticated accounts of human experience based on observation. A medical approach was influential here since clinicians had a fund of examples to draw upon that illustrated the enormous variety of human nature, both normal and pathological, and the complexity of mind-body interaction. This last point is important because there was a revulsion against seeing mind and body as separate, and a preference for showing how the two were necessarily intertwined. Of course, many savants were still dualists, but their understanding of mind-body interaction was exceedingly sophisticated, so that the difficulty in practice of separating these two
208 Ludmilla lordanova elements was clear to them. Indeed, it was suggested that, as the prominent medical ideologue Cabanis (1757-1808) put it, the physical and moral were at their base the same, both facets of 'organization' (Figlio 1976; Moravia 1980: 264). He meant by this that it was possible to understand all the functions of living things in terms of their structural complexity. The implications for a science of man were clear; even the most elaborate mental processes were to be explained biologically, by reference, for example, to the anatomy and physiology of the brain and nervous system (Staum 1980). Not only were mind and body two manifestations of a single set of natural .phenomena, but claims about a soul or free will appeared rather ridiculous. It is worth being quite explicit about why this was the case. I mentioned earlier the question of active and passive elements. Under political absolutism the populace was relatively passive, the king, active. That, at least, was the theory. Similarly, it was possible to imagine the human body as passive, the soul, mind, will, or spirit as active. And so it was with nature too, which was often seen as the passive substratum upon which God acted via laws of nature. Although it would be a mistake to imply that there was a consensus on these matters, we can gather much about the common assumptions made about them from the violent reaction elicited in the eighteenth century by theories that attributed activity to mere matter. By the end of the eighteenth century, however, natural philosophers had developed elaborate ways of understanding living things that followed a delicate middle ground. They rejected crude dualisms partly because neither soul nor free will did the necessary explanatory work in producing a convincing and naturalistic account of organic action. Equally, they mostly had little time either for overt materialism or for theories of active matter. The approach taken by Cabanis and by many of his contemporaries, which involved the study of 'organization', was the newly-found middle ground, one that was especially attractive to those who were self-consciously progressive, both socially and politically. We should note the proximity between the physiological and biological approaches just outlined and political assumptions that people could make ordered societies themselves, which were capable of considerable organizational complexity, without these being imposed upon them from a separate and higher active power. Furthermore, the overlap, play, and analogies between the human body and the body politic were, as commentators have noted, recognized at the time (Pickstone 1981; Outram 1989). It was equally evident to many people that the problems of explaining action, whether this was divine, natural, or mental, were simply different facets of a single philosophical cluster. It should therefore come as no surprise to discover that the ideologues were equally interested in the science of man, and especially 'psychology', in scientific method, in the natural, the political, and the moral sciences. All the questions mentioned in this paper could be explored at a variety of levels and through a wide range ofspecific instances. For example, at a more detailed level much of the debate hinged on the faculties of the understanding, especially because there was no consensus as to what the basic faculties were. Some commentators
The authoritarian response 209 simply eliminated will as a fundamental faculty or claimed that ideas of free will were no more than a theological trick. For others the will was not demoted completely for de Tracy the basic faculties were feeling remembering, judging, and willing. None the less, he did not see the will as detached from other bodily and mental processes. It was one faculty among others to be understood naturalistically. The important point is that, however committed such people were to a basic sensualist model, by the 1790s there was a growing awareness of its inadequacies, of the complexity of mental life and hence of the need to alter and expand the terms within which psychology was discussed (Copleston 1975: 19-36). There is no better exemplication of this point than the changing ideas of Maine de Biran (Les Etudes Philosophiques 1982; Huxley 1954: 1-152; Moore 1970). Maine de Biran (1788-1824) was an influential philosopher who was concerned above all with introspection, with explaining our inner lives. He is considered to be of 'pivotal importance in the history of French thought', a figure who 'helped create nineteenth-century French Spiritualism and twentieth-century French Existentialism' (Hallie 1959: viii). Initially, he was enthusiastic about ideologie: both de Tracy and Cabanis responded positively to his early work, and he in turn was indebted to them. Indeed, in many ways de Tracy's own dissatisfaction with Condillac's sensualism paved the way for Maine de Biran's more searching critique and for the alternative that he developed. But.he became disaffected with the ideologue approach and sought his own path. He retained, however, a conviction that constructing a science of human nature was a task of paramount importance and himself attempted to produce a synthetic account of the field - a psychology or philosophical anthropology, to use his own terms. He held a deep conviction in the importance of human consciousness, Le. inner experience, as a source of knowledge and thus introspection was a central method for him. More than this, the inside of human beings could not, for Biran, be seen as passive. Rather he sought an active human centre in the will. This had two implications. First, Biran was interested in the nature of willed effort by which the self knows or feels itself through the resistance it encounters. Second, he used this as a paradigm of causality. Indeed, the will is so central to his philosophy that it may be summed up in the phrase; 'I will, therefore I am' (Copleston 1975: 30). In the career of a single individual, nurtured in the major traditions of the Enlightenment, we can trace the progressive disenchantment with those traditions. Maine of Biran was an agnostic early in his life, he died a Catholic. He began with an interest in thinkers like Locke, Bonnet, and Condillac, then he became involved with the ideologues, especially Destutt de Tracy and Cabanis, and finally he moved away from them towards more mystical traditions, towards philosophies where the existence of God and the spiritual dimensions of human life occupied a more central position. Along with his insistence on human activity, on 'man' as a free agent, and on the basic distinction between our experience of the external and internal worlds, went a deep conviction in dualism. It is everywhere in his later ideas. Dualism was at the heart of the authoritarian response. y
210 Ludmilla lordanova For Maine de Biran the difference between mind and body, between the spiritual and the material realms, between active causes and passive effects, and between God and his created world were of paramount importance. These distinctions had a number of facets. They enabled him, for example,to stress the special nature of the human mind, which, for both theological and philosophical reasons, was a centrepiece of his thought. Free will was contrasted with matter determined by laws of nature. Such distinctions also expressed a revulsion against 'levelling tendencies', against the crassness of lumping things together - a complaint often directed against the Enlightenment. An approach that rests heavily on the existence of distinct orders of being, and that then construes these as ranged along a hierarchy, be it of power, value, morality, or degree of spirituality, requires a philosophy of difference. And, at this historical juncture, dualism was the dominant and the most attractive candidate. I am not suggesting that Maine de Biran was somehow inherently reactionary, although his politics can be characterized as conservative. Like many of the ideologues he was a public figure for large parts of his adult life. For most of the period of Napoleon's rule he was an administrator and a representative in national assemblies, although he, again like them, came to oppose the emperor. He was once more active under the restored monarchy. It is possible to argue that his philosophy was consonant with a more authoritarian approach in general and that his emphasis on the spiritual aspects of human existence supported more than an introspective approach, it actively encouraged ideas of distinct levels some of which (God, the life of the spirit, the will) were 'higher' than others. The authoritarian response manifested itself in a number of forms - some of which were closely linked with 'Romanticism' (Porter and Teich 1988: esp. 240-59). It is important to recognize that there were major differences of opinion among those we identify as the principal exponents of the position (Beik 1970). There was, for example, no consensus on the merits of Napoleon's rule, on the role an aristocracy should assume, on the precise form monarchy should take; nor was there agreement on what the principal causes of Revolutionary turmoil were, although many commentators saw the Enlightenment ~a major, if not the sale cause. That they possessed highly individual perspectives on philosophical, religious, and political matters in no way undermines my analysis of their shared position as influential exponents of the belief that clear, transcendent authority was indispensable to the well-being of human society. A revealing, if idiosyncratic example of the cult of authority is Chateaubriand (1768-1848) - noble, royalist, and romantic writer... Chateaubriand's memoirs (1849) provide eloquent testimony to his reactions to the revolution, while his famous Genie du Christianisme (1802), Iwhich came at a strategic moment in France's relationship with the Papacy, was an \enormousl y influential statement of the inspirational power of religious belief. As a \writer of extraordinary emotional energy, he was able to present many different 'aspects of the need for authority - a prominent argument in Genie is that adoration bf the deity brings aesthetic rewards.
