The radical project Sartrean investigations
Bill Martin
ROWMAN & LITTLEFIELD PUBLISHERS, INC.
Lanham
•
Boulder
•
...
42 downloads
854 Views
3MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
The radical project Sartrean investigations
Bill Martin
ROWMAN & LITTLEFIELD PUBLISHERS, INC.
Lanham
•
Boulder
•
New York
•
Oxford
ROWMAN & LITTLEFIELD PUBLISHERS, INC: Published in the United States of America by Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc; 4720 Boston Way, Lanham, Maryland 20706 http://www.rowmanlittlefield.com 12 Hid's Copse Road Cumnor Hill, Oxford OX2 9JJ, England Copyright © 2000 by Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
All rights reserved. No part of this pUblication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,.9r transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, . without the prior permission of the publisher. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Information Available Library of Congress Cataloging-i n-Publication Data
Martin, Bill, 1956The radical project : Sartrean investigations I Bill Martin. p. cm. - (New critical theory) Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index. ISBN 0-8476-9698-7 (alk. paper) - ISBN 0-8476-9699-5 (pbk. : alk. paper) I. Sartre, Jean Paul, 1905- I. Title. II. Series .. B2430.S34 M36 2000 194-dc21
00-059057
Printed in the United States of America il'Y'\TM 'Cl The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American
National Standard for Information Sciences-Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSIINISO Z39.48-1992.
For David Detmer and Kerri Mommer
/'
Contents
.'
Ackll:owledgments Intr?duction
ix
Ever since May: The radical project
1
Dictatorship "for" the proletariat: Sartre's theory of
15
2 3
Between Mao and Moses: Sartre's final decade
35
Beyond the varieties of Sartrophobia, toward Sartre's
47
4'
Political theory after Bataille and Derrida:
63
5
The political space of Sartre in the text of Derrida
71
6,
Elections: Still a trap for fools? Revisiting Same's 1973 essay
79
7
Sartre and the critique of postmodern capitalism
91
the Stalin period
legacy for radical intellectuals On the critique of "project"
Afterword: A philosopher of his century after his century
107
Bibliography
117
Index
123
By the Same Author
127
vii
Acknowledgments
Aithough this is by far my shortest book, it seems that I have more people than ev.er to thank for their help and encouragement. I hope this means that there has been a general expansion of the radical project, of its circle.
Patricia Huntington and Martin Matustik encouraged me to pull the project to
gether for the New Critical Theory series, of which I am very grateful to be a part.
I have been fortunate to have the friendship of Martin and Patricia for more than teri:years now-they are wonderful people and impressive thinkers. Maureen Mc Grogan is a legendary editor with whom I
thank her for her patience.
-l have had the
am
very pleased to be associated. I also
great fortune to participate in the meetings and discussions of
the North American Sartre Society since the fall of
Philosophy Association, when I
am
1991. As with the Radical
with the Sartreans I feel a certain sense of
"homecoming," and I look forward to every meeting. Sartreans know that we
choose our world; to refuse to do so is to live in bad faith. Having chosen the
wqrld, all of my fellow Sartreans are, I suppose,'tesponsible for the contents of this book as well, though I won't hold them to it! Still, I want to thank all of my
Sartrean fellow travelers for their comments and criticisms on my work, and for
the role they are playing in continuing the dissemination of the work of Sartre.
I would especially like to thank the following: Tom Anderson, Hazel Barnes, Bill Becker, Linda Bell, Debra Bergoffen, Robert Bernasconi, Betsy Bowman, Betty Cannon, Joe Catalano, Peter Caws, Matt Eshleman, Tom Flynn, Lewis
Gordon, Helen Heise, Sonia Kruks, Gail Linsenbard, Steve Martinot, Bill
McBride, Liz Morelli, Constance Mui, Jay Murphy, Julie Pederson, Michel Ry
balka, Ron Santoni, Bob Stone, Steven Storch, Adrian van den Hoven, Joe
Walsh, and Kathy Wider. lowe a special dept to Steve Hendley, with whom I have been paired on numerous panels, and whose comments bear quite directly on several of the essays here.
I would also like to thank the following for their continuing encouragement
and for sharing their thoughts and work with me: Linda Alcoff, Ken Alpern, ix
x
Acknowledgments '
Bob Avakian, Heather Barnes, Peg Binningham, Alison Brown, Tom Buford,
q
Al Cinelli, Ann Cudd, Andrew Cutrofello, Donald Davidson, Jac ues Derrida,
Martin Donougho, Jim Edwards, Jim Faulconer, Dia'na Fuss, Aaron Fi¢htelberg, Robert Fripp, Roger Gottlieb, Craig Hanks, Graham Harmon, Stephen Houl
gate, David Ingram, Tom 1eannot, Cindy Kaffen, Doug Kellner, Davia Krell, Niklaus Largier, Mary Jeanne Larrabee, Andrew Ligh�, Raymond Lotta, Lynne Margolies, Jim Marsh, Wjll McNeill, Joanne Molina, Darrell Moore, Bob Mul
vaney, Patrick Murray, Michael Naas, Mecke Nagel, Angelica Nuzzo, Susanna Pagliaro, Jeff Paris, Elbert Peck, Anne Pomeroy, Gail Presbey, Dan Price, Ram
sey Eric Ramsey, Garry Rindfuss, Ron Scapp, Jane Scarpantqni, Paul Schafer, Jeanne Schuler, Gary Shapiro, Christina Smerick, Chelsea Sn�lgrove, David Schweickart, George Trey', David W illiams, Whomever I have left out of this list is most welcome to up braid me mercilessly. As always, l owe a tremendous debt to my life companion, Kathleen League.
This book is dedicated to David Detmer and Kerri Mommer. David is a true
Sartre scholar from whom I have learned a great deal. Our discussions of Sartre,
Chomsky, Marxism, and politics in general are very much reflected in the essays
here. We also share an interest in that other "nineteenth-century" preoccupation, progressive rock music. Kerri is a superb editor who has helped me greatly with
disseminating philosophical ideas regarding that same subjeat. Both are also eth
ically committed vegans, and Kerri is an extraordinary cook, and without a doubt the best meals this mere vegetarian has experienced in recent years have been at
the Mommer-DetIller homestead. Their son, Arlo, is a delight, and I hope that one day he will catch an actual glimpse of the redeemed society dreamt {)f in this book. David and Kerri are from Kansas, as is my wife, Kathleen, and pow I am too-and, as the Texans say, "I'll defend it." But most of all Kerri and'David are
good friends, people with whom I have shared the experience of breaking through ' the hyperseriality of this emerging postmodem capitalist world.
Introduction Ever since May
The radical project
. . . into this world we're thrown ...riders on the storm . . .
_
-Jim Morrison If I understand a certain longstanding trend in philosophy correctly, a trend that
I identify with Plato, Aristotle, Aquinas, Kant, Marx, and others, the'most impor
tant thing is first of all to imagine the possibility of a good society and of an eth
ical relation, and then to let metaphysical or ontological concerns follow in the
wake of this imagination. Or, indeed, if I understand the point of Kant's third for-
-,mulation of the categorical imperative, or Marx's eleventh thesis on Feuerbach, the most important thing is to struggle-with our hands, our hearts, our minds to l;>rlng about a just society, and to fashion theory that serves this project.
Did Jean-Paul Sartre begin philosophical life with such a project in mind? Cer
tainly his earlier work exhibits a strong preoccupation with ontological concerns,
,though of a sort that deeply connected with wlmt Marx called (again, in those fa mous theses)
sensuous reality. "!t
the search for useful categories. In examining the relationship between Being and
Nothingness and the Notebooksfor an Ethics, one might be tempted to assimilate Sartre to what may or may not be an age-old philosophical activity-and, is it the
theological activity par excellence?-but which has certainly become a lens
through which much historical scholarship in philosophy is now focused: first
one gets the ontology right, then one can perhaps turn to ethical or social con
cerns. This is simply to recapitulate what became, in the twentieth century, the
"traditional" distinction between "hard" and "soft" philosophy-ontology, epis
temology, and logic on the one side, ethics, political philosophy, and aesthetics on the other. Certainly one can form a respectable interpretation of Sartre's oeuvre
that conforms to this schema.
Sartreans, however, tend to be resistant to this interpretation, and this has
everything to do with how and why we became Sartreans in the fIrst place. We
2
Introduction
'-
were inspired,by engagement, The rap oQ.-the early Sartre is that he, atrbest, pop ularized certain aspects of Heidegger's Being and Time, I do not have
the com
petence t6enter into a long comparison between Sein und Zeit aridL'etre et Ie neant, though this territory has been well covered by others. This much,is clear
enough: Heidegger went ever further away from the realm of social p ractic�, to create what has become, at least in some version's, a substitute religion of "Being," while Sartre, from this perspective, was hopelessly mired in the "ontic." Those of us who were drawn by Sartre into philosophy or intellectual life more generally have perpetuated this orientation toward beings, plural and perhaps
even "mere" (to echo Wallacj! Stevens's title), all the while keeping to a central
concern of all philosophers of practice, from Plato to Kant to Marx and perhaps
even Heidegger: the possibility that persons might live as ends-in-themselves and
not mere means only. We might find an interesting extension of this idea in Hei degger and some others (deep ecologists, Latter-day Saints, etc.), in which there
is a questioning of any treatment of any being as a mere "thing." In light of such thinking, perhaps there is something to Heidegger's critique of Sartre's "human
ism." Certainly Sartre can be accused of being "species-ist." Personally, I do find that to be a limitation, and yet I think that we must also worry about what might
count as a "transcendence" or "overcoming" of humanism. If there is a reaching out to the possibility of the flourishing, the co-flourishing,,Pf all beings, is this to be achieved through a sense that all ontic reality must accept appropriation by
Being Itself (which is where the Heideggerian substitute religion comes in, and
the connection to J>olitical quietism should be clear)? Or, do we only find the pos , sibility of the flourishing of other forms of life by struggling to find the possibility of our own species? _
My sense is that Sartre has at least half of the answer to that question. We would do well to hold to that half; if Heidegger has some insights tha,t,we should
also not let go of (especially having to do with language and technoiogy), even so there is generally an orientation toward practice as somehow ultimately con templative. That is, if we
are
forced by "ontological considerations" to be some
what ambivalent about humanism and the priority of ethics over ontology,'
does not mean that we should let go of humanism and what Sartre might teach us
about the humanist struggle toward the ethical relation. The fundamentally Hei
deggerian readings of Derrida's arguments on this point (as found in the seminal essays "Violence and Metaphysics" and "The' Ends of Man," and in Of Spi rit, Chap. 10) stress the ambivalence only to assimilate humanism to the "tradition"
that must be "overcome." What these readings miss is the fact that Derrida's ar guments are for a true ambi-valence, a double strategy and double reading that does not let go of either side. For those Marxists, Sartrean or otherwise, who find it hard to live with such an ambi-valence, it must be pointed out that these two tracks exist, often in great ten
sion with one another, in Marx as well. On the one hand there is the political
economy-or, as Marx put it in The German Ideology, "the real movement of
Ever since May: The radical project
3
things-that must "inevitably," through the operation of "iron laws," lead to com munism. One-sided focus on this "real movement," or perhaps more specifically
these ''things'' (recall also Engels's expression, "the pure administration of things," as a description for the political form that communism will take) is what
Sartre critiqued in "Materialism and Revolution" and attempted to provide an al
ternative to in the whole of the
Critique (both volumes plus Searchfor a Metl!od).
- IFor, just as surely, there is the other side of Marx-perhaps best exemplified in . �'the Critique of the Gotha Programme- which breaks the bounds of narrow eco . nomic calculations and moves toward a human possibility that cannot be speci fied in advance, but that transcends reification and commodification.
Another way to approach these issues is to ask what would it mean for the . ethical relation to be incarnate? Under what material circumstances might jus
tice be made manifest in the world? Kant speaks of the two things that held him
in awe: the starry heavens above and the moral law within. I can't help but think
. that he wondered if there was some connection. Though such a thought may' seem very distant from what appears, at times, to be the essential
loneliness of
. Sartre's writing (and so well captured in the sculptures of Giacometti, or in
Francis Jeanson's phrase, "the positively sequestered man"), the oscillating ten
sion between ontological concerns and the possibility of ethical relations,
staged in the context of struggle, links these two great "moralists." Certainly, if
. humanity does not come to understand the structures that actiVely prevent such
a manifestation or justice, then there cannot be such a thing. But Sartre under stands as well as Marx that such understanding does not come through a pri
marily contemplative approach to philosophy, but instead through engagement with sensuous reality, through struggle.
Having set the stage this way, let me say that the unifying element in the es
says presented here is political rather than philosophical or even thematic. My
aim is to recover and extend the
radicality of Sartre's political project. AlI of
these essays were originally presented as papers at meetings of either the North
•
American Sartre Society or the Sartre Circle sesSions at the American Philosoph
ical Association. I have benefited greatly from the comments and criticisms of my fellow Sartreans at these forums. In an earlier book
(Politics in the impasse) I
hailed my fellow members of the Radical Philosophy Association, especially the
founding generation, for the support and encouragement they have given to me and other, y ounger, rad�cal social theorists. Not surprisingly, there is a significant
overlap in membership between the RPA and the N ASS. Even more there is an overlap in spirit, as both organizations were inspired by the events of May 1968
and their aftermath. Many of us, indeed, were inspired to take up philosophy or intellectual life in a special way, an
engaged way, by the conjoined influences of
May '68 (or "the sixties" more generally) and Sartre's example. Following that example, and keeping to that conjunction, these essays may be said to be more
exercises in a Sartrean mode rather than what might be more properly called "Sartre scholarship."
4
Introduction
Indeed, these essays could easily be seen as quite marginal to a more typical scholarly project. While some of the works of Sartre that I take up hete lire those more likely to be discussed by mainstream scholars-for example, "What is Lit
erature?" or the Critique of Dialectical Reason-more often I deal witjl pieces that are quite polemical and demonstrative of very direct political engagement. These would include the 1946 essay, "Materialism �nd Revolution," as well as some of the essays and interviews given in the aftermath of May '68, and the final interviews with Benny Levy (Hope Now)-and, even with the Critique, I focus on the controversial second volume. In a couple of the essays here I am not so much interested in drawing'citations from Sartre as I am in defending his notion of the "project" from attacks by what might be called the Foucauldian or perhaps
Deleuzean Left.
What is more, some readers will readily see that there is a decidedly Maoist
cast to these essays. Certainly this will place these essays far out of the main
stream of academic scholarship on Sartre, but, I hope, not so far from Sartre's ac
tual political concerns. Sartre certainly had his moments, as for instance when, like many in France and Europe more generally, he thought that he could inter
twine the melodies of the Internationale an9 the Marsellais. (This is "'{hat Mao
called "combining two into one.") But Sartre differed from almost all of the �ther
"Western Marxists" in that he went against Eurocentrism in both theory and prac
tice. Although not a "Leninist" per se, he understood quite well that to side with the oppressed in places such as Algeria and Vietnam meant going against the in terests of "one's own" country and ruling class. (This is what Lenin called "rev
olutionary defeatism"-ignored not only by most Left intellectuals, but indeed
most of the Left in general.)ILike Marx, Sartre remained focused on the world
historic transformations and the possibilities that might be generated for human
freedom. Like Mao, Sartre was vitally concerned with what had begOlpe of the
first large-scale experiment with socialism, the Soviet Union. For both, the
"Stalin question" was not merely a problem for "backward" people outside of the
"advanced" civilization (perhaps the latter word should be in scare-quotes as well) of Europe. W hile I do not think it can be argued that Sartre was a "Maoist,"
certainly he had many concerns in common with Mao, and their positions .over
lap or complement one another in important ways. I hasten to add, however, that
in some ways Sartre was a better "Maoist" than some of his Maoist comrades in
the post-May period. For this reason, among others, I also find it hard to tlfink of Sartre as a "Western" Marxist,.despite his often being anthologized that way. This is not the place to argue for the Maoist perspective in toto; I simply hope that some of the analyses presented here will persuade readers of the efficacy of at least parts of this perspective. The Western powers and the corporate media
have been able to accomplish an immense smear job on Mao and the Chinese
Revolution under his leadership. The restoration of capitalism in China since
Mao's death, which is plain for everyone to see, ought to be one very big tip-off as to the nature of this smear. The open-minded reader will also see that my par-
Ever since May: The radical project
5
ticular Maoist approach is highly unorthodox and does not seek to set itself up as an orthodoxy. In his discussion of the Stalin question, Sartre criticizes a policy of "socialism in one country" that has assumed the character of an institution. In his view, such a set-up represents the entrenchment of the practico-inert, and there fore the possibility for strategies of reification to once more rule society. Sartre's argument here complements Mao perfectly, and both go very much against the - /.grain of European Mapdst orthodoxy. For both Sartre and Mao grasp that the essence of socialism is not primarily the creation of certain institutions; forces of reification can work through legal frameworks that "guarantee" the public own ership of means of production, if the permanence of the revolution is not contin ,!lally reaffirmed through the self-activity of the masses. Indeed, both seem to argue that there is never an end-point to this process (and Jacques Derrida has made similar arguments in his recent Specters of Marx), and Maoism might learn a thing or two from Sartre on how reification might continue to regenerate itself , even after certain formal structures of capitalism are overthrown. In any case, there are many aspects of my particular Maoist perspective that , make more orthodox Maoists, to say nothing of more orthodox Marxists, quite uncomfortable. But so be it. In particular, the way that I have argued for a "post secular" approach in social theory, taking up parts of Judaism, radical Christian ity, Kant, communitarianism, Derrida, etc., is highly problematic from,a more or ,thodox or monistic perspective. (Some of my friends call this "petty-60urgeois eclecticism," but my aim is to learn from many sources and to put this learning at the service of emancipatory projects.) However, some virtues of this perspec -rive might be seen in making a contrast between, on the one' side, the compli mentarity of Sartre and Mao, and, on the other side, a recent attempt at creating a philosophy that is fully secular. I opened this introduction with a line from Jim Morrison of The Doors. I've always appreciated the ambience of "Riders on the Storm," as well as the line I quoted, but most of the rest of the lyrics are, frankly, a somewhat flaky version of " existentialism. The more profound and ethereal ;;dstential vibe is better captured by Jim Morrison's tone and Phil Manzanera's electric piano than by the lyrics themselves. One feels adrift in the world, without any safe port, without any god to save us. Certainly the rest of the lyrics take these themes in purely individual istic and amoral (or at least morally relativistic) directions. I mention this because some would argue tha�, even if despite itself, Sartre's existentialism has to go in these directions. (And, of course, these are some Sartreans who would prefer to stay with only the lonely, individualistic side of Sartre.) A useful comparison might be made, then, between Sartre and someone else who has attempted to thirtk about politics and philosophy under conditions of absolute contingency, namely Richard Rorty. A more extended discussion of Rorty's project would show, I thirtk, that his aim is the complete secularization of philosophy, the severance of thought and politics from any notion or hint of teleology, eschatology, or some big, all-encompassing,
, �,
6
Introduction
picture. For Rorty, what has to be gotten rid of is any sense of a grand "story" (or metanarrative) that explains the state of the world or anyone's place in it. Apart
from avowedly theological visions, Rorty's prime example of the kind of big pic
,ture that must be set aside is History as one finds it in Hegel and Marx. If Marx's global history is out the window, then so is, for Rorty, internationalism ot any
larger sense of a common human project. We are left with the secular, fragmented, and contingent histories of se&ments of humanit . Anything more, in Rorty's
y
view, would constitute the dreaded and dangerous- metanarrative. Curiously, Rorty has no difficulty with expressions such as "we Americans." And yet, if one
were to take stock of what "we Americans" (or "we Frenchpersons," or "we Ger mans," or "we Europeans," etc.) means in the world, then it seems to me that the sort of immanent critique practiced by Marx would lead in the direction of an un derstanding of colonialism and imperialism and the possibility, therefore, of in ternationalism and anti-imperialism. But perhaps Rorty's argument is that stories just do not come that big? Perhaps then, for Rorty, the only way to argue for in
ternationalism or to talk about developments in world history is to "go theologi cal," so to speak. As a philosopher who writes after the death of God and in terms of a world
where we confront contingency at every turn, Sarfre seems somewhat congenial to Rorty. Indeed, one might see a connection between them that, to the best of my knowledge, has not been stated explicitly in the philosophical literature, and this
has to do with Kant. Of modern figures, it appears that Kant is the one whom
Rorty is most at pains to either refute or avoid. It is not hard to see that Rorty
would agree with Hegel that Kant's ethical philosophy constitutes an "empty for
malism." Devices such as the categorical imperative (or the Golgen'Rule of the
Sermon on the Mount) may prove pragmatically useful-that is, useful for solv
ing problems-but we do not need to afford deep metaphysical status to them. In stead, Rorty recommends, let's just agree that it may be usefuJ, for some pur
poses, to talk in a certain way, for example, in terms of "persons" who should be
treated as "ends" rather than "means." W hat this means, of course, �s that other
people really are means to my ends, but things would work out better (for me) if
I were to adopt this more "respectful" or "polite" language. The reality is actually
that other people are my "hell," and there is no sense in which the other can be understood except as, ultimately, an obstacle. If this is what Sartre reaRy thinks,
then one can see how he might be enlisted in,a fundamentally Hobbesian politi cal-philosophical project wherein conceptions of the good are ruled out (as meta
physical, as giving us grandiose world pictures that are, in Rorty's phrase, "well
lost") and the best we can hope to achieve is a situation where we avoid some of the worst aspects of the bad. In contrast, Kant can be seen as simply a moralizer, a theologizer, someone who has no place in our disenchanted and demytholo gized world. Another way to put it is that, if Kant's transcendental ethics holds central the fundamental regard for the other (in this, the requirements of his ethics
go beyond those of the Golden Rule), then an antitranscendentalist politics
7
Ever since May: The radical project
should-on a Rortyan account-simply bite the bullet and declare itself on the
side of the logic of the same. This results in Rorty's frank acceptance of ethno
centrism and of the existing political institutions of Western societies as funda mentally just. Accordingly, the "longing for total revolution" is something to be
abandoned (see "Habermas, Derrida, and the functions of philosophy, in
- I: ,�!
and Progress, 307-326).
Truth
Just to complete a thought, it seems to me that the dichotomy represented by
Kant and Hobbes, in the form of theory of the good/theory of the bad (the good
',as ideal, versus the bad as what is to be avoided), is a useful one for mapping nor ,mative social theories and political philosophies. Although one kind of Marxist
; critique might say that this language brings us too close to metaphy sical cate
gories, including ones dealing with "human nature" (an idea that, after all, Sartre
was very much interested in undermining), and perhaps even to simple-minded
, homilies about "optimism" and "pessimism," and although the warnings of this . Marxism oUght to be heeded when venturing into such territory, at the end of this
road is a place where norrnativity is not to be found at all. And although this is
indeed where one strand of Marxism (perhaps even most of the kinds that have
been dominant, intellectually and politically) ends up, my hope is that it is not the
only strand. I hope that further arguments will show that Sartre,.aimed to take
Marxism and radical social theory in another direction. Still, the point
of. the pres
:ent comparison (of Sartre with Rorty) is to show where a politics of contingency must stand with regard to norrnativity and existing social institutions.
", Also, to complete the thought as regards Kant, it ought to be noticed that, in
�orty's secularization of philosophy and politics, the presecular world ends not
with a bang, but with a whimper. With Sartre and Kant I think you get the bang.
For Kant, the age of enlightenment and autonomy means that humankind has
been released by God into an adventure, into a time of fmding its own place in the world. I think the same goes for Sartre, with the possible exception that there
is also an element of abandonment (or "thrown,pess") to this release. Kant, for
�ure, saw the dangers of this adventure. This is why (in my view), in the time of increasing global commerce and trade (and therefore "foreign relations"), Kant proposed universal principles (not only the categorical imperative, but also doc
uments such as "Perpetual Peace") that have impersonal formulations. That is, in
the face of global forces and large-scale changes in the possibilities for humanity, Aristotelian arguments about character and virtue will just not cut it. It seems to
me that Sartre follows this sort of thinking all the way, whereas Rorty finds it dan gerous because it engages too much with the terms that need, to be simply "set
aside." In other words, theologized history must end with a Whimper, it must sim ply run out of steam, otherwise one is still responding in some form to a god, even
if to one who is no longer there. Rorty hopes to affIrm one side of Sartre-the
side that philosophizes contingency -and no side of Kant. But clearly there are many sides to Sartre that Rorty does not want to
most of all.
(In
affIrm : the "Stalinist" perhaps
a larger discussion I would argue that Rorty is still caught up in
8
Introduction
interesting ways in his Trotskyist roots; Trotskyists often use tenns such as "mor
alizer" and "utopian" as curse-words, and they remain fundamentally within Eu
rocentric and narrowly economic frameworks.) In what follows, I will emphasize the key issues in a thematic way, in the hope of showing two very different ways we might think about "politics without a net" (so to speak).
. A few quotations from Rorty will give a taste o�his approach to the politics of
contingency with regard to questions of nonnativity and social institutions.
In the name of "the view'that freedom is the recognition of contingency rather
than of the existence of a specifically human realm exempt from natural neces sity," Rorty argues that we should expect less from philosophy.
In particular, we
should not expect to find what Habennas hopes for, "universalist pragmatics and strong theoretical strategies." Our aim should be to generate "proposals for spe
cific changes in social arrangements-in laws, company regulations, administra
tive procedures, educational practices, and so on." From this perspective, we will
find ourselves no longer using tenns such as "'late capitalism,' 'modem indus
trial society,' and 'conditions of the production of knowledge'" (and I assume
that tenns such as "mode of production" or "relations of production" or even "working class" are to be rejected as well), and instead we will find tenns such as "worker representation" and "laws against unprodJctive financial manipula tion" more useful.
In other words, "we" will be reformists, not revolutionaries-and it is interest
ing that Rorty connects the latter category with someone whom most of us who
believe in the need for radical social transfonnation see as completely reformist, namely Habennas. Indeed, Habennas and almost all of the Habennasians see
themselves this way, so why is Rorty picking on him? The final paragraph from the essay from which I have been quoting ties these issues together._
"
A preference for this level of concreteness rather than that characteristic' of large scale German-style "social theory" is, of course, not simply a deduction from large philosophical premises. It is justified, if at all, not simply by a desire for the recog nition of contingency but by a political judgment: namely, that the rich democracies of the present day already contain the sorts of institutions necessary for their own re form and that communication among citizens of those democracies is not "distorted" by anything more esoteric than greed, fear, ignorance, and resentment. This amounts to saying that the instruments of perfectibility are already, in the rich North Atlantic constitutional democracies, in place -that the principle institutions of contemporary democratic societies do not require "unmasking" but rather strenuous utilization, supplemented by luck. Such a judgment is risky, and perhaps mistaken. But if it is mistaken, it will not be shown to be so by "universalist problematics and strong the oretical strategies," but by continued trial and error. (Truth and Progress, 326) Presumably, Sartre in the
Critique would be quite guilty of engaging in "large
scale Gennan-style social theory," If I could ask Professor Rorty just one ques
tion at this particular juncture of his social commentary, especially taking into
Ever since May: The radical project consideration his recent
9
Achieving Our Country, it would be this: "Do you see system?" For
any room whatsoever for discussing what we used to call a social
sure, Sartre and Rorty would agree that greed, fear, etc., are contingentfeatures
of individuals, that they are part of no human "essence." Unfortunately, Rorty
does often write as though the problem is that in fact there are simply some greedy people who happen to have money or power. This allows him not to have to address capitalism as such-and he doesn't.
Sartre is much more radical in his understanding of contingency: not only are
, greed and resentment, and the rest, not an essential feature of any human persons, they are also not essential features of human social formations. But they are indeed a part of our existing societies, and they are expressive of something even deeper
that has gotten into society, something that does not accord, so to speak, with the
contingent existence of persons, but indeed imposes a certain serialized essence
,(or perhaps it is simply a necessity) on society and persons. Indeed, Sartre wants
. tb go so far, in the
Critique, as to say that there was no absolute necessity that hu-
manity took the path that it did, long ago, with regard to scarcity and the social sur
plus.
Thai is, humanity faced a crossroads at the point where social surpluses were
generated (when the labor process created more than was strictly necessary for
subsistence); as we know, the path entered into was one where society was divided into classes. Certainly this was expressive of one human possibility, even if, as
with all choices, other possibilities were closed off by it. And yet, for Sartre, this
way of looking at the issue shows (much as Engels had demonstrated empirically, in·his
The Origin ofthe Family, Private Property, and the State, where he used the
example of the Iroquois Indians of North America) that there is another possibil ity of humanity, namely
communism, that remains imbedded in history. (Consid
ering Engels's example, we might say that only some societies entered into the
path of class division, but that these have managed to "infect," in one way or an other, all other societies in the unfolding of history.) •
And yet-and again, here, I see Sartre's thinkiDg of contingency as much more
radical than Rorty's-there is no essence that is speaking through a history that might frod its way toward communism. Redemption, then, is indeed a "work,"
even if it also depends
011
the "grace" (which is in some sense infinite) of all the
possibilities that are set out before us and are indeed within us. Meaning in his�
tory has to be made, in just the same sense that Marx said the working class must
emancipate itself-no one else can accomplish this.
But, wait a second, why is Rorty not just as open to the contingencies of his
tory as Sartre? Indeed, why not see Rorty as even more open, in that he wants to
affmn the side of Sartre's thinking that seeks a "consistently atheistic position in philosophy," while abandoning anything that appears to be a theological hang
over and (what seems to Rorty to be linked to the theological language) "Stalin
ism." Perhaps the two figures find their strongest and most provocative unity
when Rorty affmns Sartre's statement at the end of "Existentialism is a Human
ism" that even Nazism, if it were to triumph, could become the "tfl!,th of history."
Introduction
10
Certainly those who ask, ironically, "Why did the heavens not darken?" (the title of Amo Mayer's Marxist analysis of the Holocaust), are recognizing, in a mate rialist way, that there is no overseer external to history who can say, "no, that is not the truth of history, instead it is this other thing." Instead of attempting, how ever, as those who raise this question do (and as Sartredid with the
Griiique and
with analytical tools such as seriality afld the practi�o:inert), a systematic analy sis of the social basis of his.t9rical catastrophe, Rorty only gives us lists of names (his usual-and shopworn-litany is Lenin, Stalin, Mao, Hitler, and Pol Pot) and vague notions such as "cruelty." This last has primarily to do, in Rorty's argot, with instances where we impose our own definitions of selfhood upon others (or where we tamper with the attempt of others to define themselves). What is seen here, given of course that Rorty is not a "Sartrean" per se, rather he instead wants to take only certain things from Sartre, is what I once called "logical existentialism," something I associated with Wittgenstein. (In my clever
exposition, in an as-yet unpublished paper, I turned the "E" in ,existentialism backwards and put it in parentheses with the "x," to form the symbol for the quan tification of "there is some x, such that.") Wittgenstein is certainly closer to Rorty's heart than is Sartre, and I wonder if this might be true of V{ittgenstein's sense of contingency as well. Of course, Rorty talks about the "world well lost," the world that can be known without any mediation (or, at least, the world that "exists" beyond any knowing of it). But then, Rorty also does not go where at least the early Wittgenstein points, toward the essential mystery of the "thatness" of the world. So, speaking of hearts, I think that Sartre and Wittgenstein take this concern deeper into their hearts than does Rorty. After all, Rorty would only see this as an interesting question insomuch as it has to do with some, specific prob lem that might be solved (though one is of�course welcome to engage in theolog ical speculation in one's private time, if one finds this helpful in the 'pursuit of self-creation). Therefore, what really "floats" for Rorty are language games and ' forms of life, personal "vocabularies." Somehow Sartre remains concerned with a world-and "being"-where con tingency goes all the way down, even to existence itself. That is� the existence of anything and "everything" is contingent. The difficulty is then one of thinking about ethics and politics in a world without necessary existence, which for both Rorty and Sartre means a world without God. And yet, clearly their senses of the meaning of such a world-a world, to use Heidegger's language, of purely ontic reality-are different, the one attempting to bring this existential project into in tegration with Marxism, the other with "postmodern bourgeois liberalism." Are these very different political engagements themselves merely contingent features of what remain similar readings of contingency, or
are
their readings of contin
gency in fact different? I wonder if the difference can be found in the different approaches of pragma tism and Marxism to the theory of knowledge. I should add here that I am only referring to Rorty's pragmatism, which may be somewhat close to Dewey's, but
11
Ever since May: The radical project
less so to James's and Pierce's. But in saying this I am arguing backwards, in that
. what I am thinking about is the way that Rorty and Dewey have both served as apologists for U.S. imperialism, while James was a leading figure in the AnticIm
perialist League. And yet I think this form of argumentation is appropriate, be
I cause it goes to the question of engagement. Mao once summarized Marxist epistemology quite succinctly: if you want to know an apple, bite into it. In· this
' · engagement, both the apple and the consumer of the apple
are
transformed. By
"contrast, for Rorty, projects of self-transformation are essentially private. Indeed, . the thing to be engaged with, when it comes to problems in society, is the way
that someone's private psychological state-as greedy, cruel, etc.-has come to
play a limiting role in society when it comes to the ability of others to engage in
private defmitions of their vocabularies. For all that some analytical philosophers see Rorty as a traitor to their cause, his :lnain activities
are
typical of at least the
predominant trend in analytic philosophy: debunking and clarifying. I do not
m�an this as a broadside against analytic philosophy (and, insomuch as a certain
trend in continental philosophy provides only a mirror image of these activities, namely hyperbole and obfuscation, it is no alternative), and certainly some of Rorty's clarifications are helpful.
But this is where one can see Sartre's basic unity with Marx's famous Eleventh
Thesis: Rorty goes part of the way -one might even say that he goes the :'bour geois liberal" part-toward grasping contingency as a
modality, as something to modality, but I do not see that he understands what it might mean not only to be thrown into a contingent world, but also, as engage ment, to throw oneself into this contingency. This is a world where Nazism may be.contrasted to necessity as a
become the truth of history-Rorty embraces this problematic, but, to put it
crudely, what does he do about it? I do not mean this as any sort of "indictment"
of the intellectual enterprise-please do not misunderstand. It was as an engaged
answer to this question that Sartre threw himself into struggles over capitalism, fascism, colonialism, racism, anti-Semitism, and imperialism. The outcome of these struggles was far from predetermined, and Sartre broke with any triumphant
"materialism" (such as that of the French Communist Party) that saw victory as
"in the cards." It was in the context of such struggles that Sartre engaged with the
Soviet Union, under the leadership of Stalin, as one possibility for how commu
nism might be incarnated in this contingent world-this world that is not simply
one'of dreaming the liberal utopia in the privacy of one's own cyberspace or
video game. (It was also from this perspective that Sartre later broke with the So
viet Union and PCF.) For this reason, Sartre also has something to tell us about the actual unfolding of the Stalin period. I do not see that one will learn anything specific on this issue from reading Rorty.
Is this backwards argument justified, or is it really just a kind of personal at
tack? Perhaps I should state for the record that I almost always find Professor
Rorty's arguments provocative. I will give him credit for this: quite often when
I read him, my first impulse is to get to work with refuting him. That is not an
12
Introduction
entirely bad thing. But let me come at this from yet another angle. If one gives up the notion that history unfolds according to some law of necessity, in other words, if one gives up History, does one therefore abandon the analysis of what indeed unfolded? If there is no totalizer, is there therefore no totality and no · work of understanding concrete totality? If there is such an analysis and work, how does the theorist situate hiffiself or herself with regard to it? To think that one could situate oneself externally seems to partake of the sort of theological and "totalitarian" approach that both Sartre and Rorty want to cast off. What is it, then, to fully grasp the alternative? In light of this question, I propose that Rorty does well enough with contingency if it is just a matter of grasping con tingency as concept or modality-but, then, does this not simply lead us into an other (illusory) externally grasped totality? Indeed, isn't contingency, under stood on this level, just as merely formal as the "freedom" experienced in postmodern bourgeois liberal, that is, capitalist, society? Finally, we might ask why, if Sartre seeks a consistently atheistic position, he is so inclined toward theological terms, even if they are "inverted." (Here Sartre is again not unlike Marx, especially the �arly Marx.) Rorty seems to be reading backwards here, from Sartre's use of such terms and his concrete political en gagements, to supposed limitations in the understanding of contingency, and it is hard to see why Rorty would not be entitled to such a reading. Let us ask the question another way: Why, unlike Rorty, does Sartre not see the contingent world in which we find ourselves as a world where we must intellectually engage in the project of disenchantment, especially if we are to break with traditional and authoritarian forms of morality and politics? My hope is that the set of investigations that form this book will give some sense as to why Sartre is a philosopher of possibility and not prImarily of secular disenchantment. It seems to me that the answer to Rorty's reading of the politics of contingency ultimately has to do with Sartre's sense of the momentousness of the struggle for human possibility, in the face of everything that is set against it. Despite the fact that we have to accept the proposition that we might not have ex ' isted at all ("we humans," or we anything, and certainly any one of us as indi viduals) in this world after Darwin and quantum mechanics, and that even so we are seemingly insignificant bits of dust wandering about on one insignificant grain of sand in an inunense beach - or perhaps because of these things -the pos sibility of making something of ourselves (the possibility, of course, of our noth ingness, not our somethingness, to use more Sartrean language, which then means concretely analyzing the structures that would reduce us to thingness) is not something to approach in a disenchanted way. More than likely, Rorty would see both Sartre and Marx as allies in the proj ects of disenchantment and secularization. This, however, would be to confuse the priorities of the latter pair. Marx and Sartre were first of all concerned to show the material bases of a society that passes beyond the narrow horizons of bour geois right, toward the possibilities of a global community of mutual flourishing.
