Lecture Notes in Mathematics A collection of informal reports and seminars Edited by A. Dold, Heidelberg and B. Eckmann, Zerich
86
m
Category Theory, Homology Theory and their Applications I
1969
Proceedings of the Conference held at the Seattle Research Center of the Battelle Memorial Institute, June 24 - July 19,1968 Volume One l
Springer-Verlag Berlin. Heidelberg-New York
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be translated or reproduced in any form without written permission from Springer Verlag. 9 by Springer-Verlag Berlin 9 Heidelberg 1969 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 75-75 931 Printed in Germany. Title No. 3692
Preface
A conference was held at the Seattle Institute
during
the summer of 1968.
gether research workers
Research Center
The object of this conference
in the fields of c a t e g o r y
w h o applied the results of these theories algebra or topology. ized conference expectation
Thus this was not,
in categorical
of its organizers
theory w i t h i n m a t h e m a t i c s the interplays
of these
algebra being
w o u l d emerge
duration.
Three
space and optimal
invated courses
D. A. Buchsbaum
Regular
F. W. Lawvere
Hyperdoctrines
about 40 seminar
talks were
ceedings
become
I would committee,
[nva!uable
time)
of which however,
after the p u b l i c a t i o n
for a working
w o u l d be highlighted.
colloquium
of four week's
this
received
the pro-
(together w i t h their
the d e s i r a b i l i t y
is the first.
All those
of publishing
Following
the
the table of
appended a list of titles of papers to appear
naturally,
require amendment
if further m a n u s c r i p t s
of this volume.
to express,
to the Battelle
and to the a d m i n i s t r a t i v e in innumerable
participants.
w i t h a view to publishing
suggested
like to take this o p p o r t u n i t y
assistance,
and that
to be turned away owing to consider-
The number of m a n u s c r i p t s
this list may,
our deep gratitude
the conference
theory and h o m o l o g y
at least that number of people,
talks were given b y conference
of this volume we have,
available
the
Local Rings
in several volumes,
in subsequent volumes!
Seminars),
Cohomology
length and somewhat random arrival
contents
size
invited to submit m a n u s c r i p t s
of the conference.
proceedings
to be, a tightly special-
from the conference
in the conference~
within
of lectures were delivered:
Generalized
giving
the m o r e clearly
to-
theory and those
disciplines
(by comparison w i t h the Midwest
had u n f o r t u n a t e l y
J. F. Adams
In addition,
and was not intended
theories w i t h other parts of m a t h e m a t i c s
of invitations,
ations of available
to their own m a t h e m a t i c a l
Memorial
was to bring
theory and h o m o l o g y
that the roles of c a t e g o r y
There were about 80 p a r t i c i p a n t s fully deserving
of the Battelle
Memorial
and clerical
respects,
on b e h a l f of the organizing Institute
for their
support of
staff of the Institute
for their
in the running of the c o n f e r e n c e
and
IV
the preparation of manuscripts.
We were,
indeed,
conference under the auspices of Battelle.
fortunate to be invited to hold our
That the conference participants fully
shared the sense of gratitude of the organizing committee towards the Battelle Memorial Institute is set in evidence b y the following resolution, p a s s e d at the c l o s i n g session of the conference, w h i c h I was charged to make public through the m e d i u m of the conference proceedings.
"This conference at the Battelle Memorial Institute, w i t h its initial object Categories,
Homology and their applications, has n o w reached its termination.
our subjects are far from complete,
the
ference has been intensive, coherent,
Though
exchange of ideas about them at this con-
lucid, and never petty, while the local facilitie~
provided b y the Institute have been infinitely productive.
As p a r t i c i p a n t s
in this
conference, we w o u l d like to thank the Battelle Memorial Institute and its most helpful and efficient staff for the e x t a o r d i n a r i l y fine facilities and services w h i c h have been placed at our disposal.
We are equally indebted to the enthusiasm of the organizing
committee and the w i s d o m of the scientific staff at Battelle for their p r o v i s i o n of this ideal setting for the natural transformation of ideas into theorems."
Cornell University,
Ithaca, November,
1968
Peter Hilton
T a b l e of C o n t e n t s
M.
Barr
D. A.
Coalgebras
Buchsbaum
Lectures
in a c a t e g o r y of a l g e b r a s
on R e g u l a r L o c a l
R. F i t t l e r
Categories
J. F. K e n n i s o n
Coreflectlon maps which
J. L a m b e k
Deductive
S. M a c L a n e
Possible
programs
R. C. P a r ~
Absolute
coequalizers
S. Shatz
Galols
H.
Derived
Stauffer
M. T i e r n e y
and W. V o g e l
Rings
of m o d u l e s w i t h
systems
................ I
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13
initial o b j e c t s . . . . . . . . . . 55
resemble
and c a t e g o r i e s for c a t e g o r i s t s
universal
coverings46
(If) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7G .................
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 152
theory ..................................... functors without
Simplicial
derived
125
146
injectives ................ 159
functors
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 167
F. U l m e r
Acyclic models
M. Z i s m a n
Derived category and Poincar~ duality
and Kan e x t e n s i o n s . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 151 . . . . . . . . . . . . . 205
Papers to appear in future volumes
Generalized c o h o m o l o g y
J. F. Adams J. B e c k
On H-spaces
and infinite l o o p - s p a c e s
H. B. Brinkmann
Relations for groups and for exact categories
S. U. Chase
Galois objects
P. Dedecker
T h r e e - d i m e n s i o n a l non-abelian c o h o m o l o g y for groups
R. R. Douglas,
P. J. Hilton
and F. Sigrist
H-spaces
D. B. Epstein and M. Kneser
Functors between categories of vector spaces
D. B. Epstein
Natural vector bundles
P. J. Freyd
N e w concepts in c a t e g o r y theory
J. W. Gray
Categorical fibrations and 2-categories
K. W. Gruenberg
C a t e g o r y of group extensions
R. Hoobler
N o n - a b e l i a n sheaf c o h o m o l o g y
M. A. Knus
Algebras graded b y a group
M. Karoubi
Foncteurs d~riv~s et K-th6orle
F. W. Lawvere
Hyperdoctrines
F. E. J. Linton
Relative functorial semantics
S. MacLane
Foundations for categories and sets
E. G. Manes
Minimal subalgebras for dynamical triples
P. May
Categories of spectra and infinite loop spaces
P. Olum
Homology of squares and factorization of diagrams
J.
Locally N o e t h e r i a n categories
E.
Roos
F. Ulmer
Kan extensions, cotriples and Andr4 c o h o m o l o g y
COALGEBRAS
IN A C A T E G O R Y OF A L G E B R A S
by Michael Barr
Let A be a c a t e g o r y and ~ = A. m
Then we may form B - A]I, the c a t e g o r y of ~
There
(FU,z,FnU)
where
More e x p l i c i t l y , ~- FU
the a d j o i n t n e s s m o r p h i s m s . u
be a triple on algebras.
is then an a d j o i n t p a i r A ( F ) B and we may ask w h e t h e r or U
n o t F is c o t r i p l e a b l e . G =
(T,n,u)
)B -~ = C
A
)I
and
we m a y form a c o t r i p l e n: 1
)UF = T
Then there is a n a t u r a l
and we are a s k i n g w h e t h e r
are
functor
~ is an e q u i v a l e n c e .
-
For g e n e r a l ~, would,
the p r o b l e m seems v e r y d i f f i c u l t .
of course, be p o s s i b l e
A]I (A ~) m
, 0 o..
m'
this process
to c o n t i n u e
forming categories
Myles T i e r n e y has g i v e n an e x a m p l e
n e e d n ' t e v e r terminate.
that it t e r m i n a t e at a n y finite step.
perhaps,
a c o n c e p t of a d i m e n s i o n of a category.
of sets
to show that
P r e s u m a b l y it is a l s o
possible
Here we give a c o m p l e t e
It
Thus we have,
a n s w e r w h e n A is the c a t e g o r y
(denoted by S), p o i n t e d sets
(denoted by
(I,S)), o r vec-
tor spaces over the field K for w h i c h while
(denoted by V ). I g n o r i n g those --K the functor T is c o n s t a n t , we s h o w that dims = 1
dim(l,S) --
S and
(I,S)
= dimV
= O.
S i n c e the main d i f f e r e n c e b e t w e e n
--K
is that the former c o n t a i n s some m o n o m o r p h i s m s
-2-
which does
do not split
(any #
) X), this concept of dimension
seem to be some kind of h o m o l o g i c a l
For the m e a n i n g and statements orems we refer to
[Be] and
it
According we must consider phisms
to the dual of the t r i p l e a b l e n e s s of w h e t h e r
it preserves
and creates
so UF-split.
phisms.
In any concrete
Lemma
theorem
isomor-
But U reflects
and an F-split p a i r is al-
the q u e s t i o n
these q u e s t i o n s of T r e f l e c t i n g
for T isomor-
c a t e g o r y we may call a triple consis-
tent if it has a model of c a r d i n a l i t y
a t least 2.
that A is one of the three categories m.i
The f o l l o w i n g
the-
of F - s p l i t pairs
are complete.)
Thus we need only c o n s i d e r
First we consider
F reflects
equalizers
all limits
itself.
assume
tripleableness
PRELIMINARIES
(since all of our categories isomorphisms
of the various
of the category.
[Li].
the question
and w h e t h e r
measure
lemma is from
We h e n c e f o r t h
mentioned
above.
[La].
I,
Let ~ =
(T,n,.)
proof.
Any o b j e c t A r A with
be a c o n s i s t e n t
triple
in A. ..m
Then
is I-i.
cogenerator.
Then
A is a ]~-algebra, can be c o m p l e t e d
to
for all A' c A, A' c
cardinality
> 2 is a
A x for some set X.
so is A X , and the given e m b e d d i n g A' c_#A X
If
-3-
A! ( ~A' ~ so that hA'
TA'
;A x /R
is i-i.
From now on we assume ~[ is consistent. seen that on S there are 2 i n c o n s i s t e n t
triples
It is e a s i l y (TX - 1 for
all X is one and TX = 1 for all X ~ ~, T~ = # is the other), while
on
(I,S)
and V
--
Proposition
there
is e x a c t l y
one.
--K
2.
T is faithful.
Proof.
If f ~ g. X---~Y,
then since
n is l-l,
Tf. nX = ,Y.f ~ ,Y.g = Tg. nX so Tf ~ Tg.
Theorem
3,
T
(and hence
Proof. morphisms which
F) reflects
For T, b e i n g
and m o n o m o r p h i s m s ,
is both
isomorphisms.
faithful,
and A has
reflects
the p r o p e r t y
SPLIT
EQUALIZERS
In order to apply the c o t r i p l e a b l e n e s s
qualizers. categories.
that a map
is an isomorphism.
2,
is n e c e s s a r y
both epi-
to have a c o m b i n a t o r i a l
description
It turns out to be the same
(almost)
theorem,
it
of split ein all three
-4-
Theorem
4. dO X ~ Y dr
Two maps
can b e p u t
into
a split
equalizer
di agr a m
t satisfying
td = E,
lowing
conditions
(i)
Equalizer
(ii)
d ~ is
(iii)
If d ~
Condition map
s d ~ = X,
are (d~
sd I
dt,
d~
dld
I) ~ r (or X = Y =
r
1 = d x'
%E
may
t
then
d ~X
=
be d e s c r i b e d
making
the
d 1 X. by
saying
following
d~
= d 1 x'
f
then
commute
d~
(kernel
The n e c e s s i t y only
is a
/Y
P is the p u l l b a c k
(i) r e f e r s
there
~-X
d
Proof.
that
diagram
E
dition
fol-
satisfied.
P
where
if the
i-I.
(iii)
u: P
~ s
pair)
of
(i)
to S anyway.)
a n d E the e q u a l i z e r .
and As
(ii) for
is
clear
(iii),
dl x = d l s d ~ x = d l s d l x ' = dldtx,
(con-
if
= d~
'
=
d o s d l x , = d O s d O x = dOx.
It is s e e n in any
concrete
that
these
category.
heavily
on the e x p l i c i t
cases.
It is o n l y
conditions
Their
sufficiency
categories
necessary
will
at hand.
to f i n d
s: Y
be n e c e s s a r y depends
very
We must
consider
) X
with
sd ~ = X
-5-
and
d~
I = d l s d I,
dt = s d 1 by
the
Case
for
then
nature
S.
t" Y
=
X
dOx
Write
s
+ Y
Y = Y O
)Yo ( a b u s i n g n o t a t i o n ) .
= dlx O
.
Then
can b e
chosen
so t h a t
of equalizers.
u
d~
;E
define
where
1
Choose
s : Y
X
x
by
Y
= ImX.
o
z X
O
Then
with
s IYo =
(d~ -I
and
O
i Y1 i s c o n s t a n t x o. sdlx
then
= x o and
d O x , = d l x ', a n d
sd~
Clearly dlsdlx
then
= X.
= dosdlx.
dlsdlx
= dlsd~
If
If d l x
d I x~
imd ~
= d~
', t h e n
' = dlx ' = d~
' =
dOsdOx , = dosdlx.
Case should
be
(i,~)o
taken
Case write
d ~ is
and
d ~ is
the
s Imd
~ ~
s o Y s Im d ~ Im dlc d,
d",
X o + Y2" d I have
~"
X1
we
Im dl-T'~Y = X o.
can
the
same
except
that
xO
In
the
equalizer
= d~
that
= d l x '.
we
terms
may
may
d I and
assume
Y = X~ + X
of
,
Then
choose
this
Y2
as
d~
8"
X1
y
1
so
= dOx
E = Xo.
+Y2
the
follows.
8
) Y2
are
= dlx
that
decomposition
representations
and
We
)Xo.
assume
of d ~ a n d
Moreover,
Hence
matrix
> Xo
exactly
d: E
inclusion.
d =
where
E be
where
i-i,
is
the b a s e p o i n t .
Let
X = Xo + X1
since
Y
to be
~K"
Now
This
arbitrary.
maps
and
-6-
Le t S
=
,
0
X1
and then the r e q u i r e d e q u a t i o n s
3t
t
ot
=
0
PRESERVATION
are clear.
OF T - S P L I T E Q U A L I Z E R S
In this we show that T - s p l i t e q u a l i z e r s ed in cases
(I,S)
and V K and e x a m i n e
in S.
The methods
that T
(and hence F) is co-VTT.
Proposition
are really quite
the sole vulgar,
are p r e s e r v -
failure of this
since
they prove
5
T (and hence
F) reflects
conditions
(ii)
and
(iii)
of t h e o r e m 4. Proof.
d~
If
X
)Y
and Td ~ is i-i, then
bY.d ~ = T d O . p X and ~X is I-i, so pY.d ~ and hence d ~ is I-i. For the other part we use the diaqram. p|
W m
w
IE---+ X
E'
d
!
)X//~X
l dl
|
!
~T
)TX
d~ ~
Td o
Td I
-7-
It is only n e c e s s a r y property ~Y.d~
of P' allows = Td~
Tdl.v'.~ d ~ .V
=
Theorem
to show that a map
d~
~: P
= Td~
=
= Td I.~Xov = ~y.dl.v
= dlv.
~P'
The u n i v e r s a l
as indicated.
Td~
= Td I 9 d'
and by lemma
,U
Now ' ,W
=
i, bY is i-i, so
d 1 .V.
6.
In cases
Proof.
(i,~)
There
and ~K' F is co-VTT.
is n o t h i n g
4.
There later w h i c h
left to prove.
S
are easy examples w h i c h w i l l become
show that T does not n e c e s s a r i l y
clear
reflect condition
(i) of t h e o r e m 4.
Theorem
7.
m
If T# ~ #, then there
(l,U) : A ~
)(i,~)
such that
A~
commutes,
is a f a c t o r i z a t i o n
(l.U))(I,S)
w h e r e V is the usual u n d e r l y i n g
there is a left a d j o i n t
(I,F) [
(I,U)
and
functor. (I,F)
Moreover,
is co-VTT.
-8-
Proof. to be
I--A-~T#
map in
(F~,A)
on objects
= UF~
=
U*)UA
(%,UA).
by letting
(F(X-{I}),A)
being
to a functor
Note
a functor,
which
~X)
)A
~X,
Define
(I,F)
Then
(I,U)A), a unique
and hence,
(I,U)A
is the unique
= U.
(I,F) has
(I,U)
is the reason
Define
= F(X-{I}).
I---~X'~-'-~X-{I}
first as an object
Theorem
V.(I,U)
Then to
)T~. ,~ F~
-- (I,S) (i
obvious.
that
where
(I,F) (i
left adjoint
is co-VTT.
a: 1
Clearly
= (X-{I},UA)
isomorphism
(I,F)
Pick a point
the last extension
by t h e o r e m
6,
cannot be e x t e n d e d
for the indirect
definition
to of
function.
8,
If T~ ~ %, then F is cotripleable. Proof. WX= since
1
If
Wz
S
1 + X, then Wl (I,F)
tripleable.
is co-VTT,
) (I,S) V.
is defined
But then
F =
it is only n e c e s s a r y
It is, in fact,
co-CTT,
by (I,F).W,
and
to show that W is
as may readily
be checked.
That is, E
is an e q u a l i z e r
Y
if and only if is.
WE
Theorem
9,
Suppose (in S).
e ~ , e 1 are
If ~----~TI
the two distinct
~T2 is an equalizer,
maps
of 1
)2
then F is co-trip-
-9-
leable.
Proof. E'
d')
Td~
TX
It is s u f f i c i e n t ,
"~TY
is
a split
E
d~ d ) X ~ Y
evidently,
equalizer,
to s h o w
then
that
the e q u a l i z e r
Td I is n o n - e m p t y .
d •
At
any
will
be
empty,
rate
condition
a map this
P
(iii)
is
)E so t h a t
means
we
can
find
reflected,
which
if E = %, so is P. a map
2
~Y
means
there
But
if P is
so t h a t
~O
x
i $i e o
i
i
)2
e This
commutes.
means
each
of the d i a g r a m s
d~
x
dI
}Y
x
1-----~e ~ 2 This
commute s 9
;Y
l'"-~ el
provides
us w i t h
a commutative
-------~ T 1 so t h a t
E' = ~.
Now we
This
that
diaqram
) T2
completes
suppose
2
the proof.
T# -
~, b u t
that
Te @
~T2
~ E---~ TI
Te 1
is an e q u a l i z e r .
Since
the u n d e r l y i n g
if
-
functor
creates
ture of a ~
equalizers,
algebra,
this structure.
map.
i0-
it is clear
so that there
Also we
Let T # be defined
let
n#~:
that E has
is a map #--~E
=
to check
(Tl,n # , u # )
Clearly
every
only new fines
free algebra
a functor
faithful model
S~ #
) S]~ which
and almost onto.
for T
but not
for ~#.
cotriples
with
the inclusion
_
_
difference, failure
again,
X =
Moreover,
on S.
already
since
checked
E is the
commute
is that
~ is a
object E, while ~ .
in
that the only
(ST)~.
of the d i a g r a m T
S I
to commute
not quite = ~.
exactly--F##
commute. Thus
= E, F% = ~ - - a l s o
In fact the comparison
(ST)~__ is as in the following.
Also
(on the nose!)
and almost onto,
# is a coalgebra
This de-
to be full,
From this it follows
faithful that
T #~ ~ # .
an algebra.
is easily
category
It is
~#X = ~X for X ~ ~,
a single p r e d e c e s s o r
S~#---~S ~.
being
if
S Y# has an initial
on each
is full,
,
The only difference
in ST , E is not initial but has the induced
the unique
**
is also a ~ - a l g e b r a ,
and it was
defining
.
a triple
"l~#-algebra
denote
n#X = nX and
that with becomes
TE u # ~ E
T#X =
by
E trivial
the struc-
makes
~ is such
that
The
-
Theorem
10.
Suppose Tr = r is non-empty. (r
=
Then
this
but the e q u a l i z e r
(S~) G may be d e s c r i b e d
(Y,Y) = i and
comparison S over,
11-
as S U {y] w h e r e
(X,y) = r for any other X E S.
~)(s1r)~ is just the i n c l u s i o n
induced
Note
E----@TI--'~T2
triple on S U
that if ~
{y} has
SY
functor.
for which
(in w h i c h
Tr = r
is a triple w i t h T#r ~ r
E ~ r and these
case it is easily
models--
that Tr = E).
T = ~),
this
constants.
constant natural set of natural
we may
between
for which Tr ~ r
owing to the lack of empty
On the other hand,
can't happen.
This
seen--
More-
as its algebras.
define ~ by Tr = r and get a i-I c o r r e s p o n d e n c e triples
The
E is called
if E = r (as w h e n
the set of pseudo-
is justified by the fact that it is the set of transformations
transformations
of U
of U r
of 0 ~ rears its ugly head again).
)U
(whereas
Tr is the
) U -- the i n d e t e r m i n a n c y
Then we may restate
our
results.
Theorem
Ii.
If the set of p s e u d o - c o n s t a n t s set of constants, as above.
then
(ST)~__ = S.
of]~is
Otherwise
equal
it is S
to the
U{y}
-
12-
REFERENCES [Be]
Jo Beck, "The Tripleableness
[La]
Fo W~ Lawvere, Theories",
[Li ]
Theorems,"
(to appear}~
"Functorial Semantics of Algebraic thesis, Columbia University,
F~ E~ Jo Linton,
(1963) ~
"Applied Functorial Semantics,
(to appear in Zur~oh Leotu~e Notes).
II, N
- 1S -
LECTURES ON REGULAR LOCAL RINGS by D.A. Buchsbaum w
Koszul complexes The aim of these lectures is to show how homological methods may be applied to local ring theory.
That homology is tied up naturally with algebra, can be seen easily by looking at the following example:
Let
R
be an element of
be a commutative ring (all rings are assumed to have an identity element), and let R.
Then we may consider the rather trivial complex
>0
where
R
x
> R
R
is by
x,
>0
>0
means multiplication by the element
Ho(K(x)) = R/(x),
and
while
Hl(K(x)) = O:x = (rs
H1
X
>R
x.
>R
x
H0
is a zero divisor.
K(x),
we see that
measures how divisible For an arbitrary R-module
M,
K(x~RM:
X
>0
H 0 ( K ( x ~ M ) = M/xM
and
>0
>M
>0
>M
H I ( K ( x ~ M ) = O:x= [maMlxm=O].
homology groups to tell us how divisible the module is a zero divisor for
>0
If we call this complex
Thus in a sense
tells us whether or not
we may also consider the complex
and observe that
x
M
is by the element
Again we may use these x,
and whether or not
x
M.
Now let us suppose that we have two elements induced by multiplication by
x,y
in
R.
Then we have the map
K(x)
~
> K(x)
y:
>0
>0
>R
>0
>0
>R
X
>R
>0
>R
>0
and it is the most natural thing in the world for homologists to consider the mapping cylinder of this map of complexes:
> 0
where
g(rl, r2) = rlx + r2y
and
> 0
f(r) = (-ry, rx).
H0(K(x,y)) = R/(x,y); H2(K(x,y)) = 0:(x,y) =
> R
f
> F@R
6
> R
Calling this complex K(x,y),
[rER/rx=0=ry].
> 0
we have
Hl(K(x,y)) = [(rl, r2)/rlx+r2y=0]/[ (-ry, rx)].
-
If we suppose that H2(K(x,y)) = 0
and thus
is an integral domain, and that neither
and that
the map sending (x)
R
14
[(rl, r2)/rlx+r2y = 0]
(rl,r2)
> r 2.
x
and
nor
If y
R
y
is zero, we see that
is mapped isomorphically onto
Under this map, the submodule
Hl(K(x,y)) = (x:y)/(x).
would be zero if and only if
x
x:y = [r~R/ryE(x)}
((-ry, rx)}
is sent onto the ideal
were a unique factorization domain, then
were relatively prime.
by
Hl(K(x,y))
Therefore we again see that a certain
amount of homological information is intimately connected with arithmetical questions. We could proceed step by step in this way, building up complexes efficient to consider the following general construction. R-module p df:AA
A
to >
R.
p-1 A A
Then we may define a complex by
df(al~...Aap)= E(-1)
It is well-known, and easy to check, that
df(c~6) = df(=)^~+(-1)Po~df(6).
i+l
K(f)
Let
direct sum of
R
R,
Also, if
then we can define a morphism
with itself s times, and K(f)
f
GEAA
and
^ a. ql
means we omit
8eAA,
a.. l
then
by
Namely, if
f:R s
> R
Xl,...,x s where
Rs
is a sequence denotes the
is defined by f(l, 0,...,0) = Xl,...,f(O,O,...,l ) = x s. K(Xl,...,Xs).
Returning to the general case of a morphism
f:A
> R,
we state two fundamental properties
K(f):
Proposition i.i.
If
a0
Proposition 1.2.
If
x
complexes
where
Before indicating some general properties of this complex, we should
In this case, we denote the complex
of the complex
be a morphism from the P (K(f))p = A A and defining
^ f(ai)al^...^a. ^...^a l pp
df2 = O.
but it is more
> R
by setting
see how it subsumes the sort of thing we have been discussing. of elements of our ring
f:A
K(x,y,z,...),
x:K(f)
is an element of
A,
then
is any element of
R,
and
f(ao)Hp(K(f)) = 0
9~ R
f:A
for all
p ~ O.
a morphism, we have the map of
> K(f):
3 > AA
> AA ~ >
The mapping cylinder of this map of complexes is
K(~)
2 > AA
> A
AA
> A
where
f
> R
> R
> R
~:~R
is defined by
~((a,r)) = f(a)+9x. The proof of Proposition 1 is obtained by writing a homotopy s(al~...^ap) = a0^al^...^ap,
and showing that multiplication by
P s:AA f(a0)
p+l > A A
defined by
is chain homotopic to the
-
zero morphism.
15
-
Proposition 2 is proved by observing that for any module
P P p-i A, A ( ~ R ) ~ A~9 A A.
From Proposition 2, we obtain
Corollary 1.3.
If
f:A
> R
is a morphism,
x
an element of
R,
and
> R
~:~BR
defined
as in Proposition 2, we have the exact sequence:
+X
--> Hp_l(K(f))
> Hp(K(f))
In particular, if
Xl,...,Xs+ 1
> Ho(K(~)) --> 0 .
> Hp_l(K(f)) --> ... --> H0(K(f))
is a sequence of elements of
R,
we have the exact sequence:
(E): ... -> Hp(K(Xl,...,Xs)) --> Hp(K(Xl,...,Xs+l)) -> Hp_l(K(Xl,...,Xs)) ~Xs+~Hp_l(K(Xl,-..,Xs)) --> --"
Using the fact that arbitrary R-module
K(Xl,...,Xs) M,
and
K(Xl,...,Xs+l)
are free chain complexes, we also get, for an
the exact sequence:
(ECM)):----->Hp(M(Xl,..,Xs)) -->Hp(MCXl,.-.,Xs+l)) --> Hp_l(MCXl,...,x s) ~Xs+~Hp_iCMCxl,...,x s) --> ...
where
M(Xl,...,Xs)
is the complex
K(Xl,...,Xs~ ~ .
From the remarks made about the meaning of
we are led to make the following
Hl(K(x,y)),
, definition.
Definition:
Let
M
be an R-module, and
said to be an M-sequence if is not a zero divisor for
Proposition 1.4.
If
a)
Xl,...,x s
M/(Xl,...,Xs)M ~ 0
M/(Xl,...,Xi_l)M.
Xl,...,x s
a sequence of elements of
For
and
s,
for each
i=l, this means that
is s/aM-sequence, then
The proof proceeds by induction on
b)
the case
Then
i, 1 < i < s, xi
Xl,...,x s
the element
being self-evident.
for all
Remark:
It is not true in general that
to show that
xi
p > O.
To go from
one merely uses the exact sequence E(M) to show that Hp(M(Xl,...,Xs) ) = 0 for p > l, x fact that Ho(M(Xl,...,Xs_l) ) s > Ho(M(Xl,...,Xs_l)) is a monomorphism (since Ho(M(Xl,...,Xs_l) ) = M/(Xl,...,Xs_l)M )
is
is not a zero divisor for M.
Hp(M(Xl,...,Xs) ) = 0 s=l
R.
s
to
s+l,
and the
Hl(M(Xl,...,Xs)) = O.
Hp(M(Xl,...,Xs) ) = 0
for all
p > 0
implies that
Xl,...,x s
- 16-
is a M-sequence.
For example, let
for the residue classes of Hp(K(~,~)) = 0 R,
for
x
p > O.
and
in
R,
Xl,...,x s
M(x 1 .... ,Xs) ~ M(x (1),...,x (s)) ~
z
with
where
is a zero divisor in
R,
~
k
we see easily that
Therefore, we obviously have that
and any sequence of elements
clear that
R = k[x,y,x]/y(x-l,z)#
in
R,
a field. x,z
is an R-sequence,
Hp(K(~,~)) = 0
and any R-module
M,
z,x
~
and
so that
(since for any ring
we have
is a permutation of the set
so that
If we write
[1,...,s}).
However,
it is
fails to be an R-sequence.
As a result of the above remark, it is natural to ask when we can prove the converse of Proposition 4. and
To this end, let us suppose that xi, 9 ..,x s
R
Let
R
R.
Then
M
if
x.
is the intersection of
and ~
an ideal in the radical of
M = O.
is in the radical of
R
is noetherian and
M
finitely generated, we conclude that
)
t,
if
in
R.
Let
R
is an epimorphism if and only if
Using these facts, we can prove
be a noetherian ring,
a sequence of elements in the radical of i)
s
we can then conclude that the map
1 >HD(M(Xl,...,~i,...,Xs))
PK (M(Xl,...,~i, .... Xs) ) = O.
Proposition 1.6.
R,
Xl,. 9
X.
HD(M(xI,9
Hp(M(Xl, .... Xs) ) = 0
R.
M
a finitely generated R-module, and
Xl,...,x s
Then
for some
p,
we have
Hp+k(M(Xl,...,xt))
= 0
for all
k ~ 0
1 < t < s:
ii)
if
Hl(M(Xl,...,Xs) ) = O,
hypotheses, we have (or for
R
is a finitely generated R-module for any sequence of elements i
and all
a finitely generated R-module,
Recall that the radical of
a finitely generated R-module,
If we now use our assumptions that Hp(M(Xl,9
R.
M
We now have Nakayama's lemma at our disposal, which says:
be a ring,
such that O?'M = M.
Moreover,
is a noetherian ring,
elements in the radical of
all the maximal ideals of
Lemma 1.5.
R
Xl,...,x s
then
Xl,...,x s
is an M-sequence.
is an M-sequence if and only if
Thus, under these
Hp(M(Xl,9
= O
for all
p > O
E(M),
together
p = 1).
The proofs of these statements are obtained by repeated use of the exact sequence with the observations immediately preceding the Proposition9
Corollar~ i~ only if
The hypotheses being as in Proposition 6, we have
x (1) ..... x (s)
Corollar~ 1.8.
If
R
is an M-sequence for every permutation
is a noetherian ring,
M
Xl,...,x s ~
of
is an M-sequence if and
[13...,s ).
a finitely generated R-modnle,
~
a prime ideal of
R
-
such that
M
= M~RR~# 0
(i.e. y
which is an M-sequence, then
Remarks:
In general, if
we denote by R,
and
RS
noetherian.
R
is noetherian and ~
ring with one maximal ideal. is flat over
w
R
R
S
a sequence of elements in
with respect to Rs
by
R~,
R~,
is an
M -sequence.
a multiplicatively stable subset of S.
R~.
However, i f ~
If
a prime ideal, then
In the case of
R~
R
S
of
R,
is a prime ideal of
is noetherian, then
is a local ring
i.e.
the unique maximal ideal is ~ R ~
for any multiplicatively stable subset
.
RS
is
a noetherian Finally,
RS
R.
Local rin~s We shall now assume that
will be denoted by of
E
is
ideal of
that
~
we have
Let
E
el,...,e t
Proof.
k;
R
is a local ring, with maximal ideal
~.
The residue field
all R-modules will be assumed finitely generated.
and all proper ideals of
R#
Lemma 2.1.
E~E
= 0
R
are contained in
if and only if
E = 0
~.
If
E
generate
E~E
R/~
In this case, the radical is an R-module and ~
an
because of Nakayama's Lemma.
be an R-module (always finitely generated), and as a k-vector space.
Then
el,...,e t
el,...,e t
elements of
generate
E
E
such
as an R-module.
Although the proof of this is well-known# we will reproduce it here since it serves as a
prototype for so many others. E
Xl,...,x s
is any commutative ring~ and
, we denote the ring of quotients
If
and
considered as elements in
the ring of quotients of
S=R-~
-
is in Supp (M)),
Xl,...,Xs,
R
17
generated by
el,...,e t.
is the cokernel of F/~F
F
> E/~
> E.
L = 0
Tensoring over > O.
so that
F
i.e.
E
Lemma 2.3.
If
E
such that
Ker g
~E
with
> E
of rank
and map it onto the submodule of
F
> E
is exact and
where
L/~ E.
contains a minimal generating set of
E;
E/~E
over
k.
F
el,...,e t
so
generate
is an R-module, there exists a free module ~F.
> 0
is now an epimorphism,
L
= O.
any
This number is equal to
Moreover, any subset of
may be extended to a minimal generating set of
is contained in
> L
we have the exact sequence
> E/~E
> 0
E
k,
t
have the same number of elements.
the dimension of the vector-space
independent modulo
R
However, F/~F
Any generating set of an R-module
two minimal generating sets of [E~:k]
F
We then have the exact sequence
> L~L
This tells us that
Corollary 2.2.
We take a free module
E
linearly
E.
and an epimorphism
g:F
>E
-
Lemma 2.4.
If
E
is an R-module such that
Lemma 2.5.
For every R-module
Proposition 2.6. If
R
E,
18
-
Tor~(k,E) = 0,
then
E
is free.
hdRE ~ h % k .
is a local ring,
gl.dim R = h ~ k .