The authoritarian response 211 We can contrast the picture of the satisfaction afforded by Christianity, which Chateaubriand painted in Genie, with the painful one of the Revolution in his memoirs: The Revolution would have carried me with it if only it had not begun with a series of crimes: I saw the first head carried on the end of a pike and I recoiled. In my eyes murder will never be an object ofadmiration or an argument for freedom; I know of nothing more servile, contemptible, cowardly, and stupid than a terrorist. ... On 14 July came the fall of the Bastille.... In the midst of these murders, the mob indulged in wild orgies.... The 'victors of the Bastille', happy drunkards declared conquerors by their boon companions, were driven through the streets in hackney carriages; prostitutes and sans-culottes, who were at the beginning of their reign, acted as their escort.... I was standing at the window of my hotel with my sisters and some Breton acquaintances when we heard shouts of 'Bolt the doors, bolt the doors!' Atroop of ragamuffins appeared at one end of the street. As they came nearer, we made out two dishevelled and disfigured heads The murderers stopped in front of me and stretched the pikes up towards me, singing, dancing, and jumping up in order to bring the pale effigies closer to my face. One eye in one of these heads had started out of its socket and was hanging down on the dead man's face; the pike was projecting through the open mouth, the teeth of which were biting on the iron.... If I had had a gun, I should have fired at those wretches as at a pack of wolves. They howled with fury.... Those heads, and others which I saw soon afterwards, changed my political tendencies; I was horried by these cannibal feasts.... (Baldick 1965: 121, 127, 128-9) I have quoted from Chateaubriand at length in order to convey the powerful manner in which he builds up an image of Revolution as terror that serves his larger purposes. He deploys two main strategies; the use of a specific vocabulary that generates an emotional response and the selection of episodes in the Revolution as emblematic of the process as a whole. He does indeed achieve his principal goal- to shock his readers into an instinctive revulsion, but the precise way in which this is accomplished is significant. Fragmentation of an entire society as well as of individual bodies is a major theme. The sev(~red head does an enormous amount of work here by allowing us to move from bodily mutilation to political chaos. The chaos, which is specifically associated with the mob, has a quite particular set of characteristics: it is criminal, bestial, and sexual. Both literal and metaphorical promiscuity are at issue here. And, the ultimate accusation is that of cannibalism. The mob, according to Chateaubriand, is no longer human, it is less than human since it carries out the worst transgressions that we can imagine. The Revolutionary processes were filthy and chaotic, how then could France be cleansed and organized? There were a number of responses to this question, which was felt to be an extremely urgent one by many members of that society. There were political,
212 Ludmilla lordanova
- -__
_
Ifr~(I.t)""'M "rwitW'tU,hIt"~~.
f:.P~f:lrul{._d!!~or~01U~t'lIM/~~W·Prin;:
FmlLJ~trVf't(:n..NhJ/~,,"y...- .
'lJ".:.~b.u.!f1"D(!fS~ol~,iIUDuJ".'
; ·'If,).·'!' ,.~\·,.Ii,,' l,~~,' "",F~;';.
~
_
8~I/.01flvhaJl4(J..~.J,./J.,
23 'Dismembering was a process that, in Gillray's imagination, had combined with Vergniaud's notorious prophecy that the Revolution would devour its own children and with the French engraving Le Peupfe mangeur de rois, showing Hercules as a sanscufotte wearing a liberty cap while cooking a noble-man over a Roman fire preparatory to eating him. In a print of 1792, Un Petit Souper, afa parisienne. .. Gillray projects beheading into devourment; the public feasts on the dismembered bodies of aristocrats and, by implication, of all civilized Englishmen and women' (Paulson 1988: 60).
Figure
religious, and philosophical responses, and what they had in common was authoritarian elements. Napoleon, to take the most obvious example, saw his destiny as providing a political solution to what he saw as 'the spirit offaction', 'the disorder' of the 1790s, since these were 'hurling the nation into an abyss from which the time has at last come to rescue it, once and for all' (Thompson 1934: 81). In concrete terms, this strategy took a number of forms; the gathering of military and political power to himself, eventually as an hereditary ruler, the elaboration of a highly structured administrative apparatus to serve his needs, the imposition of the famous Napoleonic codes, which, among other things, asserted the rights of the husband! father within the family, and the pursuit of an imperialist project (Bergeron 1981). Furthermore, Napoleon was far from being liberal when it came to intellectual
The authoritarian response 213 matters. He discouraged dissent, and most famously in 1803 he abolished the Second Class of the Institut National, the home of the ideologues, many of whom had welcomed his political participation in the early days, but who became increasingly disenchanted as his tyrannical aspects and meglomaniac aspirations emerged. An equally revealing parallel response was the development of 'traditionalist' philosophy (Dunning 1920: ch. 5; Copleston 1975: 1-18; Bergeron 1981: ch. 8; Reedy 1983). Here was an attempt to generate a coherent philosophical reaction to both the Revolution and to the Enlightenment that had given birth to it. In place of faction, the traditionalists wanted organic unity, instead of a social contract, they asked for a divinely sanctioned political order uniting God and monarch. Order was God-given, not made by human beings; accordingly, notions like the sovereignty of the people and democracy represented monstrous detours from a true path. Religion and politics should be reunited, they felt. What this entailed was, among other things, recouping the idea of revelation as able to do important philosophical work. Not only is revelation the ultimate source of authority, but there is also here a dramatic claim about the acquisition of knowledge in general. The traditionalists attacked Bacon and the scientific traditions indebted to him, and they attacked sensualism for its denial of innate ideas. In place of a view of knowledge as acquired by human effort through processes that could be understood, they substituted the idea of knowledge as, ultimately, a gift from God. Accordingly order, of all different kinds, is given from on high, not acquired from below. One' of the most important exponents of this position was Joseph de Maistre (1754-1821), a conservative Catholic monarchist, who saw the Enlightenment as the direct begetter of Revolution (Lively 1965; Lebrun 1969; Beik 1970: 62-72). For him the Revolution was 'satanic', it was a time of 'orgies', and the philosophes who unleashed it could be deemed the cause of murders, they were 'monsters' and 'scoundrels' (Church 1964: 15, 19, 20). The accusations of moral depravity are indeed striking, not least in the similarity they bear to Chateaubriand's. Of course, they partly served a rhetorical purpose to heighten the split between the Revolution and what should succeed it - if the former can be made all bad, the goodness of the latter can emerge more vividly. But if a traditionalist response was to convince, it had to do more than denounce the Revolution and the philosophes, it had to generate a fresh and compelling account of political ~and social order. For de Maistre one of the main routes for doing so was rethinking the nature of sovereignty, a project he was already engaged in by the mid-1790s. Maistre clearly needed to undermine the radical implications that emanated from the sovereignty of the people, since these served to negate the overarching character of divine power. At the same time he recognized that God acts through people and not supernaturally when it comes to the social and political order. For him, God 'has willed society, he has willed also the sovereignty and laws without which there would be no society' (Lively 1965: 94) and hence secular order derives ultimately from divine will. It further followed that ideas like the state of nature and the social contract were completely misleading. God made people sociable, and he made them
214 Ludmilla Jordanova
Figure 24 'Recognizing the value of art as propaganda. Bonaparte commissioned highly idealized images of himself in various media. In addition, portrait busts, such as those of Napoleon as first consul, were widely disseminated through prints, as well as on medallions and coins. [This print], by an unknown artist, commemorates Bonaparte's appointment in 1802 as first consul for life. The remarkable image transfigures the young, almost innocent, general into a mystical sign, a "lucky star" or apparition that has appeared in the heavens to guide the fate of the French' (based on Cuno 1988: 271-2).
into nations: 'The same power that has decreed social order and sovereignty has also decreed different modifications of sovereignty according to the different character of nations. . .. The Creator has traced on the globe the limits of nations... .' (Lively 1965: 99). Thus, nations have character traits similar to human beings, and enjoy a kind of organic unity. Each nation has its own appropriate form of government, which cannot therefore be derived from abstract general principles, but which is God-given and natural. We may notice at this point how de Maistre is bringing together diverse kinds of power and treating them all as properly deriving from God's will. Maistre's invocation of nature in the service of his argument is instructive. Indeed, in doing so, he was employing a standard device of Enlightenment writers for
The authoritarian response 215 invoking authority, but for quite different ends: 'the aristocracy is a sovereign or ruling class by nature, and the principle of the French Revolution runs directly contrary to the eternal laws of nature' (Lively 1965: 105). Such a claim is consistent with the accusations of evil, monstrosity, and depravity that he made against the philosophes, and with his distrust of reason. When people attempt to be the architects of societies, they betray exactly that false pride, shallow self-confidence, and disrespect for the true laws of God and nature of which the Enlightenment was so often accused. In his own way Maistre is exploring the problem we associate with Frankenstein and with Faust. One of the main props of de Maistre's view of sovereignty is the importance of unity: 'However sovereignty is defined and vested, it is always one, unviolable and absolute' (Lively 1965: 112). Interestingly enough, this is quite compatible with one of the cornerstones of Revolutionary thought - the unity of the nation. It would therefore be mistaken to assume that Revolution and tradition were always polar opposites. We can see the desire for a comforting wholeness in some of the 'sacred laws' that de Maistre enumerated. These included '1. The king is sovereign; no one can share sovereignty with him, and all powers emanate from him', and '2. His person is inviolable; no one has the right to depose or judge him' (117). The essence of such 'laws' is that they are not derived from human reason, but 'are written only in men's hearts, and more particularly in the paternal relationship between prince and subjects' (117, my emphasis). In de Maistre's work we can see how the familiar battlelines are clearly drawn. On the side of Revolution and the Enlightenment we have reason, abstraction, hubris, faction, chaos, depravity, and artificially constructed societies, while on the side of order and monarchy we find moral feelings, faith, unity, and cohesion, clear and transcendent sources of power, the divine will, and 'nature'. In the first the people themselves try, profanely, to construct an ordered society; while in the second, God, working with monarchs, the aristocracy, and the Church, creates the ~ocial and political order. By taking a number of prominent thinkers we can see more readily the ways in which the Enlightenment was reified and then used in a specific historical setting as a vehicle for debating wide and deep questions about order and authority. These debates were symptomatic of a larger crisis. Itfwas not only savants who perceived and tried to conceptualize an unstable situation, although their views are of additional interest because of both their active participation in a number of regimes and their attempts to produce coherent reactions to social and conceptual change. These conflicts were felt by the populace too. We know, for example, that women of the people quickly turned against the anti-Catholic fervour of the Revolution; they tried to clean churches, to atone for profane acts, to continue traditional worship, and to support their priests (Hufton 1971). When dealt with at an intellectual level, the Enlightenment, the Revolution, and the reactions against them all appeared more clear-cut than they were in reality. To an extent, this was inevitable. After all, a battle of words, images, and symbols had been enjoined, and all protagonists wanted to effect a moral polarization for their own rhetorical purposes.