- Ever since May: The radical project
13
To be sure, there were times when both lost sight of the redemptive aspects of this project. Both were at times too entirely future-oriented. This issue has been ad dressed well by redemptive Marxists from Walter Benjamin and Raymond Williams to Fredric Jameson. As with the question of humanism, perhaps there is some one-sidedness toSartre. And yet I think this is a different question from that of the one-dimensionality of Rorty's secularism, a quality for which "postmodern \' bourgeois liberalism" seems an appropriate name. tJ So, let us go now into a series of investigations into that "different question," -, the question of fmding a social time beyond reification. We will begin with what has probably been the central quandary of the twentieth century, theStalin period I and the fate of the Soviet Union and the international communist movement under Stalin's leadership. As much as there is a postmodern tendency to say "enough" to "all that," it seemed clear to Sartre that the fate of socialism in the ,twentieth century was the historical question around which all other questions 'navigated. We will conclude with an examination of the emergence of postmod ern capitalism itself, as understood especially by an intellectual with deep Sartreiln roots, Fredric Jameson. In Jameson's view, with which I concur, fateful historical questions, such as that of theStalin period, are being swept aside by the new forms of the capitalist juggernaut. In such a space, it becomes increasingly difficult for political questions to appear as such. Society passes over more and more into the "pure administration of things" (not in the sense that Engels had hoped for with the withering of the state-at least that is what one would like to believe, but we now also see that Engels's formulation was troublesome, to say the least). The permanence of the institution, rather than that of the revolution, looms. CanSartre help us here? I continue this discussion in the afterword.Sartre has been so identified with the twentieth century; what can he say to us now that "his century" is over? I have come to believe that not all nostalgia is bad. There might be a "critical Jlostalgia" that is part of a project of radical retriev�. ("Only reconnect," I said in my book, Listening to thefuture, giving a spin to E. M. Forster's well-known say ing.) Those of us of a certain generation (born in the fifties), or older, fmd our selves in the strange position of looking back upon the twentieth century with a degree of nostalgia and regret that we are leaving the place. After all, unless med ical advances drastically extend our lifespans fairly soon, it will have been the century where we spent most of our lives. But, what a strange century to look back upon with any kind of nostalgia-the bloodiest century in history! We are lucky to be getting out of it with our lives. However, I think that our nostalgia is oriented toward something even larger, a certain promise that we thought history was making, despite the fact of contingency. We associatedSartre with this prom ise. (I associate Derrlda with this promise as well, which is yet another reason wily the assimilation of his work to "postmodernism" is inappropriate-and this is what makes his remark concerning the generation of intellectuals from 1968, in his obituary for his friend Gilles Deleuze, all the more poignant, "Now I will
14
Introduction
have to go on by myself'). Now we seem to be infonned, on a d.aily this promise,is to be packed away with all of the other nicknacks of those worn out Constructs, "modernity" and "history." Too much nostalgia will lead us into the dead-end of "revolution" as some sort of grind-it's a crummy job, but some one's got to do it. But loss of connectioh altogether lands us in the posthistorical space of objectification with no outside. Can Sartre still speak to us in this diffi cult time of apocalypse as whimper? Can he speak to another generation for whom the twentieth century, the Stalin period, the struggle against fascism, the Chinese Revolution, May 1968, and the rest cannot help but seem very foreign? With these investigations, my hope is that he can and will.
1 Dictatorship "for" the proletariat i
Sartre's theory of the Stalin period
It was necessary to choose between disintegration and deviation of the Revolu tion. Deviation also means detour: Stalin was the man of that detour. "Hold on! Produce! . . . Later generations will go back to principles." And this was right, except that he did not see how in this very way he was producing generations which contained within them-as the inert materiality of the circumstances to be transcended-the deviation that had produced them and that they interiorized. -Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol. 2
S ometime ago, before postmodernity really began to set in, there used to be something that people thought of as an historical watershed. We were still en tranced by the idea that historical events could matter, that comers could be turned. Marx said somewhere that when the locomotive of history turns a cor ner, all of the intellectuals fall off. But, of course, to make such a claim is to as s\!me that intellectual activity, and for that matter,jts social basis in the practice of the masses, is on the locomotive to begin with. As we enter a period when "history" means something like the form of entertainment one receives by watching the History Channel, the sense of such turning points becomes ever more difficult to recover. In a Marxist frame, it is not hard to associate turning points of the twentieth century with wars and even battles. In 1 968, and at least into the early 1970s, there was no disputing that the Vietnam War was a turning point for Western im perialism, and for U.S. imperialism specifically. David was defeating Goliath. If one were thinking in a very teleological way, then one could see the Vietnamese resistance to the imperialists as related to, and perhaps even a continuation of, the comer that seemed to be turned at the battle of Stalingrad, when the Red Army decisively beat back the Nazi Wehrmacht. And yet, while both events constituted major victories against imperialism, neither alone nor together did they constitute even a very large interruption of the imperialist system. 15
Chapter 1
16
Marx might have said, people make historical teleology, but they do not make it just as they please. The historical forces that might overcoine capitalism are still amassing themselves. At Stalingrad, where things were especially dire, but then where it also seemed a corner had been turned, there was something else as well. The onward march of imperialism w!Js interrupted, just as it was interrupted by the Tet Offensive in 1968. But in. Stalingrad we also saw a concentrated form of . the "detour" that Sartre speaks of. . I could imagine a good arg ument that would say it is simply Eurocentric to focus on the Stalin period, and the Soviet Union and the international communist movement in that period, as the place where the gathering teleology of the move ment beyond capitalism got decisively off track. After all, one might argue that the Bolshevik Revolution represented, in the first place, a moment in the shift of revolution from the West to the East, and ultimately from the metropoles to the countryside of the world, from the First World to the Third. If one wants to point to the historical legacy of the Stalin period, why not also point to the failure of revolution in the more developed countries of Western Europe? Why isn't the failure theirs? Clearly, in at least one sense this is not a bad question: If the work ing class in Western Europe had not been so bought off with the spoils of impe rialism, if it had not been so narrowly focused on its immediate material condi tions and issues that have to do with little more than adjustments in the wage contract , if it had been able to raise its sights toward internationalism and ques tions that are properly political, then certainly we would be living in a different world today. Lenin, and Stalin after him, were keenly aware of having come into thoroughly uncharted territory, what Antonio Gramsci iroIrlcally called "a revo lution against Capital"-meaning both the social formation and Marx's book. The same tendencies, common to Sartre and Mao, that resist pinning all revolu tionary hopes on Europe (or other advanced capitalist countries, mainly the United States and Japan), also lead us to consider what might be made of a revo lution against capital, wherever it appears. Against the calls of those Lenin la beled "Philistines," whose continual bleat was, "they should not have taken to arms" (this being heard especially in the cases of the Paris Commune, the Easter Rebellion in Ireland, and the Bolshevik Revolution), Lenin argued that there are opportunities rare in history, and not to seize such opportunities constitutes his torical betrayal. The erstwhile leaders of the working class in Western Europe had indeed engaged in such betrayal; was Lenin bound, then, to follow course and wait for Germany? Now we are back into a language where such questions seem to matter. Whether that significance can still be recovered in our day is not something of which I feel entirely sure. Certainly, for Sartre, the issue of what Stalin's leadership meant for the first experiment in socialism on a country-wide scale was decisive; one could not understand the curve of the epoch (to use Sartre's expression from the Flaubert study), and therefore one could not
live in the most important sense-because to
really live is to live in the curve of one's epoch-without engaging with the ques-
Dictatorship "for" the proletariat
17
tion of Stalin. I think, and Sartre thought, that there are also reasons for moving beyond this question, toward the possibilities for postcapitalist society that were generated in the Third World, especially in China. Here, now, at the precipice of . postmodern capitalism, if there is still an historical question of capitalism, and an historical question of what comes after, then perhaps we will be able to reconnect . with the question, "What happened to socialism in the Stalin period," a question (' that remained decisive even after the movement against capitalism and imperial , ism shifted further East and South. (When I think of people struggling today in , .those parts of the world, I can imagine some postmodern response-and this is \vhere all the neoconservatives are just as blithely postmodern as anyone-saying, , "Haven't they gotten the word? Don't they know that the world is done with all that?" But, no, apparently they haven't heard.) There is a more specific issue here, regarding how we frame the .question, and this concerns the idea, accepted by even a good many Sartreans, that the need for .analysis of the Stalin period has been eclipsed by the so-called "failure of com munism" and "collapse of communism" in the 1989-91 period. (Not that the events that transpired in the former Eastern Bloc are not remarkable.) What col lapsed in the Soviet Union in those years was not socialism; without going into the question fully at this point (this will come later), it is necessary to recall that this was the position also held by Sartre, at least by the early 1960s. Mao.Tsetung came to the same conclusion around that time. A larger study exploring to what extent the views of Sartre and Mao converge regarding capitalist restoration is still to be done (though I hope that what follows contributes to such an effort). My sense is that they agree with and/or complement each other in important ways (though with significant disagreements too). They certainly share the basic per spective that, in the Stalin period, the proletarian revolution got off track, and that to investigate the reasons and factors involved is a question of immense histori cal and practical importance. With Stalin, socialism is, to say the least, very much in a muddle. In my view, one cannot understand the theory and practice of so�ialism in China, under Mao's leadership, without viewing it against the background of this muddle. And yet, even with Maoism, there is a tendency to see socialism in China as the "next stage" but without making all of the qualitative breaks with Stalin that are neces sary. Such a tendency is part and parcel of Marxism and materialism, I think, be cause there is always a pull toward reductivism and quantitative thinking. To un derstand how things could be a part of the same process, and yet also to see qualitative transformations in the process, is a hard thing, and ultimately this can not be understood apart from practice and struggle. Part of the reductivist ten dency is to give the kind of defense of Stalin that largely avoids the issue of how the ground was laid for the restoration of capitalism in the Soviet Union under his leadership. This, of course, has not been the main tendency in the discussion of Stalin and his role in the international communist movement, but Sartre's ques tion concerned the revolutionary critique of Stalin.
Chapter 1
18
With both Mao's and Sartre's arguments in mind, I believe that it is appropri ate to say that the Stalin experience is a "segment of the spiral." That is, this ex perience belongs to the proletarian revolution. However, there is
a
tendency
among the Maoists to see this segment as, on the whole, "moving upward"-even as Mao's nonlinear notion of history: 'opens the way for understanding how there can be "bad socialism," as it were. Sometimes the idea among Maoists is that the Mao experience "takes over" at the point where Stalin leaves off, which then makes the whole process linear again, and which therefore closes the way toward radical rupture. (Derrida calls such ruptures "the experience of the impossible," an idea I find crucial in this context.) One version of linearity that is well-known is Mao's famous 70/30 assessment - Stalin was seventy percent good, thirty per cent bad. Perhaps it is good on some level to try to quantify things-at least, it does not hurt to look at certain aspects of the Stalin experience and differentiate among them. Certainly this is better than to see the experience as all bad or all good. But suppose the experience on this account was sixty percent bad and forty percent good. Would we then have to say that the Stalin experience was not a part of the experience of socialist revolution? Clearly we need a way toward a more qualitative understanding. There were, to my mind, real achievements of the So viet people and the international communist movement under the leadership of Stalin (and though some of these achievements were accomplished
despite that
leadership, not all of them were). The "upward" assessment (70/30 and the rest; of course, if one wants to see the truly fawning assessment, one has to venture into Enver Hoxha territory-see
With Stalin, it is fascinating stuff) has largely
�
been a response to the unrelentingly "downward" assessm nt of an interesting array of people and political forces, from reactionaries who never hoped for any thing other than that socialism would be defeated, to honest progressives and rad icals who believe that socialism, even under enormously difficult circumstances, should have achieved much more and should have put the masses in a better po sition to struggle against and defeat capitalism. It is within such a complex field that Sartre attempted to not simply apply 20120 hindsight, but instead to get in side the logic of history. Because I have already mentioned Mao a good bit in this discussion, perhaps this is the point to say that I do not think the problems of the Stalin period go away if one simply disavows Mao (as is the fashion within much of the Left these days). Capitalism, as no one will deny, is a very tough nut to crack, especially in the way that it works through capillary movements into every nook and cranny of life and society. Mao's argument is that socialism is a contradictory social for mation, in which class struggle continues and even, in some ways, intensifies. This intensification takes place especially where power is concentrated, in the top leadership of the communist party (and, indeed, within individual leaders) . The class struggle then makes itself felt as a two-line struggle, between those taking the capitalist road and those attempting to give leadership, on various fronts, to the struggle to cross the narrow horizons of bourgeois right . Class struggle can-
Dictatorship "for" the proletariat
19
not be waged if the leadership denies that there is class struggle under socialism. Stalin did in fact deny this in the mid-1930s, arguing that the material basis for the restoration of capitalism had been completely wiped out, at least insofar as the internal dynamics of the Soviet Union were concerned. The only basis for restora tion, S ' talin argued, was external; thus all activity that ran counter to the wishes of the leadership was necessarily the work of agents of capitalist powers. It is es s!(,ntial to see thatStalin's thinking here, as dogmatic as it was, and as dogmati cally as it was applied, represented the conventional wisdom among Marxists at the time. Among these would be Trotsky, who did not argue that the dreaded "bu reaucracy" was itself a class. Here, as elsewhere, my understanding of Maoism is very much shaped by the writings of Bob Avakian, in particular his Conquer the World? The International Proletariat Must and Will. Though I have never been overly fond of the title, I find this to be an extremely insightful overview of the development of the inter.-national communist movement from the time of Marx and Engels to the present period. The present discussion, in fact, could be quite fruitfully expanded to en compass the arguments of Sartre, Mao, and Avakian. Avakian argues that, witll the seizure of power in one or a few countries, and the beginnings of socialist construction, the proletariat can no longer be said to simply have "nothing to lose but its chains" (to quote the last words of the Communist Manifesto). The exis tence of a socialist country in a world still dominated by capitalism presents the international communist movement with a contradiction that cannot simply be re solved in a linear way. This argument is very much anticipated by the section of Sartre's Critique of Dialectical Reason, volume 2, that has come to be known as "Socialism in One Country." (This is the title that was given to the section when it was published separately in New Left Review number 100; in CDR2, the section ' forms the bulk of the chapter on "the unresolved struggle as anti-labor.") Apart from arguments concerning the overall coherence of the unfinished second vol ume of the Critique, the sections on the Stalin period provide some crucial theo- retical tools. (The manuscript for CDR2 was not"ublished until 1985, five years afterSartre's death, in an edition edited by Sartre's adopted daughter and literary executor, Arlette Elkaim-Sartre. Different views on the book's integrity are pre sented by Ronald Aronson, in his Sartre 's Second Critique, where it is argued that the book essentially hangs together, and William McBride, in his Sartre 's Politi cal Theory, where the claim is that the project is not really integrated and perhaps cannot be. I am more inclined toward the former view.) In particular, I will con centrate on the idea of the "dictatorship for the proletariat" as a key link in un derstanding what happened to socialism underStalin's leadership. So, let us tum now to Sartre's conception of the impasse of socialism that was the penultimate result of Stalin's leadership-the ultimate result being the restoration of capitalism when Khrushchev and company decisively resolved Stalin's muddle. Already some of the analysis that has been presented thus far in outline form explains some important aspects of th,eStalin experience. That
20
Chapter 1
is, on some level, Stalin's errors represent limitations in what was generally understood by Marxists in that period concerning the construction of social ism. What is more difficult is to create an analysis that shows decisively where and when, in a fully contextualized sense, the Stalin "deviation" went beyond bad; dogmatic Marxism into the impa.sse of Marxism. In other words, I find the "spiral" concept explanatory on the whole, and I would especially propose the idea of the Stalin period as a segment of the spiral against those who want to deal with problems of socialism simply by disavowing major parts of the so cialist experience (so that, when things go wrong or bad, they simply say, "that wasn't us"; I am thinking especially of the various Trotskyist arguments, and an interesting point for further exploration is that we might take these argu ments as concentrated versions of all Eurocentric arguments that also take the definition of socialism to be something like the "full realization" of democ ' racy; part of my point here is that, if we do not take responsibility for social ism when it messes up, then how can we expect to fix it?). However, without some mediating concept that explains the impasse of socialism-or the aspects of the Stalin experience that represent an impasse-we will tend to have too linear a view of how revolution might be "restarted." That is, we might lose sight of the crucial point that it is never simply a matter of taking up where things left off, but , rather of reinventing revolution. The deviation and impasse are not, I think, equivalent to the idea of "de generation" as this term is often used-that is, in Trotsky's conception of a "degenerated workers' state." There was degeneration, to be sure (just as there was bureaucratization), but to describe the Stalin period as a whole as simply a period of degeneration,Sartre seems to indicate, is not accurate. Instead, the experience is more of a mixed bag. T his assessment, I would argue, is certainly implied by "Socialism in One Country," where Sartre clearly believed there was at that time still a revolution to be defended; I believe this claim is not controversial, despite the fact that some Sartreans have recently joined in with "failure of socialism" rhetoric. Part of my rehearsal of some similarities be tween Sartre and Mao on the question of capitalist restoration has to do with this turn among some Sartreans. I am recalling especially a session at the 1991 meeting of the North American Sartre Society in which the Critique was ap plied to more recent events in Eastern Europe, as if socialism had existed in that part of the world until the end of the 1980s. I found this strange and not at all true to Sartre (whatever other arguments might have been mustered for the positions offered). It also seemed to me as if the sixties, during which many people realized that the Soviet Union was not a force for liberation, Sartre not least of all (nor was he quiet about it), had been forgotten - even though (or was it especially though?) the people presenting the papers at this session were from the sixties generation. A passage from What Is Literature ? gives us a feel forSartre's sense of the im passe in 1947:
Dictatorship "for" the proletariat
21
We were not unaware that a time would come when historians would be able to survey from all angles this stretch of time which we lived feverishly minute by minute . . . . But the irreversibility of our age belonged only to us . We had to save or lose ourselves gropingly in this irreversible time. These events pounced upon us like thieves and we had to do our job in the face of the incomprehensible and untenable, to bet, to conjecture without evidence, to undertake in uncertainty and persevere " wi�out hope. Our age would b e explained, but no one could keep it from having I, been inexplicable to us. (Romano , 566)
d
This passage is quoted at the end of a review of Tony ludt's book, Past Imperfect.
ludt's ai.m is to discredit Sartre by claiming that he was an uncritical supporter of Stalin. The reviewer, Carlin Romano, does a good job of defending Sartre- even if his defense is predicated on the typical Stalin-bashing that does not move us closer to understanding the Stalin period, which is of course what S artre tried to do. It is not surprising that neoliberals are turning their guns on Sartre, as did neo conservatives before them. There
are
many dimensions to this attack, including
the need to discredit, in advance of any new period of social turmoil and rebel lion, the idea of the engaged intellectual. Although some (perhaps most) readers will find this strange, I also see this sort of attack as a reminder of why we needed (and still need, though it may be too late) a radical defense of Paul de Man and perhaps even (God forgive me) Martin Heidegger: the neoconservative attacl}s on them had nothing to do with any attempt to understand fascism, but instead were maneuvers in the general war· on critical thought that was launched as part of the Reagan era. For reasons that we will turn to in a moment, Stalin did not see the role of the Soviet Union in the Second World War as a kind of "bet." (The "without hope" part in the Sartre quotation goes beyond, I think, Sartre's critique of determinist materialism; instead, I see this 'as a kind of class marker, an expression of a petty bourgeois outlook.) Stalin did not see that fight as an "undertaking without cer tail!ty" in the name of the proletarian revolution. To l>e sure, the outcome of the war was far from certain, and the S oviet Union could have been defeated. But the perspective of putting things on the line, indeed, putting everything on the line, for the larger aims of the world revolution was not Stalin 's perspective. (Here I am especially indebted to Avakian's arguments .) In a moment we will say more about the outlook that was characteristic of Stalin, but we can already see that, under-the perspective that the revolution is only a "conjecture with evidence" (the
evidence of the one existing socialist country), the revolution could not help but
find itself in an impasse. The accomplishments of the revolution could not help but turn, in the long run, into their opposites . As Sartre so famousJy put it in
Searchfor a Method, "Marxism stopped": Marxism, after drawing us to it as the moon draws the tides, after transforming all our ideas, after liquidating the categories of our bourgeois thought, abruptly left us stranded. It did not satisfy our need to understand. In the particular situation in which
22
Chapter 1 we were placed it no longer had anything new to teach us, because it had come to a stop. . : '. Marxism stopped. Precisely because this philosophy wants to change the ' world, because its aim is "philosophy-becoming-the-world," because it is and wants to be practical , there arose within it a veritable schism which rejected theory on one side
/
and praxis on the other. From the moment the USSR, encircled and alone, undertook its gigantic effort at industrialization, Marxism found itself unable to bear the shock of these new struggles; the practical necessities and the mistakes that always arise from them. At this period of withdrawal (for the USSR), of the ebbtide (for the proletariats),
the ideology itself was subordinated to a double need: security (that is, unity) and the construction of socialism inside the USSR. Concrete thought must be born from praxis and must turn back upon it in order to clarify it, not by chance and without rules , but as in all sciences and all techniques-in confonnity with principles. Now the party leaders, bent on pushing integration to the limit, feared that the free process of truth, with all the discussions and all the conflicts which it involves, would break the unity of combat; they reserved for themselves the right to define the line and to interpret the event. In addition, out of fear that the experience might not provide its own clarities, that it might put into question certain of their guiding ideas and might contribute to "weakening the ideological struggle," they put the doctrine out of reach. The separa tion of theory and practice resulted in transfonning the latter into an empiricism with out principles; the former into a pure, fixed knowledge.
(21-22)
Even before turning to Sartre's discussion of the line struggle between Stalin and Trotsky, we might note that something of this characterization already applies to the period of Civil War and War Conununism (the latter is Lenin's term for a pe riod in which the embattled revolution must proceed as something of a "forced march")-and, certainly, it is accurate up to a point to characterize the Stalin pe riod as the return to a seemingly permanent state of War Conununism. Nothing must break the unity of combat! Given the direction the discussion of these mat ters almost always takes, my one proviso here is that, in considering the politics of desperation, even where the desperation seems to be a gross overreaction-this is always easy to say with 20120 hindsight, but certainly this characterization has to apply to aspects of Stalin's leadership-one must never lose sight of the causes of the desperation. During the actual period of "War Conununism" (roughly from the Civil War until the New Economic Program, 1918-21), for instance, some of the more authoritarian measures were authorized by Trotsky -who seemingly never hesitated over such things. In other words, simply chanting the mantra, "Stalinism," ad infinitum, does not help to explain much. At the beginning of "Socialism in One Country," Sartre claims that "[we] are simply taking an example, which we shall consider notfor its own sake but for its pedagogic value" (98). This I find hard to believe! In fact, this section, which amounts to about eighteen pages, is so rich, that a short book could be written about it. One aspect of the analysis that I will not pursue at length here has to do with the way that Sartre shows the personalities of Trotsky and Stalin interacting with the line struggle that unfolded in the twenties. One does wonder what might be said if the same question and methodology that Sartre applied to Gustave
Dictatorship "for" the proletariat
23
Flaubert -"What can be known of a man?"- were to be applied to the antago
nists in this case. In any case, Sartre does not resort to the standard Trotskyist
claim that Stalin was "the outstanding mediocrity of his time," or that Stalin had
no roots among the masses . In fact, Sartre argues that the lack of roots was pre cisely the problem for the emigres , those who spent a good deal of the period from about 1903 until 1917 in Western Europe. The way that Sartre frrst of all in fegrates the "personalities" question is in pitting the "westernizing intellectual"
-against the militants working in Russia. I believe that his analysis here is useful, at least in a preliminary way, for seeing the Eurocentrism that remains the hall mark of Trotskyism (and, again, for all forms of socialism that define the project primarily in terms of "true" or "radical" democracy; on these points, see espe
cially 1 10-1 1 ). Sartre's analysis also points to the problems of intellectualism.
But all of these issues - personality, intellectualism, a fundamentally Western ori
entation- only make sense, in Sartre's perspective, in terms of the actual contra diction embodied in Stalin's line .
Let us go directly to the relevant passages.
Against universalist radicalism, Stalin infelicitously defmed what might be called a particularist radicalism. And, of course, that monstrous object did not remain at the level of the verbal formulation. Insomuch as it was to define a propaganda, a penna nent character of praxis, and a certain future, it could be termed an institution. . : • Any positivist history that sought to explain the Stalinist slogan ["socialism in one country"] by the internal weakness and isolation of the USSR around 1925-30, and re- . garded these as passively suffered, would miss the crucial point. Of course, everyone did suffer poverty, they all did suffer isolation; but at the same time these conditions were products of revolutionary praxis . . . . Poverty, shortage of technicians and cadres·, encirclement: these were mortal dangers for the Revolution, and at the same time they were the Revolution itselfcoming into being in a particular situation. (104-5) One very important strength of Sartre 's analysis is that he does not argue that
the revolution should not have occurred because conditions were not yet
"ripe." (This was Kautsky's claim in the aftermath of 1917, representing Eu rocentric Marxist orthodoxy.) For he goes on to say that a revolution elsewhere would also have had to deal with the
particular contradictions involved in
coming into existence in a p articular situation (Sartre discusses the example of England in this light; see 107). To this it might be responded that, while it is
undeniably true , there is a particular p articularity that Marx was concerned with, namely the state of development of the mode of production. The issues
at stake here are well known: the economies of backward countries are not de
veloped enough to sustain socialism, as they are barely even able to sustain
capitalism (if that), and therefore any attempt at socialist revolution in such a
country is doomed in advance. This remains the view within certain Marxist
orthodoxies; if I may, I will illustrate using the example of a personal en
counter that is entirely typical.
Chapter 1
24 In the spring of
1 998 I had the good fortune to attend the opening confer
iIw
ence of a:new society of Marxist academics in England, meet
at John
Moores University in Liverpool. The keynote speaker for the gathering was
the well�known Marxist literary scholar, Terry Eagleton. His talk restated the
bit of orthodoxy mentioned just now, the sort of thing that has been heralded in recent years as a "return to classical Marxism." Let us recall again that, in
relation to this "classical" view, Sartre is often labeled as a "moralizer" and a
"Third World-ist." Here we see the great divide in Marxism; on the one side is
what Lenin called economism and Mao called the "theory of productive forces," while, on the other side is what I would call internationalism and anti
imperialism, and which I associate with Sartre , as well as with Lenin and Mao.
In the discussion period after his talk, I had the opportunity to raise the fol
lowing question to Professor Eagleton: "If socialism can only be built in places
where the productive forces are in an advanced state of development, what would one say then to people who are struggling in Peru , or Haiti, or Indone
sia? Should we just tell them to wait and see what the Germans come up
with?" In response, Eagleton quoted Lenin: "It can begin here, but it cannot be
finished here." Lenin , of course, was referring to Russia, and his words would
seem to be a response to the idea, which Stalin set out in the terms that we are
discussing, of "socialism in one country." But it seems to me that these words
divide into two, and that the Eurocentric slant of Professor Eagleton's use of
them actually goes against the thrust of Lenin's position. One part of Lenin's
statement is that the revolution to take the world beyond its present form of so
cial organization is a global process, one that cannot be completed within the confines of any one country. (In our time, I think we are still trying to under stand this point, and the issue is complicated by transformations within capi
talism itself.) If one reads this statement from Lenin in the context of a Marx
ism that is oriented first of all toward the developVJ,ent of the productive
forces, however, what Professor Eagleton is really saying is that we will quote this statement if the question of an economically "backwards"country, and the
particular particularity we are concerned with, namely the productive forces,
is raised; but we will not raise the iSSUe, or not in the same way, if it is a mat
ter of socialism arising in the "advanced" countries.
Undoubtedly, there are obstacles to the construction of socialism that
are
deeply and directly connected to the economic level of a given society - and its level of culture,
as well. To express these difficulties mainly in terms of the "re
turn to classical Marxism," however, then turns out to work on three levels that run up against the project of human emancipation as international and global:
( 1)
a canceling of the twentieth century, which then circumvents the development of imperialism in the sense that Lenin used the term; (2) a fundamental orientation
toward Europe, and therefore toward the better-off and more bourgeoisified strata
of the working class; (3) a return to economic determinism, whereby culture is
Dictatorship "jor" the proletariat
25
merely the epiphenomenal excrescence of the productive base. On the matter of culture, what is also missed by the economist trend is the fact that a great pro portion of the masses in imperialist countries have received decades of schooling in the culture of imperialism. Sartre locates the fundamental contradiction of the Stalin period elsewhere, and then assimilates these economic particularities to it. The crux of the matter, ,for Sartre, is the question of incarnation: . the Revolution, incarnated in the center of the world as a long-tenn praxis defined by definite material circumstances, could not itself develop without engendering-by its actual course, albeit in contradiction with its leaders' project-the impotence of for eign proletariats. In this sense,
it can be said that its incarnation was in direct con tradiction with its universalization. (105, my emphasis)
This is the most important argument here: the revolution as it must incarnate it self creates a contradiction /or the revolution. When I say, "as it must incarnate itself," I mean, as the revolution actually comes into the world. To abandon this contradiction, however, is to abandon the revolution itself-either through Kaut sky's "they should not have taken to arms," because the situation was not yet "ripe," or through Trotsky's invocations of "internationalism" or "permanent rev olution." To see why the point applies in the latter case, we need to look further at the way that Sartre fleshes out the contradiction: The contradiction here derived from the fact that the proletarian Revolution in the USSR, instead of being a factor in the liberation and emancipation of Europe's work ing class masses - as it should have been- was achieved at the cost of plunging them into relative impotence.
(105)
Sartre refers in a footnote to "[t]he subsequent and crucially important achieve ments" that the Revolution made, "directly or indire&tly (defeat of Nazism, tri umph of communism in China, emergence of the Third World)," but argues that these cannot be figured into an appraisal of the first phase of the revolution , where- I agree with Sartre-there were real contradictions between pursuing the revolution in Russia and unfolding revolution in Europe. (Perhaps the Brest Litovsk treaty is the most important example of this from the earliest period of the Bolshevik Revolution. The signing of the treaty allowed some "breathing room" for the revolution in Russia, and it also provided an example of the with drawal from imperialism, but it also allowed the nations that continued the war to attack the masses even more violently. The Soviet Union also signed border agreements that effectively traded security for the revolution for the suppression of communists in other countries.) The point, again, is that the trade-off in the concrete situation was between a "particularist universalism" and an "abstract universalism," and this trade was already being made in the earliest period of the
Chapter 1
26
revolution. In the name of the concrete gains of the revolution, the particular, the incarnate,' \.
- .'
Stalin himself, despite innumerable acts of treachery, did still help the Chinese, Spanish, etc., to the extent he believed possible without provoking armed interven tion by the West.
(106)
Everything, in other words, had to be subordinated to the defense of the Soviet Union, to consolidation of the revolution. Although this was a form of "national"
defense, and although nationalism came to play a very large role-especially leading into the Second World War, when an increasing number of icons from Russia's tsarist past were revived -the all-consuming emphasis on consolidation was not simply the "betrayal" of the revolution. (This is not to say that there was not a significant
element of betrayal.)
"socialism in one country" was the product of revolutionary praxis reflecting upon its effects and the contradictions it had engendered. Synthetically, and approaching
the dogma of the Bolshevik Party's interiorization of these contradictory results, it
an attempt to lift the mortgage of internation alism, while retaining the USSR's ability to give assistance to foreign revolutionary parties in accordance with its means and the risks involved. (106, my emphasis) can be grasped in its intelligibility as
This passage needs to be understood in its entirety. TPe problem is this: how could it be said that "the workers have nothing to lose but their chains, the work
ers have no country," when indeed the workers had now acquired a country (and a rather large one at that, one-sixth of the world's landmass)? And, if the workers
did have a country, shouldn't the workers and their leaders do their part to take
very good care of it, and not risk it carelessly? I do not believe that any . other Marxists in the first fifteen or twenty years of the revolution understood this con
tradiction any better than Stalin
did; in fact, to this day, it seems to me that the
anti-Stalin trends still do not understand the contradiction. This is because, on all
sides (Stalin, Trotsky, Kautsky) there was a tendency to think that, if it is really a
revolution we are talking about, then it must proceed without fundamental con tradictions . (After all, the revolution itself, it is supposed, would have resolved the fundamental contradiction between social production and individual accumu lation , so it is now merely a matter of staying this course, in "permanence.")
Clearly there was a good deal of dogmatism, and it obviously cannot be said that Stalin was the least of the dogmatists and determinists.
What was worse, there was a basic distrust of the masses on the part of Stalin. Ironically, although Stalin wrote his first pamphlet on the difference between Marxism and anarchism, the latter trend not being something anyone would think
to associate Stalin with, still there was something of the "outlaw" and "renegade" in at least Stalin's early life. For instance, when Stalin was a Bolshevik leader in
Georgia, his section of the Party became famous for what were called "expropri-
Dictatorship "for" the proletariat
27
ations" - armed bank robberies. While I do not have any moral qualms with such robberies-I'm reminded of Brecht's famous quip that it is better to rob a bank than to own one-a tendency to rely on such methods was sufficiently criticized by Lenin, in
What Is To Be Done? Lenin argued that there is a fundamental unity
between terrorism, on the one side, and economism and reformism, on the other. !Vhile the "expropriations" were not exactly "terrorism," still, they were armed actions that were not deeply rooted in mass activism. (Perhaps there is a similar 'tty' here to Che Guevara's theory of "focoism" -the "roving band" model of or ganization.) Sartre also presents a compelling analysis of this distrust, one more rooted in the dynamics of the "monstrosity," socialism in one country. Sartre ar gues that the contradiction embodied in the revolution's incarnation breaks "any relation of reciprocity" between the USSR and the proletarians of other lands . "If the USSR could build socialism on its own, it did not really
need foreign help;
and if it still had to intervene-when it could-to aid revolutionaries in danger in . the capitalist nations, this was its
mission, its generosity" (CDR2, 106). 20/20 hindsight, but it seems to me
Perhaps this is an observation made with
that these errors on Stalin's part, errors in handling an objective contradiction en gendered by the revolution itself, were never an adequate excuse for the slavish ness of the socialists and communists in the West. Their continual bleat (and one hears this still today from certain quarters) has been that "Stalin- or, the Stalin ists-would not let them have a revolution." The situation was enormously com plicated, of course, and ·communists and other radicals believed sincerely in the imperative not to bring the wrath of the capitalist states down on the USSR, but what kind of revolutionary waits for permission to make revolution? Fortunately, Mao did not wait. But what Mao and Sartre both grasped was that socialism is an inherently contradictory social formation, because the incarnation of the revolu tion has not yet brought about a complete transcendence of capitalism-and yet, there is no going around specific incarnations and therefore there is no avoiding the contradictions of socialism. (Mao argues , famously, that every social system will have its contradiction, even communism.) In other words, whatever aspects of Stalin's personality may have played a role in the problems of the Soviet sys tem and the international communist movement in the Stalin period, this is not the place to begin an analysis of the fate of socialism in that period. The psychobiography approach is especially associated with Trotsky and Trotskyism. One thinks of Trotsky's use of terms such as "Asiatic," which strikes me as simply racist and a reflection of Trotsky's Eurocentrism, as well as his description of Stalin as "the outstanding mediocrity of our time ," and of course the Trotskyist Isaac Deutscher wrote a psychobiography of Stalin. In this vein, allow me to make the following observation, which has somehow escaped most commentators and, to be honest, did not occur to me until somewhat re cently. The discussion of the dynamic in the Soviet Union is almost always framed in terms of "Stalin versus Trotsky." My observation is that, even if Stalin had never been born, there is no way that Trotsky would have ever become the
28
Chapter 1
leader of the Bolshevik Party or the Soviet Union. Trotsky did not have roots in the party. On the contrary, he spent a good deal of his time between 1907 and
1 9 1 6 being harshly critical of Lenin. The idea that, in 1917, Lenin came to ac
cept Trotsky's theory of revolution is a concoction- significantly, the Tr€ltsky ists maintain that, at the same time, Trotsky came to accept Lenin's "theory of '
organization." Not only is this not really the case even in its own terms, hence
the ongoing comedy of the Trotskyist splinter groups, but the terms are flawed to begin with. What Lenin proposes in
What Is To Be Done? is ftrst of all a thee
ory of knowledge-having to do with how the proletariat and its allies comes to an understanding of the possibility of its self-activity and therefore, secondarily, what forms of leadership and organization are needed in this project. Further more, because Trotsky was an intellectual oriented toward the West, who spent parts of his journalistic career arguing for spurious notions such as a "United States of Europe," there was a basic distrust of Trotsky within the Bolshevik Party and even among the masses. Trotsky was a talented orator and intellectual , to be sure, but he was also given to demagoguery -in contrast to which Stalin
was regarded as "dull ," at least by Trotsky himself. While this is not the place for a complete critique of Trotskyism, my point here is that, along with the fact that his political line did not correspond to the working out of the objective con tradiction represented by the Bolshevik Revol ution and the emergence of the So viet Union, neither was there a real possibility that he would have become the leader of the Bolshevik Party in any case. With 20/20 hindsight, and attempting to look back through many years of the "Stalin versus Trotsky" interpretation, and keeping with Sartre's arguments about the political line, one can see better why Stalin emerged as the leader. Two of the main contenders - Zinoviev and Kamenev -were discredited by their having broken ranks with the Party leadership over the insurrection of October (old calendar) 1 91 7. Bukharin was somewhat younger than the others,
and he was also seen as someone who wanted to perpetuate the New Economic
Programme more or less indeftnitely ("we will build socialism at a snail 's pace," was his proposal). Although this is something of a simpliftcation, one might look at the matter in the following way. The Bolshevik Revolution and the creation of the USSR was the affirmation of a certain "spirit," represented first of all by Lenin, or by his conception of the dynamics of imperialism and proletarian revolution. Certain institutions "incarnated" this spirit, though most of the S oviet institutions that were set up between October 1917 and Jan
uary 1 924, when Lenin died, were either not well developed or of a highly pro
visional nature -most especially the N.E .P. "Socialist construction," as it was
called (after Lenin's famous statement after the October insurrection, pro claiming the existence of the USSR: "We shall now begin to construct the so cialist order"), really fell to Lenin's successors, and had no blueprint. In the wake of Lenin's passing, all of the leaders of the Communist Party of the So viet Union published accounts of what they considered Lenin's legacy to be,
Dictatorship ''for'' the proletariat
29
what they thought the meaning of the October Revolution was , and what they thought the future of the Soviet Union should be. Stalin's contribution to this
debate was
The Foundations of Leninism. While the book is what one might
call "workmanlike" if one were reviewing its aesthetic properties, there is a
very plausible argument that, of all the accounts published at that time, Stalin's
was the one that most represented the continuation of Lenin's line .