The proofs of all the above statements are completely straightforward.
For instance, 2.3 depends
on nothing deeper than the fact that an epimorphism of a vector space onto another of the same dimension is an isomorphism. generating set of
One then chooses
F
to be free on the number of generators in a minimal
E.
The main result we are heading for now is that dimension of
R
~:k]
<_ gl.dim R,
i.e.
that the global
is never less than the minimal number of generators of the maximal ideal of
R.
The idea of the proof is the following We take a minimal generating set K(Xl,...,Xn).
di(Xi) c Z~Xi_1
this resolution with K(Xl,...,Xn) we see that
~.~.
k
R = h~k
and
Thus
f.
morphism
~:X k
K(Xl,...,Xn)
X1
> Xk_ 1
Xp+ 1
k:
>0
> k
is a subcomplex of this resolution. TorR(k,k)= X p ~ .
K(Xl, ...,Xn)
Tensoring
Since
is non-zero in dimension
n,
and we have the desired result using the facts that
> XI
is of the form:
n > AR n
8 n> ...
2 8^ >AR n ~
of our resolution to be
Assume now that
> ...
and form the complex
n = ~/~:k].
We may therefore choose morphism
> R
K(Xl,...,Xn)
hdRk >_ n
Z~,
%-
xI
makes the boundary maps zero, so that
TornR(k,k) ~ O.
a free module
% .> > x2 --
and such that
0
Xp
% x3
is a subcomplex of the resolution, and
The complex
iv)
of the maximal ideal
We then show that we can find a free resolution of
>
such that
Xl,..., x n
Xl,...,Xp
restricted to > R
such that
> k i) - iv)
Rn
Rn
with
f-~ R
dl:X 1
have been found such that k AR n > 0
is
> R
defined to be the k i) Xk = X~ ~ ARn: ii) the
8k; i i i ) K e r ~ C ~ k
is exact.
are true with
If k
p ( n,
and iv)
we will show that we can find
replaced by
p + 1.
Our conditions i)
- 19 -
P+IRn A
and ii) tell us that the composition is contained in {Sp+l(s
% = Ker % .
^...^ a. )} ~p+l
as showing that if
~Zp C ~ X p
Now
8p+l(~)
Suppose, then, that
~Pn
then each
5p+l: A R n
> PR n
R n.
is in
8p+l( )
Rn
is to say that
p + l . p+l p+l A R~A R n = R / ~ @ A En,
u
~p+l
is zero. Thus p+l are a basis of A R n,
then
But this is the same
ip+l is in ~. is such that Since
8p+l( ) is
%C~,
in
~Z,
we have
n
we must have
8--p+l: A R * ~ A
R~
8p+l( ) a ~2~-ARn.
>
Rn
Rn
is a monomorphism, we are done.
i(~) = 0 and thus that ~
p p and ~I6Rn/~2~R n = ~
5p+l(l~AiRn)
> Xp_ I
That is, we want to show that if
is in ~ % .
is in AR ,
induces a map
If we can show that
~Zp.
p+l in A R n
8p+l( ) P
= Z~-AR- ~ ~ZfCxp. Since
8p+l( A R n) c
P {Eil~...^ s i } p+l
are linearly independent modulo
+I) s ~Zp,
d P
> X
Rn
-- ~ 7i I ... IP + I " ail~...^a.lp+I
p+l is in ~ A R n.
then
P
We will show that if
^...^ s
Z 7i I .. . ip+ . 1 8p+i(s
_•
@ PR n
= 0
or ~ E ~ A
and the map
5p+ 1
since
For to say that
P+lRn"
But
sends the basis element
^
9 Clearly this map is a monomorphism, to r.(-l)J+ixi | s ^...^s ^...^ s lI lj ip+ 1 j
i| s Ip+l and we are done.
Since we have shown that
{ 8p+l(ail ~ ...^ s
)]
are linearly independent modulo
that these elements may be chosen as part of a minimal generating set for generating set
[Sp+l(ail~... ^ s
)} U [Zl,...,Zq}.
Letting
X~l
%,
~%,
we know
i.e. we have a minimal
be the free module on
q
~p+l generators, we have Xp+ 1
> Zp
is exact.
p+l A R n ~ Xp+ I > ~
Xp+ I
mapping onto
is clearly in ~/~(p+l and
Zp.
The kernel of the map
Xp+ 1
> Xp
> ...
> X1 ~>R~>k'
Thus we have completed the inductive step, and we have proved
Theorem 2.6.
If
R
is a local ring, then ~ : k ]
<_ gl.dim R.
Our next objective is to define the dimension (or Krull dimension) of a local ring show that
dim R < ~/~2 :kS.
R,
and
To do this, we shall use the method of Hilbert-Samuel polynomials which
>0
-
20-
we introduce in a slightly more general setting now.
w
Hilbert-Samuel We let
Z+
Pol~nomials.
denote the set of positive
integers,
and let
G
will be the group of integers or the Grothendieck
group of some category of modules.
Definitions.
f
elements
have
Let
f:Z +
ao,...,a d
f(n) =
> G
in
d n Z (i)ai i=O
G
be a function,
such that for all
is called a polynomial
n s Z+,
n
Generally,
be an abelian group.
function if there are
sufficiently large (i.e.
n >> 0), we
n! where
(~)
+
denotes the binomial coefficient
If
f:Z
>G
i](n-i)]
is any function, we define
Zif:Z+
difference
(functio~ of
f.
Lemma 3.1.
A function
f:Z +
> G
For any integer
> G
by
Zif(n) = f(n+l)-f(n). s > i,
we define
is a polynomial
Zif
is ca/led the first
~sf = ~(~s-lf).
function if and only if
~f
is a polynomial
function.
Proof. all
If
f
is a polynomial
n >> O.
n+l
z[( i
Consequently,
n >> 0
we have
is a polynomial
Thus
if
L~f(n)=
n >> O, Ag(n) = 0
f(n) =
for all
d n ~ (i)ai for some i=O Zkf(n) = f(n+l)-f(n) =
f(n) =
ao,...,a d
G,
and
n
z(n+l)a -i
in
- i
- z - () i-ai
d
n
Conversely,
have
fUnction, we have
so that
d+l n r (i)ai i=O
d • ( )b i i=O g(n)
for
for
n >> O,
is a constant
a O.
function.
define
g(n)=
f(n)-
Thus, letting
d n ~. (i+l)bi. i=O
a i = bi_ I
for
Then for
i > O,
we
n >> O.
We have proved Lemma 3.1 in detail, general than the usual one.
since the definition of polynomial function is slightly more
However, with 3.1 established,
we shall only state the facts we need,
and omit the proofs.
Lemma 3.2.
If
d d' f(n) = iZ= (i)ai = iE= (i)ai n n . 0 0
Thus, the degree,
d,
of
f
is a polynomial
is a well defined integer,
function,
then
d = d'
and the coefficients
ai
and
of
a. = a~. : l f
are
uniquely determined. Now consider a commutative noetherian ring
R,
and let ~
be a full abelian subcategory of the
- 21
category of R-modules.
For each integer
-
s = 0,1,2,...,
let
be the category of finitely s
generated graded
R[Xl,...,Xs]-modules
E =
E E v_>O
i)
if
s = O,
E
such that ~
is in ~
for all
u;
is in ~
for all
u
v
s > O,
if
E~
and t h e g r a d e d
X
modules Finally, let
fo
.
>~E
)
and Coker (rE
K(o~),
of
i.e.
fo
s >~E
)
are in ~ s
to an abelian group
is additive
G
with respect
i"
which factors
to exact sequences
Then
Theorem 3.3. fE
X
s
be a function from the objects of ~
through the Grothendieck group, in ~
Ker (?E
R [ X 1 , . . . , X s - 1]
Let
E = ZEv
be an object in ~ s
and define
is a polynomial function of degree less than or equal to An example of such a set-up occurs when
R-modules of finite length.
R
In that case, an
finitely generate~ and if each
E
fE:Z+
> G
by
fE(~) = fo(Ev).
Then
s-l.
is a local ring, and ~
R[Xl,...,Xs]-module
is the full subcategory of
E = E~
is an R-module of finite length.
is i n ~ s
if it is
We may then choose
G
to be
v
the group, Z, of integers and
fo(E) = length of
E.
This is of course the most usual example.
see that it is not the only example, we may c h o o s e ~ R-modules, and
G
Corollar[ 3.4.
If
to be
R
K(~)
is a local ring,
containing some power ~n and the function
itself with
E
fo
~ (E):Z+
> Z
to be the category of all finitely generated
the usual map.
a finitely generated R-module and ~
of the maximal ideal defined by
To
then
E/[E
an ideal of
R
is an R-module of finite length,
x~(E;v)= length of
E~VE
is a polynomial function
whose degree is less than or equal to To see why this is a corollary of 3.3 we observe that we have exact sequences
and therefore R[Xl,...,XsS ~(E)
Remark:
~ ( E ; ~ ) - - l e n g t h of ~ E $ ~ + l E . where
s-- ~ / ~
The graded module
:kS, and each ~ V E ~ V + l E
andS2
is a module over
is an R-module of finite length.
is a polynomial function of degree <_ s-l, and hence
If ~ i
~/E~+IE
x~E)
Thus
is what we claimed it to be.
are two ideals containing some powers of the maximal ideal ~,
i.e.
if
-
nI ~i
n2
D ~
and ~ 2 D
~
,
X n(E )
and
x~(E)
~(E).
~(R).
If
have the same degree.
R
Thus, if
~
n
<4
< ~'
n,
we must have
and hence equality.
is a local ring, the dimension of
The dimension of an R-module
In particular, they
equal.
This is seen easily by observing that for any integer
deg(~n(E)) ~ deg(X~E)) ~ deg(%(E))
Definition.
-
)(~j.(E) and )<,~,2(E) are
then the degrees of
are all equal to the degree of
29
E
R
is the degree of the polynomial function
is the degree of the polynomial function
a noetherian ring and ~
is a prime ideal of
R,
Proposition 3.5.
be a local ring, and let
then the height of T
X~(E).
If
is the dimension of
R
is
R~.
I
Let
R
~
of
s
be the smallest number of elements required to l
generate an ideal In particular,
dim R ~
R
which contains some power of the maximal ideal
~.
Then
dim R ~ s.
~:k].
Although we will not be using this fact immediately, it is important to note that for a local ring
R,
the following integers are equal: a)
the dimension of
R;
b)
the smallest number of elements required to generate an ideal containing a power of the maximal ideal;
c)
the length of the longest chain of prime ideals in ~0
3~1D'''D'~h
is defined to be the integer
R
where the length of the chain
h.
The proof that these three integers are equal is not completely trivial. to Zariski-Samuel,
The reader is referred
Commutative Algebra, for those details about noetherian rings which are mentioned
here but not proved. For various reasons, it is useful to be able to compare the dimension of a module local ring
R
with that of
E/(x)E
if
x
extremely helpful to know what happens to
is an element of dim E/(x)E
when
R. x
E
over a
From our point of view, it is is not a zero divisor for
E.
To
handle this problem, we quote the Artin-Rees Theorem:
Theorem 3.6. M,
and
I
Let
R
be a noetherian ring,
an ideal of
R.
M
a finitely generated R-module,
Then there exists an integer
h > 0
M'
a submodule of
such that for all
n ~ h
we have
(InM) N M' = I n - h ( I ~ N M').
Corollary 3.7.
If
R
is a local ring and
x
is an element of the maximal ideal
~
which is a non-
-
zero divisor for an R-module
E,
23
-
there is an integer
h > 0
such that for all
u > h,
MVE:x c ~ - ~
where ~ E : x = [e s E/xe s The proof depends upon the Artin-Rees Theorem and the easy observation that x(~E;x) = ~ E
D (x)E. For then we have
from which we conclude:
Proposition 3.8. Let
If we let = E/(~V,x)E,
R
be a local ring, If
x
ThUS length
an R-module, and
and
and ~ = ~ ( x ) ,
X~v-h
x
an element of ~.
E, we have
Then
dim E/(x)E ~ dim E -1
and
> (~,x)E~E
EI(~,x)E = ~(E/~E)
for
x a~,
Since
length
so that
d i m E ~ dim E -i.
h
and all
length
- length
> E/(~,x)E
E~E.
But
Since
> 0
(~V,x)E/~VE ~ (x)E/~VE A (x)E ~ xE/xC~E:x)
with equality holding if so that length
(E/~E:x)
v ~ h. (E~-hE)
x
x
E~E:x
E / ~ E - length (Z~,x)E/~E ~ length
If, however,
= length
suitable fixed (EKE)
E~E:x,
we know that ~ - I E c ~ E : x
E/(~V,x)E = length
(~,x)E~E)
> E/~VE
- ~(~,x)E~V~E).
( ~ , x ) E / ~ E ~ length
E.
we are interested in the length of
we have an exact sequence:
we have length
length
E
is not a zero divisor for
E = E/(x)E,
0
Thus
O (x)E) = ~ ( - h ( ~ : x ~
dim E/(x)E = dim E -1.
Proof. E~E
N (x)E = ~ - h ( ~
~E:x c~-~.
dim E/(x)E ~ d i m E -1. hence
x(~E:x) = ~ E
is not a zero divisor ~ length E / ~ - ~ .
E/~VE - length
is not a zero divisor for
E,
we have
and by 3.7, length (E/~UE:x) ~ length
Thus length
E/(~U,x)E =
length
which immediately implies that
E~V+IE
(E~V-hE)
for
(E/Z~E) - length (~,x)E/~VE dim E < dim E -i. m
In the above proof we said we were interested in the length of E~E
to emphasize the fact that
= R/(x).
dim E
as an R-module is the same as
This is mainly to ensure that when
dimension of the local ring
R.
E~E
Of course,
E = R, dim R
E~E~
instead of the length of dim E
as an R-module where
as an R-module is seen to be the
E~E
As an immediate consequence of 3.8 we have
Corollar~r 3-9. Let
R
be a local ring,
E
an R-module, and
Xl,...,x s
dim E/(Xl,...,Xs)E = dim E-s.
an E-sequence.
Then
-
In particular,
w
-
s <_ dim E.
Codimension and finitistic global dimension We will now let
such that E/~E | if
24
E/Z~'E ~ O. R~
~ O,
XlJ...,x s
6KR~
R
be a noetherian ring, Since
a finitely generated R-module,
there is some prime ideal
and this prime ideal ~
obviously contains
is an E-sequence contained in ~ ,
and thus, by 3.9,
in ~
E/~'E # O,
E
s ~ dim E @
~
.
is bounded, and any E-sequence in ~
then
~in
R
anG
~
an ideal in
such that
grC. From Corollary 1.8, we see that
Xl,...,x s
is also an
E @R R ~ -
sequence in
Hence the number of elements in an E-sequence contained may be extended to a maximal E-sequence in g~'.
prove that any two maximal E-sequences in ~
We shall
have the same number of elements but first we must
review the notion of associated prime ideals.
Definition.
If
monomorphism
E
is an R-module, a prime ideal ~
R~
associated to
> E.
Proof.
E,
denoted by
Ass(E),
E
if there is some
is the set of all primes
E.
Using the fact that
Lemma 4.1.
The associator of
is said to be associated to
If
E
R
is noetherian, we have
is an R-module, then
Clearly if
E = 0
we have
Ass(E) = ~
Ass(E) = ~.
if and only if
To show that
the set of all ideals (~' such that there is a monomorphism empty, and thus there is a maximal such ideal &~O"
E # 0 R/6~"
E = O.
implies > E.
Ass(E) ~ ~,
one considera
This set of ideals is not
One then proves easily that such an ideal
O~"0
is necessarily prime. Another useful lemma is the following:
Lemma 4.2.
Let
0
> E'
> E
> E"
be an exact sequence of R-modules.
Then
Ass(E) : Ass(E') U Ass(E"). The proof of this lemma is trivial, and one can now prove
Proposition 4.3. is a finite set.
If
R
is a noetherian ring and
E
is a finitely generated R-module, then
Ass(E)
-
Proof.
25
One first proves this for cyclic modules,
ideal of
R.
i . e . modules of the form
R/g~
where
is an
One then assumes that the theorem is true for modules generated by less than
elements, and assuming that 0
-
> E'
> E
E
is generated by
> E"
0
where
el,...,en+ 1 E'
n + i
one considers the exact sequence
is generated by
el,...,e n.
Applying 4.2 one
gets the desired result.
Definition.
If
hei6ht of R,
E
R
is a noetherian ring and
to be min height ~ w h e r e
~
E
a finitely generated R-module, we define the
runs through all primes in
we generally abuse notation and call the height of
R/~
Ass(E).
If ~
is an ideal of
the height of the i d e a l S .
An important result relating the height of an ideal with the number of generators of the ideal, is the Krull Principal Ideal Theorem. ideal generated by elements or equal to Ass(R/~),
r.
This states that if
Xl,...Xr,
In particular,
R
is a noetherian ring, and ~ i s
then any minimal prime of
height ~
~ r.
Ass(R/~)
has height less than
This follows from 3.5 since i f ~
then ~R~pdg contains some power of ~ R ~
and thus height
7=
an
is minimal in
dim R~o ~ r.
# Remarks:
l)
For any R-module
E,
the set of zero divisors of
E is the union of all primes in
Ass(E). (2)
Thus, if
E
is a finitely generated R-module (with R noetherian) and if ~
that every element of ~ that
~e
c ~ R/~ R
= 0.
For if ~ i s
for some ~ R/~
7
a Ass(E)
> R/~
If the ideal ~
E,
as above, then ~ (since
and a monomorphism
> R/~ (3)
is a zero divisor of
> E
R/y
then there is a non-zero element
c U7
Ass(E)
is an ideal such
where ~
is finite).
> E.
runs through
e
Ass(E)
of
E
such
and hence
We therefore have the eplmorphism
The image of 1 under the composite map
is the desired element
e E E.
in Remark 2 above is a maximal ideal then ~
a Ass(E).
We are now ready to prove the main theorem of this section.
Theorem 4.4.
Let
R
elements
Xl,...,x n
s+q = n,
where
q
be a noetherian ring, such that
E/g~E ~ O.
E Let
an R-module, and ~ yl,...,y s
an ideal of
R
generated by
be a maximal E-sequence in 0/'. Then
is the dimension of the highest non-vanishing homology of the complex
Furthermore,
HqCECxl'''"Xn)) ~ (Yl'''"Ys)E:~/Cyl''''~s )E
E(Xl,...,Xn)
-
Proof.
The proof proceeds by induction on
a zero divisor for ~e
= O.
Since
E
s.
26
When
-
s=O,
it means that every element of ~
so that by Remark 2 above, there is a non-zero element
Hn(E(Xl,...,Xn) ) = 0 : ~
O,
we see that
q = n
e
in
E
is
such that
and
Hn(E(Xl'''"Xn)) = ( YI'''" Ys )E:LT//( YI'''" Ys )E = 0: ~ . When
s > O,
~e consider the exact sequence
0
> E
Yl
> E
> E
Yl H~+l(g(Xl,...,Xn)) where
~
> H~(E(Xl,...,Xnl)
is zero since
Yl
and using induction, we have s+q = n.
~( YI'''" Ys )E:
. Thus
Noting that
(s-l) + g = n.
Finally, since
and multiplication by
is in ~
H~_l(E(Xl,...,Xn) ) ~ H~(E(Xl,...,Xn) ).
have
>
is the dimension of the highest non-vanishing homology group of
H~_l(E(Xl,...,Xn)
Yl
E(Xl,...,Xn). on
. . .
Thus,
H~(E(Xl,...,Xn) ) and on
H~(E(Xl,...,Xn)) = 0
Y2'''" Ys
and get the
>
> Hq(E(Xl,...,Xn))
H~+l(E(Xl,...,Xn) ) = O, H~(E(Xl,...,Xn) ) ~ 0,
> 0
while
is a maximal E-sequence in 6~ ,
Since, however, we have just shown that
q = T-l,
we
H~(E(Xl,...,Xn) ) ~ ( Y,'''" Ys )~: ~ / ( Y,'''" Ys )~
/( YI'''" Ys )E'
and since
Hq(E(Xl,...,Xn) ) =
H~_l(E(Xl,...,Xn)) ~ H~(E(Xl,...,xn
we have
Hq(E(Xl'''"Xn))~ ( YI'''" Ys )E: ~ / (
Corollary 4.5.
If
R, E, and ~
YI'''" Ys )E"
are as in 5.4, then any two maximal E-sequences in ~
have the
same length.
Definition. depth (~:E).
The length of a maximal E-sequence in ~ If
R
is called the L"-depth of
is a local ring, then codim E = depth (~:E)
where
~
E,
denoted by
is the maximal ideal of
R.
An important consequence of 4.4 is
Theorem 4.6. Let
R
be a local ring, and
E
an R-module such that
h~E <
~.
Then
codim R = h ~ E + codim E
Proof.
Let ~ = (Xl,...,Xn) , where
~
is the maximal ideal of
of the highest non-vanishing homology group of
K(Xl,...,Xn),
R.
and by
Denote by qE
q
the dimension
the corresponding integer
-
for the complex
E(Xl,...,Xn).
9.7
-
and codim E = n-qE,
Since codim R = n-q
we want to show that
qE-q = h ~ E . Now when
h~E
exact sequence
= O,
0
E
is free and clearly
> L
> F
> E
qE = q" > 0
Suppose that
with
F
h~E
~ i.
Then we have an
a free module, and
h~E = 1 + h~L.
This gives us an exact sequence:
> HqL(L(Xl,...,Xn))
Hl+qL(E(Xl,''',Xn))
> HqL(E(Xl,...,Xn))
> HqL(F(Xl,...,Xn))
> HqL_l(L(Xl,...,Xn)).
By induction on
hdRE ,
qL- q > O,
HqL(F(Xl,...,Xn) ) = 0
then
we know that
Ht+qL(E(Xl,...,Xn) ) = 0 done.
for all
qL- q = hdRL and thus
t > i.
so what must be shown is that Hl+qL(E(Xl,...,Xn) ) ~ O,
In this case, we may assume that If
YI'''"
Ys
L
and
F
qL = q'
i.e.
when
have been chosen so that
If
while clearly
Thus in this case, we would have
Our problem, then, is to resolve the case when
i + qL = qE"
qE = i + qL hdRL = 0
and we'd be
or
L
is free.
L c~F.
is a maximal R-sequence, it is also a maximal F- and L-sequence, and 4.4 tells us
that
and the map
Hq(L(Xl'''"Xn))
= ( YI'''"
Ys )L:~/( YI'''"
Ys )L
Hq(F(Xl'''"Xn))
= ( YI'''"
Ys )F:~/( YI'''"
Ys )F
Hq(F(Xl,...,Xn) )
Hq(L(Xl,...,Xn) )
( YI'"" Ys
( YI'''"
YI'"" Ys)L
is the natural map of
Ys )F:~/( YI'''"
Ys )F"
If we show that this map is not
a monomorphism, we are done. Since Since
L
( YI'''" is free,
w s zL - ( YI'''" ~ 0
in
Ys ) : ~ D
( YI' " " "' ys) ,
zL~
( YI'''"
Ys )L'
we have
( YI'''"
Ys )L"
Ys )F
zLc
w a ( YI'''"
Ys )L:~/( YI'''"
( YI''" ~' Ys )F:~/( YI'''"
But
there is a
Ys )L"
monomorphism, and the proof is complete.
z~F c ( YI'''"
Ys )L:~
However,
so that our map
z #( YI'''"
w
but
Ys ) with
Ys )F"
w # ( YI'''"
z~c
( YI'''"
Ys )"
Choosing an element Ys )L
and thus
is mapped to zero in
Hq(L(Xl,...,Xn) )
> Hq(F(Xl,...,Xn) )
is not a
-
A particular consequence of 4.6 is that if h~E
( %
then
h~E
Definition:
If
R
f.gl.dim R,
to be
28
R
-
is a local ring~ and
E
an R-module such that
~ codim R.
is a commutative ring, we define the finitistic ~lobal dimension of sup h ~ E
where
E
R# written
ranges over all finitely generated R-modules of finite
homological dimension. Before winding up this section, we state the following technical lemma:
Lemma 4.7.
If
R
is a local ring,
is not a zero divisor for
Proposition 4.8.
Proof. with
If
R
E,
then
R,
a finitely generated R-module, and
x s ~
an element which
hdRE/XE = 1 + hdRE.
is a local ring, then
We have already seen that s = co~m
E
f.gl.dim R = co~4m R.
f. gl.dim R ~ codim R.
we have (by 4.7)
h~2R/( Y I ' ' ' "
However, if
Ys ) = s = codim
YI'''"
Ys
is an R-sequence,
and hence the equality.
Putting 2.6, 3.5, 3.9, and 4.8 together, we obtain
Theorem 4. 9 .
If
R
is a local ring, we have
f.gl.dimR=
w
codlin R ~_ dim R (_ ~ : k ]
~_ gl.dim R.
Re6ular local rin~s. We are now ready to apply what we have done to the study of s me important properties of regular
local rings.
Definition.
A local ring
R
is regular if
dim R = ~/Y~-:kJ.
The following is a well-known property of regular local rings.
Proposition 5.1. maximal ideal Xl,...,x n
~.
Let
R
be a regular local ring, and
Then for each integer
L,
the ideal
is a (maximal) R-sequence.
Our first main result about regular local rings is:
Xl,...,x n
a minimal generating set of the
(Xl,...,xi)
is a prime ideal.
In particular,
-
Theorem 5.2.
A local ring
R
29
-
is regular if and only if
gl.dim R < ~.
If
R
is regular,
gl.dim R = dim R.
Proof.
If
R
is regular, 5.1 tells us that
gl. dim R = n < ~. dim R
Conversely, if
h ~ k = h~R/(Xl,...,Xn) = n = dim R,
gl.dim R < m,
then
gl.dim R = f~
R
and hence
and by 4.9, we have
=
Using this characterization of regular local rings, we obtain
Theorem 5.B.
If
R
is a regular local ring and ~
is a prime ideal of
R,
then
R~,
is a regular
local ring.
Proof. gl.dim R
L e n a ~.4. If
= h % / ~ R
R
~ hdRR~
<
is a regular local ring,
~.
E
Thus
R
is regular.
a finitely generated R-module, and ~ s
Ass(E),
then
hdRE ~_ height ~ .
Proof.
We have
hdRE >_ hdR. E ~
maximal ideal of
R~
,
Since ~
w/ha~e
codim E
R~ = 0
is obviously in as an
Ass(E ),
Ry-module.
Thus
and ~ R hdR
E~
is the
= codim R ~
dim Rnf = h e i g h t ~ . A straightforward application of the Krull Principal Ideal Theorem yields the following
Lemma 5.5.
If
R
is a noetherian ring, ~
an ideal of
is not a zero divisor for
R/Q( and
particular, if
is an R-sequence, then
Lemma 5.6.
Proof.
Let
zero-divisor for
R/(Xl,...,xt) ,
Ass(R/(Xl,...,xt) ).
height~ and thus
But if
hdRR/(Xl,...,xt) = t. s = t.
R.
~
Then
.
t = depth (6~;R).
we must have ~
x
an element of
R
such that In
height (Xl,...,Xs) = s.
depth (~;R) ~height ~
be a maximal R-sequence in 6~ i.e.
and
then height (~,x) ~ 1 + height 6~.
be an ideal in a regular local ring
By localizing we know that
Xl,...,x t
~s
Xl,...,x s
R/(~',x) ~ 0,
R,
depth (
Suppose
;R) = height
height 6E= s
and let
Since every element of ~
is a
contained in some prime ideal
E Ass(R/(Xl,...,xt) ) we have, by 5.4,
Thus, since 6~ c 7
implies height ~" ~ height ~ ,
we have
s
-
Le-~a 5:7. for
E.
If
Let ~
R
be a noetherian ring,
is in
Ass(E)
ideal ~ " ~ Ass(E/xE)
Definition.
and ~ '
E
30
-
a finitely generated R-module, and
is a prime ideal containing
(~,x),
x
a non-zero divisor
then there is a prime
such that ~' D ~ " D ~ .
We say a chain of prime ideals ~ 0 c ~ l c ... C ~ n
is no prime lying strictly between ~ i
and ~ i + l "
is saturated if for each
i
there
We say a ring satisfies the saturated chain
condition for prime ideals (s.c.c.) if any two saturated chains of primes between any two given primes ~c~'
have the same length.
Theorem 9.8.
Proof.
Every regular local ring satisfies the saturated chain condition for prime ideals.
It obviously suffices to show that if ~
Suppose, then, that
s = height ~ .
Clearly there is an element there is a prime ~ "
Remarks:l)
is saturated, then height ~ '
Then there is an R-sequence
Xs+ 1
in ~ ' - ~
E Ass(R/(Xl, ...,Xs+l) )
we cannot have ~ " = ~ .
c ~'
Thus y "
= ~'
such that
Xl,...,x s
Xl,...,Xs+ 1
such that ~ ' ~ " D ~ .
and height ~ '
= 1 + height
which is maximal in ~ .
is an R-sequence. Since height
Using 9-7,
" = s+l > height
= s+l = 1 + h e i g h t ~ .
By constructing a local ring that does not satisfy the s.c.c., Nagata was able to show that
not every local ring is a factor ring of a regular local ring.
For clearly, a factor ring of a ring
satisfying the s.c.c, must also satisfy the s.c.c. 2)
We see that if
3)
It can be shown that if
element of
R,
R
is a regular local ring, then
then height ~ , x )
R
dim R/4s
satisfies the s.c.c, and if ~
+
h e i g h t ~ = n = dim R. is an ideal of
R
and
x
and
~ 1 + height ~ .
we now come to the Cohen-Macaulay Theorem:
Theorem 5. 9 . Let
R
is unmixed
every prime ~ ~ Ass (R/6~)
Proof.
(i.e.
has height
The main point of the proof is to show that
follows easily. s=l
be a regular local ring, and 6~'= (Xl,...,Xs)
To show that
Xl,...,x s
s),
Xl,...,x s
and
an ideal of height s. Xl,...,x s
is an R-sequence.
is an R-sequence, for then the rest
is an R-sequence# we proceed by induction.
we are done (since a regular local ring is an integral domain).
s = height (Xl,...,Xs) ~ 1 + height (Xl,...,Xs_l).
But then
Then
Assuming
s > l,
Certainly when we have
s-1 ~ height (Xl,...,Xs_l) 5 s-1
so by
- 31-
induction We have divisor for
Xl,...,Xs_ 1
R/(Xl,...,Xs.1)
is an R-sequence.
It is then trivial to show that
xs
is not a zero
(by using a height argument), and so we have the result.
We end these lectures with an outline of a proof of the fact that every regular local ring is a unique factorization domain.
The proof given here is due to Kaplansky and is extremely elegant.
As
the reader ~-ill see, the tone of the proof is very different from most of what has gone before.
It
would perhaps be nice if a proof could be found using the notion of R-sequences.
Definitions.
An element
x
of an integral domain
prime ideal.
An integral domain is a unique factorization domain (ufd), if every non-unit of
a finite product of prime elements of
Theorem 9.10.
is a prime element if the ideal
(x)
is a R
is
R.
Every regular local ring
Outline of proof.
R
R
is a unique factorization domain.
We have already noted that a regular local ring is an integral domain.
Also,
R
contains prime elements since every element which is part of a minimal generating set for the maximal ideal of
R
is prime.
Let
x
be such a prime element and let
be the multiplicative set consisting
of all non-negative powers of
x.
Then it can be shown that
UFD.
RS
is a UFD.
Since
~
every prime ideal of height l) is principal.
Hence we must show that
that every minimal prime ideal of
(i.e.
RS
R
S
is a UFD if and only if
RS
is a
is a noetherian domain, it suffices to show If we could
show that every such ideal were free, it would follow that it is principal.
As a first attempt at
showing freeness, we show that minimal prime ideals are projective.
be such an ideal, and
any maximal ideal of that
R'
or
of
R',
Then since
is a regular local ring.
induction on dim R, R~
R' = ~ .
R~
we see that
R~
Since
hdR,~= 0
is a UFD.
h~,~
and ~
is an R'-module, then
E'
E
E
R'
over
R, E
we can find free R'-modules
and all maximal ideals ~Z
of
dim R,
so that by
being either a minimal prime ideal of
when }~
ranges over all maximal ideals
are principal.
R'
To see this, we first observe that if
For
we obtain one for
E' = E | R' E'
for some
by tensoring with
is a projective R'-module, then
is a projective ideal it is easy to see that
p > 1
dim R ~ <
we have
is projective.
particular, it is easy to see now that if i.e.
R~
has a finite free resolution.
and choosing a free resolution for
of length one
Hence y R ~ ,
= sup h
Next we show that projective ideals of E'
5 gl.dim. R' < gl. dim. R < %
Furthermore, it is easy to see that
we know that
itself, is free.
gl.dim. R ~
Let ~
E
R-module R'.
E,
In
has a free resolution
F 0 and F 1 such that E ~ F 1 = F O. Finally, when P P P AE = 0 for p > 1 since ( A E ) ~ A E ~ = 0 for
(because
E~
is principal for all such ~ ) .
Applying the
-
fact that
n A(A~
have
n 1 AF O ~ A E
R'~
p B) ~ E A A @ @
n-1 A Fl~
all projective ideals of have shown that
R'
n-p A B
R'
is a UFD.
32
to the situation
1 AE@
R'
(since
are principal, Thus
R,
F1
-
E~
F I = F O,
and letting n
must have rank n-l),
= rank of
and thus
and all minimal prime ideals of
R'
1 R' ~ A E
FO,
we
= E.
Since
are projective, we
too, is a UFD, and the outline of the proof is complete.