216 Ludmilla Jordanova In referring to rhetoric I do not mean to trivialize in any way the shadows constructed by writers who epitomize the authoritarian response. After all, we know the Enlightenment through the successive versions of it constructed by generations of commentators. The version produced at the end of the eighteenth century has special interest. The Enlightenment that was invented in the wake of the Revolution arose at a momentous turning point in European history. There was both a freshness and a rawness in responses to the Enlightenment during this period, because it was felt with such intensity that this movement had cast deeply threatening shadows. By examining the shadows they experienced we arrive at a better understanding of the Enlightenment itself, because these two elements, although their .forms may change, remain inseparable.
References
Adorno, Theodor and Horkheimer, Max (1979) Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. John Cumming, London. Agulhon, Maurice (1981) Marianne into Battle: Republican Imagery and Symbolism in France: 1789-1880, trans. Janet Lloyd, Carrlbridge. Aldridge, Alfred (1959) Man of Reason. The Life of Thomas Paine, London. Allison, Lincoln (1984) Right Principles: A Conservative Philosophy of Politics, Oxford. Amadas, Philip and Barlow, Arthur (1903-5) 'The first voyage made to the coast of Virginia'. In Richard Hakluyt (ed.) The Principal Navigations, Voyages, Traffiques & Discoveries of the English Nation, Glasgow, VIII: 297-309. Amnesty International (1986) 'All of this we owe to you', public statement. Anderson, Perry (1966) 'Origins of the present crisis'. In Perry Anderson and Robin Blackburn (eds) Towards Socialism, London: 11-52. Anthony, James (1973) French Baroque Music from Beaujoyeulx to Rameau, London Arendt, Hannah (1973) On Revolution, Harmondsworth. Ashcraft, Richard (1968) 'Locke's state of nature: historical fact or moral fiction?', American Political Science Review 62: 898-915. - - (1969) 'Political theory and political reform: John Locke's essay on Virginia', Western Political Quarterly 22: 742-58. - - (1972) 'Leviathan triumphant: Thomas Hobbes and the politics of wild men'. In (eds) Edward Dudley and Maximilian Novak, The Wild Man Within: An Image in Western Thought from the Renaissance to Romanticism, Pittsburgh: 141-82. - - (1986) Revolutionary Politics and John Locke's 'Two Treatises of Government', Princeton. - - (1987) Locke's Two Treatises of Government, London. Atkinson, Geoffroy (1955) Les Nouveaux horizons de la Renaissance franr;aise, Paris. Auerbach, Erich (1953) Mimesis, trans. Willard R. Trask, Princeton. Bacon, Francis (1960) The New Organon and Related Writings, ed. Fulton Anderson, New York. Baldick, Robert (ed.) (1965) The Memoirs of Chateaubriand, Harmondsworth. Batz, William G. (1974) 'The historical anthropology of John Locke', Journal ofthe History of Ideas 35: 663-70. Baxandall, Michael (1985) Patterns of Intention: On the Historical Explanation of Pictures, London.
218 References Bedard, Leon (1903) Sebastien Mercier: sa vie, son oeuvre, son temps, Paris. Beik, Paul H. (1970) The French Revolution Seen from the Right. Social Theories in Motion, 1789-1799, New York. Bentham, Jeremy (1962) 'Anarchical fallacies'. In The Works of Jeremy Bentham, ed. 1. Bowring, vol. 2, New York: 491-524. Bergeron, Louis (1981) France Under Napoleon, Princeton. Berkhofer, Robert F., Jr (1978) The White Man's Indian: Images ofthe Amen·can Indian from Columbus to the Present, New York. Bernstein, Jay (1984a) 'From self-consciousness to community: act and recognition in the master-slave relationship'. In Z. A. Pelczynski (ed.) The State and Civil Society, Cambridge: 14~39.
, - - (1984b) The Philosophy of the Novel: Lukacs, Marxism, and the Dialectics of Fonn, Brighton. Bernstein, Richard (1986) 'Mlle Liberte: does she say the same thing in her native tongue?', New York Times, 18 May, section 6, part II: 66-8, 70-2. Best, Geoffrey (1988a) 'The French Revolution and human rights'. In Geoffrey Best (ed.) The Pennanent Revolution. The French Revolution and its Legacy 1789-1989, London: 101-27. - - (1988b) The Pennanent Revolution. The French Revolution and its Legacy 1789-1989, London. Bitterli, Drs (1989) Cultures in Conflict. Encounters between European and Non-European Cultures, .1492-1800, trans. Ritchie Robertson, Cambridge. Bloch, Ruth H. (1987) 'The gendered meanings of virtue in Revolutionary America', Signs 13: 37-58. Boime, Albert (1971) 'The Second Republic's contest for the figure of the Republic', Art Bulletin, 53:1, 70-83. Bonney, Richard (1987) 'Absolutism: what's in a name?', French History 1: 93-117. Boulton, J. T. (1963) The Language of Politics in the Age of Wilkes and Burke, London. Brotherston, Gordon (1979) Image of the New World: the American Continent portrayed in Native Texts, London. - - (1982) 'The Republican calendar: A diagnostic of the French Revolution'. In Francis Barker et al. (eds) 1789: Reading Writing Revolution, Colchester: I-II. - - (1985) 'The Prairie and Cooper's invention of the West'. In Robert Clark (ed.) James Fenimore Cooper: New Critical Essays, London. - - (1986) 'Towards a grammatology of America: Levi-Strauss, Derrida and the native new world'. In Francis Barker et al. (eds) Literature Politics and Theory, London: 190-209. Brownlie, I. (ed.) (1981) Basic Documents on Human Rights, Oxford. Bruckner, Pascal (1986) The Tears of the l¥hite Man: Comparison as Contempt, trans. William R. Beer, New York. Bnlmfitt, J. H. (1966) Voltaire. Selected Writings, London. Bryson, Norman (1981) Word and Image: French Painting ofthe Ancien Regime, Cambridge. Bulkley, Rev. John (1725) 'Preface' to Roger Wolcott, Poetical Meditations, New London, i-Ivi.
Burke, Edmund (n.d.) The Writings and Speeches of Edmund Burke, vol. V, London. - - (1958) A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and the Beautiful [1756], ed. J. T. Boulton, London. - - (1961) The Correspondence of Edmund Burke, vol. III, ed. G. H. Gutteridge, Cambridge. - - (1968a) Reflections on the Revolution in France [1790], ed. Conor Cruise O'Brien, Harmondsworth. - - (1968b) Selected Wn·tings and Speeches, ed. P. J. Stanlis, Gloucester, Mass.
References 219 Bury, J. B. (1955) The Idea of Progress [1920], New York. Butler, Melissa A. (1978) 'Early liberal roots of feminism: John Locke and the attack on patriarchy', American Political Science Review 72: 135-50. Cassirer. Ernst (1951) The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, Princeton. Castle, Terry (1986) Masquerade and Civilization: The Carnivalesque in Eighteenth-Century English Culture and Fiction, Stanford. Charlton, Donald G. (1984) New Images of the Natural in France, Cambridge. Charvet. John (1974) The Social Problem in the Philosophy of Rousseau, Carrlbridge. Chateaubriand, Fran~ois Rene de (1802) Genie du Christianisme, 5 vols, Paris. - - (1973) Memoires d'Outre-Tombe [18491, Vol. 1, Paris. Chinard, Gilbert (1913) L'Amerique et Ie reve exotique dans la litterature franc;aise au xvii et au xviii siecle, Paris. Chitnis, A. C. (1976) The Scottish Enlightenment: A Social History, London. Church, William F. (ed.) (1964) The Influence ofthe Enlightenment on the French Revolution. Creative, Disastrous or Non-Existent?, Lexington, Mass. Clark, T. J. (1973) The Absollite Bourgeois: Artists and Politics in France 1848-1851, London. Cohen, I. B. (1980) Album of Science. From Leonardo to Lavoisier 1450-1800, New York. Coleman, Patrick (1984) Rousseau's Political Imagination, Geneva. Coleridge, Samuel Taylor (1976) On the Constitution ofthe Church and State [1830], ed. John Colmer, London. Connolly, William E. (1988) Political Theory and Modernity, Oxford. Copleston, Frederick (1975) A History of Philosophy. Volume IX: Maine de Biran to Sartre, London. Corrigan, Paul and Sayer, Derek (1985) The Great Arch: English State Formation as Cultural Revolution, Oxford. Cranston, Maurice (1957) John Locke: A Biography, London. Crocker, Lester (ed.) (1969) The Age of Enlightenment, London. Crow, Thomas E. (1985) Painters and Public Life in Eighteenth-Century Paris, New Haven. Cuno, James (ed.) (1988) French Caricature and the French Revolution, Los Angeles. Dante Alighieri (1949) The Divine Comedy: 1, Hell, trans. Dorothy Sayers, Harmondsworth. Daubie, Christian (1972) 'Cyrus Ie grand: un precurseur dans Ie domaine des droits de l'homme', Human Rights Journal 5: 293-304. Davies, G. E. (1981) The Scottish Enlightenment, London. Davis, Ralph (1973) The Rise of the Atlantic Economies, London. Dent, N. J. H. (1988) Rousseau, Oxford. Derrida, Jacques (1975) Of Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Chakravorty-cSpivak, Baltimore. Descartes, Rene (1897-1913) Oeuvres, 12 vols, Paris. - - (1970) Philosophical Writings, ed. Elizabeth Anscombe and Peter Gooch, London. - - (1985) The Philosophical Writings ofDescartes, vol. I, trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothof, and Dugald Murdoch, Cambridge. Diderot, Denis (1956) Rameau's Nephew and Other Writings, ed. Jacques Barzun and Ralph H. Bowen, Garden City, NY. - - (1967) The Encyclopedia: Selections, ed. and trans. Stephen J. Gendzier, New York. Diderot, Denis and Jean d'Alembert (eds) (1969) Encyclopedie, ou Dictionnaire raisonne des sciences, des arts et des metiers [1751-80], 5 vols., New York. Domenach, J.-M. (1989) 'Interrogations'. In 1989: Les Droits de l'homme en questions, Commission Nationale Consultative Des Droits de L'Homme, Paris: 21-4. Donne, John (1959) 'A sermon preached to the Honourable Company of the Virginian Plantation. 13 November 1722', in The Sermons of John Donne, ed. George Potter and Evelyn Simpson, vol. IV, Berkeley: 264-82.