. It is not simply that Trotsky had not been a member of the Bolshevik Party until
Yess than a year before the Revolution, though of course there were reasons for this, and these reasons are generally obscured in Trotskyist accounts. When Trot
sky joined the Bolsheviks, it was as part of a group of Mensheviks called the "Menshevikki Internationalists." Why were they the "internation
a!i:sts"? Because
they had broken to some extent with the Menshevik position-or nonposition
on imperialism. By this last term I mean "imperialism" as Lenin understood it,
capitalism as a fully global mode of production, which creates a bifurcation in the
world that replicates the class struggle on a global scale (imperialist countries that are in a position similar to that of the bourgeoisie in individual countries , domi
nated countries that are more in the position of the proletariat) , and which creates
a basic division in the international working class itself. Two conclusions that
Lenin drew in light of this division were that the revolutionary party had to always
strive to go "lower and deeper" among the proletariat and basic masses (and there
fore
not base itself on the immediate economic demands of the better-off work
ers-in other words, this is Lenin's critique of what he called "econornism"), and
that; in the imperialist countries, the revolutionaries had to promote what Lenin
called "revolutionary defeatism." That is, whenever the social system in an impe
rialist country goes into crisis, which in Lenin's view will ultimately lead to war,
the proletariat and its allies must work for the defeat of "their own" ruling class.
These are positions that were resisted by the Mensheviks and by Trotsky (who was something of an "independent operator" in the period from
1907 to 1916, but
was formally a member of the Mensheviks), and that-are resisted to this day by
Trotskyists. (This goes especially for Lenin's argument about the division in the
working class.) For Lenin, there was a basic connection between this understand ing of imperialism and real internationalism, and there could be no "socialist rev
olution" except on the basis of internationalism and a recognition of the reality of
imperialism. All of this became muddled somewhat through the course of
1917,
because it was widely recognired that the social system in Russia was rotten to
the core, and Lenin presented the famous "Land, Peace, and Bread" formulation
as a way of popularizing the Bolshevik program. He also made alliances with the
left wings of the Mensheviks and the Social Revolutionary Party (this was a party
of agrarian reform, popular among the peasants), in order to build the broadest
base of unity for the revolution. But the basic idea was a revolution against not only capitalism, but against what capitalism had become, namely imperialism.
When Trotskyists talk, as they often do lately, of a reaffIrmation of "classical
Marxism," they are in fact denying this qUalitative development of capitalism
Chapter 1
30
(and, relatedly, they generally affinn the most economistic side of Marx). The
Bolsheviks were known for something else, their internationalist I'\nti-imperial ism, and Stalin, for all his personal flaws and all his tendencies toWard dogmatic and nondialectical materialism, was seen as carrying on this tradition.
There is one additional element of this consideration of Trotsky and his real
prospects for leadership in the Soviet Union, an element that I cannot do justice to
here. This is the question of the role that anti-Semitism played in the whole affair. Whether this question can be elevated to a central place in the conflict with Trot skyism I am not prepared to say - but I am prepared to recognize anti-Semitism as
a factor that significantly shaped politics , including radical politics, in Russia. This
is more than obvious , I realize. Sartre does pursue the question of what he calls "Stalinist anti-Semitism" in the second volume of the
Critique (263-271), though
without focusing on Trotsky. Still , more investigation is warranted.
Now, what does this seeming digression have to do with Sartre, beyond the more general points that have already been made? I think: that developing this context helps us understand better what seems to be an extraordinary incongruity: how did this great intellectual who, probably more than anyone in the twentieth century, was associated with the idea
offreedom, come to defend-if that is the
word, but I think: it is indeed the word - a fonn of Marxism that, in power, was
very often authoritarian, reductivistic, and, to put it crudely, "locked up"? Perhaps what we really see, in the transition from Being and Nothingness to the
Critique of Dialectical Reason and Sartre's engagement with historical materialism, is the recognition that "freedom" is a very complicated issue. There may be some re
spect in which it is ontologically simple, even if with complex ramifications, but freedom is also historically, socially, and politically complex - which then of course must have ontological ramifications for an anti-essentialist philosopher such as Sartre. Let me make this very concrete. When Sartre speaks of "the subsequent and crucially important achievements" of the Soviet Revolution, and, for instance, in cludes the "triumph of communism in China," the Eurocentric and "all that" crowd tends just to say "ho hum." ButJet us consider the historical context of Sartre's claim, and how this context relates to the question of freedom- includ ing the freedom
to live. Yes , it is true that the Chinese Communists, led by Mao
Tsetung, and the Chinese people, made their revolution for the most part despite
Stalin. Part of the "locked up" aspect of Stalin's Marxism was that he could not
recognize certain kinds of new developments. (Though this is again a place
where, for example, Trotsky's understanding was not any better.) Still, when the People's Republic of China was declared in 1 949, it was recognized by and given
material support by the Soviet Union. Furthennore, the People's Republic was
supported by Stalin and the very existence of the Soviet Union; even if this may seem like the most passive fonn of "support," it was in fact a decisive element in the ability of the revolutionary regime in China to survive its early years. For, let us be realistic here and ask, what would have happened to the revolution in China
Dictatorship "for" the proletariat
31
if there had not been a powerful socialist regime i n the Soviet Union, however flawed, at the time of its emergence? Of course, we cannot know for sure - cer
tainly Mao was not one to back away from threats . But I do think that we can say
with something approaching certainty that the Western capitalist powers , and ftrst
of all the United States, would have brought down every form of violence and
military technology on the Chinese people . Let us recall: the United States in
1945 used nuclear weapons to destroy two cities in Japan (the targets having been
decided in terms of where the working class areas were)
primarily as a way of
sending a message to the Soviet Union. The U.S . military planners, including Eisenhower, were ftrm in their view that dropping the atom bombs had nothing
to do with defeating the Japanese -they were already defeated (see Alperovitz). Furthermore , the United States launched a new war in Asia soon after the triumph of the Chinese Revolution - acting under the pretext of there being "two Koreas ," when these were in fact the creation of colonialism and imperialism. The United States was undoubtedly attempting to assert itself as the inheritor of Japanese and European (especially English and French) colonialism and imperialism in Asia.
Why would we have any reason to think otherwise than that the United States
hoped not only to march across Korea, but on into China as well? The fact that Mao and the Chinese people responded to this before U.S. troops
in that specific instance made it into China (because, of course , U.S. troops had been �n China
already, not so long before)-the fact that Mao beat the United States to the punch, as it were-is no vindication of the United States, nor is it any reason to
think that China was in any sense an "aggressor" in this conflict. (Neither is it a vindication, of course, that, the United States was not able to carry out its plans.) Furthermore, taking over for Japanese and French imperialism on the south side of China, and again employing the bogus idea that a country just somehow man aged to divide itself into two parts and that one of the parts was asking for U.S. intervention, the United States proved von Clausewitz's famous adage that "war is the continuation of politics by other me�" by using the most horriftc weapons- many of which were devices of mass torture, such as napalm and agent orange -in Vietnam . In the case of both Korea and Vietnam (and China, for
that matter) , the United States continually threatened to use nuclear weapons,
holding not only those countries , but indeed the entire world, in a state of nuclear
terror and blackmail. These were also the days when, recall, the United States
promoted the idea and practice of exploding one hydrogen bomb after another ei ther in or above the ground. As a result, whole , inhabited, islands in the South Pa cific were blown up, and radiation was allowed to drift across Utah because it was
specifically calculated that the Mormons would not raise a ruckus. Those so un fortunate as to be in the vicinity of fallout were advised to simply "duck and cover" and then brush the dust off of one's clothing . This is the context in which Sartre is considering the Stalin question. Sartre is fully aware of this context. I think that it is not at all extreme to assert that, if the Soviet Union had not existed in 1 949, the United States might very well have
Chapter 1
32
dealt with the Chinese Revolution by using nuclear weapons and whatever other means of mass destruction and torture that it had at its disposal. bf course, we can never know any of this with certainty, for who knows what the course of history might have been if there had not been a revolution in Russia in 1 9 1 7 , or if Stalin had not defended that revolution in the middle twenties against the Eurocentric perspective? But I will say this: without the Soviet Union in that period, capital ism's global reign of terror would have been even far worse than it already was. I think: this is the implicit question of freedom that is in the background of Sartre's analysis of Stalin and the Soviet Union under his leadership. The historical irony is that what Sartre is calling the "monstrosity," the isola tion of the Soviet Union that required a period of "socialism 'in one country," be came a kind of "norm. This is what Sartre is calling (in the passage cited as the epigraph to this chapter) the "interiorization of the deviation." Sartre argues that one aspect of this interiorization was the "transcendence of negativity"; in the mode of permanent consolidation, the sense on the part of Stalin was that the Oc tober Revolution inaugurated an era of general positivity. Recalling the language with which I began this chapter, concerning the idea of history turning a corner (there I was referring to the Battle of Stalingrad). Stalin's consolidationist tendency, fully integrated with the events of the period from 1917 through the mid- 1 920s, was not to see things in terms of struggle and upheaval. Thus, Sartre argues that Stalin was unable to understand Mao's militant stance against impe rialism, and indeed was harshly critical of it (CDR2, 235). (However, in my view Sartre does not entirely do justice to Stalin's views; in Economic Problems ofSo cialism in the USSR, published in 1 952, Stalin reaffIrmed Lenin's basic argument that "capitalism means war," and that the road to communism was not going to simply be one of "peaceful transition.") What is more is that, Between
1948
and
1953 , Stalin's praxis became a monstrous caricature of itself. He
could not resolve the problems posed by the existence of new socialist States . The man of retreat and solitude felt only mistrust when Russia emerged from isolation.
(CDR2, 235)
This passage occurs more than a hundred pages after the section of the second volume of the Critique dedicated to the question of "socialism in one country." Let us return to the end of that section to underscore the point, and to conclude this argument. Thus the Stalinist formula-at first false, then more and more true- eventually de
cayed and lapsed into an honorific role when the situation no longer justified it: i.e., when the Chinese Revolution and the appearance of the people's democracies in Central Europe abolished "socialist isolation" and required another praxis on the part of the Soviet government. Meanwhile, of course, the counter-finalities of that tran scended praxis had transformed the USSR: stratifications , practico-inert structures. That singular incarnation was progressively singularized in the process of institu tionalization.
(CDR2, 1 1 6-17)
Dictatorship "for" the proletariat
33
The necessary particularization and concretization of the revolution now stood
in their most direct contradiction with the universalization of the revolution. The deviation became more fully internalized, producing practico-inert structures. The whole point of revolution was increasingly lost, and, in a Sartrean frame, we must
concede that there was no simple touchstone that could have been returned to in order to restore the revolution-and this includes "classical Marxism." An anti
essentialist conception of revolution is one that must continually reinvent itself through actual historical unfoldings and contradictions -the universal must be un
derstood in the concrete and particular. This does not mean, either, that we cannot
continue to raise, as a principle that all the same will remain art empty placeholder without historical engagement and contextualization, what might be taken to be
the ethical core of Sartre's work-a core that is essentially Kantian in its thrust:
the unalterable right of human beings not to be made into mere things . However, the practico-inert structures that emerged in Soviet society, transcending negativ
ity and pushing that society toward complete integration (this is language from
236-37), cannot be understood simply in terms of "ethics" (especially as that term
is most often used in philosophy today) or in terms of the categories of classical
Marxism, but instead only in terms of the imperialist organization of the world.
Sartre was the only "Western Marxist" to grapple with this-and therefore the label probably does not fit -and this is why his analysis of the Stalin peripd stands
apart from those undertaken from a Eurocentrlc perspective.
2 Between Mao and Moses
Sartre's final decade
. they are nice because I
am going to die soon." -Sartre, "Today's Hope"
Not so long after, "they" stopped being very nice. Of course, they were never nice: "God, how they hated him," was the title of one eulogy (Jean-Francois K,ahn,
194).
In the well-known and much argued-over conversations that Sartre participated
in with Benny Levy in the last months of his life, the latter remarks, "You thought
you were opening a moral perspective at the end of Being and Nothingness and then you did not write a book offering a solution, but [instead] you engaged in debate with Marxism. One must believe that both things are closely related" ("Today's
Hope,"
158). Sartre responds, "Intimately." But how might these two seemingly
disparate discourses, of historical materialist politics and economics, and the moral
dimension of human relationships , be brought together, even intimately? It is not only Sartre for whom this question is a great diffICUlty, but I hope to show here that Sartre, even if not fully closing the gap between morality and materialism, at least
maintained the problem in its difficulty, not giving up on either aspect.
Sartre's trajectory in the seventies would seem to have followed the same
course that leads from Pierre Victor to Benny Levy. (In his Maoist period, Levy
llsed the nom de guerre Pierre Victor.) The question of how much this trajectory represents the authentic Sartre has been debated at great length, no less today than back in the seventies. For some, Sartre was already no longer himself, or no
longer developing as a philosopher (but instead degenerating), even at the begin
ning of the seventies, when he allied himself with the Maoists. For others , the last
interviews with Levy represent a Sartre who has given himself over to bourgeois moralizing. (The range of positions on this question is discussed by Ronald Aron
son in his introduction to Adrian van den Hoven's translation of the interviews; see Hope Now,
3-40).
35
Chapter 2
36
y
M claim here will be that Sartre continued to develop philosophically and po
litically in the seventies. Furthermore, Sartre remained faithful to his earlier im
pulses, but he also reached toward a different (and I would say, higher) synthesis
than that represented by either his earlier, existentialist phase, or his later, Marx
ist phase. Where did his sense of the intimate connection between morality and a
possible reading of Marxism lead him? I would argue that it led him to a place between "Maoism" and "Judaism." (What are these things? This has to be spelled
out, hence the scare-quotes.) Sartre was looking for, I will argue, a "Marxism of alterity," or what might also be called a "materialism of transcendence." He came close to finding this, and we will not find this form of Marxism without consid
ering Sartre's thinking in his final decade. I would argue that we-those of us
who believe in the need for radical social transformation-very much need this Marxism of alterity. Sartre continually struggled toward this praxis of revolution:
God, how they hated him! (But, to be hated by the enemy is a good thing , as Mao
put it.) To be sure, this synthesis is not systematically worked out by Sartre; this
remains for us to do, but we can accomplish this only if we work toward a broad understanding of the project, and part of this means getting clear on what at
tracted Sartre to the Maoists and "Maoism," at least as he understood it. My be lief is that much of the commentary on this point has not been very helpful .
In this essay, I would like to generate a broad outline of the project of Sartre's
final years. This outline can be set out by looking at five documents , and by or ganizing our inquiry under four headings . Let us proceed as follows. First, let us
look at the antecedents of this Marxism of alterity in the 1 946 essay, "Material ism and Revolution." In this investigation we can also call on Hazel Barnes's
essay, "Sartre as Materialist." Second, we wiJl jump ahead to the very end of Sartre's life and consider his engagement with "Judaism" -our texts here will be
the aforementioned conversation with Levy, "Today's Hope," and a very inter
esting essay by Steven Schwarzschild, "Jean-Paul Sartre as Jew." Third, I propose
to argue from this "Jewish" position back to Sartre's "Maoist" engagement, in
order to show how the two are closely related. Here we will discuss Sartre's well
known essay, "The Maoists in France." Finally, let us attempt a definition of what I am calling a Marxism of alterity, also showing how this formulation connects
with Sartre's positions.
r?
To really give this subject the full treatment that it deserves, there
are
a num
ber of other texts that would need to be brought into play, but especially the col laborative work
On a raison de se revolter, composed with Pierre Victor and
Philippe Gavi between November 1972 and March 1974. Such a treatment is a
good deal beyond the more modest aim that I have here. My understanding is that
Arlette Elkaim�Sartre, Sartre's adopted daughter and literary executor, has not
given (and is unlikely to give) permission for this work to be translated into Eng
lish. A good way to get around this might be a book-length treatment of the text,
one that quotes a substantial number of passages. The publication of such a text or even the translation of the book would lead to an interesting test, concerning
Between Mao and Moses
37
whether anyone would any longer be interested in such works . One would not ex
pect multitudes to line up for the texts, of course, but complete lack of interest might be a bellwether. But this does not just have to do with Sartre or intellectual activity in the wake of
1968, but also what sorts of "excitement" might attend in Specters ofMarx, Fredric Jameson
tellectual activity in general. In an essay on
even puts forward the provocative hypothesis that Derrida and some other con
temporary French intellectuals are turning again to Marx (at the time of his death,
Gilles Deleuze was also writing on Marx) in part out of a reaction to the waning
of intellectual life in general in France (see "Marx's Purloined Letter") . There
was a period when Sartre defined the intellectual field (from about
1945-60),
then there was a general reaction against Sartre, which we identify with struc
turalism, but at least there continued to be an intellectual field where these reac
tions took place. Now we are seeing the loss of that. Is it overreaching to see a
close linkage between the Sartrean intellectual field , the intellectual field more
generally, political radicalism, and the passage into a postpolitical space? (These themes are pursued further in the next chapter.)
The material already before us , however, will be more than enough to occupy
us, the project here not being simply a close reading of these texts , but instead the
understanding of a project of human emancipation.
1 . "Materialism and Revolution." Like Mao Tsetung-and why no one has
been willing to put it this way is a remarkable point in itself-Sartre in the for
ties and fifties grappled with what had become of the Marxism of Stalin. As so
cial activists as well as theorists (one perhaps more "active" than the other, to be sure), both were confronted with the realities of the model of "socialist construc
tion" presented by Stalin's leadership in the Soviet Union and the Comintem. We should remind ourselves that this was not an academic question for Sartre in
France in
1946 (nor for Mao in China, especially after 1927). Though Sartre was
to become more comfortable, as Hazel Barnes demonstrates, with the term "ma
terialism" (and, again as Prof. Barnes shows, e�n a materialism that is dialecti
cal, in a well-defined, specifically anti-"Diamat" sense) , this was to be on his own terms. The key terms for Sartre in
1 946 are "consciousness" and "freedom," as
related to the project of clearing a space for human agency in the midst of a pol. itics dominated by deterministic "materialism."
The opening lines of "Materialism and Revolution" are so interesting, so
strange:
Young people of today are uneasy. They no longer recognize their right to be young.
. . . They no longer take the time, as we did at their age, to play about with ideas be
fore adopting one set in particular. . . . They are now told to choose between mate rialism and idealism; they are told that there is nothing in between and that it must" be one or the other.
(185-87)
Surely Sartre would be sympathetic, in the aftermath of the war and in light of
political possibilities that may or may not open up in this aftermath, to an activist
Chapter 2
38
,sensibility. that demands , even of the youth, that people "get on with it," decide and declare their allegiance . But what Sartre is not sympathetic to is this demand
to declare a position in a debate on ontology, first and foremost, and a debate that is skewed toward a "materialism" that is in reality the other side of the coin of the detested "idealism" at that. In the first case, a point that Sartre does not clearly frame as such, we find him speaking "a language already familiar to us, to Judaism," as Levinas put it in his eulogy thirty-four years later. For Sartre is not in the first case interested in on tology, but instead, like Marx, with praxis. As ontology, Sartre argues , materialism of the "Diamat" sort oversteps its bounds, making all sorts of claims that are clearly underdetermined by its eviden tiary base. These claims are therefore speculative and "metaphysical" in just the sense that orthodox Marxists claim to loathe. ("Diamat" and "Histomat" are names for the formulaic and dogmatic types of dialectical and historical materialism given expression by Stalin.) Among these claims are the denial of "the existence of God and transcendent finality" ( 187); and yet, coming quickly on the heels of
these denials is a material eschatology that leads the intellectual leaders of the PCF to declare that the policies of Stalin repiesent the proverbial "sure thing," with no
real wager required. "It is impossible, they think, for them to fail. History is a sci ence, its consequences are already inscribed, we have only to decipher them. This attitude is patently a flight"
(232). This flight is an avoidance not only of the pos
sibility of failure, Sartre argues , but of the fact that, without this possibility, human beings are surely reduced to the level of things and even appendages of things. But it is from the hope of revolution and of those who, whatever their avowed "mythology" (this is what Sartre calls the deterministic materialism of the ortho dox Marxists), act so as to bring about a true rebellion against reification, that hu manity rises above thingness. The movement of Sartre's thought from "Material ism and Revolution" to the
Critique of Dialectical Reason was to outline a (233). In the
philosophy that "revolutionary demands . . . trace, of themselves"
latter work, while not disavowing earlier claims about radical freedom, Sartre aims to show better how this rev
olt against thingness arises , dialectically, from material
conditions , in the midst of reification itself. One also sees better in the later work how this struggle is unending. These themes can also be connected to Marx's ar gument, in
The German Ideology, that communism is not principally a "goal" or
a "theory," but instead the "real movement of real people in history"; but this can, of course, be read in two opposing ways, and Sartre's aim is to bring to the surface
the idea that this is not a movement of mere things, but rather of conscious actors , or at least of material beings capable of conscious activity. And yet, despite this re working of materialism, Sartre argues that a central condition of this freedom is the fact that, as Hazel Barnes puts it, "no objective state of the world can by itself evoke a revolution" (670).
As Prof. Barnes goes on to summarize, "It is [people] who must question [the
world] and decide to act. Unlike natural processes , human actions are future-
Between Mao and Moses
39
oriented, motivated by the drawing power of an envisioned state which does not
yet exist" (670). Admittedly, for Sartre the experience of future-orientation, and
the imagination of a future state, is very much conditioned by material circum stances, and especially by class. The capitalist certainly finds him- or herself in
the position of imagining a capitalist future, and undoubtedly this vision is situ
ated. But even for the capitalist this future will not simply come about by itself.
The capitalist has to plan, to project. This also means that the capitalist is re
sponsible for his or her projects, at least under one valid, necessary, and irre
ducible description, even if, under another valid description, the capitalist is also
a tool of capital, of a certain material organization of soc�ety. The point is, o f course, the Kantian one, but without the usual dualistic treatment, that responsi
bility is real. For Sartre, there could be no possibility of revolution, or even a
meaning of the term "revolution," without the reality of this responsibility. Now, if I may quote one longer passage from the essay, we will already see Sartre's po
�sition set between what we may call "Maoism" and "Judaism":
[If a person] happens to plan, as Marx expressly states, to "change the world," it means
� begin with, a being for whom the world exists in its totality, [in such a
that he is
way] as a piece of phosphorus or lead, which is a part of the world and ridden by forces
to which it uncomprehendingly submits, will never be. This means that man transcends
the world toward a future state froin which he can contemplate it. It is in changing the world that we can come to know it. Neither the detached consciousness that would soar over the universe without being able to get a standpoint on it, nor the material object which reflects a condition without ever understanding it[,] can ever "grasp" the total
ity of,existence in a synthesis, even a purely conceptual one. (236).
,"If you want to know an apple, bite into it," Mao once said, illustrating the fact
that the gaining of knowledge requires a particular kind of engagement, one that changes both the knower and the known. (Mao develops an argument for this
claim, by the way -he didn't just set it down as � platitude or a bit of folk wis dom; see "On Practice," in
Five Essays on Philosophy.) And what sort of "tran
scendence" is Sartre speaking of here? When he says that this transcendence is
"toward a future state from which [a person] can contemplate [the world] ," he is, of course, not arguing that the aim o f this transcendence is contemplation, but in�
stead the creation of a new world out o f the existing world. In "Today's Hope,"
Sartre will link this transcendence with the specifically Jewish understanding o f messianism and resurrection. Sartre i s interested i n the possibility of being in the world, but not of it.
2. "Judaism." Allow me to open this part of the discussion by quoting from the
essay, "Jean�Paul Sartre as Jew," by Steven Schwarzschild. In turn, Schwarz schild quotes Sartre and Levy, and thereby brings Hegel into the conversation. Levy asks: "The history that Hegel put on our map wanted to get rid of the Jew, and it is the Jew who will allow us to get out of this history that Hegel wanted to impose
40
Chapter 2 on us?" And Sartre replies: "Absolutely . . ." Compare, to the contrary, what Sartre
Critique of Dialectical Reason [significantly, 1947]. "If there is a history it is that of Hegel. There can be no
wrote in his preparatory notes for the these notes date from other."
(1 63)
What a rich double-entendre, intentional or not, this last sentence is !
It would be the easiest thing in the world to just beat up on Hegel here, or at
least a certain interpretation of Hegel that is not all of Hegel , but an interpretation whose force has been felt historically and that accurately describes a very real historical dynamic. I think there is a "Hegel of negativity" and a Hegel of a di alectic that is open-ended, even if this Hegel must be found by reading in the mar
gins. But I also believe that there is a Hegel of violent assimilation and exclusion
and, ironically, one sees this Hegel especially in the interpretations of his work
!
offered by theorists who deny there is such a H gel. (I have dealt with this ques tion at length elsewhere, for example, in
Matrix and line, 56-63 , and Politics in
the impasse, 1 43-57.)
Well into the conversation, Sartre and Levy tum in a more focused way to Jew
ish questions . Levy says, "has one wondered what Messianism, Hebrew Mes
sianism, was exactly? No, everyone acts as if they knew. When will we recognize that we don 't know and that it is crucial for us to know? Can we forget that ig norance is at the basis of the anti-Jewish filth?"
( 1 76). In response, Sartre dis
cusses the aspects of Jewish messianism that appeal to him:
The Jewish religion implies an end to this world and the appearance at the same time of another one, another world that will be made from"this one but where things will be organized differently. There is also another theme that I like: dead Jews and the other dead, as well, will be resurrected, will come back to the Earth. Contrary to the Christian conception, they do not jave-the present Jewish dead- any existence
other than the tomb, and they will be born again as living in this new world. This new world is the end.
(179)
Levy asks, "in what way does this Jewish Messianic end interest you today?" Sartre responds, Precisely because it does not have a Marxist quality, that is, the quality of a defined end beginning with a situation that is present and projected into the future, with stages that will make it possible to attain by developing certain facts today. . . . The Jewish end has nothing of that. It is, so to speak, the beginning of the existence of men for each other. That is to say, a moral end. Or, more precisely, it is morality. The Jew thinks that the end of the world, and the appearance of the other, means the , arrival of the ethical existence of man.
(1 79)
In some respects here, Sartre seems to have not only come full circle, return ing to the critique of reductivist materialism of "Materialism and Revolution," but even to have gone quite explicitly into a kind of idealist framework. This is
Between Mao and Moses
41
somewhat the interpretation that Schwarzschild gives to these statements, though we will have to examine more fully the last sentence in the passage, which is pre sented as a summation of what has come immediately before: [W)hile the Marxist conception of ideal society is held to evolve out of paSt history and is, therefore, afflicted with the wounds and determined by the evils of the past, in Jewish eschatological historiography it is the
summum bonum that produces in
cremental truth and goodness in history-in other words, the "pro-jected" infinite fu
ture produces the past, not the other way around. The Messianic goal can be attained only through Messianic action, which in tum is defined by the law. In short, Mes
sianism tries to remake the world ethically through permanent revolution. (163; word order altered slightly)
Significantly, Levy and Sartre speak not simply of action "defined by taw," but also ofthe transcendence of the law, even if by its fulfillment rather than by mere transgression (which, as Levy notes, is an approach connected to political moder nity; we might consider this point when thinking about recently fashionable, pur portedly "transgressive" postrnodem theories that often lead to merely academic and merely llberal strategies , though sometimes with some "naughty bits" thrown in, as the English like to say; perhaps this is nothing but a minor variation on modernity, but, then again, perhaps the line between transcendence aI).d trans gression is not so easily drawn) . But let us also focus on the idea of "Messianic action," which SchwaIischild does not go on to define except obliquely, in tenns of the pennanent ethical revolution. The question we need to ask here is, What is Sartre trying to break with in setting Jewish Messianism against a Marxism of
"stages"? There are two parts to the question: (1) Would Sartre limit this Mes
sianism to a politics of incrementalism? (2) Is the infInite future that produces the
past simply "disconnected" from the past, materially? One wonders at the quota tion marks sUrrounding "pro-jected" in Schwarzschild's fonnulation-are they 'simply there to show that Sartrean tenninology is.. being referred to, or do they also play the role, even if unintentionally, of bracketing the fact that this project comes from somewhere and some time? The project cisely a materially situated "break-from."
is a "break," but it is pre
. Levy proposes, and Sartre accepts , the idea that " [t]he Jew, then, in his pro
found reality, can be disconnected from the philosophy of history." But it seems to me that this "disconnection" is in fact a matter of struggle, of material fulfill
ment and transcendence of the law, of revolution, of a material project. The "highest good" is itself a project, not a guarantee: there are material stakes, there is the possibility of failure.
3 . "Maoism." In other words , let us not forget the context, or perhaps the sev eral contexts, of Sartre's project. In "The Maoists of France," Sartre sums up the Maoists' activities under three headings: violence, spontaneity, and morality. This must be understood in contrast with an established "Left" (and especially the Communist Party of France) that had made its peace with capital (at least as
42
Chapter 2
opposed to any talk of overthrowing capitalism), that preferred any "order," in cluding that of Charles de Gaulle, over outbreaks of rebellion from the rabble (0(, "elements foreign to the working class," as they used to put it back in those days- students, non-European workers), and that only had the most narrow and philistine conception of "interest." Anything not fitting with this narrow con ception was branded "idealism." So, we are still on the terrain of "Materialism and Revolution," for it is clearly the "materialism" of orthodox Marxism's de mand for order that Sartre continues to oppose. Despite his disavowal ("I am not a Maoist"), in some ways Sartre was a better Maoist than his young comrades were. What's more, in some ways Sartre was, at least in his theoretical representations of � revolutionary project, a better Maoist than Mao himself. Mao was a busy person, of course, and while he sometimes captured in words the Maoism that he was preoccupied with giving expression to in praxis, his texts, even taken as a whole" do not adequately represent the Maoist revolutionary project, for two reasons. First, what is there in the texts-and this is quite a lot, really, and it has to be pointed out that many commentators on Mao and Maoism, especially those who make cursory dismissals, have not begun to deal with these texts-is in need of systematization. Second, there is also the mat ter, to return again to the program set out in "Materialism and Revolution," of tracing out, in theory, the meaning of the revolutionaries' practices, demands, and hopes. Sartre also put it, "I have not attempted to describe the Maoists' beliefs, but rather to bring out the implications of their actions" (238). Mao went a great distance beyond Stalin's theoretical apparatus, but there is still the need to go even further in theory, in a way to be specified, looking to the praxis of Maoism to draw out its implications-and S�e helps us here. It is unfortunate, of course, that most commentators on Sartre do not develop this context-if they did, per haps they would not express such bewilderment at Sartre's fellowship with the Maoists or, even if seeing this as the product of some sort of radical "good will," wish that all of this was not tied up with the name and project of Mao Tsetung. 1t is true that Sartre probably read only bits of Mao's works, if that (he was pretty much blind by the time he started working with the Maoists), and it is probably also true that Sartre's understanding of events such as the Cultural Revolution was spotty (though I suspect that the lack of investigation into the aims and events of the Cultural Revolution on the part of many commentators on Sartre is too much transferred from the latter to the former). But, again, Mao and Sartre both begin with deep frustration over the experience of the Stalin period, and they converge on many points. More orthodox Marxists have great difficulty accepting indeterminacy, and certainly what Sartre calls "contingency." In a Heideggerian challenge to this or thodoxy, Sartre reminds us, at the opening of "Materialism and Revolution," of not only the contingencies of history, but of existence as a whole. Of course, this question of being is dismissed in strictly positivist fashion by orthodox Marxism, as not making any sense, or else it is said that it is not politically efficacious to
Between Mao and Moses
43
even think about the question, leading as it supposedly does to despair or qui
etism. And yet, "today 's hope," on whatever day one finds oneself wondering
about human possibilities , radically depends on this contingency, and the con
comitant sense and possibility of taking responsibility for one's situation.
Unlike Stalin, Mao did in fact attempt to take account of indeterminacy, es
pecially paying attention to the innovations in physics brought about by Ein
stein and the theorists of quantum mechanics. (These innovations had been dis
missed as "bourgeois" by Soviet ideologists.) This is a real advance, but
Maoism, and Marxism generally, has not been able to deal with the idea of there being two basic categories of indeterminacy, one of them applying specifically to conscious , language-using beings . This second indeterminacy is , in Sartre's
view, irreducible to the indeterminacies of merely physical things. To the extent
that many Marxists , and many Maoists, still hope to find the "dialectics" that will reduce mind to matter (in the sense called "physicalist" by contemporary
analytic philosophers) , they are still under what Sartre called the "myth" of ma
terialism. As Sartre argues, this myth cuts both ways, sometimes helping the
cause of the revolutionary, but, ultimately undercutting revolutionary theory and practice':'iihd , we might summarize, any real possibility for today 's hope
for, in the determinist view, the future is simply a done deal, unfolding accord
ing to material-historical laws .