Since all the results mentioned in these notes are known, I have not given a detailed bibliography. Most of what has been said has its source in papers by Serre and Auslander-Buchsbaumwith material and some amplification in the already mentioned volume by Zariski-Samuel. on polynomial functions is new and not yet in print. concerned with multiplicities,
background
Perhaps the material
It will appear in a paper by Marshall Fraser
but the elements and purely formal properties of generalized polynomial
fUnctions have also been discussed by P. Wagreich.
-
CATEGORIES
33
-
OF MODELS W I T H
INITIAL
OBJECTS
by Dr. R. Fittler
INTRODUCTION The c o n s t r u c t i o n erations viewed
in the sense
as a prototype
universal
structures.
of free algebras w i t h
of Birkhoff
(cf.
for the c o n s t r u c t i o n In order
map
i: N
) I~I
freely g e n e r a t e d
(underlying
is a uniquely
determined
theory
.
Usually
such that
algebra
homomorphism
con-
of free an
by a set N if there
set of ~)
f: N " .~IMI, where M is an arbitrary
can be
the s u b s e q u e n t
of the definition
Let T be a fixed a l g e b r a i c
algebra ~ is called
Cohn)
op-
of more general
to motivate
cepts we need a little m o d i f i c a t i o n algebras.
[1], P.M.
finitary
is a
for each map
of type T there
g: ~----)M
which makes
the d i a g r a m
N
g
f
commutative. be viewed
The model M of T together
as a model M' of the
with
(algbraic)
f: N
(see definition
together with
) I~I)
i. N
14).
can
theory T' consisting
of the theory T together with new i n d i v i d u a l for each element of N
)IMI
constants, The model ~'
has the p r o p e r t y
that
one (
for each
-
model M' of T' there (in the sense define
g: ~
model ~
which
these maps
are called
theory T').
certain
I~l---~IMI
between
F-maps.
~
9) states F-initial
of this paper
model ~
theory T by the is exactly
the u n d e r l y i n g
sets
of T
They
formulas ~(see 4) each h a v i n g in T the sentence
"~x
/%
~(y)---~x
T.
(~ ( x ) •
one e l e m e n t which
u(x)
are identified
Furthermore,
an n-ary
if
formula
(~ (x I) t% ~2(x2) 1
is provable
~x
n
u-
u(x)).
set
the
(i.e., there Two such
in
is
formulas
is provable
in
..., x ) of F holds n Un if and only if the formula
Vx I
...
= y)
~x(~(x),M---~,~(x))
~i'
2
"'''
fulfills
~0 for the n-tuple ~x
(essentially
set of ~ is a quotient
that one can prove
u(x),
(see 2).
almost e x p l i c i t l y
property
exactly
one map
More p r e c i s e l y
the
, if it exists,
The u n d e r l y i n g
~xVy
to
(characterization
that one can construct
of the set of all unary
u(x)
>M'
will be called F-initial.
theorem
the following way.
g-~'
This suggests
conditions.
a given set F of formulas
The main
nique)
one h o m o m o r p h i s m
of a first order
fulfills
are maps
preserve
theorem
-
that for each model M of T there
)M,
which
is exactly
of the algebraic
an initial
condition
34
a(Xl,
A ... /% p(x ) - - ~ S ( X l , n
in
..., x n) )
in T.
A model ~ which a F-generated
model
tensor product in the category
of T.
of modules,
is constructed
in this way
(see definition localization
of all models
7).
is called
Examples
of rings,
direct
are limits
of a first order theory T where
35
the morphisms
are F-maps.
Another at left adjoints all models
class of examples of appropriate
result
i0 and remark
t- T
12).
ories in the sense of Birkhoff, in the sense of Lawvere completeness
theorem
[3].
(cf.
)T'
categories
the theory T in the of the theories
(see
If T and T' are algebraic
the-
one gets algebraic
functors
[2]) without mentioning
the individual
OF MODE~S
by x, y individual Definition
their predicate
constants.
Let
and a, b, c, .o. formulas
and
variables.
i
A set F of formulas
Formulas
i
of a theory T is called a generalized
formula if it contains
(i)
constants
By a,8,~,u we denote
of Generalized
x, y of individual
GSdel's
it.
Let S, T be first order theories with equality.
p, q, r, ... denote
of
The functors
We will use subsequently
CATEGORIES
2.
T, T'.
from interpreting
theory T' by means of a map
i.
functors between
of two first order theories
in consideration
definition
is obtained by evaluating
the formulas
variables
Under substitution ual variables
and if it is closedz
of individual
and individual
(ii)
Under conjunction
(iii)
Under disjunction
x = y for each pair
variables
constants.
by individ-
-
(iv) 3~
Remark formula is a special case of what H.J. Keisler
calls a"generalized
atomic set of formulas"
Let us introduce
models MT, NT,
preserve a(ml,
the c a t e g o r y ~
FpT" ... of T and its morphisms
the maps between
the underlying
o.., f(mn))
holds in NT~
the set of F-maps
M
Definition 9
a z F
the formula
then
By
The isomorphisms
F[~,
NT]
of
we denote
T~
of F-initial Models ,m
i
Let F be a generalized T is called F-initial unique F-map
are
)N T
6.
f, ~-----)N T
are
In [3] Keisler calls these
We call them F-maps.
are called F-isomorphisms.
[3]).
IMTI ----->INTI which
all formulas of F, i.e., if for
maps F-expansions.
.
sets
(cf.
Its objects
...,m n) holds in M T where m. ~ IM I i T
a(f(ml,
~F,T
-
Under existential quantification.
A generalized
4.
36
gz ~
|
formula of the theory T.
A model ~ of
if for each model M T of T there is one )M . T
Remark
All F-initial models of T are F-isomorphic.
-37 -
7.
Definition_ of F - q e n e r a t e d
Models
Let T be a theory and F a g e n e r a l i z e d to c o n s t r u c t
a model of T in the f o l l o w i n g way.
set of u~ary formulas ~x
p e F with
{~(x) A ~ y ( ~ ( y ) - - - ~ y
them d e t e r m i n a n t
in T9
equivalence
classes
Let
~ =
holds
~x n
in T.
Let us call relation
VxVy(~(x) J% ~ ( y ) - - ~ x
a(Xl,
ooo}
be the set of
. 9149 x n)
z F
9 9 /% Wn(X n ) - - ~ a ( x
this d e f i n i t i o n
and if there
ing p r e d i c a t e
constants
model ~ of T then ~
we define
I, .o.,
is not consistent 9
x n))
is an i n t e r p r e t a t i o n
of the remain-
of T in ~ such that one obtains
is called
an F - ~ e n e r a t e d
If it
a
model of T9
Remark
All F - g e n e r a t e d
models
Characterization i
= y)
in ~" if the sentence
(UI(Xl) A
is c o n s i s t e n t
99
that
in T.
In general
89
For
We try
Let ~ be the
an e q u i v a l e n c e
{ (w),(~),
of ~ .
(~n))
~x 2 .o9
is provable
We define
~ -- 7 if the sentence
is provable
"a((~l) , ..0,
the p r o p e r t y
= x)} is provable
formulas.
on ~ by s e t t i n g
Vx I
formula of T.
ml
i
of T are F-isomorphic 9
Theorem
9
A model ~ of T is an F - g e n e r a t e d is F-initial 9
model of T if and only if
-
Proof.
First
~ I being equivalence we define
g((~))
holds in M T. of~
38
let ~
-
be F-generated.
classes
The elements
(u) of determinant
formulas
of
,,
as the only element m ~ M T such that ~(m)
Thus g is well defined.
Because
of the structure
it is clear that g is a F-map and it is the only one. In order to show that a F-initial
generated
it is necessary
each element theory.
a c I~ I.
predicate
constants
of
~I
contains
formula
the language
of T and two unary a E ~ I.
those of T and for each n-tuple and each
a(Xl,
~a for
let S be the following
Pa and qa for each element
axioms of S include of elements
to find a determinant
For this purpose
Its language
model of T is F-
..., Xn)
r F
The
al, . .., a n
the two sen-
tences :
Vx I Vx 2 9
%IXn(Pal(x I) ;% ... ;% Pan(X n) ---~ a(Xl,
... Xn))
Vx I
~ X n ( q a l ( x I) A
"'" xn))
9
9
....
if a(al,
..., an) holds x Pa(X) ^
in~
is a model, Pa and qa both a, for each a r ~ I -
that the sentence
in S for each a ~ I~I.
the sentences
for each a r ~ I.
because ~
by the singleton
It follows is provable
, and furthermore
-~x qa(X)
S is consistent being interpreted
"'" ^ qan (xn) ---~ a(Xl'
(~x)
Because
(Pa(X),/--~,qa(X)) if it were not
-
39
-
there would exist a model N of S with different interpretations for some Pa and qa" fl and f 2 ~
)N
Hence there would exist two different maps
assigning to each a c k01 an element fl(a)
of Pa in N and an f2(a) of qa in N respectively. a model of T it follows that fl and f2 are F-maps, diction to the assumption that ~
Viewing N as in contra-
is F-initial.
For a fixed element a I r I~I the proof of the sentence ~X(Pal(x),~--~,qal(x))
in S uses only finitely many axioms.
Those which are not already in T are contained in a finite collection C of sentences
like:
V x I ... Vxk(Pal(Xl)A...APak(x k) ~ 8 ( X l ,
..., xk))
Vx I .-. ~xk(qal(xl)a...^qak(x k) ---~8(Xl,
..., x k))
x pa l(x), Sx qal(x),
..., SXPa k(x) and ..., SXqa(X;
where 8 is an appropriate
conjunction of formulas ~ from F.
Let the theory ~ consist of T together with the collection C of axioms.
We know already that
VX(Pal(x)~=~qal(x))
is provable in ~.
We claim that the unary formula ~ (x l) , defined by
- 40-
Zx 2
~x 3 ...
is a determinant is contained ~gx ~ (x)
8(x I, x 2, ..., x k)
k
formula in T.
in T because
It remains
.
The formula
it is true in ~
, hence
in
is provable
in T.
Assume
it
then there would exist a model N of T and two dif-
ferent elements in N, i.e., c2,
in ~
to show that
~x Vy(~ (x) /% , (y) ---~x = y) were not;
It is clear that the formula
in F and that ~(a I) holds
is provable
every model 9
~x
..., Ck
8(ci, c2,
such that ~(b I) and ~(c I)
bl, c I r INI
there are elements
b 2, . .. , b k
and
in N such that 8 (b I, b 2, ... , bk)
..., Ck)
and
Thus N could be extended
hold in N.
hold
to a
model ~ of ~ by interpreting
pa l(x)
by x = bl, pa 2(x)
by x = b2,
Pak(x)
by x = b k
qa l(x)
by x = Cl, qa 2(x)
by x - c2, 9 .o, qa k(x)
by x = c k
which violates
~X(Pa I (x) ~ q a
99
l(x) ) 9
We get all determinant
formulas
in this way because
is a model of T. Because ~
is F-initial
holds in ~
a formula
(for ~(x , 9149149 x ) r F 1 n if and only if the formula:
~Xl,
9149149 VXn(~al(Xl) A
and al,
a(al,
9149 a
..9 ;% ~an(Xn) ---~S(Xl,
holds in each model of T, i.e.,
..., a n ) n
r I~ I)
..9
Xn ))
if and only if it is provable
-
41-
in T.
APPLICATIONS
10.
Definition
of a m a p
t: T
)T'
of a t h e o r y T i n t o
a
t h e o r y T'
t assigns formula
to e a c h n - a r y
t(a)
formula
of T' s u b j e c t
a of T a n - a r y
to the
following
con-
ditions : (i0.i)
a and t(a)
(10.2)
t preserves
x = y a n d x = a.
(lO.3)
t preserves
the s t r u c t u r e
(e.g.,
have
t(--Ta)
the s a m e
=
free v a r i a b l e s .
of the
-'~t(a),
formulas
t[~xa
(x)] = V x t ( a ( x ) ) ,
etc.) .
(10.4)
If the s e n t e n c e
a is p r o v a b l e
in T t h e n t(a)
is p r o v -
a ble in T'.
F o r the sake of s i m p l i c i t y w e dividual
constants
assume
and variables
t h a t T' c o n t a i n s
the in-
of T'.
11.
A map
t: T
-~T'
an i n t e r p r e t a t i o n
between
theories
of the m o d e l s
M
induces
in an o b v i o u s w a y
, o f T' as m o d e l s T
of T.
-
12 ~
49
-
Remark
If F and F' are g e n e r a l i z e d ively,
and if, moreover,
induces
a functor
underlying
t*.~
formulas
of T and T' respect-
t(F) cI
F' then the map
F' ,T'
) 11~F, T
)T'
t- T
c o m m u t i n g with the
set functors.
13. For a language T c o n t a i n i n g e q u a l i t y but w i t h o u t axioms
and a g e n e r a l i z e d
that the F-maps correspondence SM(F,T).
IMTI.
with
There
formula F, K e i s l e r observes
) NT
constants
by some elements
let
t*'~F,,T,)~F,
14.
Definition
constant
of S M(FfT
[3]
holding
are
in M
which T of formulas
In order to generalize
be a functor d e f i n e d l
say
for each e l e m e n t
the free variables
of M T.
T
theory,
of the theory SM(F,T)
are the sentences
are c o n s t r u c t e d by r e p l a c i n g a c F
of a certain
is one i n d i v i d u a l
The axioms
in
with M T fixed are in one-one
the models
The p r e d i c a t e
those of T.
m
MT
additional
that,
as in 12.
)
Let M
be a model of T. The theory S (F,T') has the same T M predicate constants as T'. The i n d i v i d u a l constants of S (F,T')
are those of T' and a d d i t i o n a l l y
there is a new one
M
for each e l e m e n t m c IMTI o these elements
We do not d i s t i n g u i s h
and the c o r r e s p o n d i n g
individual
between
constants.
-
the axioms of S
43
-
(F,T') include those of T' and the sentences M
of the form
(tin)(ml, ..., m n)
the m. are elements l
15.
of
M
where
and
T
a(ml,
m(Xl,
..., x m)
..., m ) n
r F,
holds in M . T
Lemma
The pairs
(f, NT,) , where
in one-one
correspondence Proof.
f: M T
;t*(NT,)
with the models of SM(F,T').
Let us just establish
both directions.
A pair
(f: M T
scription of NT,
as a model of
of the new individual constants Conversely,
is an F-map are
the correspondence
in
)t*(N T ), N T ) is a de' ' SM(F,T'), the interpretation m c JMTI
given by the map f.
S (F,T'), we get a M model LT, of T' by forgetting the interpretation of the individual constants f:
MT
)t*LT,
ual constants
if L is a model of
m r IMTI
(T'-reduct).
The map
is given by the interpretation m c IM I T
of the individ-
in L. Q.E.D.
Let
t" T
F' be generalized t(F) c F'.
)T'
be a map of theories and let F and
formulas in T and T' respectively
such that
By Remark 12, this gives rise to a functor.t*:
~I~
%~ F' ,T'
Fe T
.
-
16.
Definition --
A model ~
c
if there T dence
-
of t*-Free Models .
.
Generated
i
%'~
i
is called
F' P T' M
44
is an F-map
a t*-free model g e n e r a t e d
i- M
by
) t*~ such that the correspon-
T
j- F' [ ~,NT,]
by M T
9
)F[ M T ,t*(N T' ) ], j (f) = t*(f)
"i
is a bijection0 17 o
Remark
This
is the usual universal
well known
that ~
definition
is d e t e r m i n e d
by M
of free objects.
It is
up to an F'-isomorphism. T
If for every
M
generated by MT.
(M T) functor
of t*
(cf.
Let
M
formula
the theory
then ~
r ~
there
FeT
is a t*-free
can be viewed
model
as the left adjoint
be a fixed model of To FiT
F' of T' generates SM(F,T' )
a generalized
by "closing"
ition 2 of a generalized 18 o
c ~
[5], S. MacLane).
T ized
T
The general-
formula
F' according
F''
of
to the defin-
formula.
Lemma t
A model ~
of
T'
is
a t*-free
if and only if the pair (according
to Len~ma 15)
model g e n e r a t e d
by
MT c ~ F , T
(i: M
) t ~ , ~) corresponds T to an F ' ' - i n i t i a l model of S (F,T'). M
-
This follows directly 19.
45
from the definitions
5 and 16.
Corollary
A model ~ of T' is only if ~
t*-free generated by M ~ ~T~ T FwT
is an F' '-generated model of the theory
S (F,T'). M
is t*-free generated by M T if it is F''-
Proof. initial
if and
(by Lemma 17).
orem 14, we know that ~
Because of the characterization is an F''-initial model of
if and only if it is an F''-generated
the-
S (F,T') M
model. Q.E.D.
REFERENCES
Ill
Cohn, P.M.
Uniuzrsal Algzbra, Harper and Row, New York,
1965. [2]
Godel, K., Die Vollst~ndigkeit
Monarch. Math. Phg6o
Funktionen-Kalk~is. 349-360,
[3]
der Axiome des Logischen 37;
(1930).
Keisler, H.J., Formulas",
"Theory of Models With Generalized
J.
Atomic
of Symbolic Logic, 25, (I)~ 1-26,
(1960).
[4]
Lawvere,
F. W.,
ries",
"Functorial Semantics
Pr0c. Nat.
of Algebraic Theo-
Acad. S~/., 50, (5); 869-872,
(1963).
[5]
MacLane, 71,
S., "Categorical (i); 40-106,
Algebra",
(1965) 0
Bull. Amzr. Math. S o t . ,
-
46
C O R E F L E C T I O N MAPS W H I C H R E S E M B L E
UNIVERSAL COVERINGS
by
J. F. K e n n i s o n
1.
INTRODUCTION
If X is c o n n e c t e d and s e m i l o c a l l y [9, p. of
78])
then one can r e g a r d the set
c: X
> X, w h e r e
c o v e r i n g of X.
1-connected
~I(X)
c is the u n i v e r s a l
as any fibre
simply connected
This o b s e r v a t i o n g e n e r a l i z e s
locally 1 - c o n n e c t e d spaces such as
(see
to some n o n - s e m i -
X = R x R \ {(2-n,0) In e Z+},
in the sense t h a t there e x i s t s a H u r e w i c z
fibration
(which is a c a t e g o r y t h e o r y g e n e r a l i z a t i o n
c: X
> X
of the u n i v e r s a l
s i m p l y c o n n e c t e d covering)
such t h a t any fibre of c can be re-
g a r d e d as
last example,
~I(X).
In this
h a v e an i n t e r e s t i n g n o n - t r i v i a l
topology
moreover,
the fibres
(see 5.8 the final
e x a m p l e of this paper).
Categorically,
e a c h of the above m a p s
can be r e g a r d e d as a c o r e f l e c t i o n
unique
c o n n e c t e d spaces.
is s i m p l y c o n n e c t e d and locally p a t h w i s e
if S is any o t h e r such space, lift
S
> X
> X,
of X into the c a t e g o r y of
s i m p l y c o n n e c t e d and locally p a t h w i s e is, X
c: X
S
then e v e r y m a p
which commutes with
c.
(That
connected, > X
and
has a
It is n e c e s -
sary to add that all spaces h a v e base p o i n t s w h i c h are p r e s e r v ed by maps.)
-
47
-
W e shall i n v e s t i g a t e a particular
coreflective
p o i n t e d spaces
this p h e n o m e n o n by c o n s i d e r i n g , subcategory Cn of the c a t e g o r y of
(i.e. spaces w i t h b a s e points).
s m a l l e s t full r e p l e t e c o r e f l e c t i v e the c o n t r a c t i b l e
spaces.
subcategory
(A s u b c a t e g o r y
Cn
is the
c o n t a i n i n g all
is r e p l e t e if it is
c l o s e d u n d e r the f o r m a t i o n of e q u i v a l e n t objects.) let
c: X
> X
We shall
be d e f i n e d to be the c o r e f l e c t i o n
of X in-
w
to
Cn .
If X is c o n n e c t e d and s e m i l o c a l l y
1-connected,
c is the u n i v e r s a l covering, b u t in general, ration w i t h t o t a l l y p a t h w i s e d i s c o n n e c t e d G(X),
c is a Serre
fibres.
fib-
We show that
the fibre of c, has n a t u r a l g r o u p and t o p o l o g i c a l struc-
tures d e f i n e d on it. ~I(X).
As a group,
G(X)
One of the t o p o l o g i c a l p r o p e r t i e s
d i s c r e t e iff c is a c o v e r i n g and TI).
is a q u o t i e n t of is t h a t
G(X)
(for X l o c a l l y p a t h w i s e
is
connected
G is f u n c t o r i a l b o t h as a g r o u p and as a space.
ing b o t h of the s t r u c t u r e s
on
and 5 . 7 ( a ) ) - - i f
Us-
G(X), we can d e t e r m i n e w h e t h e r
or n o t X is s i m p l y c o n n e c t e d in the sense of C h e v a l l e y 5.6(b)
then
X is locally p a t h w i s e
(see 4.5,
c o n n e c t e d and T I.
For such spaces, we can also o b t a i n some i n f o r m a t i o n a b o u t the u n d e r l y i n g t o p o l o g y of the u n i v e r s a l p r o - c o v e r i n g of Lubkin, [7].
The u n i v e r s a l p r o - c o v e r i n g is c o m p a r e d and c o n t r a s t e d w i t h
the c o r e f l e c t i o n X
in the examples.
We do n o t k n o w if group, b u t by 5.2, the f o r m
G(X)
G(X)
is always a t o p o l o g i c a l
a large class of t o p o l o g i c a l groups
for a r e a s o n a b l y w e l l - b e h a v e d
X.
are of
As a corol-
-
48
-
lary to 5.2, we show that if ~ is any group and N is any n o r m a l subgroup
of ~, there is a connected,
T 2 space X w i t h universal
~I(X)
connected
= ~, G(X)
covering
locally p a t h w i s e
= ~/N
and
relations
coreflective
between
subcategories.
see
[5] and
al and could be applied proper
class)
ed spaces nected tions
The methods
to any one of the large n u m b e r
connected,
and the s u b c a t e g o r y
Thus this paper liminary
report.
ed c o r e f l e c t i o n 3.2(b),
of spaces
locally p a t h w i s e
connect-
are simply
and is to some degree of
considered,
3.6 and its consequences,
con-
There may also be a p p l i c a -
In the last section was b r i e f l y
(i.e.
in the sense of Lubkin
is not e x h a u s t i v e
gener-
that lie b e t w e e n
of spaces w h i c h
in the sense of Chevalley.
[6]
For addition-
used are quite
subcategories
on
[4], and
can be found in
in the next section.
[6].
of simply
in the category
of Isbell,
These results
of c o r e f l e c t i v e
the s u b c a t e g o r y
the
is b a s e d p r i m a r i l y
the b i c a t e g o r i e s
and are stated w i t h o u t p r o o f al details,
m X
of X.
Our c a t e g o r y t h e o r y m a c h i n e r y certain
c: X .
connected,
3.7,
[6], a closely and analogs
[7]. a prerelat-
of 3.1(a),
3.8 and 3.9 were ob-
tained.
Our t e r m i n o l o g y ular,
a complete
category
is b a s e d is both
remark that the term "bicategory" meanings,
on Freyd,
[2].
left and right has acquired
In p a r t i c complete.
We
several diverse
but we are u s i n g it only as d e f i n e d below.
- 49 -
Note
F or c o n v e n i e n c e , throughout
2.
this paper,
BICATEGORY
a coreflective
be a s s u m e d
STRUCTURES
subcategory
shall,
to b e f u l l and r e p l e t e .
AND COREFLECTIVE
SUBCATEGORIES
Definition
Let B b e phisms
on B.
provided
with
a category.
Then
(I,P)
Let I and P be classes
is a l e f t b i c a t e g o r y
structure
on
that: LB0:
Every
LBl:
I a n d P are c l o s e d u n d e r
LB2:
Every member
LB3:
Every morphism
fl e I
and
equivalence
f0 e P.
is in I n P.
f can b e If
factorization,
alence
e for which
ef 0 = h
(I,P)
in a d d i t i o n
and
factored
f = gh
is any o t h e r
If,
with
then
in B.
as
f = flf0
g e I
there exists
and an e q u i v -
ge = fl"
to the a b o v e ,
is a b i c a t e g o r y
compositions.
of I is a m o n o m o r p h i s m
h e P
then
of m o r -
every
f ~ P
is epi,
structure.
Definition
Let
(I,P)
b e a left b i c a t e g o r y
X is an I - s u b o b ~ e c t
of Y if t h e r e e x i s t s
f e I.
Similarly,
Y is a P - q u o t i e n t
g: X
) Y
g r P.
with
structure f: X
on B.
Then
> Y with
of X if t h e r e e x i s t s
-50-
2L: 1
Lemma
(Diagonal
Let g E P
and
fm = ng.
(I,P)
be
f e I Then
Property)
a left bicategory
and morphisms
there
exists
structure
m and n be
a morphism
given
r with
on B.
Let
with
rg = m
and
fr = n.
2.2j~ T h e o r e m
(Isbell)
Let B be
complete
powered.
Let M b e
the
of all e x t r e m a l
iff
class
e = mg
(M, E #)
and
the
class
m e M
well-powered
of all m o n o m o r p h i s m s
epimorphisms imply
is a b i c a t e g o r y
is a l e f t b i c a t e g o r y
and e i t h e r
(that
of B and E # is,
e e E#
m is an e q u i v a l e n c e ) .
structure
structure
of B
or c o - w e l l -
on B.
on B,
Then
Moreover,
if
(I,P)
t h e n E # c_ p.
Remark
It f = flf0 smallest
follows with
fl
subobject
from
the d i a g o n a l
e M
and
f0
through
which
an o b j e c t
of B.
property
e E#
then
(2.1),
that
fl r e p r e s e n t s
if the
f factors.
Definition
L e t A be has
the u n i q u e
morphism fh=
g.
g: A
lifting > Y
property there
Then with
a morphism
respect
is a u n i q u e
f: X
to A if
h: A
~ X
> Y
for e v e r y with
-51-
Definition
Let
A
be a subcategory
the set of all m o r p h i s m s perry with respect We define for which
which
and
2.3 and 2.4,
B.
We define
have the unique
to every object P(A)
p = ig
of
of
I(A)
lifting
to be pro-
A.
to be the class of all m o r p h i s m s i c I(A)
imply
stated below,
i
p
is an equivalence.
are the main
results
of
[6].
2.3 T h e o r e m
Let category. full of
C
be a complete,
Let
A
subcategory A.
Working
be defined tients
C
in the category Let
A*
(I,P)
(c)
A*
for which
of
A.
If
B
I = I(A)
and
P = P(A)
of all P-quo-
Then:
of
B
structure
coreflective
B
is
has a represen-
is I-wellpowered
is a left b i c a t e g o r y
is the smallest
be the
of members
in C iff A = A* and
if each object
set of I-subobjects). (b)
let
B
be the subcategory
of members
(i.e.,
Let
of c o p r o d u c t s B,
is c o r e f l e c t i v e
"I-wellpowered" tative
of all quotients
of coproducts A
and c o - w e l l - p o w e r e d
be any full subcategory.
as above.
(a)
well-powered
on
then: B.
subcategory
of
A c A*.
2.4 Proposition Let
~, A*, ~, ~, and
(I,P)
be as above.
Assume
that
- 52 -
B is i-well-powered.
Then the following
statements
are equiva-
lent~ (a)
A
e A
(b)
A r B
and whenever
f: X
> A
is in
I then
N
f is an equivalence. (c)
A z B
and every B morphism
(d)
A z B
and every member of I has the u n i q u e
ing p r o p e r t y
with
3.
CONSTRUCTION
study of the smallest
valent
spaces
Working
spaces.
images)
the category
and
It is shown in
powered,
hence I-well-powered
map
c z X
of all "quotients" of members
is a left bicategory
all equi-
topo-
of all con-
PC, of all pathwise
P = P(Cn)
section.
connect-
(i.e.
of Cn.
be defined as in the
[5, p. 409]
that PC is well-
and so 2.3 and 2.4 apply.
That
system on P C which c a n be used
, the ooreflective
For each
containing
let Cn be the subcategory
previous
to compute Cn
subcategory
section to the
in the category of pointed
of coproducts
Let I = I(Cn)
(I,P)
of the previous
The subcategory
ed spaces is clearly
is,
lift-
OF THE COREFLECTION
coreflective
logical spaces, we shall
continuous
is in P.
(i.e. spaces which are homotopicaily
to a point).
tractible
> A
respect to A.
We now apply the results
contractible
f: X
subcategory
generated by C n.
X r PC, we shall construct
the corefiection
> X
associated with C n .
As explained
in the
-
introduction,
-
this map is a g e n e r a l i z e d
nected covering properties
53
of X.
of c, Cn
We shall
universal
also discuss
simply
con-
some e l e m e n t a r y
and I.
Note
(i) assumed
From here on every space
considered
shall be
to be in PC. (2)
F r o m here on the term "quotient"
in its t o p o l o g i c a l
rather
than
shall be used
its c a t e g o r i c a l
sense.
Notation
In this paper as in
the term ~
[3], that is to denote
shrink to a point.
simply c o n n e c t e d
of PC for w h i c h
[9], w i t h o u t
space shall be a connected,
assumption,
connected in
usual meanings.
that the u n m o d i f i e d
sense in
etc.,
A Chevalle~ connected
(We drop Cheval-
[i], that a space be T2.)
and H u r e w i c z
"fibration",
(or just
locally
coverings.
terms Serre F i b r a t i o n Note
all loops
any r e s t r i c t i o n s
such as local connectedness.
space w i t h no n o n t r i v i a l ley's b l a n k e t
a member
shall be used
The term c o v e r i n @ p r o j e c t i o n
coverin ~) shall be used as in on the base space,
connected
have the former
Fibration
shall have their
terms
sense in
The
"fibering",
[3] and the latter
[9].
321 P r o p o s i t i o n
(a)
Every member
of I is a Serre
fibration w i t h
to-
-
tally pathwise
disconnected
(b) totally
(Y,y0)
pathwise g:
>
section.
(X,x 0)
homotopy
)
identity map on there
exists
follows nl:
map)
that
(A,a 0)
Let
Let
(the constant
By the covering
and
nl(a0) >
the proof
(Y,y0)
of
map)
> A
and
be a
hI
the
property, no = Y0
Then the path loop.
= Y0
totally
and
such that
fn t = gh t. a shrinkable
with
ht: A
homotopy
nt: A----> Y
= n0(a0)
(a) until
(b), let
be given.
g(ht(a0)) ,
I.
(A,a 0) 6 Cn
a homotopy
(the constant lies over
A.
is in
fibres.
h0 = a0
with
PC,
fibration
(X,x 0)
with
As for
in
be a Hurewicz
disconnected
(A,a 0)
fibres,
We shall postpone
the end of this f:
fibration,
disconnected
Proof.
-
fibres.
Every Hurewicz
pathwise
54
(nt(a0))
It readily
and so
is the desired
lifting
of
g.
space,
which
3.2 Corollary (a) quotient simply in
simply
of a c o n t r a c t i b l e
connected
connected space,
and locally
is in
Cn*.
is the
Thus,
every
pathwise
connected
space
pathwise
connected
member
is
Cn*. (b)
Cn*
Every
Every
is Chevalley
locally
simply connected.
of
-
Proof. q: A
> X
(a)
implies
Let X be simply
map.
[9, p.
hence,
space,
and let Let
C:
h with
But it is e a s i l y
connected
namely
X
X
ch = q
c is a h o m e o m o r p h i s m .
locally p a t h w i s e
tient of a c o n t r a c t i b l e
(b)
A ~ Cn.
that c is a q u o t i e n t map.
every connected,
see
connected
Then there exists
shown that c is one-one,
below,
-
be a q u o t i e n t map w i t h
be the c o r e f l e c t i o n which
55
Finally
space is the quo-
the path space d e f i n e d
75].
As shown in
[9, p.
67], every
covering
is a Hure-
wicz
fibration. Thus, if X is locally p a t h w i s e c o n n e c t e d and , in Cn , then every c o n n e c t e d c o v e r i n g of X is p a t h w i s e con-
nected,
hence
in I, hence
trivial by 2.4(b).
Definition
Let path space
(X, X 0)
over X is the set of maps
([0, i], 0) logy.
r P_~C be given.
>
(X, X 0)
The base p o i n t of
P(X,
x0),
the
the c o m p a c t - o p e n
x 0)
is the constant map.
> X
be the map for w h i c h
topo-
= f(1).
When there is no danger P(X)
P(X,
from
together w i t h
We let ~ : P(X, x 0) ~(f)
Then
instead
of
P(X,
x 0).
of confusion,
we shall use
- 56
-
3.3 T h e o r e m
L e t #: P(X) where
c is m o n o
(We a r e
> X b e as above.
in P C and ~0 is an e x t r e m a l
applying
2.2
to
PC). -
c: X
Let
~
"
# as
~ = c~ 0
epimorphism
: P (X)
> X
in PC
and
0
) X.
Then ed w i t h
r
X
Cn
X* r C n *
as
We f i r s t n o t e t h a t P(X)
r Cn
under P-quotients. given
"lifts"
and c is t h e
coreflection
map associat-
X.
Proof:
ment
Factor
(see
[9, p.
It r e m a i n s
in 3.1 c a n be u s e d
v i a c.
Moreover,
~0 r P 75])
to s h o w
as
E # ~ P.
Then
a n d Cn * is c l o s e d
t h a t c E I.
The a r g u -
to s h o w t h a t e v e r y m e m b e r
the
lifting
is u n i q u e
of C n
as c is m o n o
in PC.
3.4 CorollarY
Let If X is T i' of
quotient
~: P(X) then -i
c
(x)
)
-i
X
(x)
and
c:
X
) X
b e as above.
is a t o t a l l y p a t h w i s e
for all
disconnected
x r X.
3_..5 C o r o l l a r y
L e t X be T 1 and let coreflection. and
h(1)
duced by h
= x I.