220 References Doyle, William (1989) The Oxford History of the French Revolution, Oxford. Duchet, Michele (1971) Anthropologie et histoire au siecle des lumieres, Paris. Dudley, Edward and Novak, Maximilian (eds) (1972) The Wild Man JlIithin: An Image in Western Thought from the Renaissance to Romanticism, Pittsburgh. Dunn, John (1969) 'The politics of Locke in England and America'. In John W. Yolton (ed.) John Locke: Problems and Perspectives, Cambridge: 45-80. Dunning, William A. (1920) A History of Political Theories from Rousseau to Spencer, New York. Durkheim, Emile (1964) The Division ofLabour in Society [1933], trans. William G. Simpson, New York. Du Tertre, Jean-Baptiste (1667) Histoire generale des Antilles habites par les Franr;ais, 3 vols, Paris. Dworkin, Ronald (1977) Taking Rights Seriously, London. Eames, Wilberforce (1922) 'Description of a wood engraving illustrating the South American indians (1505)', Bulletin of the New York Public Library XXVI: 755-60. Eden, Richard (1885) The Decades ofthe newe world. In Edward Arber (ed.) The First Three English Books on America, Birmingham. Eisinger, Chester E. (1948) 'The puritans' justification for taking the land', Essex Institute Historical Collection LXXXIV: 131-43. Eitner, Lorenz (1971) Neoclassicism and Romanticism 1750-1850, London. Les Etudes Philosophiques (1982) no. 1 (special issue on Maine de Biran and the ideologues). Ferguson, Adam (1966) An Essay on the History of Civil Society [1767], Edinburgh. - - (1975) Pn'nciples of Moral and Political Science [1792], 2 vols, Hildesheim. Figlio, Karl (1975) 'Theories of perception and the physiology of mind in the late eighteenth century', History of Science 12: 177-212. - - (1976) 'The metaphor of organisation: a historiographical perspective on the biomedical sciences of the early nineteenth century', History of Science 14: 17-53. Forbes, Jack D. (1988) Black Africans and Native Amen'cans, Oxford. Foucault, Michel (1984) 'What is Enlightenment?'. In Paul Rabinow (ed.) The Foucault Reader, Harmondsworth: 32-50. - - (1986) 'Kant on Enlightenment and Revolution', Economy and Society XV: 88-95. Frankfurt, Harry (1971) 'Freedom of the will and the concept of a person', Journal of Philosophy LXVIII: 5-20. Franklin, Wayne (1979) Discoverers, Explorers, Settlers: The Diligent JlIriters of Early Amen'ca, Chicago. Frantz, Pierre (1988) 'Heurs et malheurs de l' ecriture: "Le nouveau Paris" de Mercier', Litterature 69: 100-10. Freeman, Michael (1980) Edmund Burke and the Critique of
References 221 Grimsley, Ronald (ed.) (1979) The Age of Enlightenment 1715-1789, Harmondsworth. Gusdorf, Georges (1978) La Consciences revolutionnaire. Les ideologues, Paris. Habermas, Jurgen (1986) 'Foucault's lecture on Kant', Thesis Eleven 14: 4-8. - - (1987) The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, trans. Frederick Lawrence, Cambridge. Haley, K. H. D. (1968) The First Earl of Shaftesbury, Oxford. Hall, Stuart (1988) The Hard Road to Renewal, London. Hallie, Phillip P. (1959) Maine de Biran. Reformer of Empiricism 1766-1824, Cambridge, Mass. Hampson, Norman (1968) The Enlightenment, Harmondsworth. - - (1983) Will and Circumstance: Montesquieu, Rousseau and the French Revolution,
Norman, Oklahoma. Harrison, John and Laslett, Peter (1971) The Library of John Locke, Oxford. Hartog, Frant;ois (1988) The Mirror of Herodotus: The Representation of the Other in the Writing of History, trans. Janet Lloyd, Berkeley. Hay, Denys (1957) Europe: The Emergence of an Idea, Edinburgh. Hazard, Paul (1973) The European Mind 1680-1715[19351, trans. 1. Lewis May, Harmondsworth. - - (1963) European Thought in the Eighteenth Century [19461, trans. J. Lewis May, Cleveland. Hegel, G. F. W. (1977) Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller, Oxford. Heine, Heinrich (1978) Zur Geschichte der Religion und Philosophie [18341, Werke, vol. 5, Berlin. Hemming, John (1978) The Search for El Dorado, London. Herding, Klaus (1988) 'Visual codes in the graphic art of the French Revolution'. In James Cuno (ed.) French Caricature and the French Revolution, 1789-1799, Los Angeles: 83-102.
Hertz, Neil (1985) The End of the Line: Essays on Psychoanalysis and the Sublime, New York. Higonnet, P. (1988) Sister Republics: The Origins of French and Amen'can Republicanism, Cambridge. Hobbes, Thomas (1840) 'Tripos; in three discourses'. In William Molesworth (ed.) The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, vol. IV, London: 1-278. - - (1968) Leviathan[16511, ed. C. B. Macpherson, Harmondsworth. - - (1972) Man and Citizen [translation of De Cive (1642)], ed. Bernard Gert, Garden City, NY. Hobsbawm, Eric (1978) 'Man and woman in socialist iconography', History Workshop 6: 121-38.
Hodgen, Margaret T. (1971) Early Anthropology in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, Philadelphia. Hovannisian, R. G. (ed.) (1986) The Armenian Genocide in Perspective, New Brunswick. Hufton, Olwen (1971) 'Women in revolution 1789-1796', Past and Present 53: 90-108. Hulme, Peter (1986) Colonial Encounters: Europe and the Native Caribbean, 1492-1797, London. Hume, David (1963) Essays Moral, Political and Literary [1741-21, Oxford. Hunt, Lynn (1983) 'Hercules and the radical image in the French Revolution', Represen· tations 1 (2): 95-117. - - (1984) Politics, Culture and Class in the French Revolution, Berkeley. Huxley, Aldous (1954) Themes and Variations, London. Idzerda, Stanley 1. (1954) 'Iconoclasm and the French Revolution', American Historical Review 60: 13-26.
222
References
Isherwood, Robert (1973) Music in the Service ofthe King: France in the Seventeenth Century, Ithaca, NY. Jennings, Francis (1976) The Invasion of America: Indians, Colonialism, and the Cant of Conquest, New York. Jones, P. (1989) 'Re-examining rights', British Journal of Political Science 19: 69-96. Jordanova, Ludmilla (1989) Sexual Visions: Images of Gender in Science and Medicine between the Eighteenth and Twentieth Centuries, London. Kant, Immanuel (1933) Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith, London. - - (1949) 'What is orientation in thinking?', trans. L. W. Beck in Kant's Critique of Practical Reason and other Writings on Moral Philosophy, Chicago: 293-305. - - (1953) Groundwork ofthe Metaphysic ofMorals, trans. H. 1. Paton (as The Moral Law). London. - - (1970) 'An answer to the question "What is Enlightenment?''', trans. H. B. Nisbet. In H. Reiss (ed.) Kant's Political Writings, Cambridge: 54-60. - - (1977) Critique of Practical Reason, trans. L. W. Beck, Indianapolis. - - (1978) The Critique of Judgment, trans. James Meredith, Oxford. Kettler, D. (1965) The Social and Political Thought of Adam Ferguson, Ohio. Koselleck, Reinhart (1988) Critique and Crisis: Enlightenment and the Pathogenesis of Modern Society [19591, Oxford. Kosman, L. Aryeh (1986) 'The naive narrator: meditation in Descartes' Meditations'. In Amelie Okseberg Rorty (ed.) Essays on Descartes' Meditations, Berkeley: 21-43. Kumar, Krishnan (1987) Utopia and Anti-Utopia in Modern Times, Oxford. Laclau, Ernesto and Mouffe, Chantal (1985) Hegemony and Socialist Strategy, London. Lafitau, Joseph-Franyois (1983) Moeurs des sauvages americains comparees aux moeurs des premiers temps [17241, ed. Edna Hindie Lemay, 2 vols, Paris. Lahontan, Baron de (1905) New Voyages to North America [17031, ed. R. G. Thwaites, 2 vols, Chicago. Laslett, Peter (1965) 'Introduction' to John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, New York: 15-168.