But here we have. to tum to Sartre's category of "morality" as an aspect of
Maoism. It is often argued by Marxists that a recognition of two qualitatively
different indeterminacies leads us into "Kantian dualism." (For example, Helena Sheehan argues this repeatedly in her otherwise fine book, Marxism and the Phi
losophy of Science.) It seems that the (seemingly) infinite material of our uni verse can give rise to such wonders as human minds, which then do not follow
strict physical laws; whether this is a position that oUght to be called "dualism"
(and whether this "dualism" is appropriately ascribed to Kant) is a longer dis cussion. (In my view, Donald Davidson's argum�t for "anomalous monism" is
a good, "materialist" response to this claim.) But what might be of interest to us
here is that there seems to be an implicit recognition of the indeterminacy of the mental (and agency, etc .) in Mao's famous summation of historical materialism:
"Marxism consists in thousands of truths, but they all come down to one thing:
It is rignt to rebel." Note that he does not say that they all come down to the ten
dency of the rate of profit to fall, or the tendency for the organic composition of
capital to rise, or even the tendency for there to be a succession of modes of pro
duction, driven by efficiency criteria (or the tendency of the forces of production
to outgrow the relations of production), etc. Instead, Mao sums up Marxism under what sounds like an ethical imperative. One could not imagine this state
ment coming from Stalin (or from Trotsky, for that matter, and possibly not even
from Lenin -though Lenin is closer to this in spirit, I think). Of course, the "sci
ence" of this imperative is far from worked out, and it remains a stumbling block
to the Maoism that is still too orthodox. And yet, the idea that "it is right to
44
Chapter 2
rebel," 'even against Marxism itself, permeates the whole project of revolution that Mao led. Making sense of this project is the real theoretical task involved in going beyond Stalin and every other form of deterministic, economistic Marx ism. To the extent that Sartre helps us with this task, he also shows where we might draw out the possibilities of Maoism. 4. "Jewish Marxism" -a Marxism of alterity, a materialism of transcendence. When I say the Right, I mean the lkstards. This Left, either it dies, and at the pres ent moment, it is [humanity that] is dying, or it fmds some new principles. ("Today's Hope,"
1 58)
When Sartre rejects a "Marxism of stages," what is he most interested in reject ing? The general tendency is to see Sartre here as rejecting Marxism, and the sort of analysis that Marxism allows us to do, and the history of the Marxist move ments, tout court. Certainly this is the way that Benny Levy and Steven Schwarz schild interpret Sartre's interest in Jewish messianism. But, justified or not, what is represented in this evaluation is their own rejection or nonacceptance of Marx ism. In "Today's Hope," however, Sartre does not completely reject the Marxist political involvements of his past. Further, he asserts, against Levy's too-easy summation, that "[t]oday, [the term] Stalinism is used to denigrate anything." This statement and its context indicate two things , in my view. First, it is clear that Sartre rejects simply using the term "Stalinism" as though there is no obli gation to try to come to grips 1th the Marxism of the Stalin period and why it had such a hold on people. Second, Sartre rejects using this term as though it now sums up all of the possibilities within Marxism. Levy asks, "How can it be ex plained that intellectuals had a need to hold on to, I mean, find a support and a basis in that junk [that is, Stalinism]?" Sartre responds, Because it was a question of finding a future for society. It was necessary for society to stop being the shit it is today, everywhere. I did not think I could change the world
by myself. by my own thought, but I distinguished those social forces that were try ing to move forward and I found my place among
them. (160)
It does not seem to me that Sartre is, at the end of his life, rejecting this strategy. He goes on to say, evolution through action would be a series of failures from which something posi tive, already contained in the failure and ignored by those who had wished to suc ceed, would result unexpectedly. This positive result would be these partial, local successes, difficult to recognize by those who had worked for them but, which, from failure to failure, would accomplish some progress. It is thus that I have understood history.
(I61)
Now, this scheme does not sound so different from saying that there are different levels- or stages-of social development that can be attained. But it is true that
Between Mao and Moses
45
this progress works through failure, and not through a fully planned-out succes
sion of stages. For Sartre, as with Marx and Mao, we do not know in advance
where the revolution will take us, for "We are not whole [persons] . We are beings
who struggle to arrive at human relations and to a defInition of [humanity]" (161).
(We might note that, for Mao, one indication that the revolution is getting some
where is that there are
new problems.) Sartre is rejecting some major aspects of
Marxism (he speaks to many other aspects in the interview, including the pro ductivist paradigm), and especially a Marxism oftgUarantees and mere interests.
And yet it is abundantly clear that he continues to believe in both the goal of com
munism and the material analysis of society that could help to achieve this goal.
To sum up Sartre's position here as an abandonment of these material analyses
would really be to accept the argument that the [mal Sartre wasn't the "real"
Sartre. Of course, this is a possibility, but it makes much more sense to attempt to generate, systematically, what Sartre was searching for in these [mal discus
sions. Perhaps the incompatibilities of Jewish and Marxist messianisms cannot be
resolved under the heading of any Marxism, however heterodox, that could still
be recognized as such, as a form of historical materialism. I am not at all con
vinced of thi�d I worry that some are simply using the fInal interviews as an
easy way to co'nvince themselves of Sartre's "rejection" of Marxism in order to
smooth the way toward an easier reassimilation of Sartre into the mainstream of philosophical discourse. However, the possibility that the economistic and deter
ministic side of Marxism will ultimately defeat any ethical impulse that may be
seen there (or possibly read into Marxism) has to be considered. But then, the fact that we have to read Hegel differently in light of the supposedly impossible real
ity of Jewish experience does not mean that we can so easily get rid of Hegel
for he represents a reality as well, even if one that, in some respects , we might wish to escape.
That we seek for transcendence does not in itself "overthrow the difficulties of
immanence. Both Jewish messianism and Maoism"aim for the appearance of the
ethical in the midst of the law, in the midst of materiality; the paradox of the
human situation is the struggle for ethical transcendence within the material of history (without which there could be no struggle, no humanity, no situation, even
if the mere fact of materiality does not mean that there necessarily will be these things, eit1!er). Already by "Materialism and Revolution" Sartre was systemati
cally thinking the possibilities of Maoism and Jewish messianism, and therefore
it is no mistake that he gravitated to both in the [mal decade of his life. Going fur
ther with this systematic work, of creating a Marxism of alterity, a materialism of transcendence, a Jewish Marxism, or, if need be, a Marxist Judaism, means, cru
cially, bringing the ethical implications of Jewish messianism more fully to the
heart of the Maoist historical engagement. Without this kind of engagement, or
avoiding this engagement, we really would do no more than to make of Sartre a
mere moralizer in his [mal days , and we would thereby rip the heart out of Sartre's life project.
46
Chapter 2
In this essay I have quotedfrom the translation of "Today 's Hope " that appeared in Telos in the summer of 1980, not long after Sartre died, rather than from the newer translation by Adrian van den Hoven. This is onlyfor the reason that I have been working with the former translationfor many years, indeed, since itfirst ap peared. However, for those who are now coming to thefinal interviews, or are re turning to them, 1 recommend both the van den Hoven translation and Ronald Aronson 's valuable introduction.
3 Beyond the varieties of Sartrophobia, toward Sartre's legacy for radical intellectuals
He was a generous and courageous man. He always defended the cause of the marginalized, of the exploited, and of the oppressed. He always struggled for freedom, most often with the communists and, if necessary, against them. He beli�ed in .the strength of reason and in the contagious power of the idea of freedom. But above all, for me and I have said it several times, he was our Jean Jacques Rousseau. He reminded me irresistibly of the statement of Marx about Rousseau, which I quote from memory: "This man, who, no matter what his f�11ies, was of a profound intransigence, and who never accepted the least com promise with the established power." There is no greater compliment for an in-. tellectual, in my opinion. I hope, in this respect, more than all our differences of opinion, that the number of Sartre's disciples will be infinite. -Louis Althusser To be hated by the enemy is a good thing. -Mao Tsetung
For a time, in
the aftermath of the French Resistance, the movement against the
French colonization of Algeria, the movement against the United States' war
against the people of Vietnam, the Events of May 1968, and many other situations
in which ·determined opposition to the machinations of oppressive power was called for, the number of those who would come forward as disciples of Jean-Paul Sartre did indeed appear to be unlimited. Indeed, in the late sixties, when the notion of a "public intellectual" meant considerably more than providing another calm and
charming, if mildly critical, article for Harper's or
The Atlantic, three names stood
out as those of exemplary engaged intellectuals: Jean-Paul Sartre, Simone de Beau
voir, and Herbert Marcuse. Each made important theoretical contributions to un derstanding oppressive social systems and liberatory alternatives , and each was willing to go to the barricades in various ways - and none more so than Sartre.
47
Chapter 3
48
What Michel Rybalka has appropriately termed "Sartrophobia"- about which at least an entire book might be written -has been in play since
1 945. As John
Gerassi wrote in1ris biography, "No intellectual, no writer, no man is more hated by academics and newsfolk, by eggheads and politicians on both sides of the At lantic than Jean-Paul Sartre. Nor is this new: Sartre has been hated by them for half a century"
(30). In his chapter, "L' Adulte Terrible," Gerassi supplies an
amazing compendium of these hatreds , the most telling of which was Germaine Bree's from her book,
Camus and Sartre:
Finally, she damned Sartre because "he never to my knowledge supported any polit ical candidate who had the slightest chance of winning nor has he ever supported any action taken by the French government" -thus naively handing Sartre the best com pliment he ever received. (34) Beating up on Sartre, in other words, has been and continues to be a well-es tablished pastime. (One of the high points of meetings of the North American Sartre Society is the review of recent Sartre scholarship by Michel Rybalka, which includes a look at new examples of Sartrophobia. At our
1997 meeting at
Emory University in Atlanta, for instance, Rybalka noted that well-known Mexi can poet and essayist
Octavio
Paz has gotten into the act. And "leftist" writer
Tony Judt continues with his campaign against Sartre.) I would venture that this Sartrophobia has as much to do with Sartre's model of the radical intellectual as it does with any of his ideas regarding nothingness , reciprocity, authenticity, groups, the practico-inert, or the rest. To be sure, sheer intransigence- as back
handedly acknowledged by Bree- is part of this model, but so is a dynamic
thinking of the contradictions involved in attempting to do intellectual work . Both elements are present in this passage from The
Words: "For a long time I took
my pen for a sword; I now know we're powerless. No matter. I write and will
keep writing"
( 1 59). "Powerless" -why? Because the pen ultimately is not a
sword? Anyone who has read one of Sartre's polemical pieces , for instance on the execution of the Rosenbergs ("Mad Beasts,"
1953), knows that his words could
be sharper than daggers . Gerassi concludes "L' Adulte Terrible" by saying,
But he was wrong. He had a lot of power. The proof? All those who hate him. All those who followed him to the cemetery of Montparnasse. All those who love him. (36) As an intellectual, in fact, Sartre's "power" was - and perhaps remains -unri valed. Anna Boschetti has written a book on what might be called the "career" of Sartre's power,
The Intellectual Enterprise: Sartre and Les Temps Modeme. Al
though many of the details of the story that she assembles are fascinating, I find her methodology quite disturbing at times - Boschetti measures Sartre's intellec tual power not only in terms of its effect on the intellectual "field" in its time (a conception she borrows from Pierre Bourdieu) , but also in terms of intellectual capital, "market share ," and "bankability." Her quest is to discover the circum-
Beyond the varieties of Sarlrophobia
49
stances under which Sartre exercized hegemony over the intellectual field in France 1 945-60 or thereabouts. Boschetti's final chapter attempts to show how Sartre's intellectual "capital" was mostly spent by-this part is unclear, because she wraps up the sixties and its aftermath in only a couple of pages- 1960 or 1961 or 1 968 or perhaps 1970. For sure, Sartre's intellectual "hegemony" in the fifteen years following the Sec ond World War was beyond remarkable. As Boschetti writes, "To fmd comparable dominion, we must go back to Hugo, or even to Voltaire." By 1968, in Boschetti's view, this hegemony was long gone. And yet, when I and others ask, where are our Sartres and de Beauvoirs and Marcuses today, where are our radical intellectuals who can speak truth to power with a power of their own, we are talking about fig ures who led at lea�t "double lives ." Just taking the example of Sartre, what I am getting at is that, w!1ile the figure we are seeking is one of the main voices of 1968 jUld its aftermath, he is also the figure who produced important and famous philo _sophical and literary works in the period of his intellectual hegemony. To state the perfectly obvious, there is a relation between the earlier "classical intellectual" who, for the myriad of reasons that Boschetti discusses, became hegemonic in the post-war intellectual field, and the emergent "revolutionary intellectual" who playecDm important role in 1 968 and thereafter. In other words, because he was an important classical intellectual, Sartre could also play the role of an imp'ortant rev olutionary intellectual. If this is the case, however, then two things follow. First, Sartre's own underStanding of the revolutionary intellectual appears to be flawed in certain respects. Second, we need to look at Sartre's varying conception� of the engaged intellectual, conceptions that reflect both his writings on the subject as well as his actual practice; we need to do this in order to get a clearer picture of what we might call the "Sartrean radical intellectual." The "flaws" I refer to are in fact the result of a constant rethinking on the part of Sartre, of what it means to be an engaged intellectual. One might hope that it could go without saying that this rethinking is itself no "flaw." Toward the end of his life, Sartre was grappling with the possibilitY of fully making the transition from classical to revolutionary intellectual, a transition that he was quite aware of never fully completing. In some sense, it might be said that Flaubert, and Flaubert, stood in the way. But there is more to the problem than this, because it may be that, at least for this historical period in which society is divided into classes, there is nothing other for the radical intellectual to do than to be in con stant, critically reflective transition. The classical intellectual, to say nothing of what Sartre calls the "technician of knowledge," is resistant to such transition. In light of this resistance, and before attempting to draw a more systematic picture of the Sartrean model, let us turn to what might be called "left Sartrophobia." In revolt against Sartre's philosophy and the Sartrean engaged intellectual, other models of the radical intellectual de veloped in the late sixties, models that have perhaps become hegemonic in the West (or is it only in North America, or only in the United States?) in recent years.
Chapter 3
50
This new "hegemony," it must be underscored, exists almost entirely in the acad emy. There are various reasons for this, but one of them is certainly that these
post-Sartrean or anti-Sartrean models are demonstrative of a peculiarly narrow, academic form of intellectual hegemony. -Perhaps the "left-Sartrophobic" models ought to be called "anti-Sartreanlpost Althusserian," in that their rise depends on two developments. First, the Critique
of Dialectical Reason, volume one, was published at precisely the moment of ex
istentialism's wane and structuralism's rise. I do not know why we have to accept Boschetti 's terms concerning market share and intellectual capital, or even no
tions of intellectual fashions that seize the public for a time and then give way to
other trends . If Sartre's work exercised intellectual hegemony for a remarkable period, surely Boschetti's discussion of the "field" is more to the point:
The whole intelleOJual field is involved. Sartre commands the attention of the philo sophical world and the literary world, the world of high culture and that of the lead ing dailies, and thereby crosses the two frontiers which have historically marked the functioning of the field: the dividing line between the philosophical circuit and the literary circuit, and the line between legitimate success and popular fame. He unifies a polycentric system by becoming the single reference point in relation to which the other sectors must define-or redefine-themselves. So much so that we need only reconstruct Sartre's position at war's end by running the range of comments about him to be able to reconstruct the whole field. Not a single voice which counts fails to answer up in one way or another. (9) By the late fifties , as we see in the concluding chapter of Boschetti 's account, there are a number of important developments in the intellectual field, espe cially the displacement of philosophy by the human (that is, social) sciences,
and a concomitant vogue for structuralism (Levi-Strauss publishes Structural Anthropology in 1 958; Barthes's Mythologies has already appeared a year ear lier, while Foucault's Madness and Civilization followed in 1 961 ) , develop ments that began to displace Sartre and existentialism. (Significant as well is
the fact that some of Sartre's most important interlocutors in his formulation of existentialism and existential Marxism had died in a short space of time Camus in
1 960, Fanon and Merleau-Ponty in 1 96 1 .) The rigid hierarchy in the
French school system that had held for so long, and which placed someone such as Sartre , who graduated from the Ecole Normale Superieure and held the agre
gation in philosophy, in the center of the intellectual universe, was beginning
to break down. Ironically, these shifts-or their underlying causes - helped pre
pare the way for the uprisings that were to come in the later sixties. (Some have argued that, in 20120 hindsight, the uprisings themselves constituted a chapter
in a process of modernization-in educational institutions and in the economy more generally - that was required by French capitalism as much as they might
have been part of an antica pitalist movement as well.) In this light, it might be tempting to see Marcuse's and Sartre's interventions as a renewed attempt to
Beyond the varieties of Sartrophobia
51
"make the world philosophical ," as Marx put it i n his famous letter to his fa ther, regarding his own "conversion" to Hegelianism. Be that as it may, Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, French disciples of Leo Strauss, obviously take a certain glee in quoting Raymond Aron: "The god of the intellec tuals of the sixties was no longer the Sartre who had dominated the postwar period but a mixture of Levi-Strauss, Foucault, Althusser and Lacan" (French Philosophy
of the Sixties, 62). The French title of Ferry's and Renaut's book is La Pensee 68, or "68 thought." I find it strange, and I think that most sixties-inspired intellectu als would agree with me, that the notion of such a "thought" would somehow not include Sartre. But then, perhaps this is because Sartre's work in the sixties (or from the time of the Critique) was increasingly part of a larger political landscape
rather than merely one or another intellectual trend or fashion. While I am no longer as fond of Althusser or Foucault as I was some years ago , there is un doubtedly much one could learn from both of them. Lacan is perhaps interesting here for the fact that his thought seems equally indebted to structuralism and Hegel (and Kojeve) and Sartre . But then, Lacan was more of Sartre's generation than were Althusser and Foucault. My point is that, even insomuch as the work of these structuralists or "poststructuralists" can be placed under the heading "68 thought,"
still , it �as Sartre who was most of all involved with the young activists and rev
olutionaries, and not just as an intellectual "celebrity." What's odd is that, while
the chief intention of Ferry and Renaut is to discredit and negate
"68. thought,"
which they identify with "antihumanism," they rarely mention Sartre , even though they surely have no great love for him, either. This makes me wonder if, in some perverse way, Sartre is not the real target of their attack. With the rise of structuralism and the human sciences , another shift that we see in the intellectual field is a return to the separation of literary and philosophical endeavors . Or, at least, these endeavors are no longer combined in the way and to the degree that Sartre combined them. Does thiS" separation also necessarily lead to a rift between "legitimate success" and "popular acclaim" (as Boschetti put it)? One possible exception to this development-rnight be seen in the entire con stellation of work around the journal
Tel Quel. Inspired by structuralism, semi
otics, psychoanalysis, and Althusserian Marxism, "Telquelians" such as Julia Kristeva and Philippe Sollers viewed Sartre as their "major rival." The latter, for his part, argued that the events of May and their aftermath intensified the class contradiction that is at the heart of intellectual activity; that is, while even the nouradical intellectual (the technician of knowledge) must, in principle, believe in the universality of knowledge , this knowledge will all the same tend to serve the existing system. Even engaged intellectuals are caught in this class bind. They will almost certainly, as a result, suffer from a guilty conscience, but actual social rebellions and incipient revolutions demand more of the intellectual -the de mand, as Sartre put it in "A friend of the people," is for the As Danielle Marx-Scouras says in
concrete universal. The Cultural Politics of Tel Quel, "Sartre ar
gued that many intellectuals were hostile toward the May movement because it
Chapter 3
52 contested �heir role
part"
as
intellectuals and demanded a radical conversion on their
( 1 5 1 ) . Resisting- and actively critiquing - this notion of a conversion de
manded by events and social practice, the Telquelians instead embraced Al thusser 's notion of "theoretical practice." Sartre himself faced what appeared to be a dilemma: even within the period of the May events and their aftermath, he led a double life as a writer and intellectual, continuing to work on the immense Haubert project at night even as he was out in the streets by day. The Tel Quel
solution was to circumvent the dilemma and to deny the need for any sort of
transformation (or conversion), by defending writing not only as a practice but as
the only practice that the writer need worry about:
Clearly, Telqu�'lians did not assume the "guilty conscience" of the intellectual. We have seen how Tel Quel demarcated itself from the onset from this engage impasse. For Tel Quel, the writer did not have to feel guilty about being a writer; the writer's raison d'etre was in his or her writing. The relationship to writing, and to language in general, determined the relationship to society at large. (Marx-Scouras, 152) Significantly, insomuch as the Telquelians felt that they could not ignore May
1968 and its aftermath, the position they took was to align Tel Quel with the Com munist Party of France (of which, of course, Louis Althusser was a member and leading intellectual) rather than with what they took to be a "confused and ap parently ephemeral movement":
TelqueJians were not about to follow Sartre out into the streets, megaphone in hand. The fact that Sartre supported the movement was a further incentive for them to take another route, for they had always done exactly the opposite of their major rival. (153) Rather than dwell on the pathetic and disgusting specter of intellectuals, who, in the name of avant-garde writing, align themselves with what was well-exposed as a bastion of the establishment, we might instead focus on the model of intel lectual activity that is represented by this alliance. The idea seems to be that the
avant intellectual is not one who needs to change or transform him- or herself in
any way; if anything, the masses , especially that part of the masses that does not
fit into the narrow, orthodox Marxist conception of the "industrial working class" (who can supposedly, according to the PCF view of things, transform society in an orderly, well-planned way, without the need for revolutionary upheaval) , are the ones who need to be taught and led by the intellectuals . Sartre's perspective, by contrast, was much more in the spirit of Mati's third thesis on Feuerbach: "the educator needs to be educated" -or consider Mao 's advice to revolutionaries: "The important thing is to be good at learning." There are two other forms of left-Sartrophobia that might be mentioned briefly. Both are in some sense antidialectical, in that they not only valorize difference, but seem to do so in an absolute way. Counterposed to Sartre's models of uni versality and totalization , Foucault proposed the notion of the "specific intellec-
Beyond the varieties of Sartrophobia
53
tual." There are two main aspects to this conception. First, the specific intellec tual aimS to work on particular problems, with no overarching scheme of values and no large conception of history or teleology. Indeed, these things must be rig orously resisted. To play on the well-known political slogan of the post-sixties pe riod, the idea is to "think locally, act locally." Second, and taking this last princi ple even further, the intellectual is not and should not claim to be the representative (or spokesperson) of anyone other than him- or herself. Both of these questions have to do with the critique of "representation" that was a noisy intellectual fashion in the post-1968 period and that, more recently, has given us identity politics . Sartre himself grappled with these questions, and he attempted to work for a more direct relationship with the masses, and for ways that expressions of the masses could be presented in less mediated ways. The most famous example of this Jatter effort was Sartre's championing of the Maoist newspaper, La Cause du Peuple, which ran headlines and stories that were simply verbatim accounts of the words of ordinary workers. (Sartre presents accounts of his involvement with the paper in both "The Maoists of France" and "Justice and the State.") In a moment I will re�rn to the question of how this new role that Sartre had taken up in the early 1 970s squares (or doesn't square) with his conception of the intellectual presented in 1965 in "A Plea for Intellectuals." There Sartre argues that one trait of the intellectual is that he or she gets involved in things that are "not his busi ness." Clearly there was something of a shift in Sartre's thinking after 1968, but my point here is that it does not look as though he had entirely joined the camp of those who were putting forward the critique of representation -even if Sartre had his own critique of representation-and who were heading toward identity politics . Perhaps the fact that he, as a famous intellectual and as someone the state was not likely to repress very harshly, came forward to take over the editorship of La Cause du Peuple at the moment when it was banned showed that there was still a good deal of interplay occurring between the position he had set out in 1965 and his attempt to fully become a revolutionary in'fellectual (as he saw it) in the post-1968 period. All of this has to do with Sartre's refusal of the sort of politics represented by Tel Quel, which the former must have seen as simply a reification of the division of labor, and indeed a reification that was to the advantage and for ' the fundamental physical security of an elite group. A related critique of Sartre's position-or positions, as the case may be-on engaged intellectual activity has come from advocates of "micropolitics." This position is influenced, as the reader most likely knows, by Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari. Todd May presents a systematic argument for this politics in his book, The Political Philosophy of Poststructuralist Anarchism ( 1994; Foucault is a major part of his argument as well). While I cannot provide a discussion of this text here, I want to point to the way that May argues for what he calls a politics that is �tactical," as opposed to "strategic." This seems to me to connect with a common thread in all of the anti-Sartrean figures and positions mentioned,
Chapter 3
54
namely that they are also antihumanist. May puts this forthrightly: "Ifpoststruc
turalist political thought could be summed up in a single prescription, it would be that radical political theory, if it is to achieve anything, must abandon hu
manism in all its forms"
(75). The ambiguous legacy of humanism is dealt with 5 here, on Sartre and Derrida, and I have written a book on this SUbject, Humanism and its aftermath; I note here with some inter to some extent in Chapter
est that two of the key figures of these texts , Kant and Derrida, have mostly been
set aside by the advocates of Foucauldian and Deleuzean antihumanism. This is
�priate, for humanism is of a piece with ethical-political universalism and
app
with a strategic sense of political change. In a Kantian frame, Derrida argues that
this universalism is something that we are "condemned" to (just as Kant said that we are condemned to metaphysics and system-building), even while, from a de
constructive standpoint, we are also condemned to the perpetual critique of uni
versalisms and therefore to a radical questioning of the constitution of every "we" (see, for example,
Of Spirit, Chap . 10). If Sartre's humanism is , therefore,
a good deal more naive than , say, Derrida would prefer, this does not mean, ei
ther, that we ought to simply jettison it-or even that we ing that we would want to .
could do this, suppos
Arguments in this "poststructuralist anarchist" vein, such as Todd May's (an
other systematic text that should be mentioned here is Michael Hardt's and An
tonio Negri's Labor of Dionysus), often criticize what Foucault called Marxism's
"fetish for the state." The argument is that Marxism is too hung up on the state as
either an oppressive institution and the center of power relations in an oppressive society, or as, in some form , the locus of the overcoming of oppressive power re
lations (either through the radical reform of the existing state, or through the over
throw of the existing state and its replacement with some new form of state, for example the dictatorship of the proletariat). In a Foucauldian and Deleuzian mode, micropolitics recognizes no such central locus , and therefore the activity
of the intellectual must be more "specific," more narrowly focused. Sartre, of course, generally wrote and spoke of power relations as finding a concentrated
form in the state, even while also presenting, perhaps even more so in his literary
works than in the philosophical ones (though here there is the combination of phi
losophy and literature that does not exist so much for structuralist and "post
structuralist" intellectuals such as Levi-Strauss, Foucault, and Deleuze; here
again Derrida is quite different from this "poststructuralism") , an extraordinary
sense of the quotidian and the psychological. But then , Sartre is also giving us a
critique of capitalism, colonialism, and imperialism, and of societies divided into
classes, and of the mechanisms that perpetuate these social forms, so naturally he finds himself encountering the state.
Here is what is remarkable, and, I think, telling with regard to the anti-Sartrean
arguments. Whenever Sartre went up against oppressive power relations , whether in his writing (again , one might simply use his essay on the Rosenbergs as an ex
ample) or his activism, he found himself up against the state. What is telling is that
Beyond the, varieties of Sartrophobia
55
the same can be said about Foucault, Deleuze, Guattari, etc. Referring to the early
seventies, Mark Poster writes: "During these years Foucault was perhaps the most
eminent and widely acknowledged intellectual who participated in leftist politics .
Ironically, Foucault was at that time criticizing the role and function of the tradi tional intellectual"
(Foucault, Marxism, and History, 5). While every cause that
Foucault took up had aspects that cannot simply be described in the facile and re
ductive terms of "it's the state," still , there was not one of these causes , from pris
oner's rights to antipsychiatry to Stonewall and gay rights to the Iranian Revolu
tion of 1979, where state power was not a significant aspect. Indeed, in every case, as the radicality of opposition deepens , so comes closer the point where the state
will present, forcefully if necessary, its own definition of justice.
One might consider in this respect the way that some leftist newspapers tend
to write, "that's capitalism for you," as though this is self-explanatory and one does not need a systematic investigation into the capillary action of power rela
tions . Foucault excelled at the analysis of such capillary movement, which he dis
cussed in terms of "disciplinary matrices." His focus tended to be more on the
iI)ed body rather than the reified consciousness, and in some sense his po
discipl
litical sympathies were inspired by various revolts of the body. Perhaps Sartre can be faulted here for what may appear in contrast to remain a form of Enlighten
ment rationalism. After all, even though this is too quick, it is clear that 'Sartre maintained, even at the point where he was most straining against the traditional
model of the intellectual , a Socratic sense that oppositional politics must speak
truth to power; as we know, Foucault had a different view of the powerlknowl
edge relationship. Does this mean, in the latter case, that there is no place where
one might fmd the general matrix of power matrices, the sort of concentration that
Marxism finds in the state? Or, does it instead mean that overthrowing capitalism and every form of oppression is a very complicated thing? To say that it is com
plicated, that power is diffuse and that different oppressions are not so quickly re
duced to one form, is this to say that there are not nMal points and, in particular, the nodal point called "the state" where, if power is not addressed in, that form, then, as the Maoists say, "all else is illusion"?
The point, more simply stated, is that, for all of this healthy discussion over
the role of the intellectual , when it came to activism, many of the radical intel
lectuals who were advocating micropolitics and the specific intellectual more or less did the same sorts of things that Sartre did, and they found themselves up
against the state.
The discussion of these models has become exceedingly "academic" in the
United States, in some cases leading to a form of identity politics that is so nar
row that, in fact, it has to do with little more than personal careerism in colleges
and universities. What is needed instead is to see how, in France, the discussion
played out against the background of two related issues that the Events of May
and their aftermath put on the agenda in concentrated form:
(1) the Soviet model,
both during the Stalin period and after, as well as the slavish adherence of the
Chapter 3
56
Communist Party of France to "actually existing socialism"; and (2) Mao, the
Chinese Revolution, the Cultural Revolution, and the activities of the Maoists of France . In China, Mao wrote and spoke about different levels of contradictions, and about how there are contradictions among the people that are different from (even
jf related to) antagonistic class contradictions. In an essay titled, "The Ten
Major Relationships," Mao addressed all sorts of social relations (for example , between the town and countryside, and between the army and the masses) in a nonreductivistic way. Many of the discussions in France regarding the role of the
intellectual, such as those found in the Power/Knowledge collection (Foucault) or in the conversations between Foucault and Deleuze and radical students found in
the former's Language,
counter-memory, practice (where Foucault famously says
that the point of intellectual activity is to create a "tool kit for revolutionaries") cannot be understood apart from this background. There is a tendency in the United States, and now in France as well, to throw all of this background and tumult into the dustbin of "all that"; perhaps what is even more the case is that younger, postmodern intellectuals have internalized the fragmentation of capitalist society in such a way that Eurocentrism is almost an unconscious assumption. One would not suspect, for example, from recent ex amples of Foucauldian discourse , that Foucault and Deleuze conclude their con versation on "Intellectuals and Power" ( 1972) by discussing the tactics of the Vietnamese revolutionaries or the way that diverse struggles are "linked to the revolutionary movement of the proletariat" (216). Somehow all of this went by the wayside, so that it may not be appropriate to charge Foucault and Deleuze, but instead their interpreters and especially their American interpreters in the academy, with the "Sartrophobia" of which we have been speaking. Significantly, "Intellectuals and Power" begins with Foucault saying the following:
A Maoist once said to me: "I can easily understand Sartre's position in siding with us; I can understand his goals and his involvement in politics; I can partially under stand your position, since you've always been concerned with the problem of con finement. But Deleuze is an enigma." I was shocked by this statement because your position has always seemed particularly clear to me. Deleuze responds:
Possibly we're in the process of experiencing a new relationship between theory and practice. At one time, practice was considered an application of theory, a conse quence; at other times, it had an opposite sense and it was thought to inspire theory, to be indispensable for the creation of future theoretical forms. In any event, their re lationship was understood in terms of a process of totalization. For us, however, the question is seen in a different light. The relationships between theory and practice are far more partial and fragmentary. (205) Let us note two things here . First, Sartre, Foucault, and Deleuze (and many others, with the exception , significantly, of some of the Telquelians), are opening
Beyond the varieties of Sartrophobia
57
themselves to the reformulation of their intellectual practice in light of the expe
rience of revolt that is occurring around them and that they are participating in on various levels. Second, what Deleuze seems to be saying is that, through this process and the social upheaval and counterculture that are inspiring it, the dif
ference that is opening up between himself and Foucault, on the one side, and
Sartre on the other, has to do with totalization-for it is clearly no accident that Deleuze invokes this term, which is so much associated with Sartre.
Foucault and Deleuze return to this theme at the end of their conversation, and
my question is whether or not the summation they provide really does authorize an anti-Sartrean (and anti-humanist, -totalizing , -universalist, -strategic, etc.) po
sition to the extent that others have argued for this. Allow me to quote at some
length; as we reenter the conversation, Deleuze is discussing the "present revolu
tionary movement," which , he argues,
, has created multiple centers, and not as a result of weakness or insufficiency, since a certain kind of totalization pertains to power and the forces of reaction. (Vietnam, for
�e, is an impressive example of localized counter-tactics.) But how are we to
ins
define the networks, the transversal links between these active and discontinuous points, from one country to another or within a single country?
Foucault responds: The question of geographical discontinuity which you raise might mean the, fol lowing: as soon
as
we struggle against exploitation , the proletariat not only leads
the struggle but also defines its targets, its methods, and the places and instru ments of confrontation; and to ally oneself with the proletariat is to accept its po sitions, its ideology, and its motives for combat. This means total identification. But if the fight is directed against power, then all those on whom power is exer
cised to their detriment, all who find it intolerable, can begin the struggle on their own terrain and on the basis of their proper activi� (or passivity). In engaging in a struggle that concerns their own interests, whose objectives they clearly under stand and whose methods only they can determine, they enter into a revolutionary process. They naturally enter as allies of the proletariat, because power is exer cised in the way that it is in order to maintain capitalist exploitation . They gen uinely serve the cause of the proletariat by fighting in those places where they find themselves oppressed. Women, prisoners , conscripted soldiers , hospital patients , and homosexuals have now begun a specific struggle against the particularize\! power, the constraints and controls that are exerted over them. Such struggles are actually involved in the revolutionary movement to the degree that they are radi cal, uncompromising, and nonreformist, and refuse any attempt at arriving at a new disposition of the same power with, at best, a change of masters . And these movements are linked to the revolutionary movement of the proletariat to the ex
tent that they fight against the contro Is and constraints which serve the same sys tem of power. . . . In this sense, the overall picture presented by the struggle is certainly not that of the totalization you mentioned earlier, this theoretical total ization under the guise of "truth." The generality of the struggle specifically
Chapter 3
58
derives from the system of power itself, from all the forms in which power is ex ercised and applied. (216) r
Now, one might argue that Foucault and Deleuze went much further in the ar gument for locality and fragmentation and "tactics" (in the sense that Todd May uses the term) in the years after this. Perhaps it helps to contextualize the matter as follows . In the heady days of May 1968 and its aftermath, when the Maoists were a real social and intellectual force, Foucault and Deleuze and other, shall we say, post-Sartreans were drawn into some of the same terms that Sartre was grap pling with, and some of the similarities had to do with the vogue for what De1euze was to call "nomad thought." Out of this matrix also arose an interest in Antonio Gramsci and the questions of hegemony and the war of position. One might argue that, under the influence of Benny Levy, Sartre was also moving in very new di rections by the mid- 1 970s, directions that were less concerned with totalization. So, it might be argued, by this point not only Foucault, Deleuze, and the others were anti- or post-Sartre, but Sartre had moved in this direction as well. But in the second chapter here I have argued that this was not the case. A further point might be made that micropolitics as it is being practiced by in tellectuals who think they are inspired by Foucault, Deleuze, Guattari, etc., really seems to be a dead end. If this is the case, and regrounding ourselves in what Fou cault and Deleuze at least claimed to be thinking back in those heady days when they were formulating their notions on radical intellectual activity in the midst of revolutionary events , we might adopt a more modest critique of Sartre's project of totalization, and this actually has to do with modesty itself, at least when it comes to the questions of totality and representation. But then we have to admit that Sartre himself had moved toward modesty when it comes to representation, in his model of the radical intellectual from the early 1970s, and we have to ac knowledge that Sartre's model of totality, especially from the second volume of the Critique, was one that warned of a "total integration" that destroys negativity. (On the "nomad thought" response to the question of totality, see my "Nomad and empire" and "Foucault: Power/Counter-power.") Perhaps intellectual modesty is needed in the case that theoretical totalization becomes overbearing or monolithic, or where the theorizer seems to be thinking that he or she is speaking ex cathedra. In a Derridean frame, one might be criti cal of "a certain apocalyptic tone," but, speaking from personal experience, I have heard this tone just as much in micropolitics and in a politics that is supposedly critical of "representation" as I ever heard it from Sartre . Perhaps this is only to be expected in a "politics" that is often confined to fairly petty power struggles in the academy-though, admittedly, not in every case is the confinement self inflicted, and those of us who wish for the days when Sartre, de Beauvoir, Fou cault, Marcuse, and others showed public audacity and courage must grapple with the facts of postmodern capitalism, where what would constitute a counterculture is no longer clear. (On this, more in Chapter 7.)