Let
h:
C:
[0, i]
T h e n the m a p
(which s e n d s Y0
(X , X 0) > X
from
;
(X, X 0)
be a p a t h w i t h c-l(x0 )
to
to Y l iff t h e r e e x i s t s
b e the h(0)
c -I (x I)
= x0 in-
-
~:
[0, l]
> x
with
a homeomorphism. topy class
This
(x 0)
to
-i
~
the u s u a l
Taking
quotients,
mains
c ~ = h, ~(0) homeomorphism
This
which
= Y0
and
depends
h(1)
only
= yl )
is
on the h o m o -
the w e l l k n o w n
continuous
sends
~ to the p a t h
sum for paths we obtain
m a p has
invariant
the loop
having
an e n d p o i n t
the d e s i r e d
an o b v i o u s
map
inverse
from
map
from h +
in common). c-l(x0)
to
and also c l e a r l y
re-
under homotopy.
3.6 P r o p o s i t i o n
(Base P o i n t
Let be a r b i t r a r y
Consider (x I)
(using
c-l(xl).
-
of h.
Prqof: -1
57
f:
and
Chan~e)
(Y, y0 )
let
;
be in I~
(X, x 0)
x I = f(yl ) ~
Then
f:
Let
Yl E Y
>
(Y, Yl )
(X, x l)
is also in I.
Proof: and ~(i)
= YI"
> (X, x I) the c o p r o d u c t > ([0,
i)
mapping there
Let
in PC
(Z, 0)
lows t h a t desired
~:
[0, l]
h = fh.
(Z, 0)
Z =
defined
of g.
i],
i)
product).
can also
(X, x 0) .
Clearly
(Y, y0 )
+
~(i)
= Yl
Z e Cn
h(0) g:
= Y0
(A, a l)
(A, a I)
Then
regard
with
that and
if h is r e g a r d e d
~I [0, i] = ~, h e n c e
lifting
([0,
We
>
be such
(A, a I) E Cn
the w e d g e
(X, x I). into
> Y
Let
Let
(i.e.
is w e l l into
exists
~:
be given.
(X, x I) i],
Let
be
h + g: Z
as m a p p i n g h + g
as
and since
f~ = h + go and thus,
~IA
f ~ I
It folis the
-
58
-
3.7 C o r o l l a r y
Let
(x, x 0)
X r
and
iff
Cp
e
PC
Proof:
b e given.
x0, x I e X
Then
(X, x I) e Cn.
Follows
in v i e w of 2.4(b)
a n d the above.
3,.,8 C o r o l l a r y Let of
(X,
Then
x O) .
c:
c:
(X*, X 0)
Let
>
X 1 ~- X
(X , xl)
>
(X, x 0)
be
be the coreflection
arbitrary
(X, x I)
and
let
xi
is the c o r e f l e c t i o n
= c(x 1).
of
(X, x 1).
Remark
In v i e w our p r a c t i c e
of the a b o v e
results,
we shall
of f r e q u e n t l y
suppressing
c: X
be the c o r e f l e c t i o n
freely
any mention
continue
of the b a s e
point.
Definition
Let
X
the deck translation phisms phisms
g: X
@rou~
> X
Then
for X is the g r o u p of all a u t o m o r -
such that
are n o t r e q u i r e d
of X.
cg = c.
to p r e s e r v e
(These a u t o m o r -
any b a s e p o i n t s . )
3.9 T h e o r e m
Let
c: X
deck translation that whenever
) X group
be the c o r e f l e c t i o n
acts t r a n s i t i v e l y
Xl, x 2 e X
of X.
on e a c h
are g i v e n w i t h
Then the
f i b r e of c so
c ( x I) = c(x 2) ,
-
there
is a u n i q u e
Proof:
both
;
coreflections
-
deck translation
Assume
(X , x I)
C:
59
that
g ( x l) = x 2.
c(x l) = c(x 2) = x0.
(X, x 0) an d of
g for w h i c h
c:
(X, x 0)
)
(X , x 2)
in v i e w of 3.7.
Then (X, x ) are 0 Thus t h e r e
w
are m a p s
g:
(X
with
,
x 1)
(X , x I) cg
=
c
v e r s e of g and so g i s g follows
since
Proof S E Cn
Let
that
fm = ng~
m: S
g r a m of p o i n t e d
a
Let
and
spaces
TOPOLOGICAL
n: S •
This
property
AND
h is t h e
in-
[0, i]
of
as a d i a -
in S, etc.)
there exists implies
respect
any
be such
this
any b a s e p o i n t
Let
be
> X
can r e g a r d
clearly with
be in I.
> S x [0, i]
a n d so b y 2.1,
an d so f is a S e r r e
4.
>
The uniqueness
) X
g: S
spaces by choosing
homotopy
Clearly
f: Y
(In v i e w of 3.6, w e
rg = m and fr = n.
the c o v e r i n g
(X*, x 2)
in PC.
N o t e t h a t g E P by 2.4(c) r with
h:
translation.
and let
> Y
and
ch = c~
deck
(a):
be a r b i t r a r y
(X, x 2)
and
c is m o n o
of 3.1
map.
)
a map
that f has
to all c o n t r a c t i b l e
fibration.
GROUP
STRUCTURES
ON THE F I B R E
Definition
Let (X, x0).
~l(X,
c:
(X*, x 0)
We d e f i n e
G(X,
)
be the c o r e f l e c t i o n
x 0) = c - l ( x 0)
G(X,
x 0)
be the n a t u r a l
x 0)
and
G(X,
x 0)
(X, x 0)
function.
are b o t h
and
let n:
~I(X,
of x 0)
[Notice t h a t
equivalence
classes
of
loops
60
in
~-l(x0),
connected,
see 3.3.
homotopic
Since
-
G(X, x 0)
is totally pathwise dis-
loops must be equivalent in
G(X, x ). 0
Hence we can readily obtain the above function n.] 4.1 Proposition G(X, x 0) n: ~I(X, x 0) G(X, x 0)
can be given a group structure so that
9 G(X, x 0)
is canonically
is a group homomorphism.
isomorphic
Then
to the deck translation
group. Proof: translation G(X, x 0) group.
For each
g for which
x ~ G(X, x 0) g(x~) = x.
in one-one correspondence If we give
G(X, x 0)
associate the deck
By 3.9, this places with the deck translation
the induced group structure,
it
is then easy to show that n is a group homomorphism. Definition Let
n: ~ (X, x 0) > G(X, x 0) be the above homo1 We define N(X, x 0) to be the ke;nel of n.
morphism.
4.2 Proposition: ~l' G
and N are functors from PC into groups.
action of these functors is, to within an equivalence, dent of the base point. marion from
~
1
to G.
The indepen-
We can regard n as a natural transforFinally N(X)
is isomorphic to
=.(x ). r
- 61-
Proof:
Straightforward.
Remarks
G(X, x 0) cal space group,
is n o t only a group, b u t is also a t o p o l o g i -
(as a s u b s p a c e of X ).
it is a t o p o l o g i c a l
a l t h o u g h so far we can only s h o w that the "algebraic"
f u n c t i o n s of one v a r i a b l e xax-lb
for a, b fixed)
fact follows since -i
Perhaps
(such as the f u n c t i o n s e n d i n g x into
are c o n t i n u o u s
G(X, x 0)
for X a T 1 space.
This
is a q u o t i e n t of the loop s p a c e
(Xo). It can e a s i l y be s h o w n that G is a functor from PC to
the c a t e g o r y of groups w i t h t o p o l o g i e s .
If X is s e m i l o c a l l y c:
X
n:
~
> X
1-connected
(see
[9, p. 78])
then
is the u n i v e r s a l s i m p l y c o n n e c t e d c o v e r i n g ,
(X) > G(X) i d i s c r e t e topology.
is a n a t u r a l
i s o m o r p h i s m and G(X)
has the
Definition
X is s e m i l o c a l l y G - c o n n e c t e d if e a c h x e X has a n e i g h b o r h o o d U such that the n a t u r a l map
G(U)
> G(X)
is
trivial.
4.3
Theorem
Let X be c: X
> X
locally p a t h w i s e
be its c o r e f l e c t i o n .
c o n n e c t e d and T
and let 1 T h e n the f o l l o w i n g s t a t e m e n t s
- 62 -
are equivalent:
(a)
c-l(x) X
E
is discrete
(b)
X is s e m i l o c a l l y
(c)
o is a covering
Proof: x0 r X
(a)
set of X* such that
G-connected. of X (in w h i c h
connected "- (b) :
such that
pact-open
topology.
there
Thus,
KI'''''Kn
contained
such that
k E AM(Ki,
starting ~0(A)
M(K,
[0, 1]
G(U)
> G(X)
(b)-----> (c): neighborhood trivial. easily
Let
shown
of a given
~0(~)
=
c_ U}.
of x 0.
compact
sets
UI,.~
n
of X,
Let
U c_ AU i
Then any loop A, AM(Ki,
U i) .
Thus
It is now easy to
x~.
is trivial. Let U be an open, x c X
such that
{Vs} be the path
components
that each r e s t r i c t i o n
the deck translations,
>
where k is the constant
range in U, is in
and so
x 0)
is open in the com-
and open sets
neighborhood
and
~0: P(X,
are n o n - e m p t y
U) = {f E P(X)If(K)
at x 0 and w i t h
be given
Let
~0 -i (W)
Ui) c_ ~0-1(W),
connected
c W A c-l(x 0)
show that
in
of X).
Let W be an open sub-
W n p-l(x 0) = {x~}. 3, then
case c is the
x0 E X
c(x 0) = x 0.
be as in section
be a pathwise
covering
Let
(x * , x 0)
path on x 0 and
for all)
(and hence
Xo
universal
choose
for some
the Vs's
ciV
pathwise G(U)
of
> G(X)
c-l(u).
is one-one.
are canonically
connected is
It is In view of
homemor-
-
phic.
63
-
It can further be shown that each
map using
the fact that
cIUv
) u
(c is a q u o t i e n t map as % is, see Thus
clc-l(u)
clV ~
a universal
"-
(c)
I.
(a) :
connected
Then f is regular g:
valently,
(Y, y0 )
f:
(x , x 0)
G(X,
and
c% 0 = %o
)
x0).
f:
if for each >
Clearly,
Thus c is a covering.
covering
in view of 2.4 (d)
>
(Y, y0 )
(Y, y0 )
(X, x 0)
(X, x 0)
fg = f.
in I is regular
g
be in
there exists
such that
for w h i c h
is such that
>
y E f-i (x0)
(Y, y)
(Thus it follows
that on p. 74 of
It fol-
is in I.
Let
(Y, y0 )
f ~ I and by 2.4(d)) of
75],
Trivial.
Let X be T 1.
automorphism
g:
[9, p.
is a h o m e o m o r p h i s m .
as every other such covering
Definition:
is a q u o t i e n t map.
is also a q u o t i e n t map as U is open.)
lows that each It is clearly
clV~ is a q u o t i e n t
Equi-
iff the map
fg = c (which exists -i
(y0)
is a n o r m a l
that our d e f i n i t i o n
an
as
subgroup
agrees w i t h
[9].)
regularity
is i n d e p e n d e n t
of the base point.
4,4. Corollary
Let X be locally p a t h w i s e is a canonical
one-one
of X and open n o r m a l
Proof: Choose
correspondence
subgroups
group.
and T 1.
between
regular
Then there coverings
of G(X).
Let H be an open n o r m a l
any base point in X .
deck t r a n s l a t i o n
connected
Then G(X)
Consider
s u b g r o u p of G(X). can be r e g a r d e d
the q u o t i e n t
as the
space X / H o b -
-
r a i n e d from X
translation
64
-
by i d e n t i f y i n g x w i t h h(x) w h e n e v e r
h is
(regarded
as)
a m e m b e r o f H.
the d e c k
(The space
X /H
does n o t d e p e n d on our choice as H is normal.)
The map
f: X*/H
> X
i n d u c e d by c can be s h o w n
to be a c o v e r i n g by m e a n s of the a r g u m e n t s
g i v e n in 4.3.
4.5 C o r o l l a r y
Let X be l o c a l l y p a t h w i s e
c o n n e c t e d and T I.
is C h e v a l l e y s i m p l y c o n n e c t e d iff G(X)
Then X
has no p r o p e r open n o r -
mal subgroups.
Proof:
For
X, the c o v e r i n g s
locally pathwise
of X are in e f f e c t i v e o n e - o n e
w i t h the c o v e r i n g s m a r k below).
(connected and)
in the sense of Lubkin,
F r o m T h e o r e m 1 on p. 211 of
any n o n - t r i v i a l
[7],
connected
correspondence (see the re-
[7] it follows that
c o n n e c t e d c o v e r i n g of X gives rise to a n o n -
t r i v i a l r e g u l a r c o n n e c t e d covering.
Remark
In w h a t
follows, we shall r e f e r to the g e n e r a l i z e d
u n i f o r m spaces of L u b k i n s~ages ,.
The m a i n
(called spaces in
facts that w e shall use,
[7]) as L u b k i n from
e a c h t o p o l o g i c a l space is, in a n a t u r a l way, e v e r y L u b k i n space has an u n d e r l y i n g is
(connected and)
f: Y
> X
locally connected,
[7], are t h a t
a L u b k i n space and
topology.
Moreover,
if X
then e a c h c o v e r i n g
is such t h a t Y can be r e g a r d e d as a c o m p a t i b l e
-
65
-
Lubkin space and f as a Lubkin covering. kin covering
every Lub-
of such an X is of this type.
The universal
~ro-coverin~,
limit of all connected denote the underlying locally pathwise regular
Conversely
Lubkin coverings topology
connected,
coverings
of X.
of X.
Xf X is
1.4 on p. 215 of
simply
connected
We shall
[7].)
It follows
let
(connected
then X is the inverse
of X (in view of Theorem
ollary
and)
limit of all
1 on po 211 and Corthat X is Chevalley
iff X = X.
The relationship locally pathwise
X, of X, is the inverse
between
connected,
X
and X
(for connected,
X) is given by:
4.6 Theorem
Let X be and T 1.
Let
continuous
(connected
f: X
> X
function
and)
locally pathwise
be the underlying
connected
topology
associated with the universal
and
pro-c~vering
of X. Then there exists
3: X
The map ~ is the coreflection of all open normal subgroups tient space
such that
of X and G(X) of G(X).
f~ = c.
is the intersection
Moreover X is the quo-
X /G(X).
Proof: is clearly
> X
The existence
in I.
tion and that G(~)
of ~ follows
A direct proof shows
from 2o4(d)
as f
that ~ is the coreflec-
is the above intersection.
It can readily
- 66 -
be shown
that X is locally p a t h w i s e
tient map
connected
and so ~ is a quo-
(see 3.2).
Remark
Examples
5.6
(b), 5.7,
and 5.8 p e r t a i n
~o the r e l a ~ i o n -
ship b e t w e e n X and X*.
5.
EXAMPLES
5 9 1 Lemma
Let X be T I. =mq m: m
Q
-i (x)
of
where > X
q: P ( X )
> Q
is m o n o in PC.
is the largest
,-l(x).
is a q u o t i e n t map and Suppose
that for each x r X,
totally p a t h w i s e
Q = X
and
disconnected
quotien~
> Q
pothesis
and 3~
m = c.
By 3.3, we have that X
of X t h r o u g h w h i c h
f: X
such that
# factors.
mf = c.
we o b t a i n
a map
is the smallest Thus
"sub-
there exists
In view of the q u o t i e n t h: Q
It is easy to show t h a t h is the inverse a/%d
be factored as
.
Then
P rogf: object"
Let ~: P(X)------> X
> X* w i t h
by-
hq =
of f and hence,
0"
Q = X*
m = Co
5.2 Theorem:
Let G be a T O t o p o l o g i c a l for the n e i g h b o r h o o d s
group.
of the identity
Let {H } be a base
element
such that each H
-
is an o p e n s u b g r o u p . locally
pathwise
67
-
Then there exists
connected
T
space
a
(connected
X such that
and)
G(X)
is t o p o -
2 logically
and a l g e b r a i c a l l y
Proof: simply
Let
connected
e a c h ~ let Wl(Sm)
S
(S, s O )
pointed
c S
equivalent
T 2 space
be such t h a t
> ~I(S)
such that
S can be c o n s t r u c t e d ing some 2 - c e l l s ,
as in
[9, p.
a c h a n g e of the t o p o l o g y contain
connected,
such that
~l(S,
S
induces
> S )
a wedge
For
an i n j e c t i o n (Such an
of 1 - s p h e r e s
and a t t a c h -
143-148].)
attempt
Thi s
locally
s O ) = G.
m a p s o n t o Hm.
to c o n s t r u c t
on S - - r e q u i r i n g
some S .
the f a c t t h a t S, w h e n
a pathwise
~l(S
by taking
[A s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d
s o must
be
to G.
X would
involve
that a neighborhood
approach would work except
retopologized,
might
acquire
of
for
some new
loops.]
Let R be the r e a l of X as S • R w i t h
{s
line.
} • R
We define
identified
the u n d e r l y i n g
to a s i n g l e p o i n t
set cal-
0 led x0~
Let
e: S • R
logize
X so t h a t
product
topology
exist c
e
-i
> X
U c X and,
is o p e n
for
~ and a c o u n t a b l e
be the c a n o n i c a l iff
e-l(u)
map.
is o p e n
x 0 e U, w e a l s o r e q u i r e
subset
C c R
such
We topo-
that
in t h e
that there S
x
(R\C)
(u).
We
let
r: X
r is n o t c o n t i n u o u s of s e q u e n c e s .
Thus,
> S
be t h e o b v i o u s
at x 0 b u t r d o e s p r e s e r v e if
f:
[0, I]
> X
projection
function.
the convergence
is c o n t i n u o u s
, so
-
is rf:
[0, i]
> S.
and let
v: ~
equivalence ~I(X,
x O)
on G.
~ -i
-i
Hence
-~ ~l(X,
(x O)
x O)
following
k ~ DM(Ki,
-i
3)
topology
on
to the given topology
an S
implies
compact
UI,...,U n
(U), where
there exists
c N U., w h i c h
= G.
loop into its
of the identity
of the identity
Then there exist
U i) ~ v
paths
4.2).
and open subsets
Clearly
take each
to look at n e i g h b o r h o o d s
Let U be a n e i g h b o r h o o d
[0, i]
= -l(S)
We claim that the q u o t i e n t
It suffices
topology.
are h o m o t o p i c
~l(X)
induced by v, is h o m e o m o r p h i c
(see remark
tient
if f, g
be the loop space of X (as in section
(x) 0
class.
-
Similarly,
on X, then so are rf and rg. Let
68
H
sets
c U.
KI,...,K n
of X such that
k is the constant
and an
in the quo-
t E R
Thus
with
loop at x 0. e(Ss
• {t})
U is a n e i g h b o r h o o d
in the
given topology. It remains tient t o p o l o g y . find compact that
Let H
sets
h ~ NN(Ki,
to show that each H
and
KI'''''Kn U i)
union,
UIi,
nected neighborhood
be given.
and open sets
[0, i] \ h-l(x 0)
of open intervals. W of s
for all but finitely such that
)
We m u s t
UI,,..,U n
such
~ v-I(H~).
Let the open set disjoint
h r v-I(H
is open in the quo-
rh(xn)~ W,
many
be w r i t t e n
Choose
as the
any simply
con-
(in the space S). Then rh(li) c W 0 I i. [If not, let {Xn } be a sequence
for all n, and each I i contains
at most
- 69-
o n e x n.
Then h separates
Let obvious W.
I l, I 2 , . . . , I m
increasing
Let a
Let
9 .. H s a n H 8 ~ H e.
al
xalxa2x...xa ~2 "" " -an
identity hood cW.
order)
be the
n
= v(h)
intervals
for w h i c h
ai = v ( a i ) "
rh(i
sets
r He ,
hence
sends
of He.] of
identifies m q = ~. PC.
... U I m
mf = mg need
connected,
N M ( K i, U i)
In v i e w of 5.1,
and
follows
f, g:
for
(in a d d i t i o n
We shall show or f ~ g
Im c K 1 U
Let
for e a c h
in a n e i g h b o r h o o d
of t.
... K n,
neighborhood
> x
To prove on an o p e n
be such that
Let
in
f = g whenever this
claim, w e
and c l o s e d
at the b a s e
t e [0, I]
of h.
map which
to s h o w t h a t m is m o n o
f r o m the c l a i m t h a t
to a g r e e i n g
and open
2 ~ i ~ n, and t h a t
m': Q
~ Q.
r h ( K I)
r ( U I) ~ W
K2,...,K n
b e the q u o t i e n t
o n l y s h o w t h a t f and g a g r e e
[0, i]
... U
it s u f f i c e s
[0, i]
such that
is the d e s i r e d
> Q
paths.
into of the
of x 0 s u c h t h a t
intervals
I 1 U 12 U
q: P(X)
the i d e n t i t y
x in-
L e t K 1 be a c o m p a c t n e i g h b o r -
compact
so t h a t
homotopic
This e a s i l y
~8~IHs~2H 8
some neighborhood
I 1 U 12 U
Choose
Then
let
so t h a t
of
for
sends
is c o n t i n u o u s ,
t h a t e a c h U i is s i m p l y
We
hli. 1
x
= H 8.
h ( K ) c U.. i -- i
as
Choose H 8
in the
is n o t a s u b s e t
since the map sending
of the c o m p l e m e n t
U2,...,U n
)
(arranged
[This is p o s s i b l e
into a subset
~l(Ul)
1
defined
L e t U 1 b e an o p e n n e i g h b o r h o o d
and
of
f r o m its c l u s t e r p ~ / % t s . ]
b e the l o o p e f f e c t i v e l y
1
i = 1,...,m,
to
~x n}
subset
point).
that either
x = mr(t)
f = g
= mg(t).
We
- 70-
first
assume
that
neighborhood of
m-l(u)
over,
the
by means m-l(u) f ~ g
of x.
regarded
subsets of the
are of
U x H
above
is,
no
U ~
the
form
set
can be
be
shown
and
If
connected outside
shown Thus,
U • {g}
(mf)-l(u).
sequence
X
any
that
in a n a t u r a l
argument.
if U is a s i m p l y
(that
Let
It is r e a d i l y
can b e
in the
works
x ~ x 0.
as
U • G.
to b e o p e n the p a t h
hence
connected
the u n d e r l y i n g
way
in
x = x 0, the
set
Morem
-i
(U)
components
either
sequential
of
simply
f = g
same
or
argument
neighborhood
U can c o n v e r g e
of
of x 0
to x0).
5.3 Corollar~
Let Let
{H a } be
~ be
a topological
a base
for
t h a t N is n o r m a l . )
logy.
Then
there
nected
T 2 space
Proof: place
5~4
of G.
The
exists
X with
subgroup. Let
Let
~l(X)
have
X as in t h e
arguments
then
.
the
locally
= w, N(X)
T0).
of the i d e n t i t y N = NH
G = ~/N
a connected,
Construct same
(not n e c e s s a r i l y
the n e i g h b o r h o o d s
t h a t e a c h H a is an o p e n lows
group
= N,
above
such
(It t h e n quotient
pathwise and
G(X)
proof
fol-
topo-
con= G.
using
~ in
subgroup,
then
apply.
Corollary
If
~ is a n y
there
exists
Wl(X)
= w, N(X)
logy.
group
a semilocally = N
and
and N is any n o r m a l G-connected G(X)
= ~/N,
T 2 space with
X such
the d i s c r e t e
that topo-
- 71-
Thus there exist u n i v e r s a l c: X
> X
equivalent
with
=I(X)
connected
any p r e a s s i g n e d
to any p r e a s s i g n e d n o r m a l
covering
group and
spaces ~l(X )
subgroup.
5.5 C o r o l l a r y
Let ~ be any group and let {Hs} be any c o l l e c t i o n subgroups
that
of
such that: (1)
For all ~, 8, there
is a I w i t h
H A c_ H
(2)
For each u and each g z w there exists
N H 8. 8 such
g-lHsg c_ H .
Then there exists space
X such that
with
{H /N}
a connected, ~l(X)
locally p a t h w i s e
= w, N(X)
= N = NH
a base the n e i g h b o r h o o d s
connected
and
G(X)
T2
= ~/N
of the identity.
5.6 E x a m p le
(a) connected
There exists
(in fact (b)
(hence
connected
a Chevalley
simply
connected
T 2 space X for w h i c h G(X)
and
lo-
is n o n - t r i -
X ~ Cn*).
Proof:
(a)
Follows
from 5.4 w i t h
(b)
Let Z+ be the p o s i t i v e
be the group of all p e r m u t a t i o n s H n be the s u b g r o u p i ~ n.
such that X is n o t simply
can be p r e a s s i g n e d ) .
There exists
cally p a t h w i s e vial
~l(X)
X r Cn
of all
We claim that
f r G
(i) and
of Z+.
~ = N. integers.
For each
such that
f(i)
Let G
n ~ Z +, = i
let
for all
(2) of 5.5 are s a t i s f i e d by
{~n }.
- 72 -
Clearly
C h o o s e m so t h a t Thus there that
H
let
Let
c H n --
s r G
{0~}
minimal many
X with
(b).
for s o m e n. then
Note
be arbitrary.
then
s -- fg
of t h e o r b i t s
"other half" 9
where
implying
Finally Then
ite o r b i t
Let
b e given 9
for
i @ j9
v = sl(u),
sn+l(u) Clearly elements
5.7
U.
and
so
Define
s 2 ( u ) , . .9,
g(z)
g fixes
u r U
- s(z)
if
g: Z + s n (u).
open subgroups subgroup
fixes
to show
any
f e H.
s r H.)
(an o r b i t b e i n g
If s h a s
a
infinitely
to the i d e n t i t y
to the i d e n t i t y
on
on t h e
many elements
and so
a s s u m e t h a t s has o n l y a at l e a s t o n e i n f i n -
It f o l l o w s > Z+ Further
t h a t si(u)
so t h a t define
for all other values.
Thus
and such
= G
f r G
of s
s must have
at l e a s t n e l e m e n t s
f, g r H.
normal
fix infinitely
s r H9
g - i H m g c Hn.
of the i d e n t i t y .
f restricts
and g r e s t r i c t s
f and g thus
b e given.
for s o m e g a n d so
= 0~) 9
of o r b i t s 9
for
= G(X)
that
of o r b i t s
finite number
s j (u)
Then
(It s u f f i c e s
s(0~)
n > 0
t h a t H is a n o r m a l
f r g-lHng
s e t 0a s u c h t h a t
f, g c H
and
i < n.
~l(X)
Assume
b e the c o l l e c t i o n
orbits,
"half"
g r G
for a l l
g(i)
implies
set of n e l e m e n t s , Now
let
claim that G has no proper
4.5,
and t h a t
>
(2)
is a b a s e of o p e n n e i g h b o r h o o d s
We by
m
for
is a s u i t a b l e
{H n }
which
As
(i) holds.
and f fixes
g(v) g(u) Let
-- v =
f = sg -I.
infinitely
many
s = fg r H.
Example
(a)
There exists
a locally pathwise
connected
T 2 space
-
73
-
X s u c h t h a t ~ is n o t C h e v a l l e y s i m p l y connected.
x
(Equivalently,
x.) (b)
The above space X has a u n i v e r s a l
c o n n e c t e d cover-
ing w h i c h is n o t in Cn.
Proof: permutations i n t e g e r s n. la(n) I = h:
Z
Inl > Z
For this e x a m p l e ,
g: Z
s u c h that
for all n. such t h a t
the identity.
Let H h(i)
{A N H } n
n
= -g(n) a: Z
for all > Z
for
is a b a s e
i = i, 2,...,n.
Topo-
for the n e i g h b o r h o o d s
It is r e a d i l y v e r i f i e d t h a t there e x i s t s G(X)
with
be the s u b g r o u p of all
= i
of
a suit-
= G.
It is also e a s i l y s h o w n t h o s e in 5.6)
g(-n)
Let A be the s u b g r o u p of all
logize G so that
able X w i t h
> Z
let G be the g r o u p of all
(using a r g u m e n t s s i m i l a r to
t h a t A is the s m a l l e s t o p e n n o r m a l s u b g r o u p of G.
Hence, by 4.6, w e have
G(X)
o p e n n o r m a l subgroups.
Thus ~ is n o t C h e v a l l e y s i m p l y c o n n e c t e d
(in fact X = X ). in v i e w of 4.4.
= A.
B u t A is a b e l i a n and has m a n y
F i n a l l y the m a p
f: X
- X
is a c o v e r i n g
By c o n s t r u c t i o n of ~ this is the u n i v e r s a l
con-
n e c t e d covering.
Remarks
(i)
In the above e x a m p l e ,
Lubkin universal pro-covering sal L u b k i n c o v e r i n g of X.
X
it is e a s i l y s h o w n that the ~ X
is a c t u a l l y the u n i v e r -
Since Lubkin coverings
L u b k i n space X has no n o n - t r i v i a l
compose,
c o n n e c t e d coverings.
the
On the
-
74
-
other hand, we have seen that ~ has many n o n - t r i v i a l coverings.
Thus
~ ~ X
w h i c h means
connected
X cannot be a t o p o l o g i c a l
space. (2)
It should be m e n t i o n e d
covering
is not always
pathwise
connected.
but X
> X not one-one
5.8 Exam
le
Let in
lows from
and in
(see e x a m p l e s
[6].
~, is simply
[7, p. 232],
0)}.
X with
~ (X) = 0, 1 4, 7, and 22 of [7]).
This
space is d i s c u s s e d
It can be shown that the u n i v e r s a l connected
and hence,
that the group G(X)
~ = X .
It fol-
is the c o m p l e t i o n
the free group w i t h
c o u n t a b l y many g e n e r a t o r s
containing
finitely many generators.
all, but
pro-
of X* if X is not locally
There exist spaces
X = R • R\ { (2 -n,
[7, p. 232]
procovering,
a quotient
that the u n i v e r s a l
of
and open subgroups As a group G(X)
= ~l(X), but there may be o c c a s i o n s w h e n the above d e s c r i p t i o n of G(X) of
is e a s i e r
~l(X)
to w o r k w i t h than the a l g e b r a i c
as a free group w i t h u n c o u n t a b l y
description
many generators.
-
75
-
REFERENCES
[i]
Chevalley, C., Theory of Lie groups, I, Princeton University Press, Princeton,
[21
(1946).
Freyd, Po, Abelian categories, Harper and Row, New York, (1964).
[3]
Hu, S. T., Homotopy theory, Academic Press, New York, (1959).
[4]
Isbell, J. R., "Some remarks concerning categories and subspaces", Canad. J. Math., 9; pp. 563-577,
[5]
(1957).
Kennison, J. F., "A note on reflection maps", Illinois J.
Math., ii; pp. 404-409, (1967). [6]
, "Full reflective subcategories and generalized covering spaces", Illinois J. Math.,
[7]
Lubkin, S., "Theory of covering spaces", Trans. Amer. Math.
Soc., 104; pp. 205-238,
[8]
(1962).
MacLane, S., "Categorical algebra", Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 71; pp. 40-106,
[9]
(to appear) .
(1965).
Spanier, E. H., Algebraic topology, McGraw-Hill, New York, (1966).
-
DEDUCTIVE
76-
SYSTEMS AND CATEGORIES *
II. STANDARD
CONSTRUCTIONS
AND CLOSED
CATEGORIES
by J o a c h i m Lambek**
0. INTRODUCTION We wish
to explore
(1) p r e - o r d e r e d (2) deductive (3) categories By a p r e - o r d e r e d reflexive,
in mind by
(i)
with
structure.
anti-symmetric,
to give a rigorous
"structure"
illustrate
A semilattice
(A,T,A),
structure,
systems,
but not necessarily
Instead we shall
triple
sets with
between
set we mean a set with a transitive
It w o u l d be premature we have
the c o n n e c t i o n
where
~
and
relation
definition
"deductive
and ~.
of w h a t
system".
with an example.
(with largest
element)
is a p r e - o r d e r e d
set,
is a T
an
Familiarity with Deductive Systems and Categories (I) is not presumed. Thanks are due to the Battelle Institute for inviting me to give these lectures and to S. E i l e n b e r g for his s t i m u l a t i n g comments. Mathematics
Dept.,
McGill University,
Montreal
- 77
element
of
A,
A
and
-
a binary
operation
B
C~A
on
such
A
that
A ~ T, C~AA
For
(2) system
D(X)
Its
as
terms
all
finally
(It is
understood
A
>
B
are
listed
i:
A
4:
C C
A
axioms
5 6
formula
there
elements B
are
X
of
terms,
are
expressions
all are
is
so
else
B
is
a deductive
follows:
(or a x i o m
2:
A
~,
also
is
AAB.
is
T
a term.)
of
the
form
terms.
schemes)
5:
> B B A ----~ C C
'
are
is
and
rules
of
inference
; A A B C -----> B
written
>
C
6:
,
3: C
)
'
in tree-form.
A
C
For
> A >
C A
example,
a proof: 1
> A A B >B A
Any
X
set
follows:
> A A B > A
AAB A A B
& C~B.
nothing
and
,
following
and
that
Proofs the
A
formulas
as
- A
are
if
where
Its
discrete
described
a term;
Its
any
~
appearing
A B
as
1 AAB----->AAB AAB >A
4 >
B
a proof,
A A
in p a r t i c u l a r
the
last
T
, )
A B
B
- 78 -
formula,
is c a l l e d p r o v a b l e
the a b o v e t h a t A A B
> A,
b u t o n l y the
and
9 A A B, A A B
A A B
> B A A
A cartesian
(A,T,A,~,8),
where
A: A • A
natural
A
> A
HomA(A,B).