Lebovics, Herman (1986) 'The uses of America in Locke's Second Treatise of Government, Journal of the History of Ideas 47: 567-81.
Lebrun, Richard (1969) 'Joseph de Maistre, Cassandra of science', French Historical Studies 6: 214-31.
Lefort, C. (1981) 'Droits de l'homme et politique', in L'Invention democratique: les limites de la domination, Paris: 45-83. Lery, Jean de (1975) Histoire d'un voyage faite en la terre du Bri?,sil [15781, Geneva. Levin, Harry (1972) The Myth of the Golden Age in the Renaissance, New York. Levi-Strauss, Claude (1976) Tristes Tropiques, trans. John and Doreen Weightman, Harmondsworth. Libaridian, G. (ed.) (1985) A Crime of Silence: The Armenian Genocide: The Permanent People's Tribunal, London. Liberty: The French-American Statue in Art and History (1986) Exhibition Catalogue, The New York Public Library, New York. Lindley, Richard (1986) Autonomy, London. Lively, Jack (ed.) (1965) The Works of Joseph de Maistre, London. Locke, John (1958) Essays on the Law of Nature, ed. W. von Leyden, Oxford. - - (1965) Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett, New York. Lukes, Steven (1973) Individualism, Oxford. - - (1985) Marxism and Morality, Oxford.
References 223 Lyotard, Jean-Frant;ois (1984) The Post-Modem Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans. Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi, Manchester. Mace, D. T. (1964) 'Musical humanism, the doctrine of rhythmus, and the St Cecilia odes of Dryden', Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes XXVII: 251-92. MacIntyre, Alisdair (1981) After Virtue, Notre Dame. Macpherson, C. B. (1962) The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism, Oxford. - - (1980) Burke, Oxford. McRae, D. (1969) 'Adam Ferguson 1723-1816'. In D. McRae (ed.) The Founding Fathers of Social Science, Harmondsworth. Majewski, Henry F. (1971) The Preromantic Imagination of L.-s. Mercier, New York. Malcolm, Noel (1981) 'Hobbes, Sandys, and the Virginia Company', The Historical Journal 24: 297-321. Maniates, Maria (1969) '''Sonate, que me veux-tu?": the enigma of French musical aesthetics in the eighteenth century', Current Musicology IX: 117-40. Manuel, Frank and Manuel, Fritzie (1979) Utopian Thought in the Western World, Oxford. Marin, Louis (1988) Portrait of the King, London. Marshall, P. 1. and Glyndwr Williams (1982) The Great Map ofMankind: British Perceptions of the World in the Age of Enlightenment, London. Marx, Karl (1978) 'On the Jewish question' [18431. In Robert C. Tucker (ed.) The Marx-Engels Reader, 2nd edition, New York: 26-52. Masters, Roger D. (1969) The Political Philosophy of Rousseau, Princeton. Meek, Ronald (1954) 'The Scottish contribution to Marxist sociology'. In John Saville (ed.) Democracy and the Labour Movement, London: 84-102. - - (1976) Social Science and the Ignoble Savage, Cambridge. Mercier, Louis-Sebastien [17971 Le Nouveau Paris, 6 vols, Paris. - - (1772) Memoirs of the Year Two Thousand Five Hundred, trans. W. Hooper, M. D., 2 vols, London. - - (1773) Du Theatre ou Nouvel essai sur ['art dramatique, Amsterdam. - - (1781-8) Le Tableau de Paris, 6 vols, Paris. - - (1787) L'An deux mille quatre cent quarante, reve s'il en fut jamais [17861, 3 vols, Neufchatel. - - (1791) De J. J. Rousseau considere comme ['un des premiers auteurs de la Revolution franr;aise, 2 vols, Paris. - - (1971) L'An deux mille quatre cent quarante, reve s'il en fut jamais [17711, ed. Raymond Trousson, Bordeaux. Mersenne, Marin (1623) Quaestiones celeberrimae in genesim, Paris. - - (1634) Quaestiones harmonique, Paris. - - (1636) L'Harmonie universelle contenant la theorie et la pratique de la musique, 3 vols, Paris. • - - (1932-72) Correspondance, 12 vols, Paris. - - (1957) The Books of the Instruments [16361, trans. Roger Chapman, London. Michels, Roberto (1948) 'Authority', Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, ed. Edwin R. A. Seligman, New York I: 319-21. Milne, A. J. (1986) Human Rights and Human Diversity, London. Moliere, Jean-Baptiste (1953) Le Bourgeois Gentilhomme [1670], trans. John Wood, Harmondsworth. Monselet, Charles (1857) Les Oublies et les dMaignes, 2 vols, Alent;on. Montaigne, Michel de (1928) The Essayes ofMichael Lord of Montaigne, trans. John Florio, 3 vols, London.
224 References Montesquieu, Baron de (1949) The Spirit of the Laws [1748], trans. T. Nugent, New York. --(1973) Persian Letters [1721], trans. C. J. Betts, Harmondsworth. Moore, Francis C. T. (1970) The Psychology of Maine de Biran, Oxford. Moravia, Sergio (1980) 'The Enlightenment and the Sciences of Man', History of Science 18: 247-68. Mornet, Daniel (1967) Les Origines intellectuelles de la Revolution franr;aise [1933], 6th edn, Paris. Morsink, J. (1984) 'The philosophy of the Universal Declaration', Human Rights Quarterly 6: 309-34. Mumford, Lewis (1962) The Story of Utopias [1922], New York. Murdoch, Iris (1970) The Sovereignty of Good, London. Nochlin, Linda (1981), review of M. Agulhon, Man'anne au Combat, Oxford Art Journal, 4 (1): 62-4. O'Brien, Conor Cruise (1988) 'Nationalism and the French Revolution'. In G. Best (ed.) The Permanent Revolution: The French Revolution and its Legacy, 1789-1989, London: 17-48. O'Neill, Onora (1986) Faces of Hunger, London. - - (1989) Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy, Cambridge. Outram, Dorinda (1987) 'Le Langage male de la vertu: women and the discourse of the French Revolution'. In Roy Porter and Peter Burke (eds) The Social History ofLanguage, Cambridge: 120-35. ' - - (1989) The Body and the French Revolution. Sex, Class and Political Culture, New Haven. Ozouf, Mona (1988) Festivals and the French Revolution, Cambridge, Mass. Pagden, Anthony (1983) 'The savage critic: some European images of the primitive', The Yearbook of English Studies 13: 32-45. Paine, Tom (1969) The Rights of Man, Harmondsworth. Pateman, Carole (1988) The Sexual Contract, Cambridge. Paul, E. F., Miller, F. D. Jr, and Paul, 1. (eds) (1984) Human Rights, Oxford. Paulson, Ronald (1983) Representations of Revolution (1789-1820), New Haven. - - (1988) 'The severed head: the impact of French revolutionary caricatures on England'. In James Cuno (ed.) French Caricature and the French Revolution, 1789-1799, Los Angeles: 55-65. Peabody, R. (1968) 'Authority', International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, ed. David L. Sills, New York I: 473-7. Pearce, Roy Harvey (1988) Savagism and Civilization: A Study of the Indian and the American Mind [1953], Berkeley, California. Perrault, Charles (1964) Parallele des anciens et des modernes en ce qui regarde les arts et les sciences [1688-97], Munich. Pickstone, John V. (1981) 'Bureaucracy, liberalism and the body in post-revolutionary France: Bichat's physiology and the Paris school of medicine', History of Science 19: 115-42. Pilkington, Anthony E. (1986) '''Nature'' as an ethical norm in the Enlightenment'. In Ludmilla Jordanova (ed.) Languages of Nature, London: 51-85. Pointon, Marcia (1986) 'Liberty on the barricades: politics, power and the erotic in Delacroix', Ideas and Production 5: 80-103. Pollard, Sidney (1971) The Idea of Progress, Harmondsworth. Porter, Roy and Teich, Mikulas (eds) (1981) The Enlightenment in National Context, Cambridge. - - (1988) Romanticism in National Context, Cambridge. Prevost, Abbe (1746-70) Histoire generale des Voyages, 19 vols, Paris.