Beyond the varieties of Sartrophobia
59
The larger point would seem to be that, in "Intellectuals and Power," Foucault and Deleuze come full circle, for what is affIrmed in conclusion is that there is a relationship between theory and practice where the latter is primary. Yes , there is a great diversity of experience-but I do not know of any better model for the as. sertion of this diversity than Mao's leadership in forging a different perspective on revolution in the shadow of Stalin's monolithic totalization. One of Mao's chief arguments in the midst of all of that was that he heard much talk of "unity" and little of "struggle," whereas he took the latter to be primary. Totalization is generated by the system of power that is struggled against. '!\vo points ought to be made here. First, it is against this background that Sartre, Foucault, and Deleuze are grappling with the role of theory and intellectual activity; when that background is factored out, then we are left with micropolitics and identity poli tics as we have more recently seen them practiced. (I realize that I have said this already, but I think it bears repeating.) Second, if anything, Sartre, Foucault, and Deleuze can all be faulted with conceptions of struggle that do not open the way for that which escapes the dialectic of struggle and totalizing power. Certainly, on both ofvtgese points, Foucault's Hobbesian side is troubling, for it results in a "politics" where the war of all against all is taken to such microscopic levels that no system of power that exists on a more macroscopic level is really challenged. Furthermore, as Mark Poster notes , Foucault's challenge to Sartre see�s to re sult in a position that is antitheoretical, and more besides: Foucault was so deeply concerned to limit the scope of the theorist's epistemologi cal position that he refused to systematize his position or even to elaborate concepts to any great extent. He refused to explore at all the position from which he attained knowledge and at times went so far as to grant that he was a simple positivist in order to avoid the task of self-reflection. (24)
Foucault's antitheoretical stance is captured well.by Nancy Fraser's now-famous formula, "empirical insight and normative confusion ." What's more, and now to complete our compendium of posttheorizing with a brief mention of one more fIgure, Foucault is surprisingly close in this respect to someone who might be seen as the closest thing to Sartre that we have today in the United States , at least insomuch as engaged intellectual activity goes, namely, Noam Chomsky. It is neit appropriate to tag Chomsky with the "left Sartrophobia" that I think does indeed apply to some of the Tel Quelians and (seemingly all) advocates of micropolitics and identity politics. And, in fact, Chomsky's political positions are often not very different from ones that Sartre either took up or that one could imagine Sartre taking up today. But then, this could also be said of Foucault and Deleuze in many cases. The point is that Chomsky clearly thinks that all one needs is ob servations and positions; what is not needed is any kind of deep-going social the ory. As I am sure most readers of this text will know, Chomsky is extraordinar ily prolific in his political writings and speeches, which consist almost entirely
Chapter 3
60
of relentless exposures of the imperialist system. Those readers who are activists will be familiar with the form of political exposure known as the "fact sheet," the sort of thing %at is sometimes passed out at demonstrations and rallies. Chom sky's political work is something like the proverbial fact sheet whose pages, if set end to end, would perhaps reach the moon or some other heavenly body, so
dogged is he in the exposure of the workings and evil-doings of the system. A
few years ago I heard Chomsky speak at Loyola University in Chicago. His talk, which was a typical one for him, consisted in about an hour of this sort of expo sure, and then a one-line conclusion that went something like, "Never has the need for change been so great." Although a few people have attempted to show the connections between Chomsky's theoretical work in linguistics and his political work (for instance , Michael Albert , editor of
Z Magazine), Chomsky himself resists this. Although
this is a discussion that should be conducted at greater length, it seems to me that what one would find in such an examination is a concatenation of rationalism in the linguistics and empiricism in the politics. The connection might be made, at least as Albert has argued , between the basic capacity for language , especially at the level of grammar, and some basic desire for freedom-of a sort that Chom sky links with Rousseau. Perhaps one could then go further and make an argu ment about language and freedom, but Chomsky himself has not offered such an argument. Returning, however, to "our Rousseau," as Althusser called Sartre , Chomsky does present to us a provocative example . In the 1 965 argument con cerning the engaged intellectual- by which is meant the "real" intellectual Sartre gives as one characteristic of such an intellectual that he or she gets in volved in things that are "not his business." He is taking up the genealogy of the term, "intellectual," that goes back to the Dreyfus affair. Under this usage, Chom
sky is an exemplary intellectual , in that his technical expertise is in linguistics but he also expends great energy in the exposure of U.S. imperialism. Who would say that this is not highly laudable , regardless of Chomsky's relationship with social theorizing or even the fact that he seems to be very skeptical of such theorizing? After all, is it not good when an intellectual , or anyone , opposes the principalities and powers when they are rotten? Is it not good when an intellectual who has tremendous prestige in her or his field brings that prestige to bear on oppressive social systems? My point is that the example of Chomsky thematizes the contradiction that
Sartre was grappling with, from
What Is Literature? to the dialogues with
Maoists and with the post-Maoist Benny Levy, concerning the role of intellectual activity in transforming the world. For, if the intellectual is one who gets involved in what is "not his business," then is it not primarily a matter of something that the intellectual "delivers up" to the masses , a kind of transfer of intellectual cap ital? This is what we see up until at least 1 965, but it may also be what we see in the early 1 970s, when Sartre is hoping to overcome the division of labor and to dissolve himself, so to speak, into the people . At the same time, we have Sartre
Beyond the varieties of Sanrophobia
61
the philosopher and social theorist, who i s attempting t o explain the world in order to change it. Certainly Chomsky assumes the ethical-political universalism that Sartre attempted to give a theoretical foundation for, though one might won der at an "anarchist" (as Chomsky sometimes calls himself) who voted for Bill Clinton and who thinks the U.S . federal government ought to be strengthened against threats from right-wing militia groups. If we were to fmd fault with some political position that Sartre upheld (for instance, many anti-imperialists question his position on the state of Israel), would we then trace this back to his theoreti cal work, all the while, in the case of Chomsky, tracing any questionable position to the lack of political theory? The question goes back to discussions of political "expertise" that are at least as old as Plato. In either case, Sartre or Chomsky, there is the "double life," the difference being that Sartre was always struggling to resolve the contradiction. In this light, I want to rum towliI'd some concluding ' remarks on Sartre's legacy for radical intellectuals. It is quite possible that many will find the conclusion I have come to not very satisfactory, for it is a conclusion that resists closure. There are contradictions at the heJl(t of the intellectual enterprise. To be an engaged intellectual seems to mean t*o things, simultaneously: to stand with the masses against oppressive systems, and to carry forward the intellectual work of radical social transforma tion. There are numerous examples of intellectuals who mainly or eVen only do one or the other, for instance Chomsky and Adorno, respectively. Sartre did both things and took it that there was a connection between the two, and in this he was like Marx. The term that we often use for standing with the masses aild their struggle is "solidarity," and, in some versions of this idea, there is no contradic tion between the masses and those who "stand with" them. Even in his final pe riod of theorizing about intellectual activity, Sartre recognized that there are con tradictions: of class, of one's social standing and cachet, in the division of mental and manual labor, in the difference between theory and practice. To say that there are no contradictions here, supposedly because there cannot be any if this is to be "real" solidarity, is in fact to undermine possibilities for transcending the contra dictions through social struggle. The contradictions between theory and practice and between mental and manual labor were not overcome in the Soviet Union in the Stalin period by adding the term "worker" to everyone's position-intellec tual worker, cultural worker, etc. Nor is the situation helped, in the final analysis, by Althusser's term (the effects of which are seen in Deleuze's comments about theory and practice), "theoretical practice." Of course the differences are not ab solute, nor should they be hypostatized as such. In the aftermath of May 1968, especially in working with the Maoists, Sartre thought that he could effect a more direct relationship between theory and prac tice, and to perhaps even dissolve the difference between being an intellectual and being a1l1ember of the working class. The principle aspect of this, to my mind, is that Sartre saw the revolutionary situation as necessitating a further transformation in intellectual work. Sartre wanted to go beyond his own intellectual hegemony,
62
Chapter 3
and beyond the situation where intellectual work might become capital -to be de livered ov� "in solidarity," but capital all the same.
Does the fact that, at least in class society, the contradictions of intellectual
work cannot be so directly overcome, mean that the engaged intellectual will ul
timately remain a "fellow traveler"? The key to this question is to conceive fel
low traveling not as primarily aimed at an organization or movement, but first of
all toward the oppressed and their higher aspirations. Keeping in mind that Sartre's conceptions of collectivity do not require the positing of some "collec
tive subject," we can maintain that, for the foreseeable future, solidarity will re
quire a continual grappling with difference.
If we return , then , to a certain "mourning" for the model that Sartre gives us
with his life even more than with his theory of that life, a series of questions fol
lows. Of course we can ask again where our Sartres and de Beauvoirs and Mar
cuses are today. I hope the foregoing discussion has deepened the question. I
hope that we have some sense now of what Chomsky lacks that Sartre had, but
we cannot lay all of this on Chomsky. For, one thing that we all lack now is a
sense of what a deep revolt and counterculture would look like. Sartre was one of the last writers who had his initial impact before television and other elec
tronic media transformed our sense of the importance of understanding - as Neil
Postman put it, "there isn't much to watch in thinking ." Pierre Bourdieu argues
that we have now come to the point where every intellectual (who wants to be
heard, in any case) is supposed to b� telegenic, to be ready to perform as "Ie fast talker." In the United States, we did see a major revolt in recent years , starting
in Los Angeles and spreading quite far from there, in the aftermath of the first
verdict in the trial of the racist cops who beat Rodney King to within an inch of his life. Many intellectuals spoke out, including the group of thinkers who have come to be known as the "New Black Intellectuals"- people such as Cornell
West and Patricia Williams and Lewis Gordon. Nor did they fail to be eloquent
when faced with the necessity and opportunity of making their voices heard . Many of these people, including those just named , are conversant in the theo
retical issues surrounding the question of engaged intellectual work, from Sartre to the critique of representation and beyond. We have to go further in our ex
ploration of the circumstances of Sartre's hegemony, the intellectual hegemony of
1 945-60 and the political hegemony thereafter. Do these circumstances indi
cate the possibility of a revival or some sort of extension of the Sartrean model
today? Or do present circumstances only favor post-Sartre, post-Althusserian
models? This is the question of Sartre in postrnodern times; significantly, it is also the question of politics in such times as these.
4 Political theory after Bataille and Derrida On
the critique of "project"
There has been much discussion in recent years regarding the political possibil ities of deconstruction. While there are many radical and, just to say it, good, pos sibilitids, there is also at least one wrong way to go, at least in my view. In this essay I will examine some problems in works by Maurice Blanchot and Jean-Luc Nancy on the question of community. I see these works as set against, at least to some extent and in significant ways, Sartre's conception of "project." While I find elements of their work admirable, in particular their continuation of the anti utilitarianlanti-"ethic of calculation" thrust of Georges Bataille and Jacques Der rida, it seems clear to me that their critique of the idea of a human and political project is being taken up in a politically quietistic way, at least by their admirers in North American continental philosophy circles. Even apart from this scene, however, I think the quietistic aspects of what might be called Blanchot's and Nancy's "communitarianism" are in the original sources. In the next chapter I will continue the Sartre/Derrida discussion. Both chapt¥.rs are really meant as prelim inary probes, aspects of the groundwork for more extended investigations .
For the generation that came of age in the 1960s, the idea of a political " proj_ ect" is most of all associated with Jean-Paul Sartre. While Sartre did not accept the idea of a human "essence," it is still the case for Sartre that part of what it means to be human is to be able to have a project, to pro-ject oneself into the fu ture. Thus, having a "future," in the sense of having a conception of what might unfold in the future and what conscious human activity (praxis) . might do to shape this unfolding is integral to the human form of sentience. As everyone knows, Sartre's voice defined the intellectual field in France and beyond from 1945 until about 1960,'and his political activities and writings con tinued to have a major influence until his death in 1980. There are perhaps several 63
64
Chapter 4
different "generations of '68," even if some of these generations are contempo raries. Insomuch as the Events of May were "Sartrean," there was certainly a Sartrean generation of 1 968 . I wonder if there is also a subgeneration of those who either caught the tail end of the sixties, or just missed it, in the sense of active par ticipation in the struggles of the day, but who still take fundamerital orientation from those struggles. (Now I am referring not only to the Paris Events, but also to struggles from Shanghai to Chicago and from Prague to Mexico City.) As a mem ber of this subgeneration, I read and still read books such as Mark Poster's Exis tential Marxism in Postwar France and Arthur Hirsh's The French New Left with great enthusiasm, feeling inspired by the idea of the engaged intellectual. If some of this activity was seriously overrated at the time, it is underrated now, and works such as Luc Ferry's and Alain Renaut's French Philosophy of the Sixties have ap peared as neoconservative antidotes to Poster, Hirsh, and similar works. Today, many of the important voices in philosophy and intellectual life more generally, the "senior" figures, still take orientation from the sixties . Although some of these voices have mellowed somewhat, few have actually gone over to the other side. When Derrida speaks of "the impossible," it is hard not to hear a resonance with a popular slogan of the Events of May, "Be realistic, demand the impossible!" Perhaps that is simply romanticism on my part, but, then again, I think we could use a little romanticism. The underestimation of Sartre today, the avoidance of him, has been accompa · nied by a concomitant promotion of the liberal figures of the French sixties, es pecially Merleau-Ponty and Raymond Aron. (The former, it might be said, was pushed into a comer by Sartre's hyperbolic rhetoric. However, beyond whatever personal and even perhaps oedipal issues might have been presentin the conflict, 20/20 hindsight shows that Merleau-Ponty could only see liberalism-I would say "mere liberalism" - as the alternative to Stalinist Communism.) Still ignored, except by the very specialized and politically isolated (somewhat self-isolated) researchers of contemporary continental philosophy, are Sartre's earlier critics from what might be called "the other existential left," the Nietzschean left, namely Georges Bataille and Maurice Blanchot. Not that their work has not re ceived attention for itself, but the way that they were responding to the Sartrean field has been ignored by recent continental researchers, because Sartre himself is avoided. Jacques Derrida, as he has repeatedly acknowledged, owes a consid erable debt to this pair. In Bataille we find the critique of "project," of its sup posed reductivism and utilitarianism. Speaking a language that positivists cannot hear as discursive (in other words, as anything other than "poetry," perhaps good, perhaps bad-recall that Carnap praised Nietzsche as a poet, but referred to Hei degger's writing as "bad poetry"), Bataille asks, "What could be more ridiculous than reducing ' what is' -the universe, if you like-to analogies with useful ob jects !" (Guilty, 1 6) Derrida, in his essay on Bataille's reading of Hegel, "From restricted to gen eral economy," discusses the idea of a "perfect" economy, one in which every
Political theory after Bataille and Derrida
65
coin is accounted for. This economy is, of course, Hegel's system, which, while supposedly accounting for "everything," exercises a radical reduction on "what is." (This theme was already well developed by Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and other nineteenth-century existentialist thinkers.) But what is the "outside" of this economy, and what is its relation to the "inside"? Given that Hegel's economy is first of all diachronic, the succession of historical stages from a well-defined ori gin to a well-defined end, one would think that the "remainders" of this economy must necessarily be outside of the structure of history and historical time. This interpretation of the remainder
as
"momentary" (as a moment that is not
continuous with and cannot be reinserted in the temporal or historical order) seems to be supported by Blanchot, in
The Unavowable Community, and Jean The Inoperable Community. The first half of Blanchot's text is a post-Bataille, post-Derrida analysis of the Events of May 1 968 . Blanchot takes it
Luc Nancy, in
as a virtue of the y oung militants that they were not "going anywhere;' that they put forward no positive program or project.
It was not even a question of overthrowing an old world; what mattered was to let a possibility manifest itself, the possibility-beyond any utilitarian gain-of a being together that gave back to all the right to equality in fraternity through a freedom of speech that elated everyone. (The Unavowable Community, 30) Indeed, it seems that, for Blanchot, May
1968 was the big "Love-In" that fits in
well with the recent wave of apolitical sixties nostalgia (or with the reduction of sixties politics to feel-good pop psychology rhetoric, such as Bill Clinton's sup posed ability to "feel y our pain"). At least , that is how Blanchot's characteriza tion of the Events reads now, within the antiproject framework. Consider, too, the notion of an "event," contrasted to the notion of an unfolding process. The prob lem with Hegelianism is that the event drops out, it has no real existence (recall the exclusion of sense-certainty from the systenil. We will return to look at the ' flip-side of this coin, as it were, in a moment . Nancy, whose Inoperable
Community was the immediate inspiration for Blan
chot's text, focuses especially on the notions of "being toward death," which he takes from Heidegger, and "singularity." Where Heidegger, however, describes death as "that possibility which is one's ownmost"
(Being and Time, sec. 50),
Nancy is concerned with the death that summons one's finitude toward commu nity. As Patrick Hayden puts it, characterizing Nancy's position,
The finitude of community, the finitude of beings summoning community, is also the very absencing of community through this finitude. That which calls oneself into question most radically is the death of an other; not one's own death, which cannot be experienced as such, but an other's death that concerns one, that one shares. The sharing of the other's death brings out most forcefully the differences of beings-in common. Someone else's death removes me from myself, and their absence, impos sibly, is the very openness of community, its very possibility. Without death (which
Chapter 4
66
is the absolutely other, the most irreducible alterity), community would not be pos sible. ("(Re)thinking community: responding to Bataille," 21) Who is this "one" who is concerned with the death of the other? In Nancy's view, this one is not the atomistic individual of liberalism, but rather the "sin gularity." Indeed, Nancy 's remarks on the "absolutely detached for-itself' seem aimed not only at liberalism, but also at what might be understood as Sartre's radical individualism. In the place of the traditional, self-conscious subject of Descartes, the "being without relation" (4) , Nancy proposes the singular being, whose "consciousness of self turns out to be outside the self of consciousness"
( 1 9). Katherine Dow refers to this reconfigured subjectivity as "intrinsically ex trinsic" ("Ex-posing Identity," 6). Furthermore, whereas two sup,j ects merely
confront each other as objects in opposition, singular beings encounter each
other through the mode of "compearance ('co-appearance ') or mutual exchange" (Dow,
6).
Quite unclear to me, however, is whether these formulations, coupled as they are with Nancy's rewriting of "being toward death," really go so far beyond Sartre's existentialism. Indeed, they remind me of Sartre 's earlier existentialism, devoid of the later political understanding. This is the result, I think, of Nancy's and Blanchot's efforts toward avoiding any sense of personal transcendence; they seem to think such transcendence is an opening to "Stalinism" (see Nancy's essay, "The Compearance ," as well as volume
3 of Bataille's The Accursed Share,
"Sovereignty"). They are right, it does open that possibility. What, however, is the cost of foreclosing the possibility? To my mind it is
a
notion of "mutual ex
change ," in a community that does not have to be created because it is "always already" here , but that also simply reminds one of liberalism. Nancy's "compearance" is not a "union," for the latter would assume "already given subjects (objects)." Rather, compearance "consists in the appearance of the
between as such" (28-29). (Nancy would have done well to have left the words
"as such" out of this formulation, as they undermine the idea of "the between,"
or what more properly should have been called "between-ness." Martin Buber 's term,
das Zwischenmenschliche, the "interhuman ," could also help us here; see 3 1 -47 .) One assumes that the notion of "solidarity," especially in
Mendes-Flohr,
tension with "autonomy," would have problems similar to those ascribed to "union ." And yet, I find nothing in the terms that accompany Nancy's "between" that really serves as a replacement for dialectically related notions of solidarity and autonomy, especially if this dialectic is structured, as it is in Sartre 's
Critique,
as a totalizing process without a totalizer, without a transcendental spirit that pro
vides some final meaning to history. The same goes for Blanchot, especially when he speaks of a "mutual contestation" that deepens [the awareness of being isolated] in a solitude lived in common"
(Unavowable Community, 2 1 ). If the
only thing that makes this kind of talk not simply a form of gloomy existential ism is the lack of a "project," then shouldn't we say, "Vive Ie projet"?
Political theory after Bataille and Derrida
67
Perhaps Sartre's more Cartesian side is most easily seen in the famous "di alectics of boxing" example from the unfinished second volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reason. But this side is only predominant if one focuses on each boxer individually, and the point of the example is precisely to show how proj ects are not the products of isolated, self-creating consciousnesses. An existential individualism is also readily apparent if one focuses on Sartre's choice of "sport." (I look forward to the day when a new society will abolish boxing; on this point, see McBride, Sartre 's Political Theory, 1 63-68.) All the same, there is still a sense of between-ness here that structures the event as it develops in time. There might be better analogies to use than boxing, though of course Sartre was also in terested in capturing the brutality of class struggle. I like to think about a group of children on the playground, not only dividing into teams, but also making up the game itself. Then again, this ideal, "free dialectic," not grounded in any straightforward material necessity, perhaps exemplifies the carnival · spirit that Blanchot is celebrating in the "moment" of May 1 968-as when Lenin called revolution a "festival of the oppressed." That is to move too quickly, however, in more ways than one. Blanchot's festival is one where, for a moment, people live as .though they have never been oppressed, or as if it is only a distant memory. TP.e other way that this moves too quickly-for Sartre and Lenin, I would say is that the moment of such a liberatory experience, as it was manifest in,Paris in May 1968, remains conditioned by the fact that France was and is an imperialist country. It is not that there should never be the feeling of liberation, the prefigu ration of redemption, in such a society, but certainly the conditions for such an experience are different from what they would be in the Third World. So, Sartre aimed for something quite brutal and direct with his boxing example, one where the participants are not likely to forget what it is like to live in this Hobbesian world. One might question whether the example leaves Sartre, especially know ing his sometime Cartesian proclivities, with two separate, opposing subjectivi ties. However, Sartre breaks out of Cartesianism: .fue subjectivities involved here are themselves founded and structured by the struggle. If there is a residual Carte sianism or radical subjectivity here, we still might ask how the idea of "mutual contestation" solves the problem-indeed, the idea appears to be quite similar to Sartre's. In "Sartre and the Deconstruction of the Subject," Christina Howells demonstrates a number of affinities between Sartre's and Derrida's conceptions and critiques of the subject. As she points out, both Sartre and Derrida are inter ested in the "reinterpretation" of the subject, and the latter even takes Nancy to task for speaking of the "liquidation" of the subject (348). Furthermore, where Blanchot and Nancy focus so much on the momentary "always already" structure of these contestations and exchanges, a focus that collapses in their work into its own kind of Cartesianism, Sartre is concerned in his later work to absorb the mo ment in a network of social processes. In favor of Sartre, too, I would say that, for all that there seems to remain a Cartesian kernel to even his later work, his social theory must be applied to a
Chapter 4
68
culture that itself is thoroughly Cartesian. One might just as well ask about the "Cartesianism" of Kierkegaard or any thinker-Bataille or Adorno , for that mat ter- who resists the complete obliteratlon of singularity by totality. But it is one thing to stand on the side of the negative moment in the dialectic, as that which resists reification and what Sartre calls the counterfinality of the institution, and another thing to hypostatize this moment into pure self-sufficiency. The "always already " community of Nancy and Blancho.t---jgnores the boxing match of our present form of society, its inherent Cartesiani �m that must be overcome as such, from within . (Cyberspace will present new and extraordinary problems in this regard, as the possibilities for embracing the evil genius, because he is us, mul tiply and deepen. But that is another story.) There always already might be a powerful way of overcoming the Cartesianism of Western liberal societies
if it
were integrated into a project.
I have admittedly overstated my case against Nancy and Blanchot; I find their
conceptions of community an inspiration in some respects. (Significantly, Derrida parts company with them, and with me, over communitarianism, which he re jects.) Some readers will say that the problem with my critique of these concep tions is that I want to
use them, or at, least to apply them. That is right. But even
beyond the question of integrating Nancy and Blanchot (and the general project of rethinking community in the way that they do) into the project of reconfigur ing the polis (or, in my conception, bringing the polis into being), I find three basic problems in their approach . First, one sees in their work the typical
insularity of much philosophy from
France. Nancy and Blanchot (and Bataille's conception of "literary communism," which Nancy takes up in the final part of
The Inoperable Community) have to be
understood in the context of the response to Sartre. Apart from this context (and even somewhat within it) their work seems to generate a momentary excitement that has no orientation toward practice, other than perhaps to a longer term "proj ect" of quietism. Second, apart from the example of the Events of May in Blanchot's work, there is an overarching rationalism here. There is no empirical consideration of tradi tional communities or so-called "elective communities." There is little sense that liberalism is quite a bit more than merely a conception to be philosophically dis sected, that atomism is a culture and a form of life and must be addressed as such. A little attention to the notion of ideology, especially in Althusser 's sense, would not hurt either. And one of the easiest things in the world is to go on about "Stal inism" without dealing with the history of the Soviet Union, the international communist movement , and the imperialist division of the world. Third, Nancy and Blanchot seem to get a positively existential high from con sidering the pathos of isolation and death (without even machine-gunning any Nazis in the process; rather the pathos is enjoyed in the space of quiet singular ity ) . There is, certainly, a very important point to emphasizing the meaning of iso lation and solitude, as Sophocles does at the conclusion of Antigone. Creon, hav-
Political theory after Bataille and De"ida
69
ing lost all respect from his subjects because of his hubris and his self-involved emptiness, says, "Take me away, quickly, out of sight. I do not even exist-I
am
no one, Nothing." But it seems to me a kind of morbid sensibility, typical of a cer
tain strand in French philosophy since Bataille (and exemplified perhaps most of all in his "Acephale" group, which contemplated the idea of committing a ran
dom murder as a way of forging their "community; see Allan Stoekl's introduc tion to Bataille,
Visions of Excess), to focus exclusively on the death of the other
as the other side of an isolated individualism that never gives rise to "singular
being." One gets little sense from Nancy that "life is with people" (as goes an old saying from the Jews of the Eastern European shtetls, before their destruction). In
"Problems of Deconstructive Communitarianism," Kathleen League makes the point forcefully:
in speaking of and for community, many deconstructionists are one-sidedly promot ing, emphasizing, and affirming the concepts of lack, absence, death, loss of the sub ject, nothingness, and unworking. They are doing this to the near total exclusion of reference to, evocation of, and concern with life and its affmnation and nurturance. Perhaps the selective emphasis on death is merely strategic-perhaps it does not con note a dark fascination with death, but is merely used against the counterproductive or facile tendency toward mere emphasis on life . I am not convinced that this is the case, however. [This selective emphasis] on death and absence not only reinforces the binary oppositions that deconstruction is supposed to challenge, . . . it also is no more healthy than a selective emphasis on life; it probably also does bespeak nihilist tendencies and fascinations. (2) Indeed, the B ataille-inspired fascination with death often seems to be the flip
side of a sanguine and blithe affirmation . There are
found
useful, sometimes pro images here, but where is the negativity in this nihilism, where is the cri
tique?
There is some force to the critique of "project,".and the question still remains:
Can there be a political project that does not close the way to the advent of the other, of the impossible?
Is Nancy's "inoperable community" the only political possibility of decon
struction? It is the possibility, I would say, that one encounters in making a de
constructive end-run around Marx and Sartre.
This essay is a revised version of a section of my earlier book, Humanism and 20-26. In the essay I quote, with permission, from papers written for a graduate seminar I held in spring 1991 at DePaul University, on the subject ofDerrida and social theory. I thank Katherine Dow, Patrick Hayden, and Kathleen League for their contributions. its afte'rmath: The shared fate of deconstruction and politics,
5 The political space of Sartre in the text of Derrida
There are at least three places in the work of Jacques Derrida where an engage ment with Sartre seems positively invited (and many other places, of course, where such an engagement would be both possible and fruitful). First, there are the comments that Derrida makes in his essay on Bataille, "From Restricted to
General Economy." Bataille's "literary communism" is contrasted with �artre's
arguments in What Is Literature? concerning the writer and his or her audience. This contrast is worked out further by a contemporary philosopher who studied with Derrida, namely Jean-Luc Nancy (in his
The Inoperable Community).
Second, and almost certainly a more fertile ground for a larger comparison, is
the fact that both Sartre and Derrida have written substantial tomes on Jean Genet, the former's
Saint Genet and the latter's Glas. Indeed, as Christina How
ells argues in her very good introductory text on Derrida (besides the general ex cellence and judiciousness of this book, I have to admit to the pleasure of finding such a book written by a Sartrean) ,
Glas represents something of a "concealed
battle" with Sartre, especially over the question of Hegelian dialectic (85).
For readers not familiar with Glas, let me mention that it is a longish work where the text consists in two columns, one on Hegel and the other on Genet. In the largest sense, it is probably most appropriate to say that the work concerns the
questions of contamination and closure. These are, undoubtedly, two of the most important themes in all of Derrida's work.
Glas also partakes of the style of the
Kaballah, and thereby also thematizes the fact that Hegel was frustrated about his
inability to account for the Jews in his system. (On this point, see my Matrix and line, 5fr63, "The Jews who worry Hegel.") Through this thematization another
encounteli between Sartre and Derrida becomes possible, as the former is ar guably also not able to account for the Jews "as such," and then all of this leads to the discussion of Hegel and dialectic once again.
Howells goes so far as to claim, quite rightly I think, that "the commentary [in
Glas] is set up, in part, as a critical response to Sartre's seminal Saint Genet, 71
72
Chapter 5
published over twenty years earlier. Direct reference to Sartre is limited to a few relatively brief passages, but the precursor text underlies more of Derrida's writ ing than he acknowledges explicitly" (86). In moving to a third instance where an engagement between Sartre and Derrida is called for, I want to hold in the forefront of discussion a question that I can imagine Professor Howells wonders about as well, namely, how is it that Sartre always seems to drop out of the pic ture (or never enters the picture in the first place) in discussions of Derrida's work? After all, there are so many points of contact. First of all, Derrida , like many of his generation (and mine, for that matter) , became interested in philos ophy in part because of the overwhelming influence of Sartre. When Derrida first went to France from his home country of Algeria, having been drafted into the army, he heard Sartre being interviewed on the radio. This played a role in his realization that he wanted to be a philosopher. Second, both Sartre and Der
rida have fundamental orientations to 1 968, even if there are some differences over how to understand that period. Third, I note with some amusement that, while Sartre engaged with the Maoists even while saying that he was not a Maoist, Derrida has also been accused of having a bit of Maoism in him, by crit ics on the right (for example, Stanley Rosen, in
Hermeneutics and Politics) and
the left (Terry Eagleton and Alex Callinicos, both of whom are Trotskyists) .
My sense is that the riddle is solved by looking at two different trajectories that
lead toward Derrida, the one more "philosophical" and the other more straight forwardly political . In the first case there are those who come to Derrida through what is understood in the United States and England as a central stream of "con tinental" philosophy, where the work of Nietzsche and Heidegger predominates . (Of course continental philosophy is not the central or predominant stream in the academic institutions of philosophy more generally in these countries , where an alytic philosophy continues to dominate; indeed, the key figures of this Niet zschean-Heideggerian stream in the Anglo-American scene are on the whole quite marginal to the larger institutions.) But there is another way toward Der rida's work in terms of philosophy, which intersects with the political trajectory. There is a way toward Derrida that comes through Marxism in general , and Marx ist philosophy in France in particular, and especially through Sartre and Althusser. (A fine demonstration of this trajectory can be found in "On Interpretation," the long introductory chapter of Fredric Jameson's
The Political Unconscious.) As
the reader might imagine, the Heideggerians are mostly either indifferent or hos tile toward anything that comes out of Marxism or May 1968, and so this dimen sion of Derrida' s work drops out for them . What is primary here, of these two tra jectories? I would say that the political is primary, and that these different philosophical orientations are situated within the political . From the perspective of situating Derrida's work primarily within a Heideg gerian framework (that either claims to be beyond the merely ontic reality of po litical questions or that in fact retains at least some aspects of a fascistic outlook), Sartre drops out of the discussion, because he is seen as simply a bad reader of
73
The political space of Sartre in the text of Derrida
Heidegger and as someone who was deeply mired in the ontic. Derrida at least credits Sartre with a "misreading" so creative that it was able to hold sway for a generation. My perspective is that once one does situate the philosophical in
terms of the political (which means, for example, that one rejects such Heideg gerian staples as the idea that the "own-ness" of one's death places one ultimately beyond politics; Jean-Luc Nancy develops this argument in The Inoperable Com munity), there are many insights from Heidegger that can and should be assimi
lated to a radical perspective. These especially concern language and technology. In turning now to this third engagement, I want to begin to restore Sartre's place in the discussion of humanism. As I acknowledged in the introduction, I do think
there is something to be learned from Heidegger's "antihumanism," especially as regards speciesism and nonhuman animals, and especially if Heidegger's argu ments are resituated as much as possible away from their original context. But Derrida's work is often interpreted entirely in terms of this antihumanism, and
this is a one-sided reading of a philosopher who is famous for calling for the dou ble reading and the double strategy. Derrida's essay "The Ends of Man" deconstructs the humanism of Sartre
whom Michel Foucault called (in a Nietzschean mode that is also one part but not the whole of Derrida's perspective) "the last great Hegelian." This is a straw man that both Foucault and Derrida sometimes take recourse to. But decon struction is not a purely "negative" activity. Derrida does in fact criticize; and in
a purely analytical sense, Sartre's "mistake" in reading Hegel, HusserI, and es pecially Heidegger anthropologically. He also uncovers the ontotheological pre
suppositions that determine and motivate the structure of this "mistake ." What
has been missed in many analyses of this text is that Derrida is not merely re
asserting a certain (non-Sartrean, to be sure) Heidegger against Sartre. This is a very important point, both politically and philosophically. A Heideggerian de construction of humanism is not Derrida's only end here- for
this deconstruc au
tion would be no less a singular end than that posi�d by Kant. Kant's "end,"
tonomy, is really the humanism that Derrida's essay is perhaps most concerned with (the first of his three epigraphs is from the Groundwork/or the Metaphysics 0/ Morals). Derrida is intent on not allowing this end, autonomy, to be simply
c�celed by Heidegger's sense of the "ek-sistence of man" -"standing in the lighting of Being."
For Derrida, Heidegger's "proximity" (of humanity to Being) still requires a political reading . In this recognition, Derrida is not unlike Sartre, although of course Derrida's reading is quite different from Sartre's. Derrida insists that hu
manity and Being share a similar relation to their ends, even if these are not the same ends: "Man, since always, is his proper end, that is, the end of his proper. Being, since always, is its proper end , that is, the end of its proper" ( 1 34). It is the prolfimity of these twin autonomies, Being and humanity, that creates a "trem bling ." This trembling is not found in Sartre, because for him to speak of the au
tonomy of human beings is only proper, and to speak of the "autonomy" of Being
74
Chapter 5
would perhaps violate his sense of the qualitative difference between culture and nature. At the very least we can say that the trembling of human autonomy in the proximity of scarcity does not lead Sartre to the same sort of deconstruction of humanism that follows from Heidegger's analysis in the "Letter on Humanism." We will return to this point. The key to sorting out these two readings, grasping their similarity and their difference, is found a little later in Derrida's analysis. Derrida proposes that "the effects of this total trembling" be read under three general rubrics. The first and third of these concern, respectively, Heidegger and Husserl, and Heidegger and Nietzsche. Most commentators have focused on these. Of course, Husserl does have an important role to play here, for we might see Sartre's work as an attempt to be another version of Heidegger, in the sense of getting something else from Husserl- something which goes beyond the Cartesian moment toward the social world. This world hardly exists for Heidegger, even if he in some sense set him self against its modem constitution. But the second rubric concerns what Derrida calls a "strategic bet," a choice between two strategies, "from the inside" (in proximity to the "outside," from which a radical trembling comes) where "we are" (Derrida puts these words in quotation marks) . These are strategies for lis tening to the radical trembling that comes from outside. The fIrst of these strate gies Derrida calls Heideggerian: To attempt an exit and a deconstruction without changing terrain, by repeating what is implicit in the founding concepts and the original problematic, by using against the edifice the instruments or stones available in the house, that is, equally, in lan guage. Here, one risks ceaselessly confinning, consolidating, relifting (relever), at an always more certain depth, that which one allegedly deconstructs. The continu ous process of making explicit, moving toward an opening, risks sinking into the autism of the closure. ( I 35)
The second strategy, Derrida claims , "is mostly the one which dominates France today." Given that "today," in this instance, means the Events of May 1 968 and their aftermath (October, to be more specific), and that Derrida marks the date of his text in terms of the U.S. war against the people of Vietnam, the as sassination of Martin Luther King, Jr. , and the Events of May themselves , it is not especially extravagant to associate this strategy with Sartre. I hasten to add that his name does not appear at this place in the text, and instead only in the second epigraph. (But then, keep in mind that, in the second large text on Jean Genet to be written by a major philosopher, the name of the author of the first such text ap pears only rarely.) In this second strategy, the point is To decide to change terrain, in a discontinuous and irruptive fashion, by brutally plac ing oneself outside, and by affinning an absolute break and difference. Without men tioning all the other fonns of trompe-l'oeil perspective in which such a displacement can be caught, thereby inhabiting more naively and more strictly than ever the inside
The political space of Sartre in the text of Derrida
75
one declares one has deserted , the simple practice of language ceaselessly reinstates the new terrain on the oldest ground. The effects of such a reinstatement or·of such a blindness could be shown in numerous precise instances. . . . It goes without saying " that these effects do not suffice to annul the necessity for a "change of terrain." (135)
What does Derrida do with these two strategies that are somewhat at odds with one another? Derrida's answer to this question may not be surprising, but the dif ficult work of situating social theory within the problematic of his proposal has barely begun . Indeed, the reason for this , at least within social theory and prac tice that is influenced by Marxism, is that there is a strong reductivist tendency in Marxism. In the name of materialism, anything not reducible to "the one" is re sisted, set aside as philosophical idealism. (I discuss the question of "monolithic materialism" in the final chapter of my Politics in the impasse, "Crazy Quilt," 245-264.) However, regardless of whether or not Sartre's sense of dialectic may ultimately resolve into "the one" -and I cannot help but associate this with a gnosticism that ultimately must be refused, even if it serves in some cases as a regulative ideal-surely he must be credited with resisting any "materialism" in which "everything is already in the cards." This is what connects Sartre's think ing across all periods, especially from "Materialism and Revolution" to the final conversations with Benny Levy (as I argued in chapter 2). Let us rejoin Derrida at the point where he brings these strategies together: the choice between these two forms of deconstruction cannot be simple and unique. A new writing must weave and interlace these two motifs of deconstruction. Which amounts to saying that one must speak several languages and produce several texts at once. I would like to point out especially that the style of the first deconstruction is mostly that of the Heideggerian questions, and the other is mostly the one which dominates France today. I am purposely speaking in terms of a dominant style: be cause there are also breaks and changes of terrain in texts of the Heideggerian type; because the "change of terrain" is far from upsettinl! the entire French landscape to which I am referring; because what we need, perhaps, as Nietzsche said, is a change of "style"; and if there is style, Nietzsche reminded us, it must be plural. (135)
The passage on the Sartrean strategy seems to criticize the strategy for its naivete almost before it is set out. And yet, let us keep in mind that Derrida all the same refers to the strategy as a form of deconstruction. At the same time, he detects a certain naivete in the Heideggerian strategy as well: "ceaselessly confirming, consolidating, relifting [meaning to continually put back on a pedestal?], at an al ways more certain depth, that which one allegedly deconstructs" (my emphasis). The more, in other words, that Heidegger deconstructs Western ontotheology, the more he aids in its retrenchment. Indeed, the criticism of Heidegger here might be more severe than that of Sartre. Even if, Derrida argues, the attempt to brntally plate oneself outside, to affirm an absolute break and difference, is impossible, this in no way negates the necessity for a change of terrain. It seems to me that, in both his ontology and his sense of the practical necessity, Derrida is very close
Chapter 5
)6
to Sartre here. If anything, the impossibility of placing oneself "outside" is what
necessitates the attempt to do so. And, the change of terrain, which I believe I am reading correctly as the change of the social terrain, the social arrangement, ab
solutely depends on such attempts to reach an outside that perhaps cannot "fi nally" or "absolutely" be reached . But Derrida and Sartre also remain some distance apart here. Perhaps one can legitimately speak of a political space for Sartre in the text of Derrida but not the other way around. In the remainder of this essay I will sketch out the reasoning
for this claim.