Thus
is the u s u a l
also
the
1
when
9
[A,T]
are
• [C,B]
-
,
[C,A A B]
T
terminal
object
is "the"
.
is s h o r t A
of
for
and
A
product.
see l a t e r t h a t the d e d u c t i v e
but
8
system
n o t o n l y the free s e m i l a t t i c e , category
generated
interested
by
X.
in the t h e o r e m s
in the s e c o n d
D(X) but
In the of the
case t h e p r o o f s w i l l
play
role.
More D(X)
and
and
[A,B]
f i r s t c a s e w e are o n l y
an i m p o r t a n t
is an o b j e c t of
and
to c o n s t r u c t
system,
T
set,
free c a r t e s i a n
deductive
is a q u i n t u p l e
one-element
categorical
We s h a l l c a n be u s e d
are all theorems,
as f o l l o w s :
8 (A,B,C) : [C,A]
is "the"
category
is a b i f u n c t o r ,
isomorphisms
1
> B,
is a c a t e g o r y ,
~(A):
Here
Thus we see from
f i r s t is an axiom.
(3)
A,
A A B
or a theorem.
X
generally
one c a n f o r m a d e d u c t i v e
is a p r e - o r d e r e d
0: X
set by adjoining
> Y
system the a x i o m
- 79
whenever
X ~ Y
in
adjoining
a f a m i l y of a x i o m s
-
Df: X one
for e a c h m a p
it is i m p o r t a n t when
f: X
f @ g, e v e n t h o u g h
developed have
ignored;
equivalent?
Df
namely,
D
they assert
when
For technical as d i s t i n c t
g
the s a m e
on c o n c e p t s
are two p r o o f s
reasons axioms
formula.
and techniques
one q u e s t i o n
consider
by
,
X.
and
However
For example,
4 A A B A A B
is
lean heavily
by l o g i c i a n s .
is a c a t e g o r y
> Y
> Y
to r e g a r d
We s h a l l
X
X; a l s o w h e n
t h e y s e e m to
of the s a m e
formula
the p r o o f :
1 ) A A B > A
5 A A B -~-~ A A B A A B > B
6 A A B
Nobody would some
sense,
d e n y t h a t this p r o o f m i g h t b e r e g a r d e d equivalent
to the s h o r t e r 1
AAB
On the o t h e r hand, following
> A A B
proofs
there
A
A A
>AAB.
is a g o o d c a s e
AAA
In fact,
they
for c o n s i d e r i n g
as i n e q u i v a l e n t : 1 > A AA ~A
'
admit different
in
proof:
1 4
as,
5 A AA A~A
.> A A A >A
"generalizations".
the
-80-
Our p r o g r a m w i l l be to look at two kinds of structured
categories
constructions to discuss
in some detail:
standard
and c l o s e d categories.
also c a r t e s i a n
but time did not p e r m i t
It had been p l a n n e d
closed categories
inclusion
in this volume.
ment of this topic and also the d e v e l o p m e n t theory of s t r u c t u r e d
categories
and combinators, A treat-
of a general
must be deferred.
i. S T A N D A R D C O N S T R U C T I O N S
By a closure (A,T)
where
satisfying
A
s y s t e m we shall u n d e r s t a n d
is a p r e - o r d e r e d
the f o l l o w i n g
rules:
T(T(A)) A ~ B
write
T2(A)
for
A
and
it is useful
A.
etc.,
set
,
~ T(B)
It will be c o n v e n i e n t also
for c o n s t r u c t i n g
X.
of the form
Its terms T(A)
course,
instead of d e s c r i b i n g
we can,
in this case,
expressions
of
to look at a d e d u c t i v e
by a p r e - o r d e r e d expressions
B
,
~ T(A)
> T(A)
T(T(A)),
As a device
when
T0(A)
system
D(~)
are elements A
for
free closure
A.
systems
generated of
is a term.
X
and
Of
the set of terms recursively,
list all terms e x p l i c i t e l y
of the form
T
set with an o p e r a t i o n
A ~ T (A)
for all elements
a pair
Tn(x),
where
X
as b e i n g
is an e l e m e n t
of
to
- 81 -
X
and
n
is a n o n - n e g a t i v e
are e x p r e s s i o n s terms.
The formulas
A
where
> B
They also may be listed e x p l i c i t e l y
expressions present
of the form
integer.
of the form
the axioms
Tm(X)
A
of
and
D(X)
are
B
as b e i n g It remains
> Tn(y).
to
and rules of inference: 1A
A Q
A
> A
~ B
, P
B
A P~
> C
C
X ~
Y , whenever T2(A)
A h(A)_. T(A)
m(A[-
X ~ Y
T(A)
in
X,
,
P
A T(A)
T(P)_
The last rule of inference, as a rule for g e n e r a t i n g a given proof
P: A
) B T(B)
for example,
a proof
T(P):
m u s t be i n t e r p r e t e d T(A)
> T(B)
> B.
An example
of a proof
in
D(X)
is the following:
1 A
from
A>
T (A) T 2 (A)
A > T (A) - T 2 (A)
T 2(A) m(A)) 9 T (A)
denoted unambiguously
by
m(A)T2(IA ) .
T(A)
,
-
We now c o n s t r u c t
A
> B
as in
D(X),
is p r o v a b l e
D(X) ~
system.
-
the free closure
g e n e r a t e d by the p r e - o r d e r e d the terms of
89
set
A ~ B
in
in
D(X).
T(A)
seen that
means
F(X)
that F(X)
is a closure
F(X)
In w h a t sense is it free?
sets and order p r e s e r v i n g the c a t e g o r y of closure
maps.
mappings.
systems
mappings which preserve
T
Thus a strict map
A
> B
H:
A
of
(~,T)
A.
first g e n e r a l i z i n g forgetful
a left adjoint universal
(B,T)
is a map
It is a sore point of our theory
the f o l l o w i n g
functor
F
of
U
U: Clo
system
> U(F(~))
strict map
"~
and
statements
of "adjoint". > Ord.
There
k",
without is an
As is well known,
is d e t e r m i n e d by a S o l u t i o n to the Given any p r e - o r d e r e d
F(~)
so that for every closure
H': F(X)
set
and an order p r e s e r v i n g
and every order p r e s e r v i n g m a p p i n g a unique
>
= T(H(A))
the concept
m a p p i n g problem:
find a closure 6(~): ~
let us call them strict
in the above cannot be r e p l a c e d by
o t h e r w i s e we could not make
obvious
Clo we shall mean
in Ord such that
for all elements "="
By
of p r e - o r d e r e d
and those order p r e s e r v i n g
exactly,
H(T(A))
that
are
is the same in
By Ord we shall mean the category
H:
F(X)
Its elements
X.
and
It is easily
system
> A
H: ~
> ~
for w h i c h
X, mapping
system
(A,T)
there exists
- 83 -
U(H')
6(X) = H. UF (X)
F (X) k H'
(x)
\4
x
H
It r e m a i n s (X) (X) = X (X) X
order.
X ~ Y
Now, H:
X
H':
> A >
H' (T(A))
in f a c t
the
to
verified
list
formulas or
m = n
closure with or
or
system
the p r e - o r d e r n > i,
and
that
that
and verify
that
in
X,
hence
is any
then
provable
map
and,
by
where F(~)
elements
relation
are
out that
X ~ Y
Clo,
= H.
it is in f a c t
are p r e c i s e l y in
X
and
whenever successor
the
m = 0
to t h e
the n o n - n e g a t i v e
is the
= Tn(H(X)).
in
is i s o m o r p h i c
m ~ n T
map
U(H') ~(X)
They
and
and
H' (Tn(X))
is a s t r i c t
D(~).
system
Define
H' (X) = X
be p o i n t e d
Thus
for w h i c h
by
for w h i c h
of
closure
mapping.
at o n c e H'
> Tn(y)
whose
stipulate
X ~ Y
(~,T)
or all
theorems
n > i.
X
D(X) ,
preserving
strict
Tm(x)
if
in
that
it s h o u l d
all
of
recursively
(A,T)
only
X
We
F(X).
assume
Here easy
DX,Y
in
= T(H' (A)),
It is e a s i l y
~(~).
Indeed,
any order
F(X)
(~,T)
element
is an a x i o m
therefore,
A
to d e f i n e
for e a c h
preserves > Y
-
m = 0
integers, or
function.
m = n
-
We s h a l l see later, constructions, X ~ Y
in
that
F(X)
6(X)
84
-
in the c o n t e x t of s t a n d a r d
is full in the sense t h a t
only when
X ~ Y
in
X.
It w i l l also
f o l l o w f r o m w h a t w i l l be said later that Clo is e q u a t i o n a l (tripleable)
where
A
n: 1 A
o v e r Ord.
A standard construction
is a q u a d r u p l e
is a c a t e g o r y ,
- A
> T
satisfying
and
T: A
~: T 2
u. (nT) = 1
T
> T
is a functor,
say f r o m H: A
(A,T,n,~) > B
to
= ~" (Tn)
and
u. (uT) = u. (Tu).
and w h o s e maps, (B,T,n,~),
which preserve
and
are n a t u r a l t r a n s f o r m a t i o n s
Trip w e s h a l l m e a n the c a t e g o r y w h o s e o b j e c t s standard constructions
(A,T,n,~)
By
are small
c a l l e d s t r i c t maps,
are those f u n c t o r s
the s t r u c t u r e e x a c t l y ,
in the
sense that
HT = TH,
Hn = nH, Hu = uH .
W h a t has b e e n said in a p o l o g y for u s i n g s t r i c t m a p s
in
Clo also applies here.
We w i s h to c o n s t r u c t a left a d j o i n t to the o b v i o u s forgetful
functor
U: T r i p
s l i g h t l y m o d i f y the d e d u c t i v e
~ Cat.
To this p u r p o s e we
system
D(X)
m a y be any small category,
u s e d earlier.
Now
X
set,
and we m u s t s p e a k of the o b j e c t s r a t h e r t h a n of the
e l e m e n t s of
X.
not just a p r e - o r d e r e d
-
A l s o the a x i o m
D
Df:
that
Df ~ D
f: X
together with
objects
of
F (X)
are e q u i v a l e n c e certain
classes
~ B.
n, u, a n d
i
A
=
6 (X) : X
of p r o o f s
relation
~
We w r i t e
[P]
are d e f i n e d
[1A] , [P] [Q] = n(A)
=
reflexive
relation
satisfies
the f o l l o w i n g
(1)
D(X),
between
composition
o n l y by v i r t u e
thus:
=
[m(A) ] ,
~(A)
6 (X) (f) =
[Of].
the e q u i v a l e n c e
transitive,
of t h e s e
to a
of m a p s ,
[h(A)],
R{S ~ QS
F (X)
p r o o f s , to be
of
relation
symmetric, D(X)
rules
' rules
and
which
rules:
PR
of
according
[T(P)],
The s u b s t i t u t i o n
The
for t h e s e t of all p r o o f s
on the s e t of p r o o f s
P~Q
because
The maps
=
to s p e c i f y
We t a k e it to be the s m a l l e s t
> U (F (X)) .
D(X). of
construction
[pQ] , T([P])
(X) (X) = X,
It r e m a i n s
It is u n d e r s t o o d
t h e free s t a n d a r d
Identity maps,
6 (X)
,
X.
are the t e r m s of
defined presently.
T,
in
a functor
equivalence
Q ~ P: A
) Y
of a x i o m s
f ~ g.
We n o w c o n s t r u c t F (X)
X
) Y
whenever
g
-
is r e p l a c e d b y a f a m i l y
X,Y
one for e a c h m a p
85
P~Q T(P) ~ T(Q) are t h e a b o v e
- 86 -
definitions
of
(2)
[P] [Q]
and
Rules w h i c h
T ( [P] )
justified.
a l l o w us to c o n c l u d e
that
UF(X)
is a c a t e g o r y :
IBP The
l a s t rule,
following
_-- P,
P1 A
for e x a m p l e ,
A
(3)
R)
B
.
the e q u i v a l e n c e
(4)
C P'- A B
n
Rules w h i c h
(6)
assure
A
that
, T(PQ)
assure h(B)P
Rules which and
D
of the
B
>
C
T
that
n
, T(P)m(A)
assure
Q
> C P > D
C
.~ D
is a functor:
~ T(P)T(Q) are n a t u r a l :
and
~ m(B)T2(p)
the c o m m u t a t i v i t y
condi-
~:
m(A)h(T(A))
~ IT(A)
m(A)T(m(A))
~ m(A)m(T(A))
Rules w h i c h
assure
1x
DIx
PROPOSITION mapping
> B
A
~ IT(A)
T (P)h (A)
(5)
)
R
A
> D
Rules which T(I A)
universal
asserts
C
A
for
(PQ)R = P(QR)
two proofs:
B Q;
tions
- P,
, Dfg
I.
problem
that
~ DfDg
(F,6) for
~ m(A)T(h(A))
,
9 ~ (X)
is a functor:
9
is a s o l u t i o n
U; that
is,
of the
for e a c h
small
- 87 -
category and each map
X,
each
functor
H': F(X)
small standard H: X
>
Proof.
there exists
> A,
(A,T,n,u)
Given
constructions
such t h a t
H: ~
> A,
(A,T,n,~),
a unique
U(H')
~(X)
strict
= H.
we c o n s t r u c t
H'
as
follows:
H'(X)
Before
defining
P
D(X)
in
H' (T(A))
= H(X),
H'([P]),
recursively
= T(H' (A))
we d e f i n e
for e a c h p r o o f
H' (P)
thus:
H' (1A) = IH, (A) ' H' (PQ) = H' (P) H' (Q), H' (T(P)) H' (h (A)) = n (H' (A)) , H' ( m ( A ) )
It is e a s i l y
verified
sequently,
on the
w e are
length
H' (P) = H,(Q)
of the p r o o f
justified
hence
H'
one q u i c k l y
=
verifies
H' (P)
H(f)
,
of e q u i v a l e n c e .
.
that
H' ( T C A ) )
=
TCH' CA)),
H' ( T ( [ P ] )
H' (n(A))
= n(H' (A)),
H' (u(A))
is i n d e e d
=
in d e f i n i n g
H' ([P])
Moreover,
~ (H' (A)) , H' (Df)
that
P - Q---->
by i n d u c t i o n
=
= T(H' (P)),
a strict map
=
T(H' ([P]),
= u(H' (A)),
in Trip.
Con-
- 88 -
Finally
U(H')
6(X)(X)=
and these equations
REMARK a functor F
becomes
6:1
and
into a natural
in
Cat.
[F(X),
However
categories
of
In the p r e s e n t
the i s o m o r p h i s m
~(X)(f)=
As is w e l l known,
the left a d j o i n t
9 UF.
U(H')
force the d e f i n i t i o n
1.
~
H(X),
F
U
can be made into such that
with adjunction
situation
(A,T,n,u)]
,
H'.
transformation
~
this is not typical
and depends
of
H(f)
one can e a s i l y e x t e n d
[X,A]
in
Ens
to one
for s t r u c t u r e d
on the fact that
T
is a c o v a r i a n t
functor. REMARK that Beck's
Trip
2.
It may easily be shown at this
is e q u a t i o n a l
conditions.
this example structured
(tripleable)
However
to be typical,
Proof. we c l a i m that
the v e r i f i c a t i o n
is too easy in
and we shall defer
(a)
P ~ Df
2.
6(~)
it to another
is full and faithful.
Given a proof for some map
A c t u a l l y we shall show more generally > Y
length of
over Cat by v e r i f y i n g
category.
PROPOSITION
P: A
stage
has this form. P.
P. X f: X
> Y 9 Y
in in
D(X), X. I
that any proof
We p r o c e e d by i n d u c t i o n
on the
- 89
If
P = 1y,
then surely
there is n o t h i n g to prove. all ruled out. R: A
> B
we have
Q ~ Df
Therefore
P = T(A),
Q: B
> Y.
for some
assumption, P ~ DfDg
R ~ D
(b)
0
Suppose
) Y.
a proof
all o c c u r r e n c e s
of
and
i,
> Z.
later.
2
that
is the
and one n o n - i d e n t i t y
The @ e n e r a l i t y
P'
H ( 1 ) , and
in
H(
Let
H: ~
H(0)
and 9
of a proof
H: 2
D(2)
> X
such that P 9
results in
proofs have
for the moment, 9 ~
= X, H(1)
P'
P
in
for w h i c h P = H(P'). from
P'
if
are r e p l a c e d
respectively.
Equivalent
A s s u m i n g this (b).
g: X
and a lemma.
0
0, l,
L E M M A 1.
with
again by
we w i s h to prove
By the last e q u a t i o n we mean that
H(0),
are
assumption
Hence,
(a) will be given
is the set of all functors
there exists
by
m(A)
where
for some
g
P = Dr,
i.
DEFINITION. D(X)
or
By i n d u c t i o n a l
Df ~ Dg,
We need a d e f i n i t i o n
~
h(A),
If
~ Dfg.
c a t e g o r y w i t h two objects map
.
P = QR,
f: Z
An easier proof of
f = g.
P s Diy
There only remains
and
inductional
-
the same generality.
we shall continue
be d e f i n e d by
= Y, H(
>) = f .
- 90-
Then
>)
H (D
a map
x: 0
X
>
=
= Df. > 1
in
hence
,
Proof
Therefore, 2
--
f = g.
sketched.
by the lemma,
such that
H(D x) = D g .
It remains
to prove the lemma.
equivalence
Clearly,
We p r o c e e d by i n d u c t i o n
length of the proof that the given proofs For example,
there exists
on the
are equivalent.
assume that the last step in the proof of was a s u b s t i t u t i o n
P
rule,
say
_= Q
T (P) - T (Q)
By i n d u c t i o n a l Let in
H: 2 D(2).
assumption,
9 X Then
and P
H(P*)
= P.
Therefore,
H(Q')
= Q,
hence
= P, where
P*: T(A')
there exists
Q': A'
= T(H(Q'))
, B' >
B'
9 T(A)
For example,
the proof
T(A)
9 T2(A)
and with
h(T(A))
of the
T 2 (A)
to the axiom
seen to have
9 T(B')
= T(Q).
to point out that the converse
T 2 (A) ~
it is easily
have the same generality.
P': A'
lemma does not hold.
is not e q u i v a l e n t
Q
where
H(T(Q'))
We h a s t e n
T 2 ( A ) m(A)
and
= T(P'),
H(P')
above
P
T2(A)
> T2(A),
the same generality.
although
Indeed,
supposing
h(T(A))
m(A)
-- IT2(A)
.....
(7)
-
91-
we should have
n (T(A))
in
F(X).
not only
But then in
category
it w o u l d
F(X),
To see t h a t t h i s
but
free g r o u p g e n e r a t e d
deductive
For
sets,
T(A)
construction
idempotent
We s h a l l
see
l e m m a does h o l d
for the d e d u c t i v e
are known.
for the m e r e
existence
is a t h e o r e m
if and o n l y
and
m = 0
or
m = n
F i r s t we deductive
system
shall G(X)
the s a m e
but one relation
of the
a decision
terms A
A > B
this p r e s u m e s Note
if
constructions.
Given
of p r o o f s
and
is easy:
procedure B,
at l e a s t
that all maps
that a decision
if t h e r e e x i s t s
or
we have
t h a t the c o n v e r s e
of the f o r m u l a
f: X
X
set of t h e
idempotent
b y the e q u i v a l e n c e
D(X):
Of c o u r s e
in
A = the
constructions,
in o b t a i n i n g
up to e q u i v a l e n c e ? > Y
is c a l l e d
for i d e m p o t e n t
system
f i n d all p r o o f s
~ T(A)
construction.
= the underlying
constructions
later
We are i n t e r e s t e d
can w e
standard
T2(A)
A, etc.
rule to be s a t i s f i e d
on p r o o f s .
follow that
small
s y s t e m as for s t a n d a r d
additional
above
easily
in e v e r y
by
A standard .
= IT2(A)
is n o t so, t a k e for e x a m p l e
of c o u n t a b l e
nT.p = 1T2
u(A)
Tm(x) a map
procedure > Tn(Y)
f: X
> Y
n > i.
replace with
D(X)
the s a m e
by a Gentzen-type terms
and formulas.
- 92 -
However
has the following
G (X)
axioms
a n d r u l e s of
inference:
Df: X
when
P
A
" B r 6P) > T (B)
A
These
> Y
are d e r i v e d
rules
in
f: X
,
9 Y
9 B A
B 9
,
) T(B) (p)9 1 T(B)
T(A)
D(X).
9 T(B) (B)
~
P
A
In f a c t the p r o o f s
A A
in
> T (B)
, T(A)
> T 2(B) T(A)
T 2(B) > T(B)
> T (B)
show that we may define
r(P)
In v i e w of t h e s e
= h(B)P
definitions,
expanded
to a u n i q u e l y
converse
direction
(the e x p a n s i o n
of)
Proof.
I(P)
3.
= m(B)T(P)
e a c h p r o o f of
determined
we h a v e
PROPOSITION to
,
p r o o f of
.
G(X)
m a y be
D(X).
In the
the f o l l o w i n g .
Each proof
a proof
in
F o r any p r o o f
in
D(X)
is e q u i v a l e n t
G(X).
P: A
> B
in
G(~),
we
have
T(P)
= 1T(B)T(P)
-= m ( B ) T ( h ( B ) ) T ( P )
Next we shall
p r o v e by i n d u c t i o n
of
that
T
in
A
1A
~ m (B) T (h (B) P) = l(r(P))
on the n u m b e r
is e q u i v a l e n t
of o c c u r r e n c e s
to a p r o o f
in
G(X).
.
- 93 -
Surely
N o w assume
1 x ~ DIx.
IA ~ PA
in
IT(A)
There
- T(I A)
Again,
say
- h(A) l A
r(l A)
m(A)
- m(A) lT2(A)
remains
- T ( P A ) - I ( r ( P A ))
we have
h(A)
only
A,
for
then
G(X),
by the above.
the r e s u l t
- r(PA ) ,
- m ( A ) T (i T (A) ) = l(1 T (A) ) - I(PT(A) ) "
This
transitivity.
is h a n d l e d
by the
following: CUT E L I M I N A T I O N P: B
> C
to a p r o o f
are p r o o f s in
DfDg
in
G(X) ,
If
Q: A
then
PQ
) B
and
is e q u i v a l e n t
G(X).
Proof. occurrences
THEOREM.
We p r o c e e d in
by i n d u c t i o n
on the n u m b e r
of
T
Case
i.
Both p r e m i s e s
are i n s t a n c e s
2.
The
in the p r o o f
of
A, B, C. of
Dr.
Then
~ Dfg. Case
premise
uses
r.
last
step
of the s e c o n d
T h e n we have R B
A
Q-- B
R~
C
B
> T(C)
A
> T(C)
A
-_
~-~
B
B
>
A
) C
A
~ T(C)
C
- 94 -
since
r(R)Q
By in
inductional
=
(h(C)R)Q
- h(C)(RQ)
RQ
assumption
= r(RQ)
is e q u i v a l e n t
.
to s o m e
proof
G(X).
Case premises
A
use
S
T(A)
3.
I.
The
last
steps
in the p r o o f s
of b o t h
Then we have
> T(B) > T(B) T (A)
R
B T(B)
) T(C)
A
S
R
B T (B)
> T(B)
A
> T(C)
~ T (C)
T (A)
) T (C)
) T(C) ) T (C)
~
T (C)
since
I(R) I(S)
= m(D)T(R)
m(B)T(S)
-= re(D) m ( T ( D ) ) T 2 ( R ) T ( S ) _-- m(D)
T (m (D) T (R) S)
= I(I(R)S)
By in
inductional
.
is e q u i v a l e n t
I(R) S
assumption
to s o m e
proof
G(X).
Case premise second
uses
4. r
premise S
A
The
last
a n d the uses
) B
last
i.
B
R
step
in t h e p r o o f
step
of the
in t h e p r o o f
first
of the
Then we have
) T(C) R
A
>
T(B)
A
T(B)
> T(C)
>
T(C)
A
-
~
B
A
B
) T(C)
- T (C)
-
95
-
since
I(R)r(S)
= m(C)T(R)h(B)S
By i n d u c t i o n a l a s s u m p t i o n
-m(C)h(T(C)RS
RS
- RS .
is e q u i v a l e n t to a p r o o f in
G(X). The proof of the t h e o r e m is now complete.
The a d v a n t a g e of the s y s t e m D(X)
is this:
given a formula
A
G(X) > B,
over the s y s t e m we can find all
p o s s i b l e p r o o f s of this f o r m u l a in a finite n u m b e r of steps, by w o r k i n g b a c k w a r d s .
To give one a p p l i c a t i o n of P r o p o s i t i o n that
P: X
2(b); > Y
that is, that
in
D(X).
e q u i v a l e n t to some p r o o f o c c u r in the f o r m u l a f: X
let us p r e s e n t a new p r o o f
X
Q
6(X)
is full.
By P r o p o s i t i o n in
G(X).
) Y,
Q
3,
Since
m u s t be
P T
Df
Assume is does not
for some
> Y.
As a n o t h e r a p p l i c a t i o n ,
one m a y t r a n s l a t e
r e c u r s i v e d e s c r i p t i o n of the proofs r e c u r s i v e d e s c r i p t i o n of the m a p s follows that
F(X)
= F(1)
x X.
Lawvere, w h o also o b s e r v e d that the c a t e g o r y of finite o r d i n a l s
in
in
G(X) F(X).
the
into a It t h e n e a s i l y
This r e s u l t is due to Bill F(1)
is i s o m o r p h i c w i t h
and o r d e r p r e s e r v i n g maps.
We are now in a p o s i t i o n to o b t a i n the c o n v e r s e of L e m m a 1 for i d e m p o t e n t c o n s t r u c t i o n s .
-
COHERENCE Two p r o o f s
in
D(X)
Proof. to one
in
G (X)
Let
P: A
f
by
>
.
in
= X, H(1)
CONSTRUCTIONS.
D(X)
as
are equivalent.
is e q u i v a l e n t
the same g e n e r a l i t y ,
we
G(X).
in
Now,
P.
It c o n t a i n s
H: 2
))
obtained
= P.
G(X).
Define
= Y, H(
G(2)
H(P')
has the s a m e g e n e r a l i t y
has
) Y.
in
in
be a p r o o f
Df: X
Then
IDEMPOTENT
each proof
) B
be the p r o o f
-
the same g e n e r a l i t y
proofs
one a x i o m
P'
FOR
and t h e r e f o r e
H(0)
Let
with
Since
need only consider
exactly
THEOREM
96
) X
= f .
from
assume
Then there
by
P
by replacing
that
exists
Q: A
> B
a proof
*
Q
in
D(2)
Q*
is e q u i v a l e n t
H(Q*) P'
such that
H(Q').
~ Q'
It f o l l o w s
of
2.
Tm(0)
Proof. from symmetry,
=
But,
Q'
in
by Proposition G(2),
hence,
f r o m the l e m m a b e l o w
3,
also
that
hence
t
LEMMA
(P,Q)
= Q.
to some p r o o f
P = H(P')
proofs
H(Q*)
(Df,D), g
For
= H(Q')
- H(Q*)
idempotent
Tn(1)
in
constructions,
G(2)
consider
(I(P'),I(Q')),
any t w o
are e q u i v a l e n t .
We p r o c e e d b y i n d u c t i o n
we n e e d o n l y
= Q .
on
m + n.
the f o l l o w i n g
(r(P'),r(Q')),
Aside
cases:
(l(P'),r(Q'))
.
-
In the hence
first
case
97
f
-
and
g
are m a p s
0
>
i,
f = g.
In t h e assumption,
second
hence
The
We
case we have
P'
~ Q'
by
inductional
P ~ Q.
third
shall
case
is s i m i l a r
consider
the
to the
fourth
second.
case
after
the
following:
SUBLEMMA. then
B = T(C)
If
and
Proof.
A
This
of t h e p r o o f
of
is
is n o t h i n g
I, t h e r e
B = T(C)
ional
assumption,
hence
so is
and
A
> B.
is p r o v a b l e
is a l s o
provable.
induction
If the
to s h o w ,
last
so w e m a y
step
is a t h e o r e m .
C = T(D)
and
A
G (X)
length
in-this
assume
~ C
~ C
in
on the
T(A)
return
proof
it is
r.
By i n d u c t -
is p r o v a b l e ,
= B.
to the
fourth
case
in t h e p r o o f
of
2.
We have T (A)
) T(B)
Q' : T (A)
P'
~ B
is s h o w n b y
> T(C)
We n o w
there
> B
T(A)
Then
Lemma
T (A)
in
) B.
is a p r o o f
=- r(R)
and
Q'
proofs
P = I(P')
G(2),
where
In v i e w
of t h e
R: A
) B.
=- I(R),
and
P':
A
sublemma, By
Q = r(Q') > T(B)
of and
B = T(C)
inductional
and
assumption,
- 98 -
hence,
P - l(r(R))
= m(B)T(T(R)h(A)) - m(B)T2(R)T(h(A)) - T(R)m(A)T(h(A))
- T(R)
and
Q - r(l(R))
=
h (B)m(C)
T (R)
= h(T(C))m(C)T(R)
by the
the
idempotent
idempotent
rule
rule
(7).
comes
2.
We m i g h t biclosed \,
p,
monoidal
~, e,
8,
is t h e
only
place
where
in.
CLOSED
as w e l l category
Y)
This
- T(R)
CATEGORIES
start
with
a bang
as a 1 0 - t u p l e
(A,
and I,
define ., /,
where
is a c a t e g o r y , I
is an o b j e c t
9 : A_ x A_ k: A Z p p
x A P,
l,
> A_,
> A
are
~,
8, 7
p(A) : A
of
A,
/-
A_ x A ~
> A,
bifunctors, are
9 I
natural
) A,
isomorphisms:
l(A):
I
9 A
> A
> A. (B.C)
,
8 ( A , B , C ) : [A-B,C]
)
[A,C/B]
,
7 ( A , B , C ) : [A.B,C]
>
[B,A\C]
,
(A,B,C)
and
:
(A.B).C
,
a
-
such that the following
A.B
>
(A.I).B
) A.(I.B)
) A-B
,
(A.B). (C-D)
> A- (B. (C-D))
A- ((B-C).D)
>
(A. (B.C)).D
~
(A, I,
remarks
-, p, I, e)
were
Closed monoidal
categories
(A, I,
and Kelly
(1966).
(A,
., /, \ ,
Systems
and Categories
9
~
without
e, 8, 7) (I).
making
were d i s c u s s e d
were
However
and Kelly.
corresponding
categories
to residuated
(1963).
by M a c L a n e
Residuated
studied
changes,
from the paper by Eilenberg
.
" , \ , P, I, ~, 7)
in Deductive
one cannot
some other
>
Monoidal
studied by Benabou
conditions
categories
((A.B).C)-D
are in order.
"coherence"
studied by Eilenberg
studied
are identities:
>
The last two
and
maps
((A.B).C).D
categories
were
-
composite
Some h i s t o r i c a l
(1963) 9
99
strip off
as is clear
The deductive
system
had already been
in 1958 with a view of applications
to m a t h e m a t i c a l
linguistics.
With minor and Categories
changes
the proofs
(I) go through
in Deductive
to establish
Systems
the following
results: (i) together
with a functor
constructed deductive
A free b i c l o s e d
monoidal
6 (X): X
for any small category
system (2)
category
> U (F (X)) X
can be
using a suitable
D (X).
6 (X)
F(X)
is a full embedding.
-
D(X)
(3) system A
G (X) ,
> B
D(X)
(4) equivalent
may be replaced by a G e n t z e n - t y p e
allowing
in
I00-
one to find all proofs of a f o r m u l a
up to equivalence.
Two proofs of
A
> B
in
D(X)
are
if and only if they have the same generality.
To e x p l a i n in the paper
the concept
referred
to)
of g e n e r a l i t y
let us consider
(called
"scope"
two p o s s i b l e
definitions.
DEFINITION P: A
) B
where
X'
in
A.
D(X)
The G e n e r a l i t y
is the class of all pairs
is any small
category
functor such that there exists H(P')
of a proof
and
a proof
(X',H)
> X
H: X' in
P'
is a
D (X ' )
with
= P.
Here replacing
H(P')
is the proof o b t a i n e d
each object
by its image under
and each map of
X'
from
P
by
occurring
in
p,
H.
It turns out that when t e s t i n g w h e t h e r
two proofs
have the same G e n e r a l i t y we need not look at all small categories
X'
(sum of
disjoint
n
but only at c a t e g o r i e s copies
w i d t h of the given proofs. definition.
of
of the form
~), where
n
n~
depends
We make the f o l l o w i n g
on the
alternative
-
DEFINITION P: A
~
where
B
in
B.
D(X)
X' = n2
The @ e n e r a l i t y
for some finite
in
X
[A,B]
in
of a proof
is the set of all pairs
We note that compute
i01-
(3) and
F(X),
n
and
......
(4) t o g e t h e r
assuming
(X',H)
allow us to
of course that
[X,Y]
is known.
A functor is called
H
between biclosed monoidal
a strict map if it p r e s e r v e s
categories
the structure
exactly,
that is,
H(I)
= I,H(
9 ) = H(
Hp = pH, etc,
).H(),
H(~(A,B,C
)) = ~(H(A),
H(8(A,B,C) (f)) = 8(H(A),
Let
BMC
denote
categories,
the category
of exactly
A
functor
> L(B) L
is an absolute
with domain
BMC
consists
Tripleableness demand this:
isomorphisms.
and a functor
----> L(C)
> Cat
as m o d i f i e d by Par~,
Given two strict maps
C
reflects
etc.
construction
Precise
(2)
~ B
L (A)
of the s t a n d a r d
U
BMC
U: BMC
We may now ask w h e t h e r
conditions,
H(C)),
H(C)) (H(f)),
functor
(i)
in
H(B),
of small b i c l o s e d m o n o i d a l
in the sense of Beck's Beck's
(B, ...)
F.
the algebras
(UF, 6, -) Theorem.
H(B),
then the f o r g e t f u l
has a left adjoint
etc.