References 225 Purchas, Samuel (1905-7) 'Virginia's verger' [1625J. In Purchas His Pilgn'mes, 20 vols, Glasgow XIX: 218-67. Racek, Jan (1930) 'Contribution au probleme de l'esthetique musicale chez Rene Descartes', La Revue Musicale II, 109: 289-301. Raynal, Guillaume Fran~ois Thomas (1776) A Philosophical and Political History of the Settlements and Trade ofthe Europeans in the East and West Indies, trans. J. J. Justamond, 5 vols, London. Raynaud, P. (1988) 'La declaration des droits de l'homme'. In C. Lucas (ed.) The Political Culture of the French Revolution, Oxford: 139-49. Ree, Jonathan (1987) Philosophical Tales, London. Reedy, W. Jay (1981) 'Burke and Bonald: paradigms of late eighteenth-century conservatism', Historical Reflections 8: 69-93. - - (1983) 'Language, counter-revolution and the "two cultures": Bonald's traditionalist scientism', Journal of the History of Ideas 44: 579-97. Reid, C. (1985) Edmund Burke and the Practice of Political Writing, New York. Rex, Walter E. (1987) The Attraction ofthe Contrary: Essays on the Literature ofthe French Enlightenment, Cambridge. Robertson, J. (1985) The Scottish Enlightenment and the Militia Issue, Edinburgh. Rorty, Amelie Okseberg (1986) 'The structure of Descartes' Meditations'. In Amelie Okseberg Rorty (ed.) Essays on Descartes' Meditations, Berkeley: 1-20. Rose, R. B. (1987) 'Utopias and the Enlightenment', in Eugene Kamenka (ed.) Utopias, Melbourne: 35-47. Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1959-69) Oeuvres completes, ed. Bernard Gragnebin et al., 4 vols, Paris. - - (1950) The Social Contract and Discourses, trans. G. D. H. Cole, London. - - (1960) Politics and the Arts: Letter to M. d'Alembert on the Theatre, trans. Allan Bloom, Glencoe, Illinois. - - (1964) The First and Second Discourses, trans. Roger D. and Judith R. Masters, ed. Roger D. Masters, New York. - - (1968) The Social Contract, trans. Maurice Cranston, Harmondsworth. - - (1973) The Social Contract and Discourses, trans. G. D. H. Cole, rev. 1. H. Brumfitt and John C. Hall, London. - - (1974) Emile, trans. Barbara Foxley, London. - - (1979) Emile, trans. Allan Bloom, New York. Sahlins, Marshall (1987) Islands of History, London. Sandel, M. (ed.) (1984) Liberalism and its Critics, Oxford. Sandys, George (1640) Ovids Metamorphoses Englished, London. Schama, Simon (1989) Citizens: A Chronicle of the French Revolution, New York. Schochet, Gordon J. (1975) Patriarchalism in Political Thought, Oxford. Schwartz, Joel (1984) The Sexual Politics of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Chicago. Sewell, William H. Jr (1988) 'Le citoyen/la citoyenne: activity, passivity, and the revolutionary concept of citizenship'. In C. Lucas (ed.) The Political Culture of the French Revolution, Oxford: 105-23. Shklar, Judith (1969) Men and Citizens: A Study of Rousseau's Social Theory Cambridge. Slavin, Arthur 1. (1976) 'The American principle from More to Locke'. In Fredi Chiappelli (ed.) First Images of America, San Francisco I: 139-64. Smith, Adam (1838) An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth ofNations [17761, ed. J. C. McCulloch, Edinburgh. - - (1976) The Theory of Moral Sentiments [17591, ed. D. D. Raphael and A. L. MacFie, Oxford. Soboul, Albert et al. (eds) (1977) Le Siecle des Lumieres, 2 vols, Paris.
226 References Solomon, Julie (1987) Between Magic and Travel: Francis Bacon and the Theaters ofHuman Knowing, unpublished PhD dissertation, University of Pennsylvania. Spectator (1889), complete in one volume, Edinburgh. Spence, Jonathan D. (1984) The Memory Palace of Matteo Ricci, New York. Starobinski, Jean (1964) The Invention of Liberty 1700-1789, trans. B. C. Swift, Geneva. - - (1988) Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Transparency and Obstruction [1971], trans. Arthur Goldhammer, Chicago. Staum, Martin (1980) Cabanis: Enlightenment and Medical Philosophy in the French Revolution, Princeton. Swan, Michael (1958) The Marches of El Dorado, London. Swingewood, Alan (1970) 'Origins of sociology: the case of the Scottish Enlightenment', British Journal of Sociology XXI: 164-80. - - (1984) A Short History of Sociological Thought, Basingstoke. Taylor, Charles (1979) 'Atomism'. In A. Kontos (ed.) Powers, Possessions and Freedom: Essays in Honour of C. B. Macpherson, Toronto: 39-61. Thacker, Christopher (ed.) (1968) Voltaire: Candide, Paris. Thompson, E. (1952) Popular Sovereignty and the French Constituent Assembly, 1789-91, Manchester. Thompson, E. P. (1978) The Poverty of Theory, London. Thompson, James M. (ed.) (1934) Napoleon's Letters, London. Thwaites, R. G. (ed.) (1896-1901) The Jesuit Relations, 73 vols, Cleveland. Trachtenberg, Marvin (1976) The Statue of Liberty, London. Voltaire (1961) Candide, Zadig and Selected Stories, trans. Donald Frame, New York. --(1963), Essai sur les moeurs et l'esprit des nations, 2 vols., Paris. Wade, Ira O. (1959) Voltaire and Candide, Princeton. - - (1971) The Intellectual Ongins of the French Enlightenment, Princeton. Waldron, J. (1987) Nonsense Upon Stilts: Bentham, Burke and Marx on the Rights of Man, London. Walker, D. P. (1941-2) 'Musical humanism in the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries', Music Review I-III. Walpole, Horace (1937-83) The Yale Edition ofHorace Walpole's Correspondence, ed. W. S. Lewis, 48 vols, New Haven. Walzer, Martin (1966) The Revolution ofthe Saints: A Study in the Origin ofRadical Politics, London. Warner, Marina (1985) Monuments andMaidens: The Allegory ofthe Female Form, London. Washburn, Wilcomb E. (1959) 'The moral and legal justifications for dispossessing the Indians'. In James Morton Smith (ed.) Seventeenth-Century America: Essays in Colonial History, Chapel Hill, NC: 15-32. Watt, Ian (1963) The Rise ofthe Novel: Studies in Defoe, Richardson andFielding, Harmondsworth. White, Hayden (1972) 'The fornls of wildness: archaeology of an idea'. In Edward Dudley and Maximilian Novak (eds) The l¥ild Man Within: An Image in lVestern Thought from the Renaissance to Romanticism, Pittsburgh: 3-38. Woloch, Isser (1982) Eighteenth-Century Europe: Tradition and Progress 1715-1789, New York. Wood, Neal (1984) John Locke and Agrarian Capitalism, Berkeley, California. Wolf, 1. B. (1968) Louis XIV, London. Yates, Frances (1947) The French Academies of the Sixteenth Century, London. Young, Robert (1986) Personal Autonomy: Beyond Negative and Positive Liberty, London.