Why is there no space, political or otherwise, for Derrida in the text of Sartre? To answer this question we must look at the framework that Sartre sets out in the
Critique of Dialectical Reason, especially the second volume. Despite the trans
formations of his project as he moved toward Marxism, it can be plausibly argued that an essentially Cartesian kernel remains in Sartre's conception of autonomy. The great benefit of this conception, for S artre, is that it allows, and perhaps we should say demands, a place for the particularity and specificity of concrete human beings. Though it is most likely overreaching, and certainly provocative, we might venture the hypothesis that at least part of the project of
Critique vol Flaubert study: to explain the specificity of a particular person. In the case of the second Critique the person in question is
ume 2 is not different from that of the
Stalin. Sartre wants a form of explanation that will understand Stalin both as a
creation or expression of social and historical forces , and as a concrete individual who was responsible for his actions. Responsibility remains a prime concern for Sartre, but so does contingency. Stalin is, in some large and definite measure (though never entirely) responsible for "Stalinism," but this is not to say that ei ther Stalin or the form of socialism that he played the leading role in construct ing was the product of ironclad necessity. (After all, Sartre even argues that class struggle, as the form of development of human history, is itself a contingency.) Without this contingency, this indeterminancy, any attempted radical project, the change of terrain, would be condemned to endless repetition, because it is clear that the capitalist world will never be willing to leave the socialist experiment to its own devices . (The repetition will end, one would think, when capitalism, in its drive to make sure that no alternative social order is possible, simply destroys human life on this planet .) As Ronald Aronson argues, in constructing a social theory that incorporates an extreme form of individual autonomy and responsibility, "here more than any where in his
oeuvre Sartre directly and unflinchingly approaches the master prob
lem of the passage from Descartes to Marx, from cogito to society, from individ ual praxis to collective membership"
(Sartre 's Second Critique, 42). Frankly, my
feelings about this project are conflicted . On one level I think the project is fan tastic, which is to say impossible. The passage from Descartes to Marx can be carried out only by maintaining a paradigm of consciousness that is riddled with philosophical and political problems . Habermas's arguments concerning the par-
The political space of Sartre in the text of Derrida
77
adigm of consciousness and sUbjectivity in Hegel and Marx, as developed exten sively in his Theory of Communicative Action and The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, are persuasive. Habennas recommends a shift to the paradigm of intersubjectivity. To put it bluntly, the meeting place of Descartes and Marx is not Kant and intersubjectivity. This is, Habennas points out, the fault of Hegel and Marx, who also work out of the paradigm of Cartesian SUbjectivity. Cartesian Marxism and Kantian intersubjectivity may come ever so close, but they remain parallel lines that never meet. Derrida, like Habennas, represents a development of Kant's critical philosophy, and thus a disruption of the philosophical frame work of Sartre's project. (Though beyond the scope of this essay, an additional piece of this puzzle is that intersubjectivity in Kant and Habennas . becomes intertextuality in Derrida.) How could it be, then, that despite what has just been said, there is a political space for Sartre in the text of Derrida? There is a space because autonomy, re sponsibility, and contingency can be rethought. Indeed, they must be rethought. In one respect (and even if this is a gross simplification), what Sartre and Derrida have in common is the fact that Althusser comes between them. Despite the many positive contributions of Althusser's structural Marxism, there seems to be no place in it for the ethical, the place of responsibility. It is that ethical moment that is opened by Derrida's philosophy, the space which, while never fully 0utside of context, is never absolutely detennined by context, either. Perhaps it can be said that Derrida is a "poststructuralist" in this specific sense (otherwise, I rarely find this tenn helpful when discussing Derrida's work) . If we were to develop this picture further, however, we would find more bridges between Sartre and Derrida. Peter Caws, Christina Howells , and Steve Martinot, among others, have shown that there is plenty of structuralism and post structuralism in Sartre's later work and that, among other things, Sartre was plenty aware of arguments about the linguisticality of consciousness . And then there is the "Jewish connection" (which I develop. regarding Sartre in Chapter 2 and regarding Derrida in my Matrix and line). Sartre's attempted passage from Descartes to Marx is in one sense impossible: what Sartre wants to maintain as a tension breaks down on the level of philo sophical coherence. But just at the point of this breakdown Sartre locates his cri-. tique of analytical reason. And there are very good reasons for following the project from just that point: the modem human project in political life is to move from the solitude of the Cartesian ego, including in the ways that it expresses it self in seriality and what Simone Weil calls "blind collectivity," to sociality and the polis. That ego is itself a contingent creation, but one that Sartre never lets go of. In his conception, the Cartesian ego is what truly opens up the human project, what makes the project, as fundamental responsibility, possible. What wO\lld Sartre say to the possibility of embracing that responsibility while trans fonning our conception of autonomy? I would hope that he would be open to this Derridean project. But at the same time, I hope to see an opening , more and
78
Chapter 5
more , for the political space of Sartre in the text of Derrida in the rethinking of
the Sartrean political project, the extension of it, the concretization of it-in
short, a Derridean rethinking of the Critique project with the intent of radical so cial transformation . This rethinking will take us from Descartes to Marx, to be sure , but finally to Kant.
6 Elections: Still a trap for fools? Revisiting Sartre's 1 973 essay
The people who grinned themselves to death, smiled so hard, they failed to take a breath. -The Housemartins At a time that many of his friends and associates thought was preciseiy inappro priate, Sartre published an essay arguing against participation in national elec
tions . Beginning with his title, which does not include the question mark that is a
part of my title, the essay was almost pure provocation: "Elections: A trap for fools." The time was 1 973, when many progressives and left-liberals in France were hoping for the electoral victory of the "Left Unity" coalition of Socialists
(PSF) and Communists (PCF) . Among those who expressed sharp disagreement
with Sartre's position were Simone de Beauvoir and many of the group responsi
ble for producing Les Temps Modemes (where the essay was published) . This was
also a time of great involvement by Sartre in one of the radical trends that arose
during and in the aftermath of the Events of May-June 1 968, namely Maoism.
Not surprisingly, Sartre remained committed, as always , to an internationalist, an
ticolonialist, and anti-imperialist perspective. (It is useful, in this respect, to read the, essay on elections in the context of the other "political essays" presented in
the second half of Life/Situations: "The Burgos Trial," which concerns the trial of some Basque separatists, "The Maoists in France," and "Justice and the State.")
At a time when much of what calls itself politically progressive or Left in Eu
rope · and the United States is very much involved in electoral participation and strategies, Sartre's argument concerning elections deserves reconsideration. Al
though I personally accept many of the commonly heard criticisms of elections , including what I think is the basic truth in the old saying, "Don't vote, it only en
courages them," my primary aim here will be to set out the terms of Sartre's ar gument and to assess whether it is a
good argument. In the assessment, I will con
sider whether Sartre's argument was a good one in the specific context in which
79
Chapter 6
80
he offered it, and whether the argument has a more general application to the question of electoral politics in any advanced capitalist country. In working to ward the conclusion, I will begin to relate Sartre 's argument to some more com mon arguments about elections.
Sartre begins his essay by discussing the history of suffrage in France from
1 789 to the beginning of the twentieth century. He begins with suffrage for
landowners , arguing, in fact, that the vote was " given not to men , but to their real estate, to bourgeois property, which could only vote for itself' ( 1 98). Already two distinctions have entered into Sartre 's argument. First, Sartre recognizes the
emergence of a system that was legal but "profoundly unfair"; his aim is to demonstrate the difference between legality and legitimacy. Second, Sartre ar
gues that this initial form of suffrage established a pattern that continues to this day: the isolation of the voters by means of secret ballot (reflected, as well, Sartre
argues, in the system of land ownership itself) , a serialization overcome by the fact that the electoral system reflected the voter's common class interest. By the
time that universal suffrage had been granted, four years later, the Constituent As sembly had already adopted a law making it illegal for workers to organize
against their employers . Sartre argues that not only would such organization be
completely le gitimate , but, furthermore , collective organization and the exercise of "popular" or "direct" democracy is the form of political activity appropriate and necessary to propertyless wage earners ("free labor"). However, repeated at
tempts to engage in such activity, seen especially in the upsurges of 1 794, 1 848 , and 1 870 (the latter leading to the Paris Commune), were violently put down. As
Sartre puts it, "legality massacred legitimacy" ( 199). Even after the formal right of workers to form trade unions and to strike was
recognized (around the beginning of the twentieth century) , Sartre argues , this
contradiction between legality and legitimacy remains - though exactly why this is the case remains to be seen. Sartre claims that this contradiction is especially
acute, ultimately "only [to] be resolved by civil war" (200). In an essay from the same period, "Justice and the State," Sartre argues that "State Justice" and popu
lar justice are contradictory systems (the former "codified and permanent," the latter "irregular and primitive") in the following way: "if you choose one, you will be held accountable by the other" ( 1 76). We will return to this formulation.
A longer discussion might engage with the way that Sartre invokes Foucault in
this argument; the latter apparently said, regarding popular justice , that it "does not depend on any absolute principle: if a damage is done to it, it demands com
pensation" ( 1 75). (The key source here would be "On Popular Justice: A Discus sion with Maoists," from 1 97 1 , in Power/Knowledge.) I have some serious dis
agreements with Foucault's political arguments, which I would characterize as
"Hobbesian" (in another discussion in Power/Knowledge, "The Confession of the
Elections: Still a trap for fools?
81
flesh," Jacques-Alain Miller asks Foucault, "So who ultimately, in your view, are the subjects who oppose each other?" Foucault responds, "This is just a hypoth esis, but I would say it's all against all. . . . We all fight each other" [208]). In a longer discussion I would also want to show how Sartre ultimately resists what Derrida calls the temptation to define justice as mere calculation and vengeance. Sartre's remarks on Machiavellianism-for example, "Machiavellianism will turn against the small Machiavels" (209)-speak to this question. After this very quick historical sketch, Sartre presents a series of claims that are the heart of his argument against participation in bourgeois elections. From this point on, I will refer simply to "elections." Sartre 's argument is not that there couldn't be other forms of voting in other social structures that might be appro priate-though I think he would still be wary of voting as a principal form of po litical participation. He would remain concerned, I think, about the tendency for electoral methods, if seen as the primary form of political participation, to serial ize and therefore reify the participants. Furthermore, only through ignoring the contradiction that Sartre bases his argument on could we attempt to transpose these other possibilities onto the existing system of elections in bourgeois soci eties. Now let us turn to the main argument. When we go to vote tomorrow, we will once again be substituting legal pow.er for le gitimate power. The first, which seems precise and perfectly clear-cut, has the effect of separating the voters in the name of universal suffrage. The second is still embry onic, diffuse, unclear even to itself. At this point it is indistinguishable from the, vast libertarian and antihierarchical movement which one encounters everywhere but which is not at all organized yet. (200)
Note the repetition of the characterizations from "Justice and the State": an ex isting legal order that is codified and seems assured of its permanence, versus a society that is yet to be, the logic of which is unclear even to itself. The argument is often heard that, when this embryonic new soctety really emerges into the light of day, then of course it must be supported, but, in the meantime . . . . (Another form of this argument runs, "When it is time to go to the barricades, "I'll be there, but, for now, we have to make the best of the existing system.") If I am reading S$e correctly, to pursue this course is an "act of betrayal": The polling booth standing in the lobby of a school or town hall is the symbol of all the acts of betrayal that the individual may commit against the group he belongs to. (200)
For future reference, note that Sartre is arguing that participation in elections is not simply ineffective; it is a positive harm to the possibility of another system of participation and justice. ;ro return to the question raised previously, however, why is there a contradic tion between legality and legitimacy once ordinary working people have won the rights to organize and strike? How is it that the founding, manifestly unfirir logic
82
Chapter 6
of elections in bourgeois societies continues to work its way through what seems to be a broadened and more inclusive legality? Why is this legality still not legit imate? Here we encounter some of the terms Sartre developed in the Critique of Dialectical Reason, terms that flesh out what Marx meant by quantification and the violence of abstraction . Sartre argues that people, who are born into and be come acculturated by collectives, are atomized when large social forces - work conditions under the capitalist regime, private property, institutions, and so forth - bring pressure to bear upon the groups they belong to, breaking them up and reducing them to the units which supposedly compose them. (200)
(Sartre seems concerned here with particular kinds of "large" social forces, but not with largeness itself; for my part, I definitely have this latter concern as well.) Yet the word "atomization," so often used, does not convey the true situation of peo ple who have been scattered and alienated by institutions . They cannot be reduced to the absolute solitude of the atom even though institutions try to replace their concrete relations with people by incidental connections. They cannot be excluded from all" forms of social life: a soldier takes the bus, buys the newspaper, votes . All this pre sumes that he will make use of "collectives" along with the Others. But the collec tives address him as a member of a series (the series of newspaper buyers, television watchers, etc.). He becomes in essence identical with all the other members , differ ing from them only by his serial number. We say that he has been serialized. One finds serialization in the practico-inert field, where matter mediates between people to the extent that people mediate between material objects . (201)
At this point, where "serial thinking is born in me," Sartre argues, I become "an enemy [to] myself' (201-202). To put all of this back into historical perspective, we might consider voting and elections as elements of a society where some strong sense of citizenship is the ideal. Such a society would be broadly partici patory for those included under the citizenship ideal. In bourgeois society, in its revolutionary stage and for some time in the aftermath of revolution, this ideal does indeed apply, but only to a narrow slice of society. Even here. if voting and elections were the only manifestations of the ideal, the class which represented and brought forward this ideal (an ideal that is constitutive of political modernity) would not be able to articulate its system of social relations. (In other words, in creating a bourgeois society, the bourgeoisie would not rest with simply having voting rights within the prior context of a feudal, aristocratic structure- nor could it have .) At the historical point when this system is for the most part articulated, more sections of the population -working people, women , people of color, and others who have been formerly excluded- are "granted" what is the least part of this ideal, the "right" to make choices within a system that is set against their basic needs and set against their existence as real participants within a political community.
Elections: Still a trap for fools?
83
Even this right, it must be added, has most often been won through protracted struggle-or been granted as a purely diversionary measure. A good example of the latter, one that bears further examination, is the way that, in the United States, voting rights were granted to eighteen-year-olds in the early 1970s, even though there was no general clamor for such rights; indeed, there was a radical social movement at work that had much broader, transformative-even if unclear to it self-aims. Indeed, Sartre made his argument in this general context, and we need to ask what bearing this has on our understanding of the argument today. Before engaging in this comparison of contexts, however, we need to see if Sartre's argument can go at least one step further. Almost everyone will attest to the fact that the innovations of political modernity were born in a half-formed way. The challenge, many will say, is to complete the unfinished project. I am not sure that Sartre would disagree with this idea- indeed, one disagreement that I have with him is that, despite his great contributions to internationalism and an ticolonialism, he, like many French radicals, seemed to think that he could sing out of both sides of his mouth, the Internationale on the one side, and the Mar seillaise on the other. The issue is complicated, for anyone who hopes to work to ward a society based not on exploitation but instead mutual flourishing must, in some sense, build on the legacy and ideals of political modernity. But this is not quite the same thing as saying that one can keep a foot in both camps. (The resolution of this issue, to my mind, requires grasping what Lenin meant by "revolutionary defeatism," especially as it applies to the advanced, cap italist countries.) Setting these issues aside for the moment, the question might be whether a political activity channeled through the electoral process could play the role of substantively transforming the existing terms of things- as with, say, a Left-Unity movement or, in the United States, a Rainbow Coalition/Jesse Jackson movement. Of course, these movements have come to absolutely nothing (in terms of the "real gains that are worth infmitely more than programmes on paper," something Marx said and that political pra.,gmatists are fond of invoking as justification for narrowly reformist or electoral agendas); indeed, they have come to less than nothing. That is, they have contributed to positive harm, "be trayal" in Sartre's terminology, in that they have (1) wasted enormous political energy and (2) provided a safety valve and therefore support for social systems that must be challenged on much more substantive levels . But, it might be argued, these are empirical matters (or they are questions of the contingent features of particular movements and leaders); why, in principle, could there not be an elec toral movement that played an irruptive role? Sartre's answer is that too many years of "social peace" (scare-quotes in orig inal) "have gradually established serial relations among the workers" (202; in this passage, Sartre is addressing the question of workers and wages specifically, but his point also applies to ordinary people more generally). Any real challenge to the �xisting situation will require what Sartre calls a "regrouping," and the first stages of this "collective thinking" will be seriously marked by serial thinking (he
84
Chapter 6
gives several examples in terms of racism, sexism, etc.). So, it is a matter of ma terial pressures from society leading to material challenges, the latter requiring a breakthrough in consciousness. Sartre argues that to channel this embryonic breakthrough into the electoral arena is going in exactly the wrong direction: Confronting them in their abstract solitude and their separation are the groups or par ties soliciting their votes. They are told that they will be delegating their power to one or several of these political groups. But in order to "delegate its power," the se ries formed by the institution of the vote would itself have to possess at least a mod icum of power. Now, these citizens, identical as they are and fabricated by the law, disarmed and separated by mistrust of one another, deceived but aware of their im potence, can never, as long as they remain serialized, form that sovereign group from which, we are told, all power emanates-the People. (203) Why am I going to vote? Because I have been persuaded that the only political act in my life consists of depositing my ballot in the box once every four years? But that is the very opposite of an act. (206) In sum, then, the electoral process is a mechanism of serialization; those who think they can use this mechanism against itself are, to say the least, too clever by half.
When Sartre published his essay on elections, the memory of one of the great est radical eruptions in history was very fresh. Indeed, Sartre was still very much thinking in and out of that remarkable moment. In the moment of "all power to the imagination," what could be less imaginative than to try to convince people to channel their political energy into the voting booth? Obviously, this moment passed. Just as clearly, there have arisen forces and po litical actors whose whole impetus is to forestall the day when such an eruption occurs again. The Reagan era was a period of retrenchment and brazen revan chism. The corporate consensus represented by figures such as Bill Clinton, how ever, is no less a movement for political "realism" and against the imagination. Whether such a consensus, with someone such as Clinton as its representative, even represents a kinder and gentler serialization is open to empirical challenge. This might be called the "on balance" question: one recognizes (though with some hemming and hawing) that the terms of things (the electoral process) are constrained, insulting even (one thinks of a tortured prisoner being offered the choice between grilled cheese and peanut butter and jelly), but still, one says, "We have to make the best of what we have, and, on balance, it would be better to have Clinton." Even this characterization of the "choice" that one is presented with, in terms of what face will be put on serialized society, is too charitable: if the powers that be did not want Clinton to be offered as a "choice," then he most certainly would not be. (There is an episode of "The Simpsons" -probably the best social satire in American popular culture today- where the presidential can-
Elections: Still a trap for fools?
85
didates tum out to be evil extraterrestrials in disguise. The episode captures the essence of Sartre's critique of electorialism on many levels, especially when the ruse is up but people are encouraged to still choose between the candidates or else
they will have "wasted their votes" and they will have no right to complain about anything.) Without getting very far into this , it seems to me that one could easily, say from the perspective of the people of Chechniya, construct an argument to the
effect that, on balance, it would be better to vote for Pat Buchanan (thou gh the
corporate consensus rather quickly decided this choice could not be allowed in
the 1 996 election). Regarding this "on balance" question, one is also reminded of Simone Weil's insightful remark on the Nazi occupation of France: "This is a great day for the people of Vietnam." Sartre's brief discussion of Algeria is instructive on this point:
In 1959 a majority voted for Guy Mollet because he claimed he could make peace in Algeria sooner than anyone else. The Socialist government which carne to power de cided to intensify the war, and this induced many voters to leave the series- which never knows for whom or what it is voting -and join clandestine action groups. This is what they should have done much earlier, but in fact the unlikely result of their votes was what exposed the powerlessness of universal suffrage. (207) But wasn't Sartre opposed in his thinking by a whole milieu of leftist intellectu als, some of them his closest associates? And, isn't there a virtual consensus
among "progressive" and "left" intellectuals in the advanced capitalist cOl,mtries today that one has to engage with the electoral arena, even if this means "holding one's nose and voting for Clinton" or some such? Who comes up with these "on
balance" arguments, anyway, and then helps to bolster the condescending rheto ric that always says that a substantial part of the eligible voters "don't even
bother" to vote? I could imagine some leftist intellectual attempting a positive reading of the last sentence I quoted from Sartre, arguing that people have to go throu gh rituals of powerlessness in order to understand their serialized state which is rather like saying people of color have to go through rituals of racist
abuse (or women through rituals of misogynist abuse) in order to understand their relationship to racist (or patriarchal) society. But such abuse is found readily enough -we do not need intellectuals urging people to go looking for it! There does seem to be something peculiarly middle-class and therefore pecu
liarly typical of middle-class intellectuals with their shopkeeper's mentality, about always having to have certain experiences for themselves before the expe riences are deemed valid. Interestingly, such experiences are almost always ritu alized, as with certain well-orchestrated civil disobedience actions. Somehow, "I"
have to go throu gh the ritual experience of confronting cops, so that "I will know for myself' that, under certain conditions, this will get a person arrested, beaten,
etc . Of course, the line is always drawn somewhat short of getting into real trou ble, getting badly beaten, getting thrown into jail for a long period, or getting
86
Chapter 6
killed. No, these experiences, which will come upon anyone who finds him- or herself in serious and real opposition to the existing institutions, an opposition that cannot be ritualized-these are not the experiences that our day-trippers seek. I suppose the flip-side of the coin is the oft-heard cliche, "Marx himself never worked in a factory, so how could he know if factory workers are exploited or alienated?" Marxism may have some way to go in developing, in a rich way, the category of experience-sometimes Marxism itself suffers from the violence of abstraction-but narrow empiricism won't get it. (Incidentally, my point is not to say, either, that civil disobedience cannot be used effectively or that ritual is al ways a bad thing. And, on the question of experience, as a philosophical category, I think we could learn a good deal not only from the existentialist tradition, but also from thinkers in the American tradition, especially Ralph Waldo Emerson, Walt Whitman, and William James.) Such, however, is the condescension of the standard left or progressive intel lectual, the sort who employs the "they don't even bother to vote" claim. People "bother" to do all sorts of things; they would surely "bother" to spend thirty min utes or so to vote if this was even remotely a substantial expression of their real participation in a real polis. Interestingly, there is an extension of the "on balance" argument that (at least implicitly) holds that, because radical possibilities do not seem to be in view (we are not in a revolutionary situation) , as they were in the period of May 1 968, we should at least practice politics as the art of the possible. (Note that there is no Left-Unity or Rainbow in the offing at present. The "New De mocrats," "New Labour," or what-have-you, have seen to that. The temptation is to say, there is not even this alternative, but this would be to buy back into the terms that Sartre and I are trying to disrupt.) But another reading of this sit uation might be that this conception of the "possible" (against which the real ism of May 1 968 demanded "the impossible") has led to massive disaffection, which cries out for alternative visions and movements . In recent years, close to fifty percent of those eligible have opted out of that part of the series called "voting." Suppose this percentage were to take a leap to sixty or sixty-five per cent-motivated, say, by the vanilla sameness of the recent flavors, Clinton, Dole, Gore, Junior Bush ("shrub," they're calling him). The spectacle makers may realize that the boredom of a Gore versus Bush, Jr. would be too much even for those who are still paying attention-of course, the "Left" will play its role in trying to stir up some sort of lesser of two evils excitement-"the evil of two lessers," Abby Hoffman used to call it. So, there may be a need to generate interest by putting something "exotic" into the mix -Elizabeth Dole, Alan Keyes, etc. Although disaffection can, especially in an imperialist coun try, become mere cynicism, the increasing lack of interest in the establish ment's "political process" also can be a good sign. By contrast, what sort of intellectual activity (left, progressive, etc.) urges peo ple to grasp at straws rather than recognize that anomie is built into serialization
Elections: Still a trap for fools?
87
and that more serialization is not the cure? It seems to me that Sartre would say, instead, that this is the activity of the "technician of knowledge," one who serves a "lying egalitarianism [which] masks imperialism" ("A Plea for Intellectuals ,"
241), one who serves a "comfortable, smooth, reasonable, democratic unfree dom" (Marcuse,
One-Dimensional Man), one who has positioned him- or herself
at the "left" end of the existing political spectrum and corporate consensus, serv
ing as a false (and unrealistic) alternative and (therefore) as a roadblock.
Lately, Qne version of this blocking strategy is to label any position or move
ment that actually challenges the existing terms of things "utopian." Against this , something that Theodor Adorno said is very helpful:
My thesis about this [question of utopia] would be that all humans deep down, whether they admit this or not, know that it would be possible or it could be dif ferent. Not only could they live without hunger and probably without anxiety, but they could also live as free human beings. At the same time, the social apparatus has hardened itself against people, and thus, whatever appears before their eyes all over the world as attainable possibility, as the evident possibility of fulfillment, presents itself to them as radically impossible. And when people universally say today what was once reserved for philistines in more harmless times, "Oh, that's just utopian; oh, that's possible only in the land of Cockaigne. Basically that shouldn't be like that at all," then I would say that this is due to the situation com pelling people to master the contradiction between the evident possibility of ful fillment and the just as evident impossibility of fulfillment only in this way, Com pelling them to identify themselves with this impossibility into their own affair. In other words, to use Freud, they "identify themselves with the aggressor" and say that this should not be, whereby they feel that it is precisely this that should be, but they are prevented from attaining it by a wicked spell cast over the world. (see Ernst Bloch, "Something'S Missing," 4) Consider that some people are resisting that identification with the serializing
spell that comes from channeling the ideal of•the polis into the bourgeois dec
toral process, and consider the left or progressive intellectuals who continue to beat the drums for this process , and it is not hard to see who the philistines are
an appropriate tag for Sartre's technicians , who attempt to hang on to whatever
comfortable unfreedoms remain available to them. (One thinks of the puffed�up political science professor who gets to appear on television in order to express
some platitude, to offer some opinion on what the president should do and what
people should think about it or some such. There should be an organization for
political-science students who aspire to this role-"Future Kissingers of Amer ica" or something of that sort. Sartre speaks to this issue in his discussion of "as
piring Machiavellians," 208-209.)
None of this is to say that there are not issues of apathy and cynicism to be dealt
I
with; but these will never be overcome by burrowing more deeply into their source,
a social formation based on seriality. Instead, only on the basis of the "regrouping" of which Sartre speaks will anomie be transformed into a participatory collectivity:
88
Chapter 6 If the regrouping should come about successfully, there will no trace left of this pes simistic ideology [that defines politics in terms of bourgeois elections]. Its only func tion was to justify the maintenance of serial order and of an impotence that was in part tolerated and in part accepted. (202)
May 1 968 and its aftermath, I would argue, represented a partially successful re grouping. The old society remains, of course, but in the midst of the moment when significant power was channeled to the imagination , narrow philistinism and pessimistic ideology were transcended to a substantial, indeed, unprece dented degree. The old society remains , and, for those not completely dazzled by postmodern cybernetic capitalism, [I]t must be cried out , at a time when some have the audacity to neo-evangelize in the name of the ideal of a liberal democracy that has finally realized itself as the ideal of human history: never have violence, inequality, exclusion , famine, and thus eco nomic oppression affected as many human beings in the history of the earth and of humanity. (85)
These words are not from Sartre, but rather from Jacques Derrida in the recent Specters of Marx (85). I cannot imagine Sartre disagreeing with them. Derrida's analysis in the section of the book from which I am quoting goes beyond the lim ited terms of political choice-making in Western liberal democracies, to the de nunciation of the limits of a discourse on human rights that will remain inadequate, sometimes hypocritical, and in any case formalistic and inconsistent with itself as long as the law of the market, the "foreign debt," the inequality of techno-scientific, military, and economic development maintain an effective inequality as monstrous as that which prevails today, to a greater extent than ever in the history of humanity. (85)
In the face of this monstrosity, Derrida calls for a "new international ," a "link of affinity, suffering, and hope," an "almost secret link," "an untimely link, without status, without title, without name, barely public even if it is not clandestine, without contract" (85), which sounds not unlike the movement of which Sartre speaks , "embryonic, diffuse, unclear even to itself." The old society remains, and 1 968 seems like an awfully long time ago to many of us (and yet also just like yesterday) ; the old society remains, which means that we have to go beyond the movements and ideologies of the Events of May. But nothing in the present po litical "reality" and its attendant "realism" warrants a cancellation of this un precedented moment of imagination. On the contrary. In the final analysis, of course, whether or not some particular individual votes in an election is not the primary issue (indeed, it would be serialized thinking to accept the question of whether "I" participate in this specific ritual of serializa tion as the main question). So Sartre's conclusion is also my own:
Elections: Still a trap for fools?
89
Whatever we may do about [voting in the election]. we will have done nothing if we do not fight at the same time-and that means starting today-against the system of indirect democracy which deliberately reduces us to powerlessness. We must try. each according to his [or her] own resources. to organize the vast anti-hierarchic movement which fights against institutions everywhere. (210)
In some respects the analysis presented here is complementary to that presented in my essay "Participation." from Politics in the impasse. 39-51.
7 Sartre and the critique of postmodern capitalism
History is what hurts.
-Fredric Jameson Sartre finds by looking out his own window the example allowing him to ana lyze the serial group: the line fonning at a Parisian taxi station. Each individ ual has taken his number and waits for his turn to come. Paris has JJecOme Americanized. -Denis Hollier
First, the bad new things . In recent years , capitalism seems to have gone through
some qualitative developments. Fredric Jameson has argued that a new, third stage of capital , has emerged. This "postmodern capitalism" subsumes the stages
of industrial capital and imperialism described by Marx and Lenin . While this
p
new stage represents developments in the mode of roduction, it is also a form of capitalism where culture and the shaping of consciousness play heightened roles .
As is well known, Sartre's work has always been a touchstone for Jameson. En
gagement with Sartre traverses Jameson's entire career as a cultural theorist, from his fIrst book (Sartre: The Origins of a Style) and a long chapter in his Marxism and Form, to his synthesis of Sartre and Althusser in The Political Unconscious.
My seemingly modest aim in the present essay is to assemble and explicate some
of Jameson's more recent references to Sartre as regards postmodern capitalism
and its critique.
It turns out, however, that going beyond the mere assembly and explication of
Jameson's recent references to Sartre is not at all a modest task. The work of to talization here is very difficult, because the object of such a totalization becomes
the'question, What place does Sartrean critique have in this postmodern scene?
Concomitantly, What work can the Sartrean intellectual do to travel with and help encourage radical political currents in this time?
91
92
,
Chapter 7
A few words are needed in explanation of this new fonn of capitalism. Jame son opens his book, Postmodemism; or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, with the following: "It is safest to grasp the concept of the postmodern as an at tempt to think the present historically in an age that has forgotten how to think historically in the first place" (ix). Postmodern capitalism gives us a culture of pure distraction �ne of whose main features is what Jameson calls the "loss of affect," the "new depthlessness"; in this culture "the impulses of nega:tion and re volt, not to speak of those of social transfonnation, are increasingly perceived as vain and trivial" (5-6). The cultural dominant of this "third machine age" (where the paradigm "machine" is, of course, the computer and cybernetic technology in general) is space rather than time, and therefore it is not hard to see how one of Sartre's key critical categories applies very well to the current scene. That is, postmodern capitalism might be understood as a time of "pure serialization," per haps beyond anything that Sartre might have recognized. This claim might seem an exaggeration to the point of being silly, given that Sartre lived until 1980. But it is really a question of periodization. Sartre, even in the late seventies, still represented the trnth of 1968, and was still trying to carry it forward, whereas postmodern capitalism finds us in a decisively "post-1968" epoch. This purified fonn of capitalism, which increasingly purges all remainder of tradition, community, nature, and even basic civility, makes it increasingly diffi cult for Sartre's transfonnative categories-the project, the group, collectivity, authenticity-to gain any traction. In Postmodemism, Jameson concludes his chapter on the market-which he opened by remarking on the fetish for the mar ket among so-called leftists today- with the following: What is wanted is a great collective project in which an active majority of the popu lation participates , as something belonging to it and constructed by its own energies. The setting of social priorities-also known in the socialist literature as planning would have to be a part of such a collective project. It should be clear, however, that virtually by definition the market cannot be a project at all . (278)
I would go so far as to argue that, in fact, the capitalist market should be charac terized as the very essence of an "antiproject," an economic mechanism that ab solutely depends upon serialization. In its global, imperialist, cybernetic, and postmodern fonn, this serialized "collective" antiproject works on an enonnous scale and assumes a monstrous fonn, one that is hardly captured by that rather quaint word, "the market" -a tenn that invokes the kind of peaceful barter in a relatively quiet village that is the stuff of "utopian" market ideology. Even this ideological cover-up depends, in other words and up to a point, on a more utopian image of eye-level relationships and collectivity, even if the reality of the global market has nothing in common with this image. Or perhaps it should be said, fol lowing Jameson's arguments, that postmodern capitalism is an empire of images, including the quaint, personal, or utopian ones, but without content. (We see this
Sartre and the critique ofpostmodern capitalism
93
most obviously in every television commercial for some giant corporation where someone tells us, "we care" - usually to the accompaniment of insipid white-note
piano music.) The home of this empire, already seen from Sartre's apartment win
dow and confirmed in Jameson's analysis, is yet another concatenation of images,
one that goes under the name "America." The ultimate destination of this "crisis of historicity," in which the stream of human , social, and historical temporality has never flowed quite so homoge (The Seeds of Time, 17), is a world purged of narrative time, which gives
neously
rise to an "absolute violence" - the con gealment of Sartrean becoming (the very essence of the group project) into mere "Being":
Parmenidean stasis or Being to be sure knows at least one irrevocable event, namely death and the passage of the generations: insofar as the system of Par menidean simulacrum or illusion is a very recent one, constituted in what we call postmodemity, the temporality of the generations in all their mortal discontinuity is not yet visible in results, except retroactively and as a materialist hagiographic imperative. But death itself, as the very violence of absolute change, in the form of the nonimage -not even bodies rotting off stage but rather something persist ent like an odor that circulates through the luminous immobility of this world without time- is inescapable and meaningless, since any historical framework that would serve to interpret and position individual deaths (at least for their sur vivors) has been destroyed . A kind of absolute violence then, the abstraction of vi olent death, is something like the dialectical correlative to this world without time or history. (Seeds of Time, 1 9) This space "beyond the last thought" (Wallace Stevens) is where we find our selves when humanity is without either essence or history, and perhaps for this reason Jameson's references to Sartre in
The Seeds of Time ( 1 994) are not alto
gether cheery. Indeed, at one point we find Sartre linked with Richard Rorty, of all people, in their common (or at least kindred) demythologizations of "nature," human or otherwise (see 33-34). In their criticisnfs of the idea of human nature,
both Sartre and Rorty affirm the human as a site of near-infinite possibility. Rorty
argues that this range of possibility is coextensive with that of language (an ar gument that I find persuasive). But what becomes of language and possibility in postmodem capitalism, where the homogeneous flow of humanity seems to have
been shaped into a new version of (what Marx called) the "Asiatic mode of pro
duction," where something called "information" and its control has replaced water? (perhaps there is some hope to be found in the fact that, at least for the foreseeable future, water cannot be replaced.)