HI,H2:
K: B
Cat),
> C
coequalizer
is a c o e q u a l i z e r
(A, ...) such that
diagram diagram
then the pair
>
HI,H 2
(that is, for every has a
-
coequalizer
K'
We BMC
does
shall
and
shall
indeed
look
1 0 2
U (K') --~ K
not
give
satisfy
at a c r u c i a l
canonically.
here
the part
the
complete
Beck-Pard of the
proof
conditions,
argument
for
that but we
condition
(2).
Assume the
following
A~
that
x A
> B~
--
~
H
and
the
top
right
square
k
about
• A~
assigning the
functor
deal
these
x A
by the
A~
maps,
CS pp
let us
x C i
--
C __
the
two
squares
is an a b s o l u t e diagram. x ~
also
similarly
) C
denote
on the
coequalizer
It f o l l o w s to m a k e
it b y
also
canonical
• A~
with
the
\ .
that
the Then
functors
9
p
y?
transformations
> Ens 2
to e a c h m a p
functor
strict
the n a t u r a l
is to v i e w
followed
and consider
exactly.
We may
8: A ~
--
~
the b o t t o m
commute,
preserves
trick
given
> C Opp
is a c o e q u a l i z e r
is a u n i q u e
but what
are
2 Since
there
K
are
--
B L >) __
left commute. diagram,
• B
--
A
HI
K
diagram:
--
Since
and
HI,H2,
as f u n c t o r s , is the
functor
f: X x A
> Y
thus
functor
Ens 2
• Ens
/,
The
for e x a m p l e which,
> Ens
the p a i r
) Ens
to
and
when
x Ens
(X,Y) whose
yields value
at
-
(A,B,C)
is
103
-
( [A.B,C], [A,C/B] ).
We s h a l l n o w t u r n to a n o t h e r w a y of s t u d y i n g closed
categories
connection
by v i e w i n g
between
linear mappings
Gentzen's
in a l g e b r a
t h e m as m u l t i c a t e g o r i e s . method
Benabou
together with
a class
(1961).
also been
s t u d i e d by
being
any n o n - n e g a t i v e
are the i d e n t i t y m a p s composed
by
of a c l a s s
of o b j e c t s
..., A
..., A n
Among the multimaps
> A.
Multimaps
as f o l l o w s :
> B,
n
> B ,
integer.
IA: A
"substitution"
g: AI,
consists
of m u l t i m a p s
g: A1, A2,
there
have
out before
and C a r t i e r .
A multicate~ory
n
in l o g i c a n d m u l t i -
has b e e n p o i n t e d
I am t o l d t h a t m u l t i c a t e g o r i e s
The
f:
m a y be
Given multimaps
...r A,
...
> B
is a m u l t i m a p
f ( . . . , g , . . . ) : ..., A1, Substitution,
also called
T h e s e w i l l be s t a t e d
cut,
..., An, must
...
satisfy
as s o o n as w e h a v e
> B
~
four c o n d i t i o n s .
introduced
a conven-
ient n o t a t i o n .
We s h a l l u s e finite
sequences
capital
of o b j e c t s .
Greek
letters
to s t a n d
for
- 104 -
Thus a m u l t i m a p may be d e n o t e d by for the e m p t y sequence, b: ~
~ B
and
T
g: A
for w h i c h
> B.
n = 0.
We w r i t e
A multimap
may a l s o be r e g a r d e d as an e l e m e n t of are f i n i t e s e q u e n c e s of objects,
j u x t a p o s i t i o n is d e n o t e d by the c o m m a w h e n
~
or
T
#,T.
B.
If
their
The r e a d e r s h o u l d ignore
is the e m p t y sequence.
The cut
n o w takes the f o r m A
g>
A
~A,~
~,A,~
We s h a l l a v o i d the n o t a t i o n
f
B
) B
f(~,g,T)
for the r e s u l t i n g
m u l t i m a p as it tends to b e c o m e troublesome.
We now state
the four c o n d i t i o n s .
(i)
The f o l l o w i n g m u l t i m a p 1 A~ A
A
f:
f ~,A,~
#,A,T
(2)
is e q u a l to > B
> B
The f o l l o w i n g m u l t i m a p
is e q u a l to
g:
1A
A
(3)
> A ~,A,~
~; A ~,A,T
A
> A ) B
The f o l l o w i n g m u l t i m a p s
~,A,~ F,B,A > B > C F,#,A,~,A
are equal:
>
> C
,
A
F,BfA
)
F,#,A,~,A > A > C F,~~,A,~,~
B
> B
C
-
(4)
d
> D > C
The
~,C,8,D,T #,C,8,A,T
~,F,0tA,~
We may law,
following
call
and
The
multimaps
> B ~
B
F ,
(2)
A
identity
the c o m m u t a t i v e
reader
are equal:
> C > D
#,C,8,DrT
the will
class
laws,
> B
~,F,0,D~T
~,F,8,A,T
We denote [A;B].
-
> C
(1) a n d
(4)
105
9 B
> C
(3) the
associative
law for m u l t i c a t e g o r i e s .
of a l l m u l t i m a p s
appreciate
the
reason
A
> B
for u s e
by
of the
semicolon.
EXAMPLES 1. [A I,
...,
A
n
2. define
Thus,
Any
category
; B] = ~
a multicat
if w e p u t
n ~ i.
Any monoidal
category
becomes
a multicat
if w e
recursively [@;B]
=
[I;B]
,
[F;B]
=
[C;B]
-----> [F,A;B]
=
[C.A;B]
.
for e x a m p l e , [A,B,C;D]
3. if w e
for
becomes
define
Any
=
[(A.B).C;D]
(left)
closed
.
category
becomes
recursively [@;B]
=
[I;B],
[C,F;B]
=
[F;C\B]
.
a multicat
106-
-
Thus,
for example,
[A,B,C;D]
=
[C;B\(A\D)]
=
[I;C\(B\(A\D)) ] .
We also m e n t i o n given multicategory, categories M.
one application.
If
M
we may define M-categories,
for which
[A;B]
is
any
that is
is in some sense an object
of
This may be done in the same way as it was done by
Benabou
(1965)
for monoidal
Certain multicats monoidal
categories.
structures
are more easily
than into categories. multicats,
multicats,
Thus we may readily
left closed multicats,
and b i c l o s e d
introduced
multicats
into
define
right closed
by leaving
out u n w a n t e d
data
from the following.
A biclosed (M, I , . ,
/, \,
and
\
and
i: @
l: A,A\B mappings
monoidal
i, m, r, l)
are binary
where
operations
> I, m: A,B > B
multicate~or[
r: A/B,B
> A,
A.B,
>
T; C]
., /,
of
[r >
~; C] [r
,
A, B,
IF; A/B]
>
[F, B; A]
,
[F; B\A]
)
[B, F; A]
.
T; C]
M,
and
such that the following
and onto:
[~, I, ~; C] [r
is a multicat,
on the set of objects
> A.B,
are multimaps
are one-one
M
is a 9-tuple
induced
-
The
following
third
of the
cuts
s h o w how,
above
i >
I
mappings
~, I,
~, ~
_N
with
and with
E(f):
and
each
Let
are
induced:
> C
, F
E: M
> N
object
A
E ( A n)
Mult
the
first
> A/B
between of
f: AI, -----> B,
be the
M ...,
and
r>
A/B s B
A
) A
multicategories
an o b j e c t
E(A)
An
a multimap
> B
it p r e s e r v e s
category
and
of s m a l l
of
identities
multicategories
functors.
By a s t r i c t multicategories, structure
E(I)
monoidal functors
an e q u i v a l e n c e show
this
least
between
biclosed
which
preserves
= E(A)-E(B),
etc.,
E(i)
etc.
BMM be
> BMC
on o b j e c t s .
the
= i,
l
the c a t e g o r y and and
of c a t e g o r i e s ,
in d e t a i l .
monoidal
a functor
multicategories BMM
E
Thus
= I, E(A.B)
Let
map
we mean
exactly.
E (m) = m,
at
for e x a m p l e ,
F, B
each multimap
E(AI) , ...,
a n d cuts.
-
> C
A functor associates
~
107
Here
of
small
strict
maps.
BMC
> BMM.
but
biclosed There They
it is r a t h e r
is a d e s c r i p t i o n
are
obvious
establish
tedious
of t h e s e
to
functors,
- 108-
BMM
> BMC.
category
(M, I,
., /, \,
(A, I , . ,
/, \,
p,
multimaps
which
are n o t m a p s
example,
as
(A,
> A > A
A.I
> A
I,.,
I, u,
any biclosed
i, m, 8, Y)
r,
i),
as
follows.
monoidal
multi-
form
and define
p,
> B.C A,B,C
A,
Suppress u,
8,
all
B -1,
for
follows:
A A,I
A,B
Given
B,C
A.B,C (A.B) .C
> A.B A.B A,B ) C A > C/B
> C
BMC
Given
as f o l l o w s .
> A. (B.C) > A. (B.C)
> C/B
C/B,B
A,B
)
A.B
) C
) C
C
I
> BMM.
/,\,
A
B.C > A. (B.C) ) A.(B.C)
p,
I, u,
Define
A1,
any b i c l o s e d
B, y),
...,
form
A n
monoidal
(M, I,
> B
.,
/,
category \,
m,
as in E x a m p l e
r,
i)
2 above.
Let
i: @ m:
similarly
We
> A.B
mean
1
: A.B
B----> A
mean
B-I(IA/B) : A / B
now
whose
terms B
I
shall
M(X)
and
li:
1.
multicategory
A
mean
for
small
if
I
A,B
r: A/B,
and
)
are
turn
~, are
we
our
attention
can f o r m
the objects
terms;
A'B
of
and whose
>
I
8
> A.B
to BMM.
a deductive ~;
I, and
formulas
have
, ) A
9 B
Given
any
system A.B,
A/B,
the
form
A\B
-
AI,
A 2,
...,
Its
axioms
An
and
1 A.9 A
> B rules
> A
whenever >
~,~ ~,I,~
I; A , B
> C > C
;
relation
closed functor
of
U.
We deductive as
those
are
f: X,
...,
A-B;
X
~
;
can
and use
A,B A
showing
now
replace
M(X)
G (X) .
Its
terms
are
its
Here
Mf: whenever
and
and
) Y
f: Xl,
...,
Xn
) Y
>
I
>
9
F F,A
> C 5 ) C'D
r
) D
r
~,A,B,'~ r176
the
free
X
and
over
bia
left
Mult.
a Gentzen-type
Xn
@
- A ; B\A
equiva-
is t h e
formulas
axioms
;
B,A A
;
by
F
equational
by
) B
A\B
a suitable
that
...,
I
A,
'
;
> A > A/B
XI,
>
X
generated
be
M(X).
> Y
to c o n s t r u c t
F(X)
terms.
Xn
introduce it
are
in
> A;
BMM will
shall
B
follows:
> Y
n
C -~ C
> U (F (X)) Again,
as
A/B,B
that we
M(X)
and
M f : X 1 , ...,
multicategory
system of
inference
r ~,A-B,~
~ (X) : X
adjoint
Ai
cut;
~
on
monoidal
the
the
It is c l e a r lence
where
of
;
109-
rules
in ~
are
>C
the
of
same
inference:
_X , C
) C ) C
I
9
)
-
/
A,B
> \
> A
A
and
> A > B\A
A
> B @cArT @,A,B\A,T
Note
that, a s i d e
f r o m the a x i o m
> in
., /, \,
symbols
working
backwards,
in
eliminating
\
>
involves
s e r v e to i n t r o -
The notation
book.
Every
i.
) /
Surely,
one s y m b o l
r u l e of
\ ----> .
The o n l y n e w r u l e s
Here
is h o w the f i r s t
PROPOSITION to the e x p a n s i o n
Proof. of s y m b o l s
IA: A
Mf w h i c h
the r u l e s
left.
in K l e e n e ' s
A --~ D C,D > C'D F --~ C C,A > C'D F,A > C'D
whose
>
given
proofs
at e a c h
a
of it b y step.
is a d e r i v e d
G(X)
M (X).
Proof. and
half
> C ) C
w e c a n f i n d all p o s s i b l e
PROPOSITION
/
) C
on the r i g h t a n d the o t h e r h a l f
one on the
G(X),
-----> C
r
is f o u n d
formula
rule
@,A!T
B,A A
to i n t r o d u c e /
> B
> A/B
one of t h e s e
serve
-
A'
n o n e of the s y m b o l s duce
110
in
proof, > A.
A,
2.
A
in
when expanded
in
two are s h o w n
>
in
in
,
M(X): >
c
is e q u i v a l e n t
M(X)
G(X).
> A
A
., /
>
F i r s t w e show, that
>
A/B,B > A 0,A,~ ) B @ , A / B , B , T ---~ C
Each proof
of a p r o o f
are
by induction
on t h e n u m b e r
is a t h e o r e m
M(X),
in
is e q u i v a l e n t
G(X) to
C
-
Clearly
MIx:
> X,
X
C.D
) X
ix : X
since
6 (X)
> C.D
111-
is e q u i v a l e n t
is a f u n c t o r .
m a y be p r o v e d P
C
and we may and
assume,
Q -- 1 . D
equivalent
by
inductional in
thus
in
G(X) :
Q D ) D ) C.D ) C.D
) C C,D C.D
Expanding
to
assumption, we
M(X),
see
that
that the
P - ic above
is
to 1D D
) D
C,D
) C.D
Ic C
> C C,D
C,D > C.D > C-D
C.D
since
F(X)
=
> C.D
is a m u l t i c a t e g o r y .
is e q u i v a l e n t
to
[C.D;
>
C.D]
C/D
IC.D: [C,D;
C.D
C.D]
> C/D
Finally,
~
C.D,
Q D
) D C/D,D C/D
and we may and
assume,
Q - 1 D.
by
> C.D
C.D
) C.D
the
last proof
since
is o n e - o n e
m a y be p r o v e d
C,D
a n d onto.
thus
in
G (X):
P C > C
) C
) C/D
inductional
assumption,
that
P - 1
C
-
E x p a n d i n g in
M(X),
112
-
we see that the above
is e q u i v a l e n t
to
1C 1D D
C/D,D_ ) D C/D,D C/D,D > C C/D
since
~
F(X)
> C ) C
C/D~D ) C C/D --'-> C/D
is a m u l t i c a t e g o r y .
[C/D; C/D]
>
C\D
C/D
IC/D: [C/D,D;
C]
) C\D
Finally,
> C/D,
the last proof
since
is o n e - o n e and onto.
is t r e a t e d s i m i l a r l y ,
the i n d u c t i o n proof that
IA: A
> A
thus c o m p l e t i n g
is e q u i v a l e n t to a
G (X) .
) A.B
A,B
A
m a y be p r o v e d thus in
) A
B
A,B
Expanding
) C
C/D
is e q u i v a l e n t to
p r o o f in
C
in
>
G(X) :
- B
A.B
and u s i n g the above result, w e see that
M (X)
this is e q u i v a l e n t to 1B IA
B
> B
A,B
- A.B z
A,B
since
A'B
is a m u l t i c a t e g o r y .
A/B,B
with.
~
> A.B
F(X)
similarly.
A,B
>
A
and
B,B\A
>
A
are t r e a t e d
T h e r e remains the cut, w h i c h w i l l now be dealt
Let us,
for the moment,
a d d e d to the rules of
G(X).
assume that the cut has b e e n
,
-
1 1 3
-
CUT E L I M I N A T I O N THEOREM.
Every proof
G(X)
in
w i t h cut is e q u i v a l e n t to a p r o o f w i t h o u t cut.
Proof. G(X),
We a s s u m e that
e x p a n d e d into p r o o f s of
P
and
M(X),
Q
are p r o o f s of
and w a n t to s h o w that
the cut
A
Q - A
~tAr~
~,A,~
P )
B
) B
is e q u i v a l e n t to a p r o o f w i t h cuts of s m a l l e r degree.
By
the d e ~ r e e of the e x h i b i t e d cut we m e a n the t o t a l n u m b e r of o c c u r r e n c e s ~,
A,
~t
At
of the symbols
Case
We d i s t i n g u i s h
i.
P = Mf
and
Mg A
g
into
f,
in
since
>
Then
~(X)
,
> Y
~tAr~
Mh
> B
,
> B
X
o b t a i n e d by s u b s t i t u t i n g
is a functor.
The last step of
the m a i n o p e r a t i o n symbol of I
\
four cases.
Q = Mg.
~fX,~
is the m u l t i m a p in
C a s e 2.
it is
and
Mf > X ~,A,~
h
., /,
B.
Proof.
where
I,
A.
Q
does not i n t r o d u c e
For example,
then we c l a i m that
assume that
- 114 -
F,A F,I,A
R
R
> A > A
CtA, T P ) B 9 B
r
where
the
cut
this,
observe
on the
by
showing
>
I
> A
follows
the m a i n
A
degree.
I F,A
in v i e w
Hence,
our
~
B
r 9
To v e r i f y
F,I,A > A
of the
task
9 A
isomorphism
is e q u i v a l e n t
to
B
~
~
)
3.
>
,
the
the
The
F,A
associative
last
symbol
then we
cut on t h e
similarly
step
of claim
right
to C a s e
for multicategories.
I
F,I,A >
A
) A
~,A,~
r
from
operation
I
treated
>
'
F,A,A,T R C B 9 A FrI,A,A,~ > B FtI,A,A,T > B
where
> B ) B
> B
Case
Q
~
M(X),
~,F,I,A,~
this
it is
smaller
9 B
that
r
But
in
[F,A;A].
F,I,A >
has
> A 9 A
"inverses"
[F,I,A;A]
s
P
r
that
r,A F,I,A
must
right
FtA 9 A CtF,A,T CrFtItA,T
A.
of
law
P
for m u l t i c a t e g o r i e s .
does
not
For example,
introduce
assume
that
that
A Q > A
F,A,A,~
FrAtAf~
>
F,I,A,A,W
has
~
> B
smaller
2 above, u s i n g
) B
B
> B
degree. the
R
This
is
commutative
law
B
-
Case 4. introduce
115
-
The last steps of b o t h
the main o p e r a t i o n
assume they are
> I
and
symbols I
of
>,
r
)
P A.
and
For example,
then we c l a i m that
B
r r
>
> B
-----> B
This is an immediate [r
Q
consequence
of the i s o m o r p h i s m
[r
The reader may object that the examples u n d e r cases subcases
2 to 3 are h a r d l y
typical.
have already been t r e a t e d
Categories
in D e d u c t i v e
n + 1
objects
i,
..., n + 1
and
in
we mean the set of all pairs
is a finite direct H: X'
>
X
P'
M(X')
> n + i.
and only one n o n - i d e n t i t y
i, ..., n
in
Systems
we shall m e a n a category
multimap M(X)
all o t h e r
(I).
By a t e s t i n @ m u l t i c a t e g o r y with
However,
chosen
By the ~ e n e r a l i t y (X',H)
where
sum of t e s t i n g m u l t i c a t e g o r i e s
is a f u n c t o r with
PROPOSITION
H(P')
3.
of a proof
such that there exists
X'
and a proof
= P.
Equivalent
proofs
in
M (X)
have
the same generality.
This may easily be shown by i n d u c t i o n of the proof
that the given proofs
on the length
are equivalent.
-
PROPOSITION
116
-
The functor
4.
> U F (X)
~ (X) : X
d e f i n e d by
(x) (x)
=
x
6(X) (F) =
,
[Mf]
,
is full and faithful. The proof result
is similar to that of the c o r r e s p o n d i n g
for s t a n d a r d
constructions
COHERENCE are e q u i v a l e n t
T H E O R E M FOR BMM.
In view of P r o p o s i t i o n
show that two proofs same g e n e r a l i t y
involves
in
P
P,Q:
A ~
are equivalent.
X'
into
multimaps ...,
is the i n j e c t i o n X'
M(X)
in
2, it suffices G(X)
to
w i t h the
Look at all the axioms Suppose
the i-th axiom
" Xi,n (i) +i
be the d i r e c t sum of the t e s t i n g m u l t i c a t e g o r i e s
i,
Ki
in
the m u l t i m a p
whose non-identity
If
B
from left to right.
f i : Xi ,1 , ..., X.1,n(i) Let
Two proofs
only if they have the same generality.
Proof.
appearing
and will be omitted.
I
let
H: X'
HKi(J)
are > n(i)
n (i )
+ 1
.
of the i-th testing m u l t i c a t e g o r y .> X
be d e t e r m i n e d by
= Xi, j, HKi(
~) = fi
"
-
Now
generalize
P
fi
by
testing
P
the
i-th
is a s s u m e d
a proof
Q*
Proposition Therefore, P'
2,
Q*
That
LEMMA. multicategories
G(X)
any
for s o m e
X
and
be
assume
no o b j e c t
two p r o o f s
P
G (X') ,
Then
that
~ Q,
Let
in
proof
Q'
P ~ Q
will
a finite
in
X
occurs
and
Q
of
by
G(~).
follow
from
in a lemma.
> B
of
Since
we have
Now,
direct
A
= P. Q,
= Q.
shown
that
as
H(Q*)
be
replacing
H(P')
generality
is so w i l l
and
in w h i c h
Then
~ Q'
this
P'
same
such
H(Q')
-
multimap.
the
M(X)
also
~ Q'.
to a p r o o f
to h a v e in
117
is a f o r m u l a
more
A
s u m of t e s t i n g
than
once.
in
G (X)
> B
in
are
equivalent.
Proof. induction After and
on the
disposing P =
>
the
P =
last
roll
number of t h e
i.
step
F,~,~ ~ F,I,@,A
up o u r
of o p e r a t i o n
>
I,
Suppose of
Q
is
> C.D C.D
"
we
the
--->
Q _
in
and proceed
symbols
cases
9
step .
in
the
of
Then,
FtI,@
F-,I,%~
P
is
hence
F,8
~
C
also has
F,I,@ ~ - ~ > C
a proof
Q*
C
~ Q
~
C.D
C
in
Q = Mg,
I
say
I
,
> B.
following.
M(X)
F,@
by
A
P = Mf,
consider
last
-
Now we have
sleeves
preliminary
I, Q =
Case and
We
G(~).
> D
9
>
- 118-
By i n d u c t i o n a l
assumption
A*
pi
~ C ~ F,G ~ F,0,A .
.
Thus,
.
.
.
.
we wish
F,0
.
.
QW
to s h o w
A
F,I,0,A ;
these
,
.
FrO,A
[F,I,8,A;C]
Q,
proofs
in
M(X),
we
claim
D
A > C.D
that
C.D F~O--~ C A --~ D C,D--> F,I,0--> C C~A ~ C.D F,I,@,A -~ C.D
isomorphisms >
> C > C
~,@ > C [,I,0 ) C F,I,@tA
----> D > C'D > C'D
A--~ D C~D -~ C C,A - ~ C - D F,O,A--~ C.D r,I,O,A--> C-D
of the
F,0 F,I,0
that
f,0--~
In v i e w
put
N"
A ~-----~ D > C.D
> C
Expanding
we may
[F,I,8;C]
[F,8,A;C]
this
>
[F,0;C]
is t a n t a m o u n t
C-D
and
to s h o w i n g
that
g--~
I
F,I,0--~
F , I , 8 --~ C ..... C C~A--~ C.D F,0,A ~ C.D
F~O-.~
and
this
holds
Case and the
last
P =
As b e f o r e , both
i
C,A --> C . D > C.D
C
F,I,@,_A
F,0,A - ~
C.D
by associativity.
2.
step
Suppose of
Q
F,A P' ) A / B F,I,A ----> A / B
we use
premises
>
may
the
the
is
'
last > /
Q =
inductional
equivalently
be
step .
of
Then
F tI,A,B F,I,A
P
I
>
say
~ A ~ A/B
assumption inferred
is
to s h o w
from
that
F,A,B
~
A.
- 119 -
In v i e w of the monoidal
multicategory,
this
holds
~
3 and
a n d the
These
cases
the
cases,
p =
last
are
Case and
last only
show
the
4.
~--~ T,A
A
a biclosed
to v e r i f y
5.
Suppose
step
treated
of
I
that
F,I,A --> A / B > A/B A/B,B F,~,B--> A
> A
step
of
Q
Q
is
the
last
/
)
is
one of w h i c h
we
shall
) C ) C '
inductional
the
last step I
)
or
step
of
P
of
P
is
9
>
.
similarly.
Suppose
~,@,A/B,A,~ ~,I,0,A/B,A,~
Using
.
consider
A
I
as a b o v e ,
)
are t h r e e
sub-
as an e x a m p l e .
> B ~,I,8,A,~ ~,I,0,A/B,A,~
Q =
assumption
There
is
one w a n t s
) C ) C
to
that A
)
B
#,8,A,~
~,8,A/B,h,~ ~,I,8,A/B,A,~'
We omit
the e a s y
There have
one w a n t s
of
by a s s o c i a t i v i t y .
Cases I
isomorphisms
F,I,A--~ A/B A/B,B--> I r,I,A,B > A F,~,B > A
>
and
fundamental
already
ies
(I).
not
at all
>
C
> C > C
r
A {
~
C
> B ~,I,@,A,~; ) C ~,Z, 0 , A / B , A , ~ ----> C
verification.
are e s s e n t i a l l y
been
discussed
Unfortunately typical
the
of the
nine
other
in D e d u c t i v e five
cases
difficulties
cases.
Systems
and Categor-
considered that may
These
here
arise.
are For
120
-
example, X
have
cases,
assumptions
not yet been three
to t a k e warned
the s p e c i a l
the
lemmas
that
If
r
to
into
lemmas
The
these
the
remaining
reader
who wishes
matters
(Lemma
should
i), m u s t
be
be modified
as f o l l o w s :
>
B,
the m u l t i c a t e g o r y
To d e a l w i t h
to look
context
about
required.
one of t h e s e
in the p r e s e n t
is p r i m e
used. were
trouble
-
then
B
is p r o v a b l e
A
>
I
and
in
G(X)
r
~
and
B
are
theorems.
The We
say
that
contains
definition A
of
"prime"
is p r i m e to
no m u l t i m a p
~
f: Xl,
must
in
...,
also
G(X), X
be m o d i f i e d :
provided
> Y
with
some
X
n occurring
in a t e r m
of
A
and
Y
i
occurring
in a t e r m
of
4.
Just one
further
are
;
9
to g i v e
case.
the
Suppose
then we may
8
p
p = F
P--~ C
reader the
an idea,
last
steps
assert
that
a multimap
f: Xl,
and
D.
of
Y d
(Y = Yj)
in > D or
Q
t~ D F,@,A
...,
X
Y
through ZI,
and
> D
is p r i m e
Now
P
tl
9,.~
8
of
put
9
We
let us d i s c u s s
...,
to
> Y
n
must some Z
q
D.
be
For, in
> Y.
YI'
C-D
otherwise,
X --
introduced
axiom
>
...,
with
X. i
into Yp
there in
8
the p r o o f
----> Z
is
- 121-
The
first
possibility
as a d i r e c t In the
sum:
second
assumed is n o t
the
case
components
all
among
Z., 3 c o m p o n e n t s of
that both By
and, X,
0
>
inductional
~
I
Substituting that both
and
>
Q
One
final
the
Proposition
A
in
the A
) B
coherence > B
are
M(X)
would
up
theorem
be
X. in t w o
) D
lemma
to
are t h e o r e m s
in
F Q,
G
9
~
into
P
I
F,G
and
Q,
; C
F,I
9
C
) C
we may
show
to
A ) D C,D CrA ) D ) C-D F,I,A > C.D > C.D
) C-D
) C F,A
details.
word
results.
once,
mentioned
are e q u i v a l e n t
I
We omit
A
D
proofs
F,G,A
M(X) .
than
Y
in c o m m o n .
a contradiction.
above
'
F
in
more
of
As w e h a v e
> D
> D
these P
and
nothing
A,D.
therefore,
the
definition
assumption,
IrA
'G,A
I
in
occurs
again
invoke
A p,, ~ 8
X
by the
can have
occur
of
the
Now we may
G(X).
Z. 3
that no object
disjoint
infer
is e x c l u d e d
about
2 tells
the usefulness us h o w
to e q u i v a l e n c e . tell
equivalent.
us e x a c t l y
to f i n d
of t h e
all p r o o f s
Proposition when
above of
3 and
two proofs
of
-
Since multimaps in in
M(X),
F(X).
F(X)
122-
are equivalence classes of proofs
we thus have a method for computing
[A;B]
in
This assumes, of course, that the sets
[XI, ..., Xn; Y]
in
_X are known.
REFERENCES For additional items see the references in 4. [i]
Beck, J., "The tripleableness theorem", manuscript.
[2]
Benabou, J., "Alg~bre ~l~mentaire dans les categories avec multiplication", 258; pp. 771-774,
[3]
C. R. Aoad. Sc. Paris,
(1964).
Benabou, J., "Categories relatives", Paris, 260; pp. 3824-3827,
[4]
C. R. Acad. Sc.
(1965).
Lambek, J., "Deductive systems and categories
(I)",
Math. Systems Theory, to appear. [5]
Par~, R., "Absolute coequalizers"
in this volume
-
123-
POSSIBLE PROGRAMS
FOR C A T E G O R I S T S
by
Saunders
i.
Communication number
of u n s p o k e n
matician ples,
should
INTRODUCTION
among M a t h e m a t i c i a n s
rules.
talk about e x p l i c i t
late this e x c e l l e n t
Category
theory
arises
field and its p r o s p e c t s
a generality
in s u i t a b l e disciplines; ledge.
are the many p a r t i c u l a r
Logic,
knowledge
and folklore
of further d e v e l o p m e n t
a flourishing
it exists
designed
a variety
and a
fields in develops;
of formal Indeed,
of d i f f e r i n g
full
category
On the other to e n c o m p a s s w i t h from special
Mathematical
concepts
has
historically
generalities:
General Topology,
in that
demand
of results
to help o r g a n i z e
as a generality.
Set Theory,
specialty.
is an a c t i v i t y
formal concepts
been a s u c c e s s i o n
to vio-
in a field w h e n the k n o w l e d g e
No one c o l l e c t i o n
sufficed
I propose
In the last six or eight years,
theory has b e c o m e hand,
programs.
or concrete exam-
today is both a s p e c i a l t y
w h i c h current M a t h e m a t i c a l
time workers.
theorems
that a Mathe-
rule.
Specialities
a new s p e c i a l t y
is g o v e r n e d by a
One of these specifies
and not about s p e c u l a t i v e
generality.
MacLane
know-
for long there has
Mathematical
A b s t r a c t Algebra,
-
Lattices,
Structures
makes
of Mathematical
it all the more
ities be developed vigorously. speaks
of Category
Theory
to Algebraic
Topology,
other potential
ideas and Mathematical
imperative
that good general-
and its Applications,
of this conference
emphasizes
Homological
But Category
and Categories.
The title of this conference
organization
Geometry.
-
(in the sense of Bourbaki),
Today the proliferation specialities
124
Theory,
applications.
and the
the applications
Algebra,
and Algebraic
as a generality,
has many
Here we shall explore
a few
of them. 2. Our vital should develop,
NEW GENERAL first question
CONCEPTS is: What other generalities
above and beyond those of Categorical
I refer here not to refined types of categories like categories,
but to such brand new notions
suited to the codification
of knowledge.
Algebra?
or systems as may be
I do not venture
to predict what the new notions will be, but only that their development
will require
of Mathematical
results 3.
sharp attention needing
of category
theory require
ing, and adaptation general use.
comprehension.
THE REFINEMENT
For their efficient
to the multiplicity
OF CONCEPTS
use as generalities,
the concepts
a long period of polishing,
to put them in the most effective
For example,
the notion of an abelian
perfectform for
category
-
required before
time,
adjustment,
it became
and a p p l i c a t i o n
much
longer s h a k e d o w n
abstract
of adjoint
period.
like that of adjoint
successful
codification
functor.
are the u n i v e r s a l
Still,
adjointness
flexible
constructions
illustrate
the interplay
The d e v e l o p m e n t
the same point,
an e f f e c t i v e
generality
(not an elaboration)
4.
CATEGORIES
scene presents
are a few w h i c h
categories
("vertical"
and
lead to the of this
and B o u r b a k i
defining
these two aspects
a suppleness
of
of h o m sets)
may
theory as
and a p e r f e c t i o n
of concepts.
STRUCTURE
of generality, added elements
a category w i l l often of structure.
The
too many and v a r i e d such elements.
seem likely to live,
are e q u i p p e d w i t h
"horizontal"):
(1948)
adjoint
of many other concepts
WITH A D D E D
almost
idea
to shake down into fully
vive b e t t e r w h e n they are more s u i t a b l y double
idea about
isomorphism
in the u t i l i z a t i o n
come e q u i p p e d w i t h suitable
Here
between
is
but the
that the use of category
requires
As an i n s t r u m e n t
present
(1958)
required
the n o t i o n
sources
of Samuel
and natural
six or eight years
form.
of the latter
The p r o K i m a t e
(universality
took another
To begin with,
did not d i r e c t l y
and the basic paper of D. M. Kan functors.
functors have
linear t r a n s f o r m a t i o n ,
1929 by Stone and von N e u m a n n idea of adjoint
to sheaf theory
really workable.