Index
absolutism 25, 92, 163, 179, 180, 205, 207, 208 academies 51, 52, 59, 60,95, 127, 156, 207, 213 Addison, Joseph 124 Adorno, Theodor 4 aesthetic(s) 7, 47, 55, 64, 127 Africa 5, 7, 39, 43, 45, 46, 97 Agulhon, Maurice 132, 133, 135 algebra 94 Amadas, Philip 23 America(s) 1, 5, 7, 8, 10, 17, 19, 22, 23, 24, 25, 26, 27, 28, 29, 30, 32, 33, 35-46, 64, 84, 88, 96, 121, 136, 203 Amphion 49, 54 ancients and moderns 47, 54, 60, 62 Anderson, Perry 160 anthropology 8,35,67, 73, 101, 110, 206, 209 Arendt, Hannah 67, 78, 79 Argentina 39 Aristophanes 95 Aristotle 49, 57 art 2, 13,48,53,55,96,126,127,204 Artaud, Antonin 46 arts 8, 14, 50, 59, 60, 63, 68, 96, 98, 111, 112, 116, 120, 159 Asia 5, 7, 43, 44 astronomy 14, 68, 94 Atkinson, Geoffroy 16 Augustine 49 Australia 5 authority 10, 11, 25, 64, 70, 80, 133, 184,
185, 186, 187, 188, 190-1, 192, 193, 194, 196, 197, 200-16 autobiography 12, 185, 187 Bach, J. S. 49, 63, 64 Bacon, Francis 2, 3, 9, 20, 21, 22, 84, 86, 97, 213 Baif, Jean Antoine de 51, 52, 54, 59 ballet 57, 58, 59, 61 barbarism 9, 17, 51, 101, 102, 132 Barlow, George 23 baroque 49 Barthes, Roland 146 Bartholdi, Auguste 136, 138 Beethoven, Ludwig van 63 Bentham, Jeremy 169, 176, 177, 178, 179, 181 Bible, the 5, 8, 9, 26, 30, 41 body politic 67, 200, 201, 208 Boime, Albert 135 Bolingbroke 144 Bonnet, Charles 209 Bougainville, Louis 10, 11,35 Brazil 35, 39 Britain 88, 158, see also England Buffon, Georges 10 Bulkley, John 30-1,32 Burke, Edmund 4, 9, 25, 126, 132, 140-62,169,176,177,179,180,186, 201, 203 Cabanis, P. J. G. 208, 209 Calas, Jean 36, 96
228 Index Carrlbert, Robert 59 Campanella, Tommaso 86, 144, 145 Candide 8, 16, 19, 35-46 cannibals/cannibalism 7, 12, 16, 18, 19, 20, 24, 35, 38, 41, 42, 201, 211, 212 Caribbean 20, 22, 28, 30, 40, 96, 201 Carlyle, Thomas 155 Carmontelle 127 castrati 57, 58 Caudwell, Christopher 150 Cavalli, Pietro Francesco 58 Cavendish, William 24 Chardin, Jean 126, 127 Charles IX 51, 52 Charlevoix, P. F. X. de 102 Chateaubriand, Rene de 45,200,201, 210-11, 213 China 7, 16, 18, 19, 43, 97, 171 Chinard, Gilbert 38 Christianity 19, 33, 41, 42, 50, 78, 93, 164,210 Chrysostuffi, John 49 Churchill, Awnsham 8 Cicero 20 citizen(s) 39, 44, 52, 53, 67, 76, 77, 78, 93,95, 103, 111, 113, 114, 115, 116, 119, 120, 122, 125, 129, 131, 141, 163, 164,171-83, 191, 193, 196,205,206 civility 9, 23, 25 civilization 8, 17, 19, 24, 25, 32, 45, 69, 70, 74, 77, 101, 102, 109, 110, 124, 134, 161 Clark, T. 1. 135 classical 3, 59, 64, 88, 128, 164 Colbert, Jean Baptiste 47, 58, 59 Coleman, Patrick 131 Coleridge, Samuel Taylor 155, 159 colonization 8, 17, 23 colonialism 18-34,40 Columbus, Christopher 20, 22, 30, 38, 40, 45 comparative methods 7-10, 109 Condillac, l'abbe de 128, 129, 207, 209 Condorcet 99, 101 Cook, James 10, 11 Cooper, James Fenimore 45 Copernicus, Nicholas 3, 50, 189 Corneille, Pierre 58 Corrigan, Paul 160 cosmology 3 Crocker, Lester 2
Crow, Thomas 124, 127 Crusoe, Robinson 8, 12, 19, 38, 70, 164, 165-6 d'Alembert, Jean 1, 64 dance 52, 59, 60, 62, 64 see also ballet Dante, Alighieri 21, 50 Daurnier, Honore 135 David 49 David, Jacques-Louis 127, 128, 130, 134 Defoe, Daniel 164 de Fontenelle 64 Delacroix, Eugene 136, 139 de Maistre, Joseph 200, 213-15 de Pauw, Cornelius 10 Derrida, Jacques 159 Descartes, Rene 3, 5, 7, 8, 12, 16, 18-22, 33, 51, 55, 85, 95, 184, 185, 187, 188, 190 Destutt de Tracy 207, 209 d'Holbach 94 Diderot, Denis 2, 4, 8, 10, 11, 13,32,35, 36, 48, 64, 88, 121, 126, 127 division of labour 69, 72, 111, 112, 113, 114, 118, 120 Donne, John 24,28 Durkheim, Emile 114 du Tertre, Jean Baptiste 16 Eden, Richard 22 Egypt 53,97 El Dorado 37, 38, 42, 43, 44 Encyclopedie 1,4,8, 10, 13, 14, 86, 94, 131 England 2, 3, 5, 23, 27, 28, 33, 78, 89, 90, 95, 96, 97, 147, 148, 149, 153, 158, 160, 161, 162, 204, 212 enterprise culture 103-20, 140, 141 equality 25, 26, 72, 74, 87,91,92,99, 113,132,133,134,148,155, 172, 174, 185, 186 Europe 1, 2,3, 5, 6, 7, 8, 11, 17, 19, 20, 23,24,30,35,36,37,38,39,40,41, 42,43,44,47,53,64,88,96,97,101, 138, 149, 202, 203, 216 Faust 201, 215 Fenelon 95 Ferguson, Adam 8, 17, 101-22 Ficino, Marcilio 49, 50, 52 Filmer, Robert 204,205
Index 229 Forbes, Jack 45 Foucault, Michel 4, 185 Fragonard, father and son 174 France 2, 5, 10, 11, 16, 18, 19, 35, 38, 43, 47, 49, 52, 57-9, 62, 78, 93, 95, 96, 97, 101,123-39,149,156,160,162,174, 201, 203, 204 Fran<;ois I 39 Frankenstein, Victor 12, 20], 215 Frederick the Great 195 French Revolution of 1789 2, 4, 48, 67, 79, 84, 85, 89, 98, 99, 100, 121, 122, 123, 140, 146, 147, 148, 154, 156, 157, 158,162,164,165,171,175,176,177, 178,179,180,200-16 Freud, Sigmund 72, 134 Fried, Michael 127 Galiani, l'abbe 88 Galileo 3, 5, 50, 54 Garcilaso de la Vega 43 Gay, Peter 1, 15, 101 gender 10, 66,121,122,124,130 general will 67, 78, 79, 80, 81, 82, 83, 176, 200 geometry 14, 68, 98 Germany 3, 4, 5, 18, 19, 20, 88, 96, 97 Gibbon, Edward 2, 7, 88, 94 Gillray, James 201, 212 God 9, 10,29,30, 50, 52, 75, 94, 153, 187, 188, 189, 190, 192, 198, 205, 206, 208, 209, 210, 213, 214, 215 Godwin, William 144 Goethe, 1. W. von 186 Greece 1, 8, 52, 54, 56, 60, 97, 109, 138 Gregoire, l'abbe 129 Greuze, Jean Baptiste 127 Guiana 36 Gulliver 8, 85 Habermas, Jiirgen 4 Haiti 201 Hakluyt, Richard 8 Hampson, Norman 2 happiness 11,43, 75, 89,92,99, 104, 106, 107,108, 109, 110, 114, 115, 178 Harrington, James 86 Haydn, Joseph 63 Hazard, Paul 3 Hegel, G. W. F. 69, 71, 72, 114, 186 Heine, Heinrich 188
Helvetius 94 Helvetius, Madame 207 Henry IV of France 57,90 Herodotus 41, 95 Hesiod 8 Hobbes, Thomas 8, 24, 25, 33, 69, 70, 71, 74, 102, 107, 118, 200 Hogarth, William 124 Horace 95 Horkheimer, Max 4 humanism 20, 22, 24, 25, 31, 33, 49, 50, 51, 52-4, 55, 60, 63 human nature 2,9,24,41, 67, 80, 103, 104, 105, 106, 107, 109, 110, 113, 115, 116, 117, 118, 119, 120, 132,206,207 Hume, David 2, 4, 86, 94, 104, 105, 185, 187 Hunt, Lynne 129, 132 Huxley, Aldous 84, 100 Huygens, Constantin 57 ideologue(s) 207, 208, 209, 210, 213 India 5,97 individualism 12, 164, 167, 169, 173, 181, 184, 195, 205 inequality 27, 68, 69, 71, 72, 74, 111, 112, 113,115,118,119,123,173 interest(s) 68, 77, 78, 79, 81, 82, 83, 103, 104, 107, 108, 109, 110, 114, 115, 116, 117, 119, 120, 161 Italy 5, 47, 49, 57-9 Japan 97 Kant, Immanuel 1, 4, 184-99 Kepler, Johann 50 knowledge 1, 3, 4, 7, 12, 14, 18, 20, 22, 52, 76, 95, 99, 105, 112, 113, 121, 157, 186, 189, 190, 213 Lac1au, Ernesto 141, 161, 162 Lafitau, Jean-Fran<;ois 38, 102 LaMettrie, Julien 94 language 25, 33, 48, 54, 59, 69, 70, 97, 105, 107, 110, 122, 140, 141, 145, 146, 149,159,161,173,179,181,204 Lanson, Gustave 3 Las Casas, Fray Bartolome de 38 law(s) of natureInatural law 24, 25, 26, 27, 28, 30, 33, 87, 92, 126, 206, 208, 210, 215