This is enough to send those of us who still seek after the possibilities of the polis pleadin g for essence, and indeed such pleas are heard from many quarters ,
ranging from contemporary identity politics to nationalisms or tribalisms of vaHous kinds to ri ght-win g fundamentalisms of all sorts. (In this context, Jame son' argues that Christian, Islamic, and other fundamentalisms are themselves "postmodem.") At the opposite end of the spectrUm (that is, on the other side
94
Chapter 7
of the coin) there are recent attempts at "micropolitics" inspired by Foucault, Deleuze, and Guattari, and specifically formulated against Sartre (even if Roquentin's machine gun seems motivated by the same anarchist impulse). Per haps the practical model for such a politics is the famed "detournement" of the Situationist International -recall that they labeled Sartre an "imbecile" -a pro cedure not entirely unlike deconstruction. (However, in my view, detournement lacks deconstruction's essentially ethical core; perhaps detournement should be understood, despite its association with wild provocations, as a formalistic or proceduralistic gloss on deconstruction.) As with deconstruction, detournement finds ways of occupying that which it hopes to subvert. My hypothesis is that postmodern capitalism, in which ironic parody has been replaced by pastiche (and in which, as Jameson puts it, "Picasso and Joyce [are] no longer ugly; they now strike us, on the whole, as 'rather 'realistic' " [Postmodernism, 4] ) , has now achieved an end-run around such preoccupations and other micropolitics, and rendered them into mere forms of "ecstatic seriality" (to coin a term, but to bor row from Baudrillard). Having mentioned many of the so-called "postmodern" philosophers - and al luding to Jacques Derrida by my invocation of deconstruction - I find it necessary to finally say what perhaps should have come up earlier, namely that postmodern capitalism and "postmodern" philosophy are not necessarily connected in the ways that the reader might assume. Jameson's aim, and mine, is to understand a society that has in some sense become "postmodern." Some of the aforementioned thinkers are to some extent symptoms of such a society, others offer the basis for a powerful critique, and some fit under both headings. I generally set Derrida apart from the others, and it seems to me that a coarticulation of Sartre and Derrida is necessary for bringing the former up to speed with postmodern capitalism. "Possibility" - if it can be called that -remains in the information economy, as long as it is a marketable possibility. But what of human possibility-are we en titled any longer, in a Sartrean frame, to ask about this? What can we do with this possibility, what projects can we conceive, assuming that we are able to find it? Marketed possibility-really just Adorno's and Marcuse's one-dimensionality, "smooth functioning," administered society, and the culture industry working at an ever-greater efficiency and with new cybernetic tools -would also seem to be a brilliant end-run around a Sartrean conception of human possibility. In my own earlier work (especially the first chapter of my first book, Matrix and line) , I at tempted to generate a contradiction between possibility and "counterpossibility," with the former drawn out and forward by what might be called its "third" or "other," impossibility. This is already to mix Sartrean and Derridean approaches. In The Seeds of Time , however, Jameson argues that contradiction -in that living, temporal, sensuous, and historical sense in which historical materialists have used the term -has experienced a basic "slippage," "toward the more logical [cate gory] of the antinomy" (3) . Antinomy shares with Parmenidean "Being" (change less being-in-itself) the quality of stasis or, as Jameson says of Paul de Man's
Sartre and the critique ofpostmodern capitalism
95
practice of deconstruction, paralysis-"the conceptual freeze-frame" (3). The filmic, screened, and spatialized image is apt, though one might also see this as the triumph of analytic reason, and therefore the triumph of an imposed and overdetermined essence over existence. The situation still exists, but now as fully scripted, and in such a way as to exclude all surprises. The philosophy of this sit uation, then, is analytic reason (which is not necessarily to say "aiJ.alytic philoso phy," though often this is clearly appropriate), purified of all traces of contradic tion and difference. How then does contradiction (or, better, negativity), and therefore possibility and project, gain a foothold in a society thoroughly lacking in depth, thoroughly "Americanized" if you will? Although I agree with Jameson's characterization of postmodern capitalism as "American" (on a clear day I can look out of my apartment window and see the Sears Tower, about seventeen miles away), I dissent (and I imagine that Jameson does as well) from some of the more Francophile complaints about "American imperialism." Of course the McDonaldsization of the world is a disgusting thing, but much more so for the millions of cows whose possibility of eudaimonia is sacrificed so that billions and billions can be "served," and much more so for those Third World peoples whose countries have been turned into massive cattle factories and other forms of "resource" providers . I'm less sympathetic to wor ries about words such as "weekend" havingJlolluted the mother tongue. To com pare the United States and France in global terms is to compare first- and second rate imperialisms (and the positions were reversed some time ago). However, it is undoubtedly the case that postmodern capitalism bears the stamp of America's empire of signs. The capitol of this empire is, of course, Los Angeles. There is a point to this seeming diversion. In Jameson's view, postmodernism represents a "third" stage of capitalism, building on and subsuming the classic in dustrial stage analyzed by Marx and the imperialist stage analyzed by Lenin. This subsumption, however, is neither complete nor seamless . In other words, there is combined and uneven development. One way to..see this is to taJs;e stock of the current rhetoric of computers and the internet. The latter may even be the best ex ample we have of ecstatic seriality, presented under the guise of "cybercommu nity." On the one hand, computers and information technology have certainly .brought about basic changes in production. In some sense, in this imperialis� globalized economy, we all live in the "information age'" and the "world" of cy bernetics. On the other hand, fully fIfty percent of the Earth's people have never talked on a telephone. As other writers besides Sartre have shown, it may be that the main contradiction of this period will show itself in ecological crisis. The cy bernetic revolution in production has led to the curious development that, on the one hand, we are ever more dependent upon fmely tuned electronic equipment, while, on the other, the air is increasingly fIlled with particulate matter. To para phrase Neil Young, "dust never sleeps," and while we see on television that com puters can do practically anything, the roads are filled with holes and toilets don't flush properly-and this is in the "advanced" world.
96
Chapter 7
To give another definition to postmodern capitalism, one that seems implicit in Jameson's description but perhaps not stated outright, this "third stage" is the meeting place of imperialism and the culture industry. What we find is a graft in search of a full integration, a "lonely hour of the economy," in Al thusser's memorable phrase, that may never arrive or is at least still some dis tance down the road . Imperialism, in the sense that Lenin understood it, as the sUbsumption of the entire planet under the capitalist mode of production, but where there is a fundamental bifurcation that divides the world into "bour geois" and "proletarian" countries, still reeks havoc over the greater part of the globe. (It is worth noting here that the various avenues of cyberutopianism, such as Wired magazine , simply take it for granted , and blithely state as much, that most of the continent of Africa will simply be written off.) In terms of the "foothold," the places where contradiction is a felt human reality, this is vitally important- there is not yet such a full integration of postmodern capital that brutal exploitation and oppression can no long be thematized as such-and Sartre has much to say regarding this situation. It may be the case, in other words, that significant parts of the world (and not just the First World) have been Hollywoodized to the point where , because of the "new superficiality," the alienation of labor power from itself (that is, exploitation) no longer gives rise to either the felt or "spiritual" experiences of alienation that motivate people to address their social circumstances . Lenin al ready had a good explanation for this, the aforementioned bifurcation of the world into imperialist and imperialized countries , where a part of the spoils taken by the former are given to at least a significant number of people in the imperialist countries ("crumbs from the table"). This understanding needs to be integrated with an analysis of what Marcuse called "the new forms of con trol" (affirmative culture, administrative apparatuses, positivist philosophy, public relations , hype in general, etc.). But these means of control extend only tenuously into parts of the world where (what Lenin called) superexp[oitation is the rule rather than the exception . I have insisted on this point in part be cause we are moving into a strange period of society where it may be possible for some significant part of the population in the First World to spend large amounts of time in a space where the notion that "history is what hurts" does not make much sense . In other work, I have called this passage into the im passe "going Neuromancer," after William Gibson's great novel (admired by Jameson also; in fact I first became aware of it through him), where people "jack into the matrix" of cyberspace worlds where identity and experience is extremely fluid. Although, in global terms, this experience will remain for some time available only to a small minority, this does not mean that cyber consciousness is not already playing a role in shaping perceptions of social crises and possibilities . So, how to bring Sartre's ideas back in, as a liberating response to ecstatic seriality? Here , Jameson gives us some useful clues.
Sartre and the critique ofpostmodem capitalism
97
We might begin with the question of how to "jump start," as it were, what Jameson calls the "stalled dialectic" (what I am calling the "impasse"). In the re cent article, "The Sartrean Origin," Jameson argues that
the most influential contemporary thought modes have passed their own Sartrean heritage ove; in what may not necessarily be a guilty, but certainly a suspicious, si lence. I refer to anti-foundationalism and anti-essentialism on the one hand, and "queer theory" on the other, or in other words, the concept of "constructedness" and that of "performativity."
(11)
I n describing the shift from modernity to postmodernity, "the difference be
tween our own historical situation and that of Sartrean existentialism," Jame
son relates these concepts, associated with diverse fi gures such as Derrida, Rorty, and Judith Butler, to the fundamental Sartrean category of contingency. First, Jameson identifies con tin gen cy as a medieval term having to do with the "gap between words and things" and "the very incommensurability of bein g to human thinkin g and praxis" ( 1 8) . This sense of contingency has to do with
alienation from God. Jameson does not quite put it this way, but the modern
encounter with contin gency might be understood as alienation at yet another degree of removal from metaphysical foundations . (One could then perhaps understand the special role of the aesthetic in modernity as having to do not only with a seeming avenue toward"transcendence and the sublime, but also as mirroring the human condition as being at least two degrees removed from the Idea.) In this respect, Jameson calls modern encounters with contingency an
"apprenticeship" in the "fading away of all the ideologies of nature and natu ral meaning that organized pre-capitalist societies ." In speaking of the "death of god" as having been revealed to us by "the ex
traordinary possibilities and potentialities of human praxis in industry, the sci
ences , and the transformation of both the natural world and the social one," Jame son points to a basic "historical conundrum,"
that this unique and remarkable experience of human shaping power over the world and nature should itself be accompanied by that equally shattering intellectual dis covery of meaninglessness that we call contingency. (18)
And yet there has been a strange "overcoming" (my word, not necessarily Jame son's) of contingency in this "postalienated" postmodern world-an overcoming that is not only not a dialectical sublation, but is instead characteristic of th� im passe of the dialectic . As Jameson puts it,
Today that historical conundrum is joined by another one, equally mysterious and
striking: namely the waning of the experience of contingency in the postmodern, the I vanishing away of all those shattering discoveries of the non-meaningful and the non-natural in a more fully humanized information society. (18)
98
Chapter 7
As this postmodem world becomes more "complete," more sealed up within its own empire of signs, it is not clear how the reengagement with Sartre might be effected. Jameson's essay, which was published as the lead article in the very first number of the new Sartre Studies International ( 1 995; the paper was presented the previous year as the keynote address to the North American Sartre Society), is his first longer reassessment of Sartre in light of postmodernity. It ends with something of an injunction, but an ambiguous one: Sartre is a hidden origin of much that is at work and of concern in our present situa tion; but he is also the name for an unfinished project, with which we may find our selves reengaging. However this may be, he is also the marker of a whole historical period and moment of our immediate past against which the present needs to meas ure itself, however painful or embarrassing may be the resultant historical self knowledge. (19) Well, however much all of this may be the case, we might still wonder whether it is enough to charge our present historical situation -our situation that is at tempting to define itself as posthistorical-with an embarrassment! There is something wistful about this conclusion Jameson comes to, and though I resonate with this , we obviously would hope for more than simply nostalgia for the period when Sartre was riding high as an engaged intellectual. So, please allow me to make a very simple turn. Sartre analyzed the serial structure of capitalism in a way that showed that, although it offends no human essence to live in this limited way, neither does serial life speak to our greater ca pacities . I have identified postmodernity as a time of "ecstatic seriality," which certainly fits with Jameson's invocation of Baudrillard in describing the "Ameri can" empire of signs. The difficult thing for those of us who will turn out to have been "twentieth-century people" - we will have spent most of our lives in the twentieth century (there are already science fiction novels that have snotty teenagers saying to their parents, "that's so twen-cen")-is that, while we look back with nostalgia upon this seemingly "done with" period where things seemed to matter, we have to admit that no one in their right mind could be in all that much of a hurry to repeat the experience, either. Is there a measure to be had there, or something to reconnect with, to reengage with? Is there, or was there, some historical thread, that could have opened up better possibilities for human ity, forms of life that are somewhat richer than Lyotard's "nodes" in the informa tion network? Certainly Sartre attempted to engage with the threads of revolution and resistance. While it is necessary to remain connected to those threads -or: at least Jameson thinks so, and I do too-there is also the need to understand the bad new things . In this respect I want to go back just a few years before "The Sartrean Origin" to a remarkable document, "Secondary Elaborations," which is the very long conclusion (well over one hundred pages) to Jameson's Postmodernism. Jameson describes what might be called the new form of "mechanical materi alism" (to use Marx's term) appropriate to postrnodern capitalism, what he calls
99
Sartre and the critique ofpostmodem capitalism
"sheer demography." (The irony is that capitalism passes from mechanism to cy bernetics without passing through what would seem to be the middle term, or
ganism. But this is to be expected in a cyberutopia that is choking on dust.) What we are seeing, Jameson argues, is a transformation in "that peculiar thing we all
take for granted, namely, the existence of other people" (361). Insomuch as the
peculiar thing was fIrst made into a philosophical problem by Sartre (we will tum to Jameson's acknowledgement of this in a moment), then we might also look to him for clues to understanding this transformation. Jameson speaks of the "radi
cal cultural effects" of the "enlargement of the peopled universe" (359). "We need to explore," he says ,
r:�''1i'J
the possibility that there exists , in what quaintly used to be called the moral realm, something roughly equivalent to the dizziness of crowds for the individual body it self: the premonition that the more other people we recognize, even within the mind, the more peculiarly precarious becomes the status of our own hitherto unique and "incomparable" consciousness or "self." (358) Certainly, this precariousness, this vertigo, would seem to be enough to make one nauseous , despite whatever postalienated, posthistorical space we seem to be en tering into. Jameson addresses Sartre's role in this analysis in a strange formulatiop: As far as I know, the only philosopher to have taken demography seriously, and to have produced concepts on the basis of an evidently idiosyncratic lived expe
rience of it, was Jean-Paul Sartre, who wanted no children as a result, but whose other historic philosophical originality- to have made a philosophical problem out of that peculiar thing we all take for granted, namely, the existence of other people-may, in fact, tum out to be the consequence of this one, rather than the other way round. (361) Those of us familiar with Jameson's methodology of the "dialectical sentence" will be used to such circuitous formulations, but, even so, it is difficult to sort this one out. Is Jameson really saying that the philosophical problems that he is uniquely as sociating with Sartre are in fact a result of Sartre's not wanting children? Thinking of the generations that have come in Sartre's wake, and who make up, for instance, . the North American Sartre Society, I am reminded of the quip about baby boomers as "the generation that forgot to have children" -and though the Sartre Society is
made up of more than boomers, the characterization may still be somewhat apt. Of course, we are intellectuals, and we tend to look at our written work, our books and whatnot, much as Sartre and de Beauvoir did, as our offspring.
(In later life they
both adopted daughters who are now their literary executors .) But still, the decision whether or not to have children, when looked at as a social trend and not as the iso lated decision of this or that individual, can serve as a social barometer, a demo graphic measure. Did Sartre have an "idiosyncratic lived experience" of demogra phy? In his "search for a father," as the title of one study of Sartre puts it, did he not
Chapter 7
100
have the psychic space for children of his own? Or was he simply hesitant to add one more number to the series? If the baby boomers forgot to have children, is a new generation, coming to age more fully in the time of postmodem capitalism, not as likely to forget? (I note anecdotally, as well, that a number of my boomer con temporaries have now remembered-in their late thirties-to have children .) How can this new demographic be related to the old one, and what embar rassments will we find? Surely if postmodemity is a period of postalienation, and
even of ecstatic seriality, then embarrassment is not enough to close the gap be
tween the practico-inert-objectification embraced, "jack into the matrix" -and the possibility of a consciously made history. What, then , of scarcity, of need? Three students of Georg Lukacs (Agnes Heller, Ferenc Feher, and Gyorgy Markus) argued some time ago that Eastem European, "Soviet"-type societies worked through a "dictatorship over needs." One might convincingly argue that, at least in the first world, postmodem capitalism is creating a cyberdictatorship over needs, over the very conception of a "need," that the crude manipUlations of the past could never come close to resembling. Arguably this has not yet fully happened, and one might even argue that it cannot come about completely, that something else will stand in reserve as it were. But, how to find this "human re serve" and activate it, and how will Sartre help us in this project? How will
the
philosopher of the project help us to recover the sense of a human project? Or, will we discover that this project is only something that we can now look back upon -those of us old enough to do so, for it will be a generational thing-with nostalgia and embarrassment? In 'the culture of postmodem capitalism, Jameson argues, "What the past has to tell us is . . . little more than a matter of idle curiosity, and indeed our interest in it . . . comes to look a little like an in-group hobby or adoptive tourism" (36 1 ) . I n the mode o f embarrassment and nostalgia, this leads to what I call the "Look what the funny man is saying now" phenomenon , which is again working out as a generational thing, especially at the point where the market is fully driven by demographics and niches. (If you're so into history, dude, there's a channel for that, so chill out.) But perhaps this
is, as yet, a First World thing - and perhaps it can only be
such. Even so, let us again consider the social dialectic as Jameson understands
it now, in these postmodem times . One aspect of what Jameson calls "absolute vi olence," especially in the Third World, is brutal hurt without history, the flip-side of which is empty "history" ("blithe history," we ought to call it, and the point ex tends to intellectual work in general) without hurt in the First World. There is a gap here, an impasse, the reduction of the contradiction to an antinomy, and it is around this gap that any possible collective project must take shape. So, let us quote at length from "Secondary Elaborations" in order to get a deeper sense of the dynamic of sheer demography - this is an essential passage:
The West thus has the impression that without much warning and unexpectedly it now confronts a range of genuine individual and collective subjects who were not there be-
Sartre and the critique ofpostmodem capitalism fore, or not visible, or-using Kant's great concept- were still
101
minor and under tute
lage. Everything that is condescending about this very ethnocentric view of global re
ality . . . clearly falls back ignominiously on the viewer, but equally clearly does not
diminish the interest of the "impression" itself. Here, for example, is a savage reca
pitulation of the matter by a radical writer, whom, as will be apparent in a moment,
we have other reasons for quoting in this context: "Not so very long ago, the earth numbered two thousand million inhabitants: five hundred million
people and one natives; The former had the Word; the others merely had use of it." [This is from Sartre's Preface to Fanon's The Wretched of the Earth;
thousand five hundred million
the italicized word "men" has been retranslated here to read "people."] Sartre's figure mocks European racism at the same time that it grounds its objectivity as an ideolog ical illusion in history (it is only
since decolonization and its aftermath that the "na
tives" have turned out to be "human beings") and in a certain philosophy of the sub
ject and of the recognition of the Other as a subject which he shares with Fanon, and which stresses not the inert fact of my existence as a subject but rather the active and
energetic, violent, gesture whereby I compel
recognition of my existence and my sta
tus as a human subject. The old Hegelian fable of the master and the slave- by now
as familiar as Aesop-shows through this philosophy like an archetype, again demon
strating its reliability for what it <explains not of revolution itself or liberation but
rather of their consequences: the emergence of new subjects; that is to say, new peo
ple, other people, who were somehow not even there before, even though their bod
ies and their lives filled the cities and certainly did not materialize yesterday. .' '.' So
it was not just the extra cables and the klieg lights, the hand-carried camera equip
ment, and the fortuitous presence of Western reporters in "godforsaken" places, but
rather some new visibility of the "others" themselves, who occupy their own stage,
a kind of center in its own right-and compefattention by virtue of their voice and of the act of speaking itself, which- far above and beyond Fanon's old punctual act of physical violence-becomes a language-conscious generation the first primordial vi
olent act by which you force yourself on another's attention. (356-357)
However, after this powerful invocation of the wretched of the earth, Jameson launches into the discussion of demography-feating, it seems, that even the Third World voice might be absorbed by the ever-expanding albeit extremely shallow ocean of postmodern depthlessness . Can the "hurt" of history be fully overcome by cybernetic means? If not,
are
we all the same left with a warmed
over version of Lin Biao's arguments about the Third World as fundamental transformative agent, "killing the imperialist octopus by cutting off the tenta cles"? (Lin Biao was a Communist leader in China
who wrote Long Live the Vic tory of People's War, widely understood to reflect Mao's perspective.) If so, so
what? After all, it is not such a radical thought that many people in the First World will not give up their ill-gotten privileges until something affects them directly. In this light I would like to make a comment regarding economism. Econo mistic trends in Marxism (such as Trotskyism or social democracy) hold to the idea that socialism can only be built on the basis of advanced forces of produc tion. To attempt to build socialism in a "backward" country, so the argument goes, will lead to authoritarian-bureaucratic methods of economic planning and social
102
Chapter 7
direction (that is, "Stalinism," as this story has it). But herein lies a conundrum: if a large percentage of working people in the First World are kept well-fed and politically complacent by the spoils of imperialism, then, on the orthodox econo mist-Marxist assumption that people are only motivated by their basic ecpnomic interests, then what additionally follows is that many people will continutto sup port the imperialist organization of things, until society literally falls apart around them (which then also becomes the breeding ground for the fascist form of col lectivity). However, when society comes undone in this way, productive forces are often destroyed as well , and this applies to both aspects of these forces: the means of production themselves, as well as to the lives and the cultural level of the working people. Economist trends find themselves, therefore, oriented toward the better-off parts of the working class in the First World, and, not being able to press too far with the claim that this strata really constitutes a class "that has noth ing to lose but its chains," must instead put forward "transitional demands" that amount to saying, "You think you are doing well now, but the fact is that you could do much better in a socialist system." In light of "the voice and the act of speaking itself' by which the Third World sometimes manages to make itself heard, but also in light of the post modern depthlessness that increases First World blitheness and even threatens to engulf the most wretched, the question again arises: What can break through this impasse, and how can Sartre help? The need is to go from what Simone Weil called the "blind collectivity" of capitalism to the conscious collectivity of a society in transition to communism. For Sartre, what activates this con sciousness is a "third," a common danger in respect of which humanity must unite . There is an additional element here, which Sartre calls "the oath," the open and public decision to practice conscious collectivity. From the moment that such an oath is made, conscious collectivity is embattled by reassertions of the practico-inert. Materiality threatens to draw us back into thingness. ' Sartre thinks , as does Marx, that there are crisis tendencies in �apitalism that call forth the gravedigger of the system, the proletariat. But Sartre writes in the age of imperialism and neocolonialism, and is fully aware of the material mechanisms and the structures of consciousness and the forms of symbolic representation that allow the one-quarter of humanity that consists in "people" to set aside the superexploitation and brutal dehumanization of the three-quar ters who are the "natives ." What "third" and what "oath" can bridge this gap and allow humanity to transcend its present state? Having rehearsed some el ements of "Later Sartre 1 0 1 " this final time , I want to conclude this investiga tion into postmodem capitalism with three brief points. First, let us consider Jameson's conclusions, from the very end of Postmod ernism. Allow me to quote from the third from last paragraph of the book. Jame son begins by characterizing our current situation. [T]here has never been a moment in the history of capitalism when this last enjoyed
greater elbowroom and space for maneuver: all the threatening forces it generated
Sartre and the critique ofpostrrwdem capitalism
103
against itself in the past-labor movements and insurgencies, mass socialist parties, even socialist states themselves-seem today in full disarray when not in one way or another effectively neutralized: for the moment, global capital seems able to follow
its own nature and inclinations, without the traditional precautions. Here, then, we
have yet another defmition of postmodernism, and a useful one indeed, which only an ostrich will wish to accuse of "pessimism." The postmodern may well in that sense be little more than a transitional period between two stages of capitalism, in which the earlier forms of the economic are in the process of being restructured on a global scale, including the older forms of labor and its traditional organizational in stitutions and concepts. That a new international proletariat (taking forms that we cannot yet imagine) will reemerge from this convulsive upheaval it needs no prophet to predict: we ourselves are still in the trough, however, and no one can say how long we will stay there. (417)
Of course, it is not very satisfying , for anyone of radical inclinations, to say noth
ing of those who suffer the daily brutality of the system, to conclude with a recog
� spend
nition that we are condemned t
time in the ditch. However, Jameson is
surely right about the intellectual task that confronts us, one of "systematizing
something that is resolutely unsystematic , and historicizing something that is res
olutely ahistorical," hoping to "outflank" this something "and force a historical
way of at least thinking about that." As Jameson puts it, a formula that he identi
fies with the "high point of the sixties" finds a revival and a necessity; "We have
to name the system" (41 8). Clearly, this work is still served by the theoretical ap paratus created by Sartre, especially insomuch as the system seems to be not only
"postmodern" but in fact "hypermodern." Thus we have the seriality of moder
nity pressed to qualitatively new levels and run through means of production that
are cybernetic. The Sartrean apparatus needs supplementation here, but it still forms a viable core.
Related to this last point, and second, the one-sidedness of Sartre's concep
tions of the Other and the "oath" show up in light of the discussion of
economism and its new forms under postmodern capitalism. Economism can be
understood, in a sense, as a denial or destruction of memory, in the name of present needs and desires . Sartre's orientation against imperialism and neo colonialism, and toward ethical categories, gets him tagged as a "Third-World
ist" and "moralizer" by economistic Marxists. The alternative is a form of "an
ticapitalism" that, in fact, is not ultimately against the existing system, because capitalism has become the imperialist mode of production. This anticapitalism
holds aside, as irrelevant to the "real , everyday struggle," the mass of human
ity that is superexploited (the ones who survive, that is, given the extreme rates
of infant mortality in the Third World). How are such forms of "anticapitalism"
ultimately any different from cyberutopian predictions such as one reads in
Wired magazine, where it is left for a tiny footnote or parenthetical remark, at
best, that large parts of humanity- "the natives" again - will be left out of the
"general" prosperity? (Actually, despite proclamations of the "postindustrial
104
Chapter 7
economy," which seem also to include the subtext, "never mind agriculture ," there is still plenty of industrial and agricultural production going on- a point that would seem more than obvious except in the vicinity of the citadels and virtual spaces of postmodem capital .) Sartre was never politically complicit with these trends of thought or activism; on the contrary, he did everything to resist them. But there is a sense in which we need more, theoretically, than what Sartre gives us on the question of the Other and the oath, even if we must not abandon what Sartre provides. I cannot develop this argument at length here (though I am developing it elsewhere) , but what we need is to integrate Sartre's thinking into the "double strategy" that we find in Derrida's work, and espe cially into the language of redemption found in Specters of Marx. This text is partly inspired by Walter Benjamin's arguments about anamnestic solidarity. The point is to find forms of solidarity and collectivity that do not simply say, "the dead are dead and will not rise again" (this is what Max Horkheimer said to Benjamin, calling the latter's perspective "theological") . The relevant point for Sartre is that there must be that other side of the strategy that not only sees the oath of collectivity as a response to an external danger, but is also an act of radical affirmation. There is affirmation of human possibility aplenty in Sartre, but a further integration of this affirmation into the languages of redemption that we find in Benjamin and Derrida is necessary to keep Sartre's thinking from falling into a merely reactive and Hobbesian rut. For, indeed, on more than one level this is the ditch that perpetuates the impasse of postmodem cap italism. In initiating a systematic project for the overcoming of capitalism, Marx and Engels wrote, "We affirm the permanence of the revolution." Capitalism, al though ultimately a "blind collectivity," has a certain genius for integrating into itself experiences of resistance. In our day, postmodem capitalism "affmns" the permanence of the impasse. This does not mean that the impasse will be perma nent-the history of this remains unwritten, though in a day when we are faced with the sharply uphill battle to "historicize something that is resolutely ahistori cal" -but the ugly "affirmation" does have its effect, it creates a deep cynicism that not only works on the level of "ideology," but has real material effects and promotes the self-fulfilling prophecy of the impasse. So, finally, there is an urgency to this radical project. What was just said brings to mind again the Sartre who was at the end of his life "between Mao and Moses," the "Jean-Paul Sartre as Jew" that Steven S chwarzschild wrote about. Schwarzschild (who passed away in 1 989 and whose work deserves a much wider audience) was linking S artre to the infinite task of social trans formation that confronts us in the form of the practico-inert and the constant struggle to overcome reification. In this project, Schwarzschild links Sartre with another major, "Jewish" thinker, Immanuel Kant, who said, famously, that "ethics sets an infinite task." However, though the work may be infinite, this does not mean that the radical project of humanity has infinite time to
Sartre and the critique ofpostmodern capitalism
105
complete it- indeed, the impasse of postmodern capitalism is one in which time - and things that take time, such as history and memory - are themselves embattled. Franz Kafka wrote , in his
Parables and Paradoxes, "there is plenty
of hope, just not for us." Is there hope for Sartre, for the radical project? Is there time? Let us not fool ourselves into thinking that the project cannot be foreclosed, or that we have all the time in the world.
Afterword A philosopher of his century after his century
History is in danger of dying in the world of nonhistory. c-.
-Sartre, Notebooks for an Ethics
Marx wrote something to the effect that the proletariat would need seventy-five years or more of struggles, civil wars , and failures to make itself ready to exer cise power. This length of time stands out in the present context, for those were the number of years given to Jean-Paul Sartre on this earth. Many revolutionar ies in the twentieth century, and certainly many radical intellectuals, were in spired by the example of Sartre. What is it like to live life for a revolution that does not come? The seventy-five years Marx spoke of ended some time ago. At the time of Marx's writing, the proposed time for the maturing of revolutionary agency stretched into the twentieth century, but now this century is over - and one might legitimately wonder if the dynamic of tbis period is over, as well. Originally I had planned to subtitle this book, "Essays in the political thought of Jean-Paul Sartre." I changed that subtitle for two reasons. First, the original subtitle was simply inaccurate, in that it promised a book of historical scholar ship. Although there is some of this sort of scholarship in the book (or, at least, I hope that the reader finds this), I realized that, instead, what the book really came to was a political reckoning and fellow-traveling with Sartre. So, the second rea son, more positively, was that I realized I was engaged in an attempt to inhabit some of the central political questions of the twentieth century with Sartre. I has ten to emphasize the word "some" in this last sentence-for this is a short book, and a good deal more needs to be done. But, will the motivation be there? I am asking this question not just for myself, but for all of the radicals who have at tempted to be cothinkers and co activists with Sartre. Are we now entering a pe riod when the tenns of things will change (or rather, we will finally see that these tenns have already changed) to the point where we will say, "Sartre was a man
107
AftelWord
108
for the twentieth century, but we are not in that time anymore"? After all, for us no longer to be
in that century and yet still of it would seem to be both pathetic
and, indeed, hardly "Sartrean ."
In a couple of places in this book I alluded to a certain nostalgia that I feel , here in the summer of 1 999, for this twentieth century that still has a few months to go (though these months will be gone- and perhaps what I am writing here will be
an embarrassment -by the time you, the reader, see these words) . Part of what I was trying to say in the previous paragraph is that I take my involvement with Sartre personally, in the sense that it is a life-shaping thing, and it is something
that will not fit into merely academic terms- thank heaven . I did not know or ever meet Sartre personally, but neither do I even have "the feeling that I knew him." Of course I envy those of my confreres in Sartrean circles who did know Sartre personally, especially Hazel Barnes and Thomas Flynn , and I feel fortunate enough to know them. I probably could not have thrived in the actual vicinity of Sartre-too much cigarette smoke ! But, to continue on a personal note , it does seem as though my publishing activities of the past several years demonstrate a certain preoccupation. In 1 996 and 1 997 I published two books on the subject of progressive rock music . This music, for readers who do not know about it, flour ished especially from about 1 968 to the mid- 1 970s. It was produced mostly by English groups such as King Crimson, Yes , Jethro Tull , Genesis, Soft Machine,
etc . The music was countercultural and utopian in a way that was specifically tied to English Romanticism, especially William Blake. Progressive rock groups
tended to be made up of very good musicians, sometimes virtuosos even , and they tended to produce epic works, often of a "symphonic" character, in the sense of employing a very broad musical palette. The reason I mention this is to illu minate a strange connection with Sartre and to illustrate what seems to be a pre occupation. Of course there is the relationship to 1 968 , but I am thinking of some thing else, something more long-term. Michel Foucault wrote, in a mode that probably has to be described as sarcasm, that "Sartre is the last great philosopher of the nineteenth century." A similar remark was made by Brian Eno. For those readers here who are not familiar with him, Eno is a figure whose mark is every where in contemporary rock music, from the mainstream to the avant-garde. He is a composer and record producer, but most especially one might call him a "con ceptualist." He isn't quite a "philosopher," whatever that means, but he has a par ticular knack for being attuned to the times, and he "comes up with ideas ," often quite interesting ones. (At present I am completing a book on the avant-garde in rock music, and Eno will receive a good deal of attention, so please stay tuned .) Eno said about progressive rock that it isn't so much about doing something new, but instead about completing something old, namely the Romantic music of the nineteenth century. For both Foucault and Eno the implication is clear: those epic-universalist proj ects of the nineteenth century may have been fine in their time (though one sus pects that both protagonists here actually do not think this) , but they are certainly
A philosopher of his century
109
outmoded now. Hence the appearance of these projects as "quaint" in our post modern times. Now, one might try to turn the tables and show that both Foucault and Eno have more of a relation to these projects than they themselves might want to think, but perhaps that strategy would really only amount to an act of de nial. The more important question is whether this postrnodern thinking is right, that the epic project of social transformation, from Marx to Sartre as it were, is a thing of the past. Let us consider a moment in the transition to postmodern capitalism. I re ceived, as the reader might imagine, a fair amount of criticism for the paper that became the essay here on Sartre and elections. No one agreed with me (in Granville, Ohio, where the North American Sartre Society meeting was held that year), which is to say, no one agreed with Sartre. I am wondering how Sartre scholars , including those directly oriented toward political questions , could find themselves succumbing to mere left-liberalism-and now to what I am calling, after Fredric Jameson, postrnodern capitalism. By way of answer, and in a few quick comments, I want to tie together the arguments presented here on elec tions, postmodern capitalism, and the Stalin period. Ultimately we have to ex amine the material pulls that operate on intellectuals as much as on anyone else, but one way to come at this matter can be understood in terms of the recent tra jectory of the Democratic Party in the U�ited States . When I presented. my talk on Sartre and elections, the main arguments against it were framed in fairly stan dard terms: lesser evils , political realism, the electoral process as a school for so cial involvement, etc. In the name, indeed, of political realism, the terms in which Sartre analyzed the question were basically abandoned. And though I did enjoy having to hear, repeatedly, that "Bill and Sartre" "think," "want to de fend," "believe that," "argue," etc.-what remained painful to me was the idea that one could conduct this discussion in terms of the sort of language heard most often from Habermas or The Nation. In other words, the terrain of the dis cussion was shifted toward "the public sphere" llitd "democratic community," as though these things now exist, and "easier forms of dissent," such as the secret ballot, without the necessary suspicion concerning whether any real dissent would ever come easily. The terms that are obscured are capitalism, the bour geoisie, and, most of all, imperialism. Why does Sartre equate the promotion of electoral processes with "a lying imperialism"? I mean , that is rather severe does he mean to say that, if I perform the relatively easy task of going into a bal lot box and pulling a lever, then I am participating in imperialism, helping it even? What always gets to me in this sort of response- which is a typical re sponse-is that the defense of the process amounts to something like, "How can you say that this is a complicity with imperialism, when really what I've done is 'pretty innocuous?" I'm reminded of REM's song, "Losing My Religion": "That's me in the corner, I'm drinking my orange crush" -in other words, "hey, I'm not really hurting anyone, so why are you laying this heavy language about imperialism on me?" Sartre is really saying two things in the essay. First, voting
1 10
Afterword
as the primary fonn of politics really is innocuous, and it would be such under any social system. One is quite aware that one is not doing anything deeply po litical, deeply concerned with shaping the polis. But Sartre is making a second point that is the real rub, especially for those who still want to defend "easy fonns of dissent"; to participate in elections in advanced capitalist countries is a positive harm, it bolsters systems that carry out superexploitation and worse on a daily basis . We have seen the effects of this narrowing of political horizons in an especially ugly fonn in the liberal and left support (or at least defense) of Bill Clinton and his war in Serbia and Kosovo. A deeper analysis is needed, but I think that we can see the underlying dynamic in this "political realism" -what I would call "cynical re alism" -with just a few fonnulaic statements. All of the good liberals, including those Sartreans who see left-liberalism as the limit of politics today (as well as, of course, the other leftists whose also confonn to this realism), came to the defense of Clinton when he was under threat of impeachment and removal from office by right-wingers, some of whom shade over into outright fascism. Certainly it would not have been a good thing if fascists and other advocates of a New Inquisition had been able to carry out an administrative coup and remove Clinton. But opposition to fascism is a tricky thing, as socialists, communists, and other radicals found in the first half of this century and especially during the Stalin period. That rabid right-wingers and fascists could carry out, or seriously attempt to carry out, an ad ministrative coup, should tell us something about the nature of fascism itself, namely that it is a part of the apparatus of the existing system, not something that comes at the system from outside. At the very least, we ought to say that, those who are optimistic about the electoral process as a way of choosing some lesser evil or of "schooling" people in "their democratic community" (which fundamen tally leaves out the question of whose school it is and for what purpose-besides the fact that such expressions are extraordinarily condescending and bespeak typ ical intellectual elitism, reminding us once again that it is the educator who needs educating) ought then also to be optimistic when fascists use the same system to further their ends. After all, isn't this democracy in' action once again? The larger point is that the "politically realistic" pull is toward opposing what seem to be the more noxious aspects of the existing system with what seem to be, from a certain liberal or left-liberal perspective at any rate, more palatable aspects. From this per spective, however-and this is the point about "democracy in action" -how does one respond to the person who does not want a philanderer and possible sexual ha rasser as president? Does this person's point of view not deserve representation also, given the "realistically" accepted tenns of things? In other words, the question is, how do we oppose the system when it becomes even more oppressive, without simply reinforcing the overall workings of the system itself? Here we have to bring together the questions of imperialism and postmodern capitalism. I think that Sartre helps us with both questions, and I also think that coming at it this way ties together the different ends of this book.