The basic notions a much
125-
though some may sur-
renamed.
two sorts
Ehresmann's
of c o m p o s i t i o n
They have a v a r i e t y
of realiza-
-
tions,
including
some recent
(not yet published) ~liqative
tive up to a c o h e r e n t
arrows
categories
consist
compositions
position
cluded as the special
sufficiently
complex,
clear w h e t h e r gories"
The com-
only up to
category
is in-
just one object.
of this idea is most suggestive,
so that it may be a w h i l e before
the s t r a i g h t - f o r w a r d
H where
generalization
but
it is
to "tricate-
Modifying
role is p l a y e d by those m u l t i p l i c a t i v e
for each object the functor
has a right a d j o i n t an e a r l i e r
m i g h t best be called
(an i n t e r n a l h o m functor terminology autonomous
lar, that their d e f i n i t i o n lying c a t e g o r y
Xl
is a s s o c i a t i v e
Gode-
is viable.
categories
each
calculus.
bi-
with
following
case of a b i c a t e g o r y w i t h
A fundamental
special
and
Benabou's
and two-cells,
so the m u l t i p l i c a t i v e
development
they
of objects
and of two-cells,
in a b i c a t e g o r y
associa-
isomorphisms;
five rules of f u n c t o r i a l
c o h e r e n t isomorphisms,
are c a t e g o r i e s
of arrows,
arrows,
The multi-
operation,
consists
with composition of objects,
of arrows
The further
product
a category
both of arrows
ment's well known
categories)
family of n a t u r a l
While
(morphisms),
tensor
by Paul P a l m q u i s t
of adj~nctions.
( = monoidal
an a b s t r a c t
are omnipresent.
applications
to the theory
cate~origs
equipped with
126-
case;
of sets.
of Linton's, cate@ories.
requires
A cartesian
it is a c a t e g o r y w i t h
> A >< X
X! Y:
> A | X ;Hom
(A,Y)).
such categories Note,
no r e f e r e n c e
in p a r t i c u -
to an under-
closed c a t e g o r y 9 is a finite p r o d u c t s
has a right adjoint;
in w h i c h
the lectures
of Law-
-
127-
v e r e at this c o n f e r e n c e i n d i c a t e the i m p o r t a n c e of this n o t i o n (the t e r m i n o l o g y ,
due to E i l e n b e r g - K e l l y ,
since t h e i r s o - c a l l e d c l o s e d c a t e g o r i e s With autonomous
categories
tensor p r o d u c t is n o t b o t h Xl
to the b i a u t o n o -
commutative,
the a b s t r a c t but where
> X ~ A h a v e r i g h t adjoints.
e x p e c t that t h e s e n o t i o n s
5.
comes
categories where
(known to be)
> A ~ X and Xl
do n o t e x i s t in nature).
one n a t u r a l l y
mous categories--multiplicative
is not fortunate,
still r e q u i r e
One can
a shake-down.
AXIOMATIC MANIFOLDS
C a t e g o r y t h e o r y o r i g i n a t e d in c e r t a i n q u e s t i o n s a l g e b r a i c topology,
and h i t h e r t o its a p p l i c a t i o n s
to c l u s t e r there and in a l g e b r a i c
geometry.
have t e n d e d
In the future,
this may n o t be the case; t h e r e m i g h t d e v e l o p e x t e n s i v e cations in other fields of M a t h e m a t i c s . m a y be the case in d i f f e r e n t i a l n o t yet u n d e r g o n e
I speculate
geometry,
appli-
that this
a s u b j e c t w h i c h has
the r a t i o n a l i z a t i o n e x p e r i e n c e d by t o p o l o g y
and a l g e b r a i c geometry.
For instance,
one m i g h t s e a r c h for
axioms on the c a t e g o r y of all C ~ - m a n i f o l d s gory e n l a r g e d
of
to c o n t a i n s u i t a b l e
or on this cate-
infinitessimal
objects
(as
in L a w v e r e ' s u n p u b l i s h e d w o r k on c a t e g o r i c a l dynamics).
6.
It is an e l e m e n t a r y
UNIFOLDS
observation
that c a t e g o r i c a l
m e t h o d s h a v e had no e f f e c t u p o n analysis,
classical
There m a y y e t be some n o t i o n s
open to such appli-
of a n a l y s i s
or abstract.
-
cations.
128-
One p o s s i b l e p l a c e is the t r e a t m e n t of t h o s e
p e r t i e s of f u n c t i o n s Xl,...,x m
f ( x l , . . . , x m)
of s e v e r a l v a r i a b l e s
w h i c h d e p e n d n o t on the e x p l i c i t
choice of the v a r i -
ables, b u t on the local g e o m e t r i c a l p r o p e r t i e s U with coordinates
X l , . . . , x m.
local p r o -
of a n e i g h b o r h o o d
These are, if you will,
proper-
ties of the s m o o t h m a n i f o l d in w h i c h U is a n e i g h b o r h o o d . ever,
the~e are m a n y such p r o p e r t i e s w h i c h are s t r i c t l y
and so n e e d no g l o b a l r e f e r e n c e to a manifold. n o t i o n may be that of a "unifold".
How-
local
The a p p r o p r i a t e
A C m- u n i f o l d
(a u n i f o l d of
class m) is d e f i n e d to be a set U t o g e t h e r w i t h a set F of r e a l valued functions
f: U---> ~, for w h i c h
i n t e g e r n, a list
Xl,...,x n
there e x i s t s a p o s i t i v e
of f u n c t i o n s in F and an open set
!
U
in _Rn all s u c h t h a t
u:
>
(Xl(U) ,...,x n
(u))
is a b i j e c t i o n
$
of U to U
for w h i c h the f u n c t i o n s
f in F are p r e c i s e l y the com!
posites words,
g ( x l , . . . , x n)
w i t h g a C m f u n c t i o n on U
to ~.
a u n i f o l d is just an open set in R n, b u t w i t h o u t
c h o i c e of any one c o o r d i n a t e
system.
In other the
Those local p r o p e r t i e s
of f u n c t i o n s of s e v e r a l v a r i a b l e s w h i c h are i n d e p e n d e n t of the c h o i c e of v a r i a b l e s folds.
can be n a t u r a l l y
For instance,
teristics
s t a t e d as p r o p e r t i e s
this is the case for the t h e o r y of c h a r a c -
of first order p a r t i a l d i f f e r e n t i a l
7.
of u n i -
equations.
A X I O M S ON THE C A T E G O R I C A L L E V E L
The a x i o m a t i c m e t h o d is u s u a l l y t a k e n to b e a w a y of s t u d y i n g a g r o u p or a t o p o l o g i c a l space by axioms v a l i d in any one g r o u p or in any one t o p o l o g i c a l ,, L
space.
An alternative
129
-
now open is that of considering holding
for the category
spaces. axioms
-
as axioms
those properties
of all groups or of all topological
This prospect was first envisaged by Lawvere for the category
Category
of Sets)
(The Category
and others.
many such systems--not
axiom systems
have been studied
just the one, noted above,
UNIVERSAL possible
ALGEBRA use of category
algebra has not yet been realized.
the basic idea,
as formulated
in Lawvere's
braic system is usually described tain unary, binary, fied identities. with a binary (the inverse), which together
ternary,..,
For example,
operation
satisfy
For each group-word
operations
in
Let us recall
thesis.
An alge-
satisfying
speci-
a group is a set G together
operation
the well-known
a unary operation
(the group identity) group axioms.
However,
are clearly not the only ones at hand.
W(Xl,...,Xn)
free group)
in n letters
x i (in the
there is the n-ary operation
> w(gl,...,g n) on G.
deals simultaneously
theory
as a set together with cer-
(multiplication),
and a nullary
these three operations
corresponding
of axioms
of all smooth manifolds.
The attractive
gl,...,gn:
for Mathematics).
It would seem that there might be
8.
universal
of all categories
as a Foundation
such "global"
on the category
(An E l e m e n t a r ~ Theor ~ of the
and for the category
of Cate@ories
Some additional by Schlomiuk
of sets
in his
The theory of groups
with all these operations.
really
By speaking
-
of m - t u p l e s
tive integers).
theory
This
as m o r p h i s m s
a category
is an i n v a r i a n t
It c o m p a r e s
inverse, abstract
by p a r t i c u l a r
group compares
generators
rewriting
the results
invariant
language
still remains
practise
of M a t h e m a t i c s
of C a t e g o r y categories
Theory.
years
(multipliof an indi-
of that group
The i m p o r t a n t
algebra
in this
task of
appropriate
FOUNDATIONS
that the c l a s s i c a l m e t h o d
set theory
as a f o u n d a t i o n
is no longer adequate
The device
in some G ~ d e l - B e r n a y s
a r r a n g e m e n t w h e n it was
operations
of group
to be done.
It is an open scandal Zermelo-Fraenkel
of the theory
description
to a p r e s e n t a t i o n
of u n i v e r s a l
applying
the n o n - n e g a -
just as the n o t i o n
and relations.
9.
> m, the
description
to the c l a s s i c a l
and identity)
n
(with objects
as the study of three p a r t i c u l a r
cation, vidual
-
of n - a r y operations
theory of groups b e c o m e s
of groups.
130
of
for all
to the p r a c t i s e
of h a v i n g b o t h
large and small
set theory was a c o n v e n i e n t
first p r o p o s e d by E i l e n b e r g - M a c L a n e
ago, but it no longer convenes
for functor
23
categories
(with large domain category)
or for the c a t e g o r y of all cate-
gories
of fibered c a t e g o r i e s
as used in the t h e o r y
bou's profunctors. in a G r o t h e n d i e c k
The a l t e r n a t i v e
U n i v e r s e has been e f f e c t i v e
w i t h the d e v e l o p m e n t tions
arrangement
of M a t h e m a t i c s ,
as to i n a c c e s s i b l e
to do w i t h the case,
or in Bena-
of categories
for g e t t i n g
but it i n t r o d u c e s
on
assump-
c a r d i n a l s w h i c h p a l p a b l y have n o t h i n g
and it leaves u n s e t t l e d
(as yet)
a variety
-
of q u e s t i o n s
of the p o s s i b l e
131
-
effects
resulting
from a shift of
universe.
W h a t should we conclude? v i d e d by one "monolithic" Principia Mathematica lithic character, lated w i t h i n of labor,
f o u n d a t i o n has b e e n
one system.
This p r o v i d e d
between Mathematicians form)
the system various
is i r r e t r i e v a b l y Mathematicians
lost;
s e c u r i t y pro-
lost.
and then Z e r m e l o - F r a e n k e l
that all w o r k i n g M a t h e m a t i c s
(usually in a "naive" within
The happy
who
First
had this m o n o could be formu-
a convenient
just "used"
division
the s y s t e m
and the L o g i c i a n who i n v e s t i g a t e d
classical
problems.
This p a r a d i s e
it is high time that o p e n - m i n d e d
set to work to c o n s t r u c t
young
a new one--perhaps
less
monolithic.
10 .
This brief the p r o f i t a b l e
survey does not p r e t e n d
current problems
as a generality. various
CONCLUS ION
specific
A much b e t t e r talks
in C a t e g o r y coverage
to cover all
Theory
and its use
is p r o v i d e d by the
given at this c o n f e r e n c e - - a n d ,
by the other new and d i f f e r e n t
ideas w h i c h
we hope,
lie in the future.
-
ABSOLUTE
132-
COEQUALIZERS
by
R o b e r t Pare~
The c o n c e p t of s p l i t c o e q u a l i z e r plays role in B e c k ' s t r i p l e a b l e n e s s this n o t i o n does have
theorem
(see
[i]).
an i m p o r t a n t Although
some j u s t i f i c a t i o n in the f a c t that
it is p a r t of a c o n t r a c t i o n of a s i m p l i c i a l
object,
it is
s o m e w h a t artificial.
In this p a p e r we c o n s i d e r an e q u i v a l e n t f o r m u l a t i o n of B e c k ' s
t h e o r e m in w h i c h
the n o t i o n of s p l i t c o e q u a l i z e r
r e p l a c e d by the m o r e n a t u r a l n o t i o n of a b s o l u t e A l t h o u g h the n e w c o n d i t i o n s w o u l d appear, be m o r e d i f f i c u l t
to verify,
p r a c t i c e is the a b s o l u t e n e s s
it seems property.
fact that we have no e q u a t i o n ,
is
coequalizer.
at first glance,
to
that all we n e e d in In m a n y cases,
but only a b s o l u t e n e s s
the
leads to
m o r e c o n c e p t u a l proofs.
In the first p a r t of this paper, we give the n e c e s sary d e f i n i t i o n s
and o u t l i n e
this p o i n t of view.
the p r o o f of B e c k ' s
theorem from
Then a p r o o f that the c a t e g o r y of semi-
groups is t r i p l e a b l e o v e r sets is s k e t c h e d to show h o w t h e s e new conditions
can be used.
-
133
-
The second part contains of absolute absolute
coequalizers.
coequalizers
Professor
characterizations
Then it is shown that
which
like to thank my d i r e c t o r
Lambek,
for his guidance
Definition
there exist
are not split.
I would
I. d Y1 -'L'>
several
of research,
and e n c o u r a g e m e n t .
Let A be a category
i:
and let
d Yo
*" Y
be a c o e q u a l i z e r
d i a g r a m in A. -
(do, dl;
d)
1
is called an a b s o l u t e and every
functor
coe~ualizer
G : A
> C,
if for every
category C
(G(d o) ~ G(d I) ; G(d))
is
also a coequalizer. e Let U : B
>
A be a functor.
do
Definition
2,
Let
Yo be maps
Y1
in
B.
dI d is U - a b s o l u t e
(do , d I) 9
if there e x i s t
U(d ~ )
in A such that
U(Y I)
--
Z and
> z
U(Y o)
d
~
U(Yo)
> Z is an absolute
co-
U (d I )
equalizer.
Definition each U - a b s o l u t e essarily
3:
B has U - a b s o l u t e
pair of maps
absolute)
in B.
in B has
coequalizers
a coequalizer
if
(not nec-
134
-
Definition if w h e n e v e r Yo
> Y
Y
1
~
in ~,
>
-
4:
U ~
U-absolute
Yo
is U - a b s o l u t e
the c a n o n i c a l
map
and h a s
Z
coequal izers a coequalizer
> U(Y)
is an i s o m o r -
phism.
Definition Y1
> Y
> Yo
by U implies essarily
5:
U reflects
being
Y1
mapped
> Yo )
absolute)
: A
> B.
to a triple algebras
and
is a c a n o n i c a l
:
map
U
adjoint
(T,n,~)
UT
coe~ualizers
an a b s o l u t e
if
coequalizer
is a c o e q u a l i z e r
(not n e c -
in B.
This
T =
into
> Y
F r o m n o w on let F
U-absolute
: B
pair gives
on A.
2A
> A
_ > A
# : B
Let A 2
have rise
(see
[6] or
be the category
its u n d e r l y i n g > AT
a left adjoint
making
[2]) of T-
functor.
There
the f o l l o w i n g
dia-
gram commute : r
Definition has
6:
U is s a i d to be t r i p l e a b l e
a left a d j o i n t ~ s u c h t h a t
the a d j u n c t i o n s
i
if > r
AT and
r162
> 1
are n a t u r a l
isomorphisms.
B
We can n o w
Theorem: has U - a b s o l u t e absolute
state Beck's
tripleability
U is t r i p l e a b l e
coequalizers,
coequalizers.
-:
-
theorem.
U has
and U p r e s e r v e s
a left adjoint,
and reflects
U-
135-
-
dO Y I ~
Remark:
if
there
exist
lowing e q u a t i o n s
h
dl
Y-----~
YO
d Yo
is a split c o e q u a l i z e r
> Y hI
and
u
such that the fol-
> Y1
0
are satisfied: ddo = dd I dh
= i
hd
= doh I
Y
dlhl = iyo Equations izer,
(i) imply that
(1) 9
(do, dl; d)
thus we conclude that split c o e q u a l i z e r s
If we replace in the p r e c e d i n g
the w o r d
definitions
is a c o e q u a l are absolute.
absolute by the w o r d
split
and theorem, we obtain the origi-
nal form of the theorem.
Proof special
of theorem:
case of absolute
Since split
ones,
coequalizers
the s u f f i c i e n c y
are a
of the c o n d i t i o n
offers no difficulty. Now, that
B = AT
reflects,
suppose
that U is tripleable.
and prove
uT-absolute
that
and U T p r e s e r v e s
(YI' el)
> >(Yo,
8 o)
T be a U - a b s o l u t e
dI pair of maps equalizer
in A T .
and
coequalizers. do
Let
A T has,
We can assume
We have
the f o l l o w i n g
in A: do
Y1 ~-~---~ Yo L
~
1
d
> Y "
absolute
co-
-
136-
Consider the following diagram: T (d) O
T (d)
T(YI
~ T(Y )
j
T(dl)
01
1 eo
do
> T(Y)
>Y~ )
Y1
18
d
~Y
dI The upper and lower squares on the left commute s i n c e d o d I are T-homomorphisms.
Thus,
dSoT(d o) = ddo81 = ddl81 = deoT(d I) , but is a coequalizer; e
: T(Y)
and
(T(d o) , T(d l) ; T(d))
therefore there exists a unique
> Y making the square on the right commute. We shall prove that (Y,e) is a T-algebra.
Consider
the following cube : TT Yo)
J
TT(d)
T(Y )
T(d)
"~ T(Y.)
T(d) ~u(Y)
"Yo-
T(Y
TIe) ~ T(Y)
The top face commutes because of the 8o-aSsociativity
axiom.
One lateral face commutes by naturality of u, the other three by definition of 8.
Since
(TT(d o) , TT(d I) ; TT(d))
is a co-
137
-
equalizer mutes
TT(d)
-
is epi, and thus the bottom face also com-
(see [7], p. 43).
This proves the 8-associativity axiom.
To prove the 8-unitary axiom, consider:
"•) d
T
Yo ) T(d)
1
Y
d
~ I Y
/ T(Y)
The top face commutes
by the @o-unitary axiom, one lateral
face commutes by naturality of n, one by definition of 6, and the other trivially. commute.
Since d is epi the bottom face must also
(This diagram is actually a degenerate cube.) We have proved that
(Y,8) is a T-algebra,
and by de-
finition of 8, d is a T-homomorphism. Finally, morphism,
d = coeq (do, d I)
x, coequalizes
(do, d l)
in A_T for if a T-homo-
in A_T, it also does in A,
and thus there exists a unique z in A such that the following diagram commutes : do Yl--dl
d ~ Y~
/ /zY X~
It is easily verified that z is a T-homomorphism.
-
We have This
-
shown that A T has
construction
UT-absolute
138
also shows
UT-absolute
that UT preserves
coequalizers. and reflects
coequalizers. Q.E.D.
As an a p p l i c a t i o n t he c a t e g o r y i n t o sets,
of s e m i g r o u p s ,
is t r i p l e a b l e .
out for any a l g e b r a i c
of this with
theorem,
the u s u a l
The a r g u m e n t
we will
underlying
functor
can e a s i l y b e c a r r i e d
category. d
L e t Yl'
show that
Yo be t w o s e m i g r o u p s
and let
o
Y
> Yo
d 1--a l d o
b e two h o m o m o r p h i s m s .
absolute
coequalizer
structure
Assume
in sets.
that
Y
> Yo
We must define
respectively,
(dQ,d 0) 1
x Y1
....
1 d o and d~
a functor,
a unique
m
do
Y
X
m
d
> %
;~
d 1 are h o m o m o r p h i s m s ,
left c o m m u t e .
do)
> Y
m o
y
dmo(do,
of Y 1 a n d Yo
(d,d) ~. Y0 > x Yo
mI
fines
a semigroup
we have:
Y
o n the
is an
on Y, so t h a t d is a h o m o m o r p h i s m .
If m I a n d m o are th e m u l t i p l i c a t i o n s
Because
~- g
Since
the u p p e r
X-~-~-> X x X, f---~--> (f,f)
the t o p row is a c o e q u a l i z e r
= ddom I = ddlm I = dmo(dl, : Y x Y
> Y
and l o w e r
making
d I)
de-
diagram.
thus there
the s q u a r e
squares
exists
on the r i g h t
-
139
-
commute.
To see that m is associative,
consider
the following
cube :
iyo
.iyo
y2 ~
(d,d,d)
~ " ~ y2
(d,d)
(d ,d)
The top face commutes because faces
commute by definition
fore the b o t t o m must a semigroupo
It is easily
(d,d,d)
This
the lateral
is epi,
shows
that
there-
(y,m)
is
of m, d is a homomorphism.
verified
of semigroups.
the u n d e r l y i n g We conclude
of d, and
also commute.
By d e f i n i t i o n
the category
m ~ is associative,
d = coeq
It is also easy
functor preserves
that the category
that
to verify
and reflects
of semigroups
(do, d I)
in that
the right
things.
is tripleable
over
sets.
II. absolute
We shall now see several
coequalizers.
characterizations
of
-
140
-
d o
Theorem:
Let
d
Y1
~ Yo
> Y
be a c o e q u a l i z e r
d1 in A.
The
following (i)
(do, dl;
d)
statements
(do, dl;
d)
is p r e s e r v e d
(ii)
(d o , dl;
are e q u i v a l e n t :
is an a b s o l u t e
coequalizer,
i.e.
by all f u n c t o r s d)
is p r e s e r v e d
b y all r e p r e s e n t a b l e
functors (iii)
(d o , dl;
d)
is p r e s e r v e d
by
[Y, -] and
an i n t e g e r
n ~ 0 and ~h,
hi
(i ~ i ~ n)
[Yo , -]
(iv) in A such
that h
Y
h. I
~ Yo
> YI
verifying dd o = d d I
d
u(2)
dh
= 1
hd
= d
h
= d
i
d u(4) h 2
=
d
Y
~(I)
uC3)
h1 h2
~(5) h 3
o
a
d~(2n)h n where
~(i)
= 0 o r ~i. Proof:
(Jill
= iyo
.... (iv)
(i) : [Y, Yl ]
"- (ii)
"- (iii)
[Y,d ] .7 >
[Y,d 1 ]
[Y,Yo]
obvious. [Y,d]
>
[Y,Y]
maps
- 141 -
is a c o e q u a l i z e r Let
diagram
h s [Y,Yo]
in sets.
such that
is t h e r e f o r e
[Y,d] (h) = iy, [Yo,
Now
[Y,d]
i.e.
dh
=
onto. iy.
[Yo, d]
d o] > >
[Yo, Y1 ]
[Yo' Xo]
>
[Yo, Y]
[Yo ' d I] is also a c o e q u a l i z e r
[Yo,
d] (hd)
in sets.
= dhd
= d =
[Yo,
d] ( i y )
,
0
thus,
by the c o n s t r u c t i o n
of the c o e q u a l i z e r
in sets,
hd ~ 1y O
w h e r e '~ i s
the
equivalence
relation
generated
R = { (dox , dlX) I x 6 Thus
there e x i s t s
an i n t e g e r
by the
relation
[Yo , Y 1 ] } -
n > 0 and
~h. : Yo
> Y
1
(i = i, 2, 3,
.~
n)
such that hd = d
~(i)
h1
d ~(2) hl= d v (3) h 2 d~(4)h2 = d
d (2n)hn= where
9(i)
= 0 or 1.
(5)h3
iyo
We o b v i o u s l y
also h a v e
the r e l a t i o n
dd o = dd I 9 (iv) that
(do, dl; d)
preserved
~- (i)
: The e q u a t i o n s
is a c o e q u a l i z e r ,
g i v e n in
(iv)
imply
and they are o b v i o u s l y
by any functor. Q.E.D.
-
Remark absolute
i:
coequalizer
142
-
It can be shown that <
(d o , dl; d)
is an
is p r e s e r v e d by all
;- (do, dl; d)
full embeddings.
Remark 2:
It is not n e c e s s a r y
(do, dl; d)
is a c o e q u a l i z e r but
coequalizers
by the functors
It is n a t u r a l different sider
to assume that
only that it is m a p p e d
[Y, -],
[Yo, -],
to ask if absolute
from split coequalizers.
and
into
[YI' -]
coequalizers
The answer is yes.
"
are Con-
the diagram: do
iy ^ ; > Yo
Y1
> Yo
do (do, do;
iy )
is an absolute
coequalizer,
but it is split
O
<
> do
is a split epi.
Definition: zer is n - s p l i t
if there e x i s t
(iv) of the p r e c e d i n g
Above coequalizers n-split
exist n-split O<
n
maps d i
is verified.
is an example
of a 0-split
It is readily
coequali-
such that c o n d i t i o n
theorem
are 1-split.
implies
We
We shall say that an absolute
coequalizer.
seen that for
Split n>
(n + l)-split.
can show that for every coequalizers
which
integer
n > 0, there
are not i-split
for any
i
Indeed,
define
dO Yo
d > Y1
d~
> Y
in sets
as
0,
-
1 4 3 -
follows:
Y
o
= Y
1
d o = iy
= {1,2,3,...,
n + i}, Y =
, dl(i)
(i-l,
= max
i),
{i}
d(i)
Now
= i.
define
o
h
: Y
hk(i)
> Y = max
we have
the
1
b y h(1)
= 1 and define
(i + k - n ,
i).
following
results:
hk:
Y1
) Yo
h n _ 1 (i) = m a x
Then
(i-l,
by l)
and
n-k
=
hk
(hn_ I)
d I = hn_ 1 It f o l l o w s
immediately
that we have
the relations:
dd ~ = d d I
dh = iy
hd = dlh I =
(hn_l)n n-1
Thus
(do, dl;
d)
doh I
= dlh 2 =
(hn_ l)
doh
= 1
(h
..o, m)
Y
= o
n-i
)0
.
is n - s p l i t .
On the o t h e r (i = l, 2,
n
hand,
such
that
if t h e r e
exist
h'
l
h!i r
144-
-
h'd = d
d
~(2)
d we
can e s t a b l i s h
of the i m a g e s
the
h4 ~
= d
in g o i n g
following
of the m a p s
llm(dh') I = i least
n + 1
(do, dl;
d)
and
under
i.e.
is n o t i - s p l i t
example
~
2
= %
or
0
Im(h~) I
-1
to the f o l l o w i n g , b y at m o s t
for any
a more
i.
. the c a r d i n a -
But
thus t h e r e m u s t b e at We c o n c l u d e
m > n.
to M i c h a e l
to r e p l a c e
on the c a r d i n a l i t i e s
Im[h; ) l
IIm(iyo) I = n + l,
equations,
1
consideration:
can be c h a n g e d
I am i n d e b t e d preceding
h'
relations
f r o m one e q u a t i o n
lity of the i m a g e
~(3)
h'
(2m) h' m = 1Y o
IIm(d ,(i) h~) i ] Thus
v(1)
that
i < n. Barr
for s u g g e s t i n g
complicated
one.
the
-
145
-
REFERENCES [1]
Beck, J. "The Tripleableness
[21
Beck, J.
"Triples, Algebras,
(Diaser~ut~on, [3]
Theorem"
(Manuscript).
and Cohomology",
(1967), Columbia University).
Linton, F. E. J. "An Outline of Functorial Semantics", (Lecture Notes in Math, Springer - to appear).
[41
Linton, F. E. J. "Coequalizers in Categories of Algebras", (Lecture Notes in Math, Springer - to appear).
[5]
Linton, F. E. J. "Applied Functorial Semantics I",
(Ann~li d~ Ma~ema~ca, [6]
to appear).
Manes, E. G. "A T~iple Miscellany:
some aspects of the
theory of algebras over a triple", Wesleyan University, Middletown, [7]
Mitchell, B. York,
(Dissertation,
Conn.,
1967).
Theory of Categories, Academic Press, New
(1965).
-
146
GALOIS
-
THEORY
by
S t e p h e n S. Shatz
INTRODUCTION
This w i l l be a summary w i t h o u t proofs,
or w i t h b a r e s t
and d i s c u s s i o n
indications
- mostly
of same - of my
recent w o r k on Galois T h e o r y
for field extensions.
t i v a t e d by certain
applications
"obvious"
and these a p p l i c a t i o n s sort of theorems
suggest
classify
for an a r b i t r a r y
zt~s
coverings.
flat,
finite
yield
a description
scheme.
lines
for the
to c o n s t r u c t
connected
instead
a "fundamental
scheme,
so as to
of just c l a s s i f y i n g
For this one will need a Galois T h e o r y
coverings
of schemes.
of the B r a u e r
if it is the "correct"
those elements plication
the b o u n d a r y
one wants
the flat coverings
fine case)
of any such theory;
one needs.
Specifically, group scheme"
I was mo-
Any Galois Group
theory;
A blueprint
all isogenies
for
Theory will
(at least in the afone wishes
split by a given flat covering.
is to c l a s s i f y
the
to study
The t h i r d ap-
of a given group
for d o i n g this is given by the c l a s s i c a l
*The author w i s h e s to a c k n o w l e d g e the s u p p o r t of N . S . F . G . P . 7654, B a t t e l l e M e m o r i a l Institute, and S t a n f o r d U n i v e r s i t y during p r e p a r a t i o n of this manuscript.
-
s e p a r a b l e case,
147
-
and the h e i g h t one case as d o n e by S e r r e
A good Galois T h e o r y ought to put these t o g e t h e r
[3].
consistently,
as w e l l as e n a b l e one to h a n d l e the case of h e i g h t n > i.
To k e e p the e x p o s i t i o n short, w e shall d e a l only w Z t h the case of a finite, K/ko
Actually,
purely inseparable
generalization
field e x t e n s i o n
to the case of an a r b i t r a r y
fZnite e x t e n s i o n is easy, but r e q u i r e s m o r e space. to e m p h a s i z e t h a t t h e o r e m s in the field t h e o r e t i c treat the g e n e r a l
i~
We w a n t
s t a t e d b e l o w have b e e n p r o v e n o n l y
case - m o r e w o r k w i l l be n e c e s s a r y to
affine case.
THE GROUP S C H E M E AUT,
R I N G SCHEMES
Our p o i n t of v i e w is that any Galois T h e o r y s h o u l d be a r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n o b j e c t s morphisms.
Moreover,
closely as ~ossible
and
"groups"
it s h o u l d be f u n c t o r i a l ,
the m o d e l of the c l a s s i c a l
of their autoand f o l l o w as case.
It has b e e n r e c o g n i z e d for some time that, situations
for w h i c h o r d i n a r y groups
w h i c h groups o u g h t to p l a y a part, group scheme.
So, q u i t e n a t u r a l l y ,
Grothendiecks
a u t o m o r p h i s m functor,
if X, Y are schemes, is that f u n c t o r w h i c h
~: Y
> X
g r o u p of S - a u t o m o r p h i s m s
of
are i n a d e q u a t e and in
the c o r r e c t n o t i o n is a we are lead to c o n s i d e r Aut,
[1].
a morphism,
associates
in m a n y
Recall that then Aut
(Y/X)
to e a c h X - s c h e m e 9, the
Y x 9. X
T h a t is,
-
Aut
(Y/X)
148
(S) = A u t %
If Y and X are a f f i n e , spectively, of
and if ~ m a k e s
finite presentation, = Aut
type o v e r
(~/A)
A.
braic
k-group
K = k
say with
rings
then
Aut
~ a n d A re-
projective
then one trivially
is r e p r e s e n t a b l e
A-module
sees t h a t
by a group
scheme
if K / k is an a r b i t r a r y (K/k)
is r e p r e s e n t a b l e
Aut
(Y/X)
of f i n i t e finite
b y an a l g e -
scheme.
Observe, scheme.
(Y XXS).
~ a finite,
In p a r t i c u l a r ,
field extension,
-
Indeed,
however,
that
in the s i m p l e s t
(8), 82 = t, t ~ k 2 , ch
Aut
(K/k)
is a " l a r g e "
non-trivial
(k) = 2, o n e
case:
finds
an e x a c t
se-
quence 0 Now
> ~2 Aut
> Aut
(K/k)
defining
so m e r o l e
t u r n k, K i n t o f u n c t o r s
ing r e m a r k s
of this s e c t i o n .
a "k-algebra
> ~m
is a f u n c t o r i a l
ing k, K, and s h o u l d p l a y we must
(K/k)
construction
in the G a l o i s
as w e l l ,
in v i e w
F o r this, w e
scheme"
> 0.
Theory.
But
of t h e o p e n -
can c o n s i d e r
(and k, the same),
involv-
K as
say K, v i a
the e q u a t i o n K
(S) = A f f i n e = K ~k
(For k one s h o u l d any k - s c h e m e ; sentable
read:
and one
r i n g of
(Affine r i n g of S). k
(~) = A f f i n e
finds,
by r i n g s c h e m e s
(Spec K XkS)
trivially,
- more
exactly,
r i n g of S),
Here
S is
t h a t K and k are r e p r e k-algebra
schemes.
-
A simple verification Aut
(K/k)
> Aut
shows
(K_/k)
149
-
t h a t the n a t u r a l
is an i s o m o r p h i s m
injection - so the A u t d o e s
n o t h a v e to be c h a n g e d .
N o w the s u p p o s e d be a I-i l a t t i c e schemes But,
of K / k a n d the
this is n o t w h a t
those That
subringschemes there
ample,
arising
subfield
from subfields
above:
a ring scheme between of the l a y e r K / k
of
Aut
check.
(K/k).
02 = t , etc. ,
K | A = A | A (A)
For e x -
(as m o d u l e s ) .
such that
y
k a n d K, n o t a r i s i n g
(there are n o n o n - t r i v i a l
The g r o u p s c h e m e
One m o r e o b s e r v a t i o n : is c o n n e c t e d
the subring-
of the l a y e r K/k.
K = k(0),
< x, y > s K
should
We can o n l y c a p t u r e
yield'
is g i v e n b y
look at all p a i r s
we obtain
between
the r e a d e r m a y e a s i l y
(A)
There
subgroupschemes
our m e t h o d s
in the case d e s c r i b e d A, K
is clear:
correspondence
(closed)
are o t h e r s ,
for any r i n g If w e
inverting
structure
if and o n l y if K / k is a p u r e l y
2
= 0,
from a such').
Aut
(K/k)
inseparable
exten-
sion.
2.
Given want first
THE G A L O I S
a closed
to a s s o c i a t e w i t h attempt
subgroupscheme
H of
it a s u b r i n g s c h e m e
Aut
of K/k.