230 Index Lawrence, D. H. 46 Lazarus, Emma 138 LeBrun, Charles 60 Leibnitz, Gottfried 37 Lery, Jean de 35 Levi-Strauss, Claude 35 liberalism 4, 27, 99, 161, 180, 181 liberty 11, 72,92, 103, 104, 106, 111, 113, 114, 115, 116, 120, 122, 126, 129, 130, 131, 132, 133, 134, 135, 136, 138, 139, 170, 172, 175, 176, 178, 179, 181, 186 Locke, John 2, 3, 8, 10, 16, 17, 25-34, 69, 70,71,72,102,172,173,176,179, 182, 205, 209 Louis XIV 2,47,58,59,60,61,90,204, 205 Louis XVI 2, 200 Lucretius 95 Lully, Jean-Baptiste 49, 58, 59, 60, 63 luxury 66, 68, 90, 92, 99, 107, 115, 116, 118, 119, 120, 145, 154 Lyotard, Jean-Franc;ois 160, 161 Machiavelli, Niccolo 78, 79 MacIntyre, Alasdair 181, 182 Macpherson, C. B. 32, 152 macrocosm/microcosm 47,52 Maine de Biran 200,209 maps 4-7,9 Marat, Jean-Paul 128, 130 Marcus Aurelius 11 Maria Theresa, Infanta 58 Marie Antoinette 147, 149, 158, 160, 201 Marie de Medici 57 Marmontel, Jean-Franc;ois 38, 43 Martyr, Peter 22, 32 Marx, Karl 28,32,82, 102, 114, 119, 132, 168,177,179,186 Marxism 4, 83, 150, 165, 171, 177, 180 mathematics 14, 47, 55, 191 Mazarin, Cardinal 58 medicine 94, 95, 206, 207 Mercier, Louis-Sebastien 84-100, 101 Mersenne, Marin 50,51,55-7,59 Millar, John 101, 104 Milton, John 53, 193 mind and body 47, 144, 206, 207, 208 modern(ity) 49,60, 64, 66, 68, 73, 77, 78, 181, 182 Moliere 58, 62 monarch(s/y) 41, 52,92,99, 111, 113, 123,
132, 133, 147, 148, 155, 158, 159, 160, 162,172,206,210,213,215 Montaigne, Michel 16, 20, 24,32,35,38, 39, 44 Montesquieu 2, 8, 97, 101, 102, 105, 106, 180 Montgolfier brothers 97 More, Thomas 84, 86, 88 Morgan, Lewis Henry 17 Mornet, Daniel 98 Morris, William 86 Mouffe, Chantal 141, 161, 162 Mozart, Wolfgang Amadeus 49, 63, 64 Mumford, Lewis 86 Murdoch, Iris, 192-3 music 47-65
Napoleon Bonaparte, 12, 85, 89, 158, 160, 203, 210, 212, 214 nation(s), 8, 18, 20, 27, 28, 32, 41, 47, 62, 78, 107, 110, 111, 114, 115, 116, 119, 122, 129, 133, 138, 139, 149, 157, 160, 173,175,180,182,214,215 natural law see law natural philosophy 47 nature 3, 7, 9, 10, 11, 12, 14, 18-34, 39, 43, 45, 66, 77, 78, 87, 92, 94, 99, 104, 108, 122, 129, 134, 139, 143, 148, 149, 152, 154, 155, 158, 186, 189, 205, 206, 214, 215 Newton, Isaac 1, 2, 3, 20, 105 Nietzsche, Friedrich 186, 193 Nochlin, Linda 134 O'Brien, Conor Cruise 147 opera 57, 58, 59, 60 optimism 12 Orpheus 49,~54 Ovid 8,22-3,31,32,95 Ozouf, Mona 126, 129 Paine, Thomas 89, 140, 150, 152, 160 painting see art Paraguay 39, 97 Pascal, Blaise 43, 187 passion(s) 47, 54, 56, 57, 62, 63, 71, 75, 107,109,117,126,143,146,157,185 patronage 47 perfectibility 98, 101, 104 Peri, Jacopo 57 Perrault, Charles 62, 64
Index 231 Peru 43, 44, 88, 168, 170 physics 14, 94 physiology 144, 207, 208 Pitt, William 43 Plato 49, 50, 52, 84, 128 Poland 97 Polo, Marco 7, 19 Pope, Alexander 3, 200 Pope, the 78, 93, 203, 210 Portuga119, 28, 97 positivism 12, 165, 171 Poussin, Nicolas 60 Prevost, l'abbe 8 Price, Richard 140 progress 1, 7, 8, 10, 43, 84-100, 101, 102, 104, 111, 122, 135, 136, 138, 148, 161, 186 property 12, 25, 26, 27, 30-1, 32, 69, 72, 73, 91, 103, 109, 111, 112, 115, 116, 117,148,155,156,157,173,177,178 prostitutes 90, 130, 211 Prud'hon, Pierre-Paul 132, 133 psychology 104, 144, 207, 208, 209 Ptolemy 50, 51, 56 Purchas, Samuel 8, 23 Pure 60 Pythagoras 49, 50, 54, 94 Quinault, Philippe 58,59,60 race 10, 33, 41, 124, 173 Racine, Jean 59 Raleigh, Walter 23 Rameau, Jean-Philippe 59,63,64 rationality 29, 30, 32, 33, 69, 92, 103 Raynal, G. F. T. 10, 96 reason 1, 4, 11, 13, 14, 18,29,30-1,32, 33, 42, 43, 47, 53, 54, 55, 62, 69, 70, 71, 74, 76, 80, 91, 92, 93, 98, 99, 105, 112, 118, 129, 130, 131, 134, 139, 152, 178,184-99,201,215 religion 7, 8, 91, 93, 94, 99, 126, 130, 142,152,153,159,161,173,188,189, 210, 213 Renaissance, the 16, 53, 54 Restif de la Bretonne 91 Reynolds, Joshua 11 Richelieu, Cardinal 58 right(s) 12, 23, 30, 72, 97, 113, 126, 140, 148, 163-83, 205 Robespierre, Maximilien 89, 100, 134, 176
Robertson, William 101, 104 Romanticism 63, 210 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques 2, 7, 8, 12, 16, 36, 40, 41, 42, 43, 64, 66-83, 84, 89, 93, 95, 101, 102, 121, 122, 123, 124, 125, 126,127,128,131,132,170,172,173, 180, 181, 192, 200, 201 Rubens, Peter Paul 60 Russia 88, 97, 166, 203
Sacrati, Francesco 58 Saint Cecilia 49 Saint Pierre, l'abbe de 95 Sandys, George 22-3, 31 .Sappho 95 savage~8, 9,16-17,18-34,36,102 savages 11, 18, 20, 23, 24, 32, 39, 45, 69, 70, 74, 89 Sayer, Derek 160 Schwarz, Joel 131 science(s) 3, 5, 8, 9, 14, 20, 22, 33, 46, 50, 68, 91, 94, 97, 98, 99, 105, 107, 122, 150,155,186,204,206,207,209,213 Scotland 3, 5, 99, 101, 104, 105, 115 Scott, Walter 102, 160 sculpture 96, 127 self, the 7, 73, 78, 117, 209 self-interest see interest sex(es) 11, 39, 41, 66, 81, 91, 121, 123-39,173,211 Shaftesbu~ 27, 28 Shakespeare, William 50 Shelley, Ma~ 12, 186 slave(~/s) 7, 28, 36, 39, 41, 45, 72, 96, 111, 119, 145,201 Smith, Adam 4, 32, 33, 101, 102, 104, 109 social contract 73, 150, 168, 172, 177, 192, 213 social science(s) 9, 204 sociology 8, 99, 101, 104, 112, 114, 166 society/societies 11, 12, 23, 24, 32, 42, 53, 71, 72, 78, 93, 102, 105, 106, 107, 110, 113, 114, 115, 132, 143, 144, 145, 149, 150, 153, 156, 162, 163, 164, 166, 167, 169,176, 180,210,213,215 sOl~3, 5~ 5~ 69,71, 7& 12~ 143, 20~· 207 Spain 22, 28, 40, 89, 96 Sparta 77 Starobinski, Jean 124, 126
232 Index state, the 53, 56, 60, 61, 63, 68, 70, 72, 73, 76, 77, 78, 79, 80, 81, 82, 83, Ill, 118, 119, 120, 122, 123, 129, 148, 150, 160,161,170,172,173,179,182,187, 191, 193 state of nature 5, 8, 11, 16, 25, 26, 31, 69, 70, 72, 73, 74, 101, 102, 105, 123, 145, 171,213 Statue of Liberty 122, 135-9 sublime and the beautiful, the 143, 144, 145, 146 Swift, Jonathan 85 Switzerland 5 Tacitus 95 technology 97, 138, 139 Terror, the 2, 79, 134, 202 Thatcher, Margaret/Thatcherism 140, 141, 143, 150, 158, 161, 162 theology 13, 47, 78, 93, 94, 96, 206, 207, 210 Thibault de Courville, Joachim 51 Thompson, E. P. 150 Timotheus 49 Torelli, Giacomo 58 Trousson, Raymond 89 Tupac Amaru II 43 Turgot 99, 101 Turkey 97 Tyard, Pontus de 52
United States of America 10, 135 USSR see Russia utilitarianism 104, 107, 108, 109, 117, 165,169,170,173,176,179,181 utopia 35, 77, 82, 83, 84-100, 103 Vespucci, Amerigo 19, 84 Vico, Giambattista 101 virtue(s) 42, 67, 68, 71, 74, 75, 76, 81, 83, 87, 91, 100, 104, 106, 107, 108, 109, Ill, 113, 114, 115, 116, 119, 120, 121, 130, 132, 133, 134, 139, 146, 150, 152, 163, 193 Voloshinov, Valentin 146 Voltaire 2, 16, 35-46, 95, 96 von Humbolt, Alexander 43 Walpole, Horace 88 Warner, Marina 134, 135 WaUeau, Antoine 125 Wells, H. G. 86, 98 West Indies 32, 101 Winthrop, John 28 Wolcott, Roger 30 Wollstonecraft, Mary 140 woman 10, 76, 81, 82, 91, 132 women 67, 72, 81, 119, 131, 132, 133, 215 Wordsworth, William 20 Zarlino, Gioseffo 55
United Nations 164, 165-6, 169, 170, 171, 173, 176, 177, 178, 179, 180, 181