A philosopher of his century
111
One very simple way to come at the new political realism of the left and of many Sartreans is that, like Sartre, they oppose fascism. For the first half of the twentieth century, the terms of things were such that, if you opposed fascism, then you were also in favor of the transcendence of the systems that gave rise to fas cism. In other words, you were for socialism. But socialism seemed to be derailed with Stalin-and, here is the heart of it, something I am still trying to come
to
terms with myself-many Sartre scholars are derailed by Sartre 's involvement in the Stalin question, in his clear commitment that one cannot simply avoid, through some entirely other route . this "detour" (as he put it) that was represented by the Stalin period. What makes things even more complicated is that Stalin himself promoted the view that there were two ways of opposing fascism. The an tifascist movement that Stalin promoted least was socialist revolution; the move ment that he promoted more , out of his own political realism, was bourgeois democracy. Sartre gives us some tools for sorting out these complicated ques tions, in a way that does not simply leave us with a political realism that does not get at the :fundamental social structures. But Sartreans will not be able to grasp these tools without going back into the "StaliniSartre derailment," if I can put it that way (and this includes dealing with what Sartre called the "real achieve ments" of the Soviet Union under Stalin's leadership). Here is an even simpler way of putting the issue: the Sartreans who . do not agree with Sartre on elections will find, if they really think about it, that they do not agree with him (or they do not go very far with him other than on a purely ab stract level) on colonialism and imperialism, either. It is easy for a split to occur, between the concrete question of participating in elections and a very vague, in tellectual "assent" that there might be something to the issues of colonialism and imperialism, because the effects of the latter are at some remove from our lives in the imperialist citadels. Here again I find the comment of Simone Weil on the German occupation of France so brilliant: "This is a great day for the people of Vietnam," To people who are being systematical� murdered, by extraordinary forms of war-making and torture such as the United States used in Vietnam and elsewhere in Southeast Asia, it matters not one whit whether the administration of the social system in the imperialist aggressor countries is bourgeois democratic or bourgeois-authoritarian. Of course it was not a great day for the people of France when the Nazis marched in, nor would it have been a great day for the people of the United S�ates if fascists, right-wingers , and other inquisitors had managed to remove Bill Clinton from office, but only to see things in these terms does not ultimately do what Jameson, echoing a great slogan of the sixties, says that we need to do: name the system. So, if we name the system both imperialism and postmodern capitalism, what does the latter do for us as regards present examples? Certainly, now that we are in a time when what is called public discourse-that is , the operation of the cor porate media-can come to focus on the penis of the president (perhaps the next step in a process that began in the mid- 1980s with a CNN reporter asking in a
1 12
AftelWord
press conference with the White House spokesperson, after Ronald Reagan had had an operation on his rectum, whether the president had had a bowel movement yet- such fertile ground here for Freudians, Lacanians , or what-have-you! ) , it would seem clear that we have moved into a new state of the society of the spec tacle. (If we view the Clinton presidency as a transition from the question, "Did he inhale?" to the question, "Did she swallow?", then we can also bring the oral into this picture of the bourgeoisie's psychological drama.) But I think there is a material ground here that is generally missed in popular discussions, and in much of the academic or intellectual discussion as well. On the day after Clinton's impeachment, the Dow Industrial Average went up slightly, but the Nasdaq average went up significantly. The latter measures the performance of high-technology corporations. Now, these things fluctuate and will continue to do so (until the day they crash altogether), of course, but there is something emblematic in those measures , something representative of transitions that are occurring within the workings of capital. A transition of potentially epoch-making proportions cannot be analyzed in a few lines, but there are a few relevant points that can be set out easily enough. Throughout the period of Clin ton's embattlement with right-wing forces, and especially in the period of his im peachment and Senate trial, I asked myself repeatedly, "What is really going on here?" My bottom-line assumption was, and is, that imperialist superpowers (or any bourgeois power, most likely) do not significantly shake up their political structures just because the top administrator (if that is what the president is, even, though to ask the question thematizes the issue of where the real power lies) re ceives fellatio. For sure, there might be other security issues at stake when some one who is privy to top-secret information is sexually driven the way Clinton is, or the way that his role model , John F. Kennedy, was. In the latter case, Eastern Bloc spies were possibly able to gain access to the White House. So perhaps the ruling class had a problem with that and wanted to clean things up, but I suspect that this also does not get to the root of the problem, because things could be cleaned up some other way without interfering with the sexual recreations of politicians, which are taken to be one of the perks of the job and are taken up just as enthusiastically by leaders of the New Inquisition, if not more so. (I realize that there is a comic element to talking about sexual promiscuity in the vicinity of Sartre ! But at least one could never imagine hearing from Jean-Paul the words, "I never had sex with that woman.") Could the elevation of the president's sexual pursuits, and the juicy details thereof, to the level of everyday and pervasive pub lic discourse have been simply the next chapter in postmodern capitalism's cul ture of distraction? I do think this is one of the dimensions of the spectacle, and yet there is still something more fundamental. The Clinton/anti-Clinton scenario was pitched as a conflict between tradi tional/conventional morality, on the one side, and post-sixties morality or lack thereof, on the other. It is not insignificant that the conflict was posed this way; indeed, it is highly significant that the right-wing agenda was carried forward as
A philosopher of his century
1 13
yet another attack on the sixties. But here, too, is where the opponents of this right-wing agenda allowed the system to defme the terms . Clinton was put for ward as some sort of "representative" of the sixties, and one recalls all of the "it's our tum" rhetoric of the 1992 election. The idea was that, finally, the sixties gen eration will hold the levers of power. What remains of that generation, apparently, as embodied in Clinton, is marijuana, draft-dodging, sexual promiscuity, and therapeutic rhetoric. On a related level, we saw the sorry spectacle of various left liberal feminists saying that they too would be happy to take up their presidential knee-pads. But although this argument about conventional morality (often repre sented by politicians who have no intention of following such "morality" them selves) and postconventional lifestyle politics is significant, it also masks some thing else. There are transitions occurring within capital, which can be thematized under the categories of globalism, flexible production, and advanced technology (not only cybernetic technology, but also materials science, bioengineering, transport, etc .). When there are shifts in capital, the basic contradiction of the sommodity form manifests itself more intensely, and there are winners and los ers . There are blocs that form around different units of capital, and there are po litical representatives of these blocs . In the largest frame, the conflict is between "traditional" capital-which mainly means the set-up in advanced industrial cap italism that emerged after the Second World War (but that has its roots in the tran sition from "classical" industrial capitalism to imperialism)- and the newly emerging forms of capital that Jameson calls postrnodern and that Clinton asso ciates with his "bridge to the twenty-first century." All of this may sound terrifi cally "orthodox" (as Marxism, that is), very "base/superstructure," but the alter native is to think that the social system can really be convulsed by an incident of oral sex. (And then we have to listen to "sophisticated" European intellectuals going on about the "prudishness of the Americans," etc.) While the outcome of the Clinton impeachment was not certain, and it was not out of the realm of possibility that he could kave been removed from office (though one might also argue that the right-wing agenda could achieve just as much, if not more, by simply discrediting Clinton), it seems to me that the out come of the factional struggle within capital is much more assured: in the long run, postrnodern capital will supplant traditional capital. Without being overly de terministic about the issue, I think this is why Clinton was not removed from of fice: postconventional lifestyle politics, which ultimately comes to a more purely commodified and consumerist conception of "choice" (as opposed to the thicker sense of autonomy that would be necessary for anything that truly deserves to be called "politics"), fits better with the new forms of capital that are emerging. To conclude, then, with a few comments that speak to the question once again of "project." Sartre was my first love in philosophy, and he remains in or close to that posi tion. I find in Sartre a radical revolt against purposelessness. This returns to is sues that were raised in connection with Richard Rorty in the introduction , and
1 14
Afterword
also in my final chapter (where I quoted Jameson on Rorty and contingency), I brought that chapter to a close with a somewhat apocalyptic tone, I'm worned, There are really three "firsts" at work in this book, One is the "first love" that I hope can still invigorate our radical responses to oppressive social forms, Another is that this book will be the first, or one of the first, in a publication series called "New Critical Theory," As I understand it, one impulse behind the series is to bring forward the radicality of the "first generation" of Frankfurt School theorists (especially Adorno, Marcuse, and Benjamin, as I see it-the series editors can speak for themselves, of course), a radicality that is mostly lost with the second generation (Habermas and his cohort), We are assembling a "team," so to speak, and we hope that this team will help us speak some truth to power and possibly even help generate some counterpower. Sartre was involved in trying to theoretically resolve certain things that perhaps cannot be resolved- or perhaps cannot be resolved "in theory," Among these things are ethics and politics, and intellectual work and radical activism, In both of these areas it is possible, I suppose, to say that Sartre "failed," But I hold his "failure" infinitely higher than either blithe resolutions that do not deal with the issues in all of their practical and theoretical difficulties and complexities, or what seems to be the emerging postmodem ethos. As Jameson argued, perhaps we can continue to hold up Sartre as an "embarrassment" to this ethos; I attempted to go further (though in the spirit of what I think Jameson was actually putting forward) and to ask if Sartre can still give us some instruments of a pointed critique. This emerging epoch or subepoch or halfway-house epoch of postmodemity (Jameson wonders if postmodem capital is not truly a "third stage" of capital, but instead a transitional period to something that we at present cannot foresee; in that light we might say that postmodemity is "stage two-and-a-half') is perhaps the time to stop trying to bring resolution (under a regulative ideal) to the aforementioned is sues. In other words, as Jameson argues, postmodemity replaces contradiction with antinomy. In a similar vein, we might ask if postmodem capitalism gives us the reverse of Sartre's formula, a time of totalizers without totalization. Each in creasingly "autonomous" -in the absolutely thinnest and most pliable of senses-individual becomes a lawless , directionless god in their own cyber worlds, to no end. Perhaps Sartre foresaw the emergence of something like this, as the logical and high-tech outcome of seriality run completely amok, and per haps that is why his final words to us in the Benny Levy interviews raise themes of redemption and utopia. People living together and for one another- imagine! Finally, on that Lennonist note, and to play off of the counterfeit "it's our tum"l"sixties generation finally in places of power" phenomenon that we have seen with the Clinton presidency ("we've been without adult supervision," wrote someone in the New Yorker), we might raise a generational issue. The "sixties/Sartre generation," if I can put it that way (even if, technically, it is made up of two, three, or four generations), will ultimately not be very comfortable with postmodem capitalism, one hopes. Capitalism is a pointless economic form.
A philosopher of his century
1 15
Postmodem capital pushes this pointlessness to a kind of full integration, colo nizing and thereby obliterating every lifeworld (to use Habermas 's language) . Sartre's phrase, "man is a useless passion," has often been misinterpreted as pes simistic or cynical. His point instead (and not foreign to Bataille's anti-utilitarian arguments) is that whatever meaning there is to be found for us in society and his tory is a human meaning and not the instrument of some transcendent totalizer. Human life is therefore an experiment, or what Derrida calls "the experience of the impossible." What postmodem capitalism is doing is to make a new kind of assault on this experience-it channels all passions either into calculated uses for the profit of a few, or into the sort of distractions where the point of one's life be comes to have the highest score in the video game. One dimension of the sixties rebellion was a revolt against boredom and pointlessness. At its best, the rebel lion joined with the revolts against the sort of pointless organization of things that grinds people in the Third World and marginalized peoples in the First World lit
erally into the ground. We might define a certain "fifties generation" as one that fi�s well with emergent postmodem capital. I'm thinking of the "organization man" -the paradigm, really, of what "rational economic man" looks like in a well-regulated citadel of a far-flung empire. People expect one generation to suc ceed another, eventually. Instead what we got was the Clinton phenomenon, and a lot of people have bought into that illusion. Even more have some people
rucially
bought into the illusion that a fuzzy, bourgeois democracy (as always, c
supplemented-I mean this in the sense of Derrida's term, the "dangerous sup
plement" -by a much larger zone of brutal, authoritarianism in the Third World and in the margins of the First World) is the most that humanity can achieve. Will the radical project, the realistic demand for the impossible, have another day, an other chance?
Bibliography
1 . WORKS BY
J EAN-PAUL SARTRE
(These works are listed chronologically, by their dates of publication in French. These
dates appear in brackets at the end of each entry.)
Being and Nothingness. Hazel E. Barnes, trans . New York: Washington Square Press, 1966. [1943]
"Existentialism Is a Humanism."
In Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre. Walter
Kauffman, ed. New York: Meridian, 1975. [ 1 946]
"Materialism and Revolution."
In Literary and Philosophical Essays. Annette Michelson,
ed. and trans. New York: Criterion Books, 1955. [ 1 946]
What Is Literature? and Other Essays. Bernard Frechtrnan, trans . Cambridge, Mass: Har vard University Press, 1988. [1 948]
Notebooks for an Ethics. David Pellauer, trans. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992. [written in the late 1940s, published posthumously by Gallimard, 1983]
Saint Genet: Actor and Martyr. Bernard Frechtman, trans. New York: Mentor Books, 1964. [1952]
"Mad Beasts." In
The Writings ofJean-Paul Sartre. Vol. 2, Selected Prose. Michel Contat,
Michel Rybalka, eds. Richard McCleary, trans. Evanston, Ill . : Northwestern University Press, 1 974. [ 1 953]
Search for a Method. Hazel E. Barnes, trans. New York: Vintage Books, 1968. [1 960] Critique of Dialectical Reason. Vol. I , Theory of Practical Ensembles. Jonathan Ree, ed. Alan Sheridan-Smith, trans. London: Verso, 1982. [ 1 960]
Critique ofDialectical Reason. Vol. 2, The Intelligibility of History. Quintin Hoare, trans.
London: Verso, 199 1 . [written in the late 1 950s, published posthumously by Gallimard, 1985]
The Words. Bernard Frechtrnan, trans. New York: Braziller, 1964. [ 1 963] "The Burgos Trial." In Life/Situations. [1971] Between Existentialism and Marxism. John Mathews, trans. New York: Morrow Quill, 1979. [1 972]
"A Friend of the People." In
Between Existentialism and Marxism. [1 972] I I7
Bibliography
1 18
"The Maoists in France." In Life/Situations. [1972] "Justice and the State." In Life/Situations. [1972] "Elections: A Trap for Fools." In Life/Situations. [1973] On a raison de se revolter. With Pierre Victor and Philippe Gavi. Paris: Editions Galli mard, 1974. LifelSituations: Essays Written and Spoken. Paul Auster, Lydia Davis, trans. New York: Pantheon, 1977. [1976] Hope Now: The 1980 Interviews. With Benny Levy. Adrian van den Hoven, trans. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996. [1980] "Today's Hope: Conversations with Sartre." With Benny Levy. Telos 44 (Summer 1980). [1980] 2.
OTH ER WORKS
Alperovitz, Gar. The Decision to Use the Atomic Bomb and the Architecture of an Ameri can Myth. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1995. Althusser, Louis. "Our Jean-Jacques Rousseau." (Eulogy for Sartre.) Telos 44 (Summer 1980): 197. Aronson, Ronald. Sartre's Second Critique. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987. Avakian, Bob. Conquer the World: The International Proletariat Must and Will. Chicago: RCP Publications, 198 1 . Barnes, Hazel E . "Sartre as Materialist." I n The Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre. Paul Arthur Schilpp, ed. La Salle, III.: Open Court, 198 1 . Bataille, Georges. Guilty. Trans. by Bruce Boone. Introduction by Denis Hollier. Venice, Calif.: Lapis Press, 1988. . Visions of Excess. Allan Stoekl, trans. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985. Blanchot, Maurice. The Unavowable Community. Pierre Joris, trans. Barrytown, N.Y.: Sta tion Hill Press, 1988. Bloch, Ernst. "Something's Missing.: A Discussion between Ernst Bloch and Theodor W. Adorno on the Contradictions of Utopian Longing." In Bloch, The Utopian Function of Art and Literature. Jack Zipes, Frank Mecklenburg, trans. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988 . Boschetti, Anna. The Intellectual Enterprise: Sartre and Les Temps Modernes. Richard C. McCleary, trans. Evanston, III.: Northwestern University Press, 1988. Bree, Germaine. Camus and Sartre: Crisis and Commitment. New York: Dell, 1972. Caws, Peter. "Sartrean Structuralism?" In The Cambridge Companion to Sartre. Christina Howells, ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992. DeJeuze, Gilles. "Nomad Thought." David B. Allison, trans. In David B. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985. Derrida, Jacques. Writing and Difference. Alan Bass, trans. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978. . "Violence and Metaphysics: An Essay on the Thought of Emmanuel Levinas." In Writing and Difference. -- . "From Restricted to General Economy: A Hegelianism without Reserve." In Writ ing and Difference. --
--
1 19
Bibliography --
. "The Ends of Man." In
Margins of Philosophy. Alan Bass, trans. Chicago: UnI
versity of Chicago Press, 1982. --
. Glas. John P. Leavy, Jr., Richard Rand. trans. Lincoln: University of Nebraska
Press, 1986. --
. Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question. Geoffrey Bennington, Rachel Bowlby,
trans. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989.
. Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the New In ternational. Peggy Kamuf, trans. New York: Routledge, 1994.
--
Dow, Katherine. "Ex-posing Identity: Denida and Nancy on the (Im)possibility." Unpub lished manuscript in my possession.
Engels , Frederick.
The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State. Eleanor
Burke Leacock, ed. New York: International Publishers, 1972.
Feher, Ferenc, Agnes Heller, and Gyorgy Markus.
Dictatorship over Needs: An Analysis of Soviet Societies. New York: Basil Blackwell, 1983 . Ferry, Luc, and Alain Renaut. French Philosophy of the Sixties: An Essay on Antihuman ism. Mary Schnackenberg Cattani, trans. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1990.
Language, Counter-memory, Practice. Donald F. Bouchard, ed. Donald
Foucault, Michel.
F. Bouchard, Sherry Simon, trans. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1977.
. "Intellectuals and Power." With Gilles Deleuze. In Language, counter-memory, practice. . Power/Knowledge. Colin Gordon, ed. Colin Gordon, Leo Marshall, John ,Mepham,
--
--
Kate Soper, trans. New York: Pantheon Books, 1980.
Gerassi, John. Jean-Paul Sartre: Hated Conscience ofHis Chicago Press, 1989.
Gibson, William.
Century. Chicago: University of
Neuromancer. New York: Ace Science Fiction, 1984. Theory of Communicative Action. 2 vols . Thomas McCarthy, trans.
Habermas, Jurgen.
Boston: Beacon Press, 198411987.
--. The Philosophical Discourse ofModernity. Frederick Lawrence, trans. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987.
Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri. Labor ofDionysus: A neapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1994.
Critique of the State-Form. Min
Hayden, John Patrick. "(Re)thinking Community: Responding to Bataille." Unpublished manuscript in my possession.
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. John Macquarrie, Edward Robinson, trans. New York: Harper and Row, 1962.
Hirsh, Arthur.
The French New Left: An Intellectual History from Sartre to Gort.. Boston:
South End Press , 198 1 .
Howells, Christina. "Sartre and the Deconstruction of the Subject." In
The Cambridge Companion to Sartre. Christina Howells, ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
-- . Derrida: Deconstructionfrom Phenomenology to Ethics. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1999.
Jameson , Fredric. 1984.
Sartre: The Origins of a Style. New York: Columbia University Press,
--. Marxism and Form: Twentieth-Century Dialectical Theories of Literature. Prince ton, NJ.: Princeton University Press, 197 1 .
120
Bibliography
. The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic Act. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cor nell University Press, 198 1 . . Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 199 1 . . "Marx's Purloined Letter." New Left Review, 209 (January-February 1995): 75-109. . The Seeds of Time. New York: Columbia University Press, 1994. . "The Sartrean Origin." Sartre Studies International 1 , n.1/2 (1995). Kahn, Jean-Francois. "God, How They Hated Him." (Eulogy for Sartre.) Telos 44 (Sum mer 1980): 194-196. League, Kathleen. "Problems of Deconstructive Communitarianism." Unpublished manu script in my possession. Lenin, V. I. What Is to Be Done? Burning Questions of Our Movement. New York: Inter national Publishers, 1969. Levinas, Emmanuel. "A Language Familiar to Us." (Eulogy for Sartre.) Telos 44 (Summer 1980): 199-20 1 . Mao Tsetung. Five Essays on Philosophy. Peking: Foreign Languages Press, 1977. . "On the Ten Great Relationships." In Chairman Mao Talks to the People: Talks and Letters, 1956-197/. Stuart Schram, ed. New York: Pantheon, 1974. Marcuse, Herbert. One-Dimensional Man. Boston: Beacon Press, 1964. Martin, Bill. "Foucault: Power/Counter-power." Arena 73 (Winter 1985). --. "Nomad and Empire: Nietzsche, Guerilla Theater, Guerilla War." Arena 77 (Win ter 1986). . Matrix and Line: Derrida and the Possibilities of Postmodern Social Theory. Al bany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1992. . Humanism and Its Aftermath: The Shared Fate of Deconstruction and Politics. At lantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1995. . Politics in the Impasse: Explorations in Postseculqr Social Theory. Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1996. . Music of Yes: Structure and Vision in Progressive Rock. Chicago: Open Court, 1996. . Listening to the Future: The Time of Progressive Rock, 1968-1978. Chicago: Open Court, 1997. Marx, Karl. Critique of the Gotha Programme. Peking: Foreign Languages Press, 1972. Marx, Karl, and Frederick Engels. The German Ideology. C .J. Arthur, ed. New York: In ternational Publishers, 1970. Marx-Scouras, Danielle. The Cultural Politics of Tel Quel: Literature and the Left in the Wake of Engagement. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996. May, Todd. The Political Philosophy of Poststructuralist Anarchism. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1994. Mayer, Arno J. Why Did the Heavens Not Darken? The "Final Solution " in History. New York: Pantheon, 1988. McBride, William. Sartre 's Political Theory. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 199 1 . Mendes-Flohr, Paul. From Mysticism to Dialogue: Martin Buber's Transformation ofGer man Social Thought. Detroit: Wayne State University Press: 1989. --
--
--
--
--
--
--
--
--
--
--
Bibliography Nancy, Jean-Luc.
The Inoperative Community. Peter Connor, Lisa Garbus, Michael
121 HoI
land, Simona Sawhney, trans. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 199 1 . Poster, Mark.
Existential Marxism in Postwar France: From Sanre to Althusser. Prince
ton, NJ.: Princeton University Press, 1975. --
. Foucault, Marxism, and History; Mode ofProduction versus Mode ofInformation.
Cambridge: Polity Press, 1 984. Romano, Carlin. "Kicking Judt." The Nation (April 26, 1 993): 562-66.
Truth and Progress. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century America. Cam-
Rorty, Richard. --
.
bridge: Harvard University Press, 1998. Rosen, Stanley. Hermeneutics and Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987. Schwarzschild, Steven. "Jean-Paul Sartre as Jew." In Schwarzschild,
The Pursuit of the Ideal. Menachem Kellner, ed. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990. Sheehan, Helena. Marxism and the Philosophy of Science: A Critical History. Atlantic Highlands, NJ.: Humanities Press, 1993.
Situationist International An thology. Ken Knabb , ed. and trans. Berkeley, Calif.: Bureau of Public Secrets, 1 98 1 . Stalin, J . V. Th e Foundations of Leninism. Peking: Foreign Languages Press, 1970. . Economic Problems of Socialism in the U.S.S.R. Peking: Foreign Languages Situationist International. "Interview with an Imbecile." In
--
Press, 1972.
Index
Adorno, Theodor, 6 1 , 87, 94, 96, 1 1 4
Callinicos, Alex, 72
Althusser, Louis, 47, 50, 5 1 , 52, 60, 6 1 ,
capitalism, 9, 92, 109.
analytic philosophy, 1 1 , 43 , 72, 95
Camap , Rudolph, 64
anti-Semitism, 30
China, 4, 17, 25, 30
Aristotle, I
Chomsky, Noam, 59-61 , 62
Algeria, 47, 85
68, 72, 77, 91 , 96
anomalous monism, 43
Aquinas, Thomas, 1
Camus, Albert, 50
See also
postmodern capitalism
Caws, Peter, 77
Chinese Revolution, 32, 56
Aron, Raymond, 19, 35, 64
Clinton, Bill, 6 1 , 65, 84, 85, 1 10-15
Avakian, Bob, 19, 21
communism, 9 , I I , 1 6 , 38, 68, 102
Aronson, Ronald, 19, 35, 76
colonialism, 6, 79, 102, 103 , 1 1 1
autonomy, 66, 73
Communist Party of France (PCF), 1 1 , 38 ,
Bames, Hazel, 36, 37, 38-39, 108
communitarianism, 5 , 68, 69
Barthes , Roland, 50
Bataille, Georges, 63, 64, 66, 69, 7 1 , 1 1 5
Beauvoir, Simone de, 47, 58, 79
Benjamin, Walter, 1 3 , 104, 1 14 Blanchot, 11aurice, 63-68 Bolshevik Party, 28, 29
Bolshevik Revolution, 1 6 , 25 , 29 Boschetti, Anna, 48-49, 50
41-42, 52, 56, 79
contingen�, 8 , lO, 12, 1 3 , 42-43 , 76, 97 -
culture industry, 96
Cultural Revolution in China, 42, 56
cybernetics, 95, 96, 99, 103 cyberspace, 68, 96
Davidson, Donald, 43
de Gaulle, Charles, 42
Bourdieu , Pierre, 48, 62
Deleuze, Gilles, 1 3 , 37, 53-55, 56-59, 6 1
Brecht, Bertolt, 27
Derrida, Jacques, 2, 5 , 1 3 , 1 8 , 37, 54, 58,
boxing, 67
Bree, Germaine, 48
Buber, 11artin, 66
Bukharin, Nikolai, 28
Butler, Judith, 97
de 11an, Paul, 2 1 , 94-95
63 , 64, 7 1-78, 8 1 , 88, 97 , 104, 1 1 5
Descartes, Cartesianism, 67, 68, 74, 76, 78
determinism, 44
Deutscher, Isaac, 27
123
1 24
Index
Dewey, John, 10-1 1 Dow, Katherine, 66 Dreyfus affair, 60 Eagleton, Terry, 24, 72 Easter Rebellion, 1 6 econorrllsm, 24-25, 29-30 , 44, 45, 1 01-2, 103 Einstein, Albert, 43 electoral politics, 109-11 Elkaim-Sartre, Arlette, 19, 36 engagement, 2, 3, 1 1 , 21 , 39, 49, 59, 62, 64, 98 Engels, Frederick, 3, 13, 104 Eno, Brian, 108-9 Eurocentrism, 4, 20, 23, 24, 27, 30, 32, 33, 56 Fanon, Frantz, 50 fascism, 21 , 102, 1 10-1 1 Ferry, Luc, 51 , 64 Flynn, Thomas R., 108 Foucault, MiChel, 50, 51 , 52-53, 54-55, 56-59, 73, 80-8 1 , 1 08-9 freedom, 30 Gavi, Philippe, 36 Genet, Jean, 7 1 Gerassi, John, 48 Giacometti, Alberto, 3 Gibson, William, 96 globalism, 1 13 gnosticism, 75 Gordon, Lewis, 62 Gramsci, Antonio, 1 6, 58 Guattari, Felix, 53, 55, 58 Guevara, Ernesto "Che," 27 Habermas, Jilrgen, 8, 76-77, 109, 1 1 4 Hayden, Patrick, 65-66 Hegel, G. W. F., 6, 39-40, 45, 5 1 , 64-65, 7 1 , 73, 77 Heidegger, Martin, 2, 10, 21 , 42, 64, 65, 72-74 Hirsh, Arthur, 64 Hobbes, Thomas, 6, 7, 59, 67, 80, 1 04 Hoffman, Abbie, 86
Holocaust, 10 Horkheimer, Max, 1 04 Howells, Christina, 67, 7 1 Hoxha, Enver, 1 8 "human nature ," 7 humanism, 2, 54 Husserl, Edmund, 73, 74 identity politics, 53, 55, 59, 93 imperialism, 6, 15, 29, 60, 68, 79, 92, 95, 96, 102-3, 109, 1 1 1 , 1 13 indeterminacy, 42-43 internationalism, 6, 16, 79 intersubjectivity, 77 Israel, State of, 6 1 Jackson, Jesse, 83 Jameson, Fredric, 13, 37, 72, 91-92, 94-103 , 109, 1 1 1 , 1 1 3 Jeanson, Fran�ois, 3 Judaism, 5, 36, 38, 39-41 , 45, 71 , 77 Judt, Tony, 21 , 48 Kamenev, Lev, 28 Kant, Immanuel, 1 , 2, 3, 6, 7, 33, 39, 43, 54, 73, 77, 78, 101 , 104 Kautsky, Karl, 23, 25, 26 Kennedy, John F., 1 12 Khrushchev, Nilcita, 19 Kierkegaard, S¢ren, 65, 68 King, Martin Luther, Jr., 74 Kojeve, Alexander, 5 1 Korea, 3 1 Kristeva, Julia, 51 Lacan, Jacques, 5 1 League, Kathleen, 69 Left Unity electoral coalition, 79, 83 Lenin, Vladimir Ilyich, 16, 22, 24, 27, 28, 29, 32, 43, 67, 83, 91 , 95, 96 Les Temps Modemes, 79 Levi-Strauss, Claude, 5 1 Levinas, Emmanuel, 38 Levy, Benny, 35, 36, 40-41 , 44 , 58, 60, 75 liberalism, 66, 68
125
Index Lin Biao, 101
Reagan, Ronald, 21 , 84
Lyotard, Jean-Franyois, 98
reification, 1 3 , 38 , 68 , 104
Lukacs , Georg, 100
Mao Tsetung, l 1 , 16, 17, 1 8 , 24, 27, 3 1 ,
32, 35 , 37, 39, 42-45 , 52, 56, 59, 101
Maoism, 4, 5 , 17, 1 9 , 35, 36, 39, 41-42,
reductivism, 1 7
religious fundamentalism, 93 Renaut, Alain, 5 1 , 64
representation, critique of, 53, 58, 62
Resistance, French, 47
45 , 53 , 56, 60, 61 , 72, 79
responsibility, 76
1 14
Rorty, Richard, 5-13, 93, 97, 1 1 3-14
Marcuse, Herbert, 47, 50, 58, 87, 94, 96, market, 92
Martinot, Steve, 77
Marx, Karl, 1-4, 6, 9, 12-13, 1 6 , 45, 5 1 , 6 1 , 69, 77, 78, 82, 91 , 95 , 102, 104, 107 , 109
Marxism, 4, 5 , 10, 17, 20, 24, 33, 35 ,
40-4 1 , 44, 45 , 52, 54 , 55 , 75 , 76, 86, 10 1 , 1 1 3
Marx-Scouras, Danielle, 51-52
Romano, Carlin, 21
Rosen, Stanley, 72
Rosenberg, Ethel and Julius , execution of, 48
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 47, 60 Rybalka, Michel, 48
Schwarzschild, Steven, 36, 39-41 , 44, 104
Second World War, 26
materialism, l 1 , 17, 38, 40, 75
Secularism, 5, 12, 1 3
May 1968, events of, 3 , 47 , 52, 55, 58, 6 1. , 64, 65, 67, 68, 74, 79, 86, 88
Sheehan, Helena, 43
May, Todd, 53, 58
Mayer, Amo, 10
McBride, William, 1 9 , 67
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 50, 64
seriality, 77, 80, 8 1-84, 86, 87-88, 92, . 94-96, 100, 103, 1 1 4
"The Simpsons" (television program), 84-85
Situationist International, 94
messianism, 39, 40, 45
social democracy, 101
modernity, 83
solidarity, 66
micropolitics, 53, 55, 58, 59, 94
Nancy, Jean-Luc, 63, 65-68, 7 1 , 73
Nazism, 1 1 , 25
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 64, 65, 72, 74, 75 Paris Commune, 16
Paz, Octavio, 48
Socialist Party of France (pSF), 79, 85 Sollers, Philippe, 5 1 Sophocles, 68-69
Soviet l1ilion, 4, 1 1 , 1 3 , 16-33, 37, 38, 42, 43
speciesism, 2, 73
Stalin, Joseph, 4, 5 , I I , 1 3 , 16-33 , 37 , 38 , 42, 43 , 44 , 55 , 59, 76
Plato, 1 , 2, 61
Stalingrad, Battle of, 15-16, 32
Poster, Mark, 55, 64
structuralism, 37, 50, 5 1
positivism, 59, 96
Postman, Neil, 62
"Stalinism," 7 , 9, 22, 44, 64, 66, 68, 76
postmodern capitalism, 1 3 , 88, 104, 105,
Tel Quel, 5 1 -52, 53
project, Sartre's notion of, 41 , 92
Third World, 16, 1 7 , 25, 1 1 5
109, 1 14-15
proletariat, 102-3
quantum mechanics, 43
queer theory, 97
Tet Offensive (Vietnam), 16
totality, 12, 56, 58, 59, 66, 68, 1 14, 115
Trotsky, Leon, 19, 20, 22, 25-30, 43
Trotskyism, 8, 20, 23, 101
126 Victor, Pierre. See Benny Levy
Index Williams, Raymond, l 3
Vietnam War, 1 5 , 3 1 , 47, 57, 74
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 10
Weil, Simone, 77, 85, 102, 1 1 1
Young, Neil, 95
Williams, Patricia, 62
Zinoviev, Gregory, 28
West, Cornell , 62
By the Same Author
Matrix and line: Derrida and the possibilities ofpostmodem social theory Humanism and its aftermath: The sharedfate of deconstruction and politics Politics in the impasse: Explorations in postsecular social theory Music of Yes: Structure and vision in progressive rock Listening to the future: The time ofprogressive rock, 1968�1978
127