(K/k) , w e The n a t u r a l
at a f u n c t o r A ~
is n o t a f u n c t o r , ize"
CORRESPONDENCE
a n d has
it or u n i v e r s a l i z e
(K | A) H(A) the w r o n g
values.
it on the m o d e l
One must
of a l g e b r a i c
"localgeometry
-
150
-
[2], so as to d e f i n e Fix H
(A) = { ~ E K ~ A I for e v e r y A-alg.
in K | B is left fixed by
of
all of H This d e f i n i t i o n Fix H; m o r e o v e r
A~--~-> Fix H the p r o c e s s
B, the i m a g e
(A)
(B)}.
clearly yields
a functor,
is q u i t e o b v i o u s l y
the e x a c t ana-
(suitably c h a n g e d
for f u n c t o r i a l
log of the c l a s s i c a l p r o c e s s purposes),
Proposition.
For any e x t e n s i o n K/k,
Fix H is a sheaf in the f a i t h f u l l y loqy over k; in. fact, s qheme c o < r e s p o n d i n g
Fix H
flat~ ~ u a s i - c o m p a c t
to~-
is r e p r e s e n t a b l e by th e r i n g
to a u n i q u e
This field L is d e t e r m i n e d
the f u n c t o r
s u b f i e l d L of the layer K/k.
f r o m the e q u a t i o n
L = Fix H
(k),
and for e a c h A, one has Fix H
(A) = L ~ A.
O b s e r v e the r e m a r k a b l e
fact that the k - r a t i o n a l
p o i n t s of the s c h e m e Fix H d e t e r m i n e t h a t scheme.
N o w it may h a p p e n t h a t d i s t i n c t s u b g r o u p s c h e m e s H, h a v e the same Fix functors,
i.e.,
their associated
( = k - r a t i o n a l p o i n t s of the Fix functor) example,
in the o f t e n cited case
one finds that
Aut
(K/k), -
field.
~2
k
a ,
fields
are the same.
For
(8) = K, 8 2 = t , etc. , all h a v e k as a s s o c i a t e d
2,
T h e r e f o r e , we d e c r e e t h a t two s u b g r o u p s c h e m e s H, H
!
-
w i l l be called Galois
151
equivalent
!
Fix H
if and only if Fix H
(k) =
!
(k).
We w i l l w r i t e H ~ H
Fix then e s t a b l i s h e s classes
-
a mapping
of s u b g r o u p s c h e m e s
Given a (closed) associate with
following definition
case.
The functor
from the Galois e q u i v a l e n c e
of Aut to the subfields
of K/k.
, J
subringscheme
it a s u b g r o u p s c h e m e
our e x p e r i e n c e w i t h Fix,
Inv. S
in this
of
~ of K/k, we w a n t
Aut
(K/k).
j
and the c l a s s i c a l
is c o m p l e t e l y
(A) = {a E Aut A
to
In view of
definition,
the
natural:
(K | A) I for every A-alg. the image of a in Aut
B,
(K ~ B) B
when restricted
to S
(B) shall
be the identity.}.
Since Inv.
S
Aut A
(K ~ A) = Aut
(it is clearly
such)
Proposition.
Aut
is to show that they are
group scheme
Aut
(K/k).
Inv. S i s r e p r e s e n t a b l e (K/k).
If L is the smal-
b o t h Inv and Fix invert order,
doing this, however, Inv.
we w i s h
"mutually
to make
and w h a t
inverse".
some remarks
L.
Before
on the
L.
In the c l a s s i c a l Galois
of
of
of K/k such that S c L, then Inv. S = Inv.
Clearly, remains
(A), the functor
is a s u b f u n c t o r
The functor
b ~ a closed s u b g r o u p s c h e m e lest subfield
(K/k)
group of K/L.
theory,
the g r o u p
In the more general
Inv. L is the
theory,
this w i l l
-
be i m p o s s i b l e w h i l e Inv.
since
Aut
152
(K/L)
-
is a group s c h e m e over Spec
L is a group scheme over Spec
k.
However,
L,
the n e x t
b e s t t h i n g is true, namely:
Proposition.
The n a t u r a l m o r p h i s m
Inv.
L | L
> Aut
(K/L)
is an i s o m o r p h i s m for e v e r y s u b f i e l d L of the layer K/k.
S u p p o s e we start w i t h a s u b g r o u p s c h e m e H of Aut
(K/k),
and form the a s s o c i a t e d s u b f i e l d L
of the layer K/k.
=
Fix
H
(k)
N o w w e f o r m the a s s o c i a t e d g r o u p s c h e m e Inv.
W h a t is the r e l a t i o n b e t w e e n H and Inv. closed immersion
H9
> Inv.
N o w by the u s u a l can e a s i l y show that
L?
Answer:
L.
"double c o m m u t a n t "
L c Fix
T h e r e is a
(Inv~ L)
i n e q u a l i t y w h i c h r e q u i r e s m o r e proof.
(k).
reasoning, we It is the c o n v e r s e
However,
i_~f L is a l r e a d y
the f i e l d a s s o c i a t e d to some g r o u p s c h e m e H, then one finds, upon application H 9
> Inv.
of the f u n c t o r Fix to the c l o s e d i m m e r s i o n
L, that L c_ Fix
Consequently:
(Inv. L)
(k) c_
For those s u b f i e l d s
fields to a s u b @ r o u p s c h e m e H of A u t L
=
Fix
(Inv. L)
clas9 c ~ 1 7 6 m a x i m a l member.
(k).
Moreover,
Fix H L which ~/k),
(k) = L. arise as a s s o c i a t e d w e have:
in the Galois e q u i v a l e n c 9
tO L, the ~ r o u p s c h e m e
Inv. ~ i s the u n i q u e
L.
-
3.
153
-
GALOIS THEORY;
COUNTING
W e m u s t n o w p r o v e t h a t for a g i v e n field e x t e n s i o n Z/k,
e v e r y s u b f i e l d L arises
g r o u p s c h e m e of
Aut
(K/k).
as a s s o c i a t e d A necessary
tion that L be the "fixed field" AUt
(~/k) ,
field to a sub-
and s u f f i c i e n t
condi-
of a s u b g r o u p s c h e m e of
is that
(*)
L = Fix
(Inv. L)
(k)
The p r o b l e m is c o n n e c t e d w i t h " s u f f i c i e n t l y many"
automorphisms
the e x i s t e n c e of
as we shall now sketch.
Be-
cause of the i s o m o r p h i s m Inv. equation
L ~ L ~>
(K/L),
(*) is c l e a r l y e q u i v a l e n t w i t h
(**)
k = Fix
Equation
Aut
(**)
is, in turn,
(Aut
(K/k)) (k).
equivalent
to the " m o v i n g p r o p e r t y " :
Let ~ be an e l e m e n t of e x p o n e n t one in K, t h e n t h e r e exists k - a l g e b r a A and an a u t o m o r p h i s m ~ s A u t A ~
Q A) such that
If an e x t e n s i o n K/k has the m o v i n g p r o p e r t y , shall say that it is a good e x t e n s i o n . f o r m of this work,
Now,
we
in the o r i n g i n a l
I p r o v e d that e v e r y e x t e n s i o n had an e m b e d -
d i n g in a good e x t e n s i o n by a fairly e l a b o r a t e procedure. ever,
I have since s h o w n that e v e r y p u r e l y i n s e p a r a b l e
K / k is good. state:
a
C o n s e q u e n t l y , we m a y now s u m m a r i z e
How-
layer
s e c t i o n 2 and
-
Theorem. extension,
154-
Let K/k be a purelY
then K/k is a good extension.
subgroupschemes
of
lence relation;
in each e q u i v a l e n c e
m a x i m a l member,
an d the c o r r e s p o n d e n c e s
Aut
cl
(K/k)
lattice
K/k~
Moreover,
in its class.
cl
of
Aut
Inv L
(K/k)
correspondence
sketched
of s u b g r o u p s c h e m e s
analog the statement: the famous groups? general
connection
above
subqroupscheme
member
actually
of
relation.
In each
(a field~),
and the
runs b e t w e e n
classes
of subringschemes.)
t h e o r e m of Galois Inv L ~ L ~ > between normal
Aut
Theory has as a n a t u r a l (K/L).
subfields
differences
W h a t about
and n o r m a l
sub-
occur b e t w e e n
the
cases.
alizer of H in G, d e n o t e d (%) = {u E G
of
of the t h e o r e m may be
Recall that if H is a s u b g r o u p s c h e m e
NG H
classes
that the s u b r i n g s c h e m e s
It is here that s t r i k i n g and c l a s s i c a l
the e q u i v a l e n c e
equivalence
and classes
The s u b g r o u p
there is a u n i q u e
and all the subfields
if one notes
there is a u n i q u e m a x i m a l
equiva-
(k)
the s t a t e m e n t
K / ~ are fibred by a n a t u r a l class
class
is the u n i q u e m a x i m a l
(Actually,
made more s y m m e t r i c
The set of all closed
(Inv L)
inverting F between
of s u b @ r o u p s c h e m e s
finite,
is fibred by a n a t u r a l
(H)-~-~ Fix H L ~
are i-i,
inseparable,
of G, the norm-
N G H, is d e f i n e d by the e q u a t i o n
(S) I for every
in G (U) n o r m a l i z e s
scheme U over ~, the image of the s u b g r o u p H
(U). }.
-
155
-
H e r e ~ is a scheme o v e r the same b a s e as 2, and G
(~), etc~
m e a n s p o i n t s of G w i t h v a l u e s
in S.
tion works
A s u b g r o u p s c h e m e H of G is n o r m a l
for c e n t r a l i z e r s .
in G w h e n and only w h e n
N
H = G. S
~
The same sort of d e f i n i -
We shall w r i t e H ~ G for
~
~
this ~
If K/k is a f i e l d e x t e n s i o n ,
and if L is a s u b f i e l d
of the layer K/k, we shall say that L is K/k - normal, only if for e v e r y k - a l g e b r a A, e v e r y a u t o m o r p h i s m t r a n s f o r m s ~(A)
into itself~
Observe
of a t o w e r of fields,
L of K/k is K / k - n o r m a l ,
k c K c
s 6 AutA(K|
that this is a
r e l a t i v e c o n c e p t - it d e p e n d s u p o n the field Ko give e x a m p l e s
if and
One can e a s i l y
~, w h e r e
b u t is N O T a/k-normal.
a subfield
The p r o b l e m is
that no longer does an a u t o m o r p h i s m m a p a g i v e n field e l e m e n t only on f i n i t e l y m a n y choices,
it m a y have i n f i n i t e l y many.
This m a k e s n o r m a l i t y v e r y s t r o n g l y d e p e n d e n t on the s t r u c t u r e of
Aut
(K/k).
Proposition.
Let K/k be a f i e l d extension.
A neces-
s a r y and s u f f i c i e n t c o n d i t i o n t h a t a s u b f i e l d L of K/k b e K/k-normal Aut
(K/k).
Sweedler,
is that
Inv ~
be a n o r m a l s u b ~ r o u p s c h e m e
W h e n K / k is a p u r e e x t e n s i o n , [5]), the n a t u r a l m o r p h i s m Aut
(K/k)
of
(in the sense of
(of ~ r o u p schemes)
> Aut
(L/k)
qiven by r e s t r i c t i o n of an a u t o m o r p h i s m is a s u r ~ e c t i o n of ~roupschemes with kernel Aut
Inv ~.
(L/k) = A u t
Consequently, (K/k)/Inv L~
156
-
Is such a large group After
all,
the c l a s s i c a l
-
as
Aut
(K/k)
case gives us a finite
order is e x a c t l y
the degree of the extension.
one w o u l d e x p e c t
some sort of finite
In the J a c o b s o n Theory, the Lie A l g e b r a
of k - d e r i v a t i o n s
that such an algebra termined [4].
[K: k] equals
pn, we find that
that the order
sociated
(pn)pn =
benius
But one knows
space of a u n i q u e l y height
de-
l, say G,
the field K over k.
As
Then one
of G is p r e c i s e l y Thus the @roup scheme
K/k of e x p o n e n t
as-
1 b~ the J a c o b s o n
[K: k] [K: k].
Let K/k be a p u r e l y
in w h i c h each g e n e r a t o r has
Let G (K/k)
[.
dim k L = n pn.
[K: k] [K: k].
Theorem. extension
of K, say
to obtain
to the e x t e n s i o n
m e t h o d has order
to work.
of i over K is n, w h e r e n is the n u m b e r
necessary
pdim k i =
B a s e d on this,
group scheme
of Frobenius
of generators
knows
group w h o s e
a large role is played by
is the t a n g e n t
finite group scheme
The d i m e n s i o n
necessary?
denote
the k e r n e l
m o r p h i s m on
Aut
i n s e p a r a b l e , pure
the same e x p o n e n t
of the r-fold power
(K/k).
r~
of th e Fro-
Then G (K/k) has order
[K: k] and i n t e r s e c t i o n
of the classes
groupschemes
Aut
of
of G (K/k) w h i c h
(K/k)
of Galois e q u i v a l e n t
w i t h G (K/k)
still classifies
in@ t ~ the p r e s c r i p t i o n s
above.
yields
the subfields When
sub-
a fibration of K/k accord-
r = i, G(K/k)
is_~-
-
c•
157
-
the g r o u p s c h e m e [ i e l d e d b[ the J a c o b s o n method.
Remarks
1.
The c l a s s i c a l t h e o r y can be put into this frame-
w o r k v e r y e a s i l y once we r e a l i z e that it is a c t u a l l y the s t r u c ture of K ~ K as K - a l g e b r a w h i c h is at stake in the u s u a l m o r e general)
Galois Theory.
The n o r m a l b a s i s
(and
t h e o r e m asserts
that K | K is a d i r e c t p r o d u c t of copies of K i n d e x e d by the u s u a l Galois group,
and this g r o u p acts on K | K as K - a u t o m o r -
p h i s m s by left translation.
2.
One can count Inv
scheme c o r r e s p o n d i n g to Inv ~), this c o u n t i n g process.
L
(the c o r r e c t finite group-
and do the u s u a l
things w i t h
A full e x p o s i t i o n w i l l be p u b l i s h e d
w h e n all the p r o o f s of the above are published.
4.
A CRITIQUE
The m o s t d i s t r e s s i n g t h i n g a b o u t the - h e o r y above is the use of classes of s u b g r o u p s c h e m e s . a c t e r i z e the m a x i m a l e l e m e n t s the g r o u p s c h e m e s
an A r t •
- Hasse)
Inv L in e a c h cla: s?
Inv L are e x a c t l y the K - s t a b l e
in each class, w h e r e K acts on k e r n e l of p o w e r s
H o w , an one char-
of F r o b e n i u s ,
Aut
(K/k), or a1
via a generalized
Probably,
groupschemes least on the (perhaps even
exponential.
I am e n d e a v o r i n g to answer this q u e s t i o n in some s a t i s f a c t o r y way.
-
158
-
REFERENCES [l]
Grothendieck, A., "Technique de descente et thGoremes d'existence en Seometrie Algebrique II", Sem. Bour-
baki, [2]
[1959-1960], Exp. 195.
Grothendieck, A., and M. Demazure, Seminaire
Geometrie
Algebrique de l' Institut des Haute8 Etudes Scientifique8, [3]
[1963-1964].
Serre, J.P., "Quelques proprietes des variet~s ab~liennes en caracteristique p" 739,
[4]
#
Amer
9
J. Math., 80; 715-
[1958].
Shatz, S.S., "Cohomology of Artinian groupschemes over local fields", Ann. of Math, 79; 411-449,
[5]
[1964].
Sweedler M., "Structure of purely inseparable extensions",
Ann. of Math., 87; 401-411,
[1968].
-
DERIVED
159
-
FUNCTORS W I T H O U T
INJECTIVES
by
H. B. Stauffer
1.
INTRODUCTION
Given a c o v a r i a n t where A is a small abelian category derived
satisfying
dir
of F.
in
_dir A
actually
using
functors
of
F
its right
category
~dir
extension
functor
of F are o b t a i n e d by dir
--. to A
a "right completion"
)B
This can be
a "unique"
functors
, and r e s t r i c t i n g
Saul Lubkin
injectives.
and allows
The d e r i v e d
taking the derived
F: A
and B is an abelian
by e m b e d d i n g A in a "larger"
w h i c h has injectives F
category
functor
AB 5 , one can c o n s t r u c t
functors w i t h o u t
accomplished
additive
, u s i n g the injectives ~dir
The c a t e g o r y
of A.
I would
is
like to thank
for his help and encouragement.
2.
-dir A
w
category
Let A be any category. We shall c o n s t r u c t a _dir A from A in the f o l l o w i n g way. The objects
of
are d i r e c t e d
-dir A
directed (Bj;
sets.
8jj,)j
systems
The m o r p h i s m s
are o r d e r e d pairs
is a set map and
fi: Ai
(Ai; eii,)i from
(Ai; ~ii,)i
(~,f)
~ B~(i)
in A over
where
to
~: I
is a m o r p h i s m
) J in
160-
-
for each
i ~ I
such that
in I implies
i' > i
there
j > r (i), % (i') in J such that the diagram commutes:
exists
fi
,
| .. ~_
Bq,
iifi A
An equivalence ((Ai; aii,)i
3
1
)j
%(i)
relation is introduced. , (Bj; 8jj,)j)
let
In
Hom~dir !
(~,f) ~- (r
I
only if there exists
(r
~"(i)
for all i and the diagrams
> r
r f
dominating both;
f )
|b
if and
i.e., commute:
f W!
l
(i) r 1
i ; Be,, (i)
Ai
(i)
fi,~T
B ~(i)
We shall refer to
as
(Ai; aii,) I
8r162 B~, (i)
(Ai) I where the meaning
is clear. Propo@ition
2.1
Let for
,
(A 2)
12
,
.
.
.
,
1 ~ h ~ k ~ n , let Mh, k c Hom~dir
be finite. in
(AI)I I
A-dir
(Bk ) ) I
(An )
~,k
= 8kl~
e
((Ah)~,
Then there exists isomorphisms
, 1 _< r _< n, and
In
8r:
A-dir
,
and,
(Ak)ik) (Br)i---~=(Ar) I
08 h c HOmA--dir ((Bh) I,
such that: (i)
set I, and
all
r
(Br)i are indexed by the same directed
161-
-
each morphism
(ii) by
(%,f)
where
= 11
Proof. (A 2 ) I 1
x
I
If t h e r e
and n o m a p s ,
12
2 = { (il,
if and
only
if
the o b v i o u s
i2)lil i I ~ i{
If w e h a v e
and
e I2'
Br (il,i2)
r
(A I)
(if'
systems.
and
I
1 set
directed i2)
Then
i 2 ~ i~}.
one m a p i2
of d i r e c t e d
two o b j e c t s
i2
and we
~ (A 2)
ii
are
by
c a n be r e p r e s e n t e d
f is a m a p
e If,
morphisms,
(%,f) : (A I)
M' h,k
we can construct
be g i v e n
(Br) I 1 x 12
and
in
' (if'
~
i'
2)
let
= A{ i r , r = 1,2,
with
are done. represented
then
we can
by first
choose
I
(BI)j
8-~--~(AI)__ ii
whose
image
indexed
and
objects
by a cofinal
(BI) I
=84 > ( B I ) j
finite
number
of
subset
where
by a c o f i n a l
We have
N
in
Then
the
image
(A 2) I2
of
set
{ili whose
12.
objects
are
we can choose
(@' , f' )0 e~
subset
(%,,,f,,) w h o s e
our
(@,f)0e~
i 0 ~ I is p r e c e d e d
(i.e.,
(~" , f")
are
12.
each
i ~ I
and
(%'",f",) N
~
{A~, 2 (j) IJ E J }
is finite) indexed
(~' ,f')
a
~ i o in I} image
Finally give
by o n l y
objects
we can
the d e s i r e d
choose (B2) I.
result:
(AI)I l (%'f)
.> (A 2) 12
(i, f ,,') ~
(BI)
(B2)
I The methods.
situation
with
n maps
c a n be h a n d l e d
by
similar
-
162-
Theorem 2.2 m
Let A be any category. (i)
Then
~dir is closed under lim (over directed sets).
(ii) The obvious covariant is a full embedding, F: A
)B
functor
and, given covariant
I~: A
functor
where B has !i~ (over directed sets),
exists a unique Fdir: A-dir
(up to equivalence)
)B
which preserves
and yields the commutative A--d.ir
(iii) A additive (iv)
covariant li b
)A -dir
there
functor
(over directed sets)
diagram: Fdi r
implies -dir A is additive 9
A small and abelian implies -dir A is abelian,
satisfies AB 5, and has enough injectives.
I~: A
) A-dir
is exact. Proof.
(A~)ieij ' jej conglomerate
In
A--dir li
(A~)
=
i~lj
, the directed system obtained by the of all objects and maps 9
F dir is defined by
Fdir(A i; uii,)i = li~ {F(Ai) ; F(uii,)} I use Proposition and abelian in computed
9
We can
2.1 to show that A-dir is additive (iv); for example,
"pointwise".
lim is exact
in B.
in (iii)
kernels can then be
The AB 5 property is immediate:
Since we have a set of generators
namely the objects of ~, there is a generator.
in A-dir This
I
-
ensures
the e x i s t e n c e
of e n o u g h
to
A e A
injectives.
_dir (Ai) I r A
Let us say that
object
163-
if and only
if
admits
~ final _dir (Ai) I is i s o m o r p h i c in A
(A).
Propgsition
If
2.3
(Ai, uii,)i
(i)
there
J ! io, Aj = A e Bj (ii) that
ajj,
admits
exists
i0 e I
for some
for e a c h
Proof.
If
such
there
(r
be the i n d e x of the i m a g e
that,
exists
for e a c h
a final
> (Ai,
e i i , ) i ----> (A) of
j' ~ j
such
.
(A)
object
A, t h e n
e A, a n d
> A 9 Bj,
(p,g) : (Ai,
at the c o m p o s i t i o n
object
(Ai, ~ i i ' ~ a d m i t s
isomorphisms
and its i n v e r s e
Bj
j > i0,
= 1 e 0: A 9 Bj
then we h a v e
a final
(~,f)
of the i s o m o r p h i s m s ,
.
and,
easily
object,
~ii,)i We
let i 0
looking obtain
the
results.
3.
Let tive
functors
F,
DERIVED
{Fn}n>0
n: F
)F ~
= F*: ~----~ B
with A small
AB 5, and F* a c o n n e c t e d be a n a t u r a l
FUNCTORS
and a b e l i a n ,
sequence
be c o v a r i a n t B abelian
of functors.
transformation.
addi-
satisfying
Let
-
Let
{A*:
is a r e s o l u t i o n category lifting
0
) A
1A in A.
) A~
Given
f: A
pushouts
f*: ~ A
is a f u n c t o r .
Theorem
Sn
-A
:
. . . [A*
of the s m a l l
of r e s o l u t i o n s
) B
of A
and resolution
We then have
) -B, n ! 0, g i v e n b y
f*(A*)
A* of B;
the i n d u c e d = A *lim e ~ A~ H n (F(A*)).
Sn(A)
3.1
(i)
n: F
are e q u i v a l e n t :
) F~
transformation
functor, ~: F ~
~
we get a resolution
The f o l l o w i n g
natural
) A'
all m a p s
of A, by u s i n g
functors
-
of A in A} be the o b j e c t s
~A with morphisms
) ~B
164
there 9 L
exists
is u n i v e r s a l
6: F
left exact
~ L, a c o v a r i a n t
a unique
natural
(i.e.,
given
left exact
transformation
such t h a t the d i a g r a m F 0
L commutes),
and F n + l is the r i g h t s a t e l l i t e (ii) The c o n n e c t e d
and,
if
functors there {f
n
G* = {Gn}n>0 with
exists
Y: F unique
}n>0 = f*: F*
sequence
is an e x a c t ~ G~
natural ~ G*
of f u n c t o r s
connected
a natural
such
transformation,
t h a t the d i a g r a m
:fo GO
F* is e x a c t ,
sequence
transformations
Fo
commutes;
of F n, n ~ 0;
of then
-
(iii)
Consider
165
-
the d i a g r a m
~dir
Fdir
A
Fn = Rn(Fdir) I
Then
= Rn(F dir)
0 I~
, n > 0 , where
f the
Rn(F dir)
(defined
are the right
on a c a t e g o r y (iv)
Fn
Proof. F* = {F n}
with
Sn
=
enough
, n
>
An
(exact)
: ~ ---~
lifts
n>0
F *dir = {(Fn)dir}n>0" . ~ d i r functor
F: A - - - - ~ B
Fdir:
~dir
lifts
to a n a t u r a l
defined
) B.
by
lifts
We c o n c l u d e
{A*:
~ (A) -----)(A~
resolution C--dAir w i t h
of
morphisms
n > 0, given by that
~
all maps
Tn(A)
sequence
to an
(exact)
) B
Similarly
connected
ndir:
i) }
and
functor
in B.
are
(iv).
~
.
be the o b j e c t s of r e s o l u t i o n s functors
.
.
= T n , n > 0.
these straightIf we
IA*
is
let a
of the c a t e g o r y of
(A) l i f t i n g
T n : -A d i r
- A*elicit~ H n (F dir (A*)) .
Rn(F dir)
) G dir
Using
(ii)---~(iii)
(AI)II
the i n d u c e d
n: F -----~G
F dir ,
(iii)r
sequence
a left e x a c t
transformation
by p r o v i n g
(A) in -dir} A
1 (A) in -A d i r , we have
immediate
connected
transformation
(i) ~===~ (iii)
of F dir
injectives);
to a left e x a c t
A natural
forward.
functors
0.
n dir(A.) 1 I = lii ~ { n ( A
observations,
0
derived
Clearly
) -B,
It is -C A c C--dAir
-
Conversely, the
if
finite 9
A*
maps
(A n ) in
sequence
)
e C-~Air
0
~ (A)
)
(B n)
(B)
) (B n+l)
.
can use ; (A ~
in A* 9
~ (B ~
I
I
Since
(B) I.
Proposition
>
I
. . .
H n (F d i r (A*))
=
, we
use
Proposition
at
resolutions
I
The
situation
reduces
to
may
looking
over
A @ B., j > i 0 in I. It is e a s y to s e e 3 resolutions map into resolutions o v e r A. Hence,
we
2.1 on
~ . (A') ~ . . . Io I1 W e o b t a i n the i s o m o r p h i c
> (B I)
I
~l i m F (Bi)n I ) = l iI m) H n ( F ( B n ) )
Hn(
on
, we
; (A n + l ) i n + l
0
166-
are
that
2 3
such
done.
REFERENCES
[1]
Buchsbaum,
D
A.,
9
Ann. of Math., [2]
Freyd, York,
P.
J.,
71;
Abzs
"Satellites 199-209,
and
Universal
Functors"
(1960).
Categories,
Harper
and
Row:
New
1964.
MacLane,
[4]
Mitchell,
B.,
New
1965.
York,
S.,
Homology,
[3]
Springer:
Berlin,
Theory of Categorizs,
1963.
Academic
Press:
8
-
SIMPLICIAL
167-
DERIVED FUNCTORS
by
Myles T i e r n e y
1o
and W o l f g a n g
INTRODUCTION
In this note we sketch where)
a theory of d e r i v e d
eralization
of the classical
functors
and a p r o j e c t i v e
After the c o m p a r i s o n w
In w
notions cotriple
class
kernels",
introducing
of derived ~
in
rived functors is abelian 0-level
addition
E
of E i l e n b e r g
if
A
has
concepts
functors
the theory
then our p r o c e d u r e
is additive, and Moore
functors
class
limits
and s t a t i n g
of w
yields
the
of D o l d - P u p p e
in
with other
if there is a
of Barr
as models,
then we o b t a i n
[4].
finite
are d e f i n e d
agree w i t h those of Andr~
functors
project-
the given p r o j e c t i v e
derived
the p r o j e c t i v e
derived
that kernels
this theory one can
In p a r t i c u l a r ,
that realizes
of w
gen-
is abelian~
the d e r i v e d
the cotriple
With
the basic
functors.
A
[2] ; if we choose
ized)
B
except
and absolute
)B
we show how to compare
then we obtain
A
ones.
E: A
and
theorem,
that is a simple
procedure,
ives are replaced by relative arbitrary
(details w i l l appear else-
functors
are replaced by "simplicial
derive
Vogel
class,
and Beck
then the de-
[I]o
(suitably
Also,
if
relativ-
[3], and if in
the relative
theory
-
We Evrard
remark
theory
t h a t the m e t h o d
[5] in the a b s o l u t e
us t h a t b o t h
case.
of
w
Michael
h e and M a x K e l l e y h a v e
was
also used by
B a r r has
informed
also considered
this
(unpublished).
2.
2.1
168-
DERIVED
FUNCTORS
Definition
Let
A
be
a category,
and
fo
X
J '
)
Y
fn a
sequence
kernel
of
of
n
(fo,
+
1
_ -,
_
A-morphisms fn)
for n >_ 0 .
A sim~licial
is a s e q u e n c e
k~
) K
| I
X
kn+l
of
n + 2
0 < i<
j
A-morphisms < n +
1
,
and
satisfying universal
fikJ = f J - l k i with
T h a t is, if h o
H
! J h n+l
X
respect
to
for this
property,
-
is any o t h e r 0 < i < such
sequence
kih
= hi
Obvious simplicial
morphisms
2.2
and
lat e r
exists
yields
for
a unique
h: H ~ K
of a co-
of d e r i v e d
functors
are u n i q u e
up to iso-
class.
simplicial
if t h e y e x i s t ,
the n o t i o n
a theory
to an i n j e c t i v e
Clearly,
fihJ = f J - l h i
0 < i < n + 1 .
dualization
kernel,
respect
prove
satisfying
j < n + 1 , then t h e r e
that
with
169-
kernels
and c o n c e r n i n g
existence
one c a n
easily:
Proposition
If exist
A
has
finite
for any s e q u e n c e
limits,
(fo
_
We review briefly in
A
of
A.
, for d e t a i l s W e say t h a t
see
_
, fn )
the n o t i o n
[4].
f: A
_
then simplicial
Let
~A'
P
a n d any
n
kernels > 0.
of a p r o j e c t i v e b e a class
is P - e p i m o r p h i c
class
of o b j e c t s if for all
X s P , A(X,f) is s u r j e c t i v e . A c A
We c a l l
there exists
~A(X,A')
P a ~ro~ective
a P-epimorphism
A sim~licial out degeneracies)
: A(X,A)
o b j e c t of
in a d i a g r a m
A
class
e.. X
~A
augmented
if for e a c h with
over A
X r P.
(with-
- 170-
3 ~
d o
n-i X
: ,
n
"X
I i l
n-i
~n ~
D o oh
Xn_ 2- _ _ X 1 ) ~n-i
1
n-1
1
n
,A
Xo 9
~O
in
A, w r i t t e n
X~A,
such
~i n-i i
The
are c a l l e d
~j = n
that
~j-1 n-i
i
0 < i < j < n
and in the
face o p e r a t o r s ,
future we will
n
denote
a diagram
s u c h as
o
~n )
x
X n
j
n-i
I
~n n
simply by
X
0
We w i l l
to
such
n. as
n )X n 1 ' a g r e e i n g
n
~i n
also often
if this
~o
and
X
omit
does n o t
always
that
i runs
the'subscripts
lead to c o n f u s i o n .
from
in m o r p h i s m s If f: A
)A',
~o
)A
o v e r A and A',
and X'
)A'
are a u g m e n t e d
then a m o r ~ h i s m
~
over
m
f X
~X'
A
)A'
simplicial
f, w r i t t e n
objects
-
consists of
~'n:
~-morphisms
171-
for n > 0 satis-
X-----~X~ n
fying
n ~n = ~n-I
n
for 0 _< i _< n , where we put f-i = f" ~O
A, and
If P is a projective class in
X
~A
is an augmented simplicial object over A, then we say ~o X ~A is P-projective if each X n ~ P . If A has simplicial kernels, then we have a factorization (2.3)
~o n+l
n
0
1
~A
Xn+len+l~ ~ /i+ i ) xn%
/ ~
~'-i---
Xe l ~
%+1
for
KI
kin Kn-------~Xn_ 1
where
)/~~
i
~n-i
is
n > i, if we put m
a simplicial X
= A.
X
kernel ~o )A
of
Xn_ 1.
~Xn_ 2
is said to be P-exact
--1
~O
if ~o o ~ro~ective
exact.
and
e
n > 1 n
are
resolution of By 2.2, if
be so resolved.
is a
P-
P-projective and
P-
P-epimorphic.
X
;A
--
A
A
if it is
has finite limits then each
A E A
can
Moreover, such a resolution is unique up to
simplicial homotopy equivalence as results immediately from
-
172
-
the following comparison theorem. 2.4
Theorem 0
Let
P-exact.
X ~ )A
be a P-projective
Then any morphism
fz A
.)A'
and
X' ~* ~A'
be
can be extended to
a morphism
A
over f.
Furthermore,
homotopic,
'
any two such extensions
That is, if
f, then there exists
f
T,~z X
)X'
are two extensions of
~-morphisms
hiz X ----) n n Xn+ 1
0
9
i
such that
~o
n+l
h o
n
=
n
~n+l h n n+l n = ~n
i hj =
and
~
hj-I 3i
i 9 j
h j ~i-i
i 9 j + 1
~j+l hJ+l . ~ j+l hj
are s i m p l i c i a l l Y
9
173
-
By u s i n g
similar
-
(but easier)
techniques,
one
can
O
show
that
a P-projective
degeneracy
operators.
resolution That
sJ:
is,
Xn
X ~ )A
there
)Yn+l
0 < j < n --
i
sJ-i
~
i
i < j
J
i = j, j + 1
s
s j ~i-i
In g e n e r a l
the i d e n t i t y
fied,
as we s h a l l
but,
E: A
Given
2.4,
when
B
)B
a projective
us denote mension Y
by n )Y
n
see,
First,
the chain Y
n
,
n- 1
resolution
and if
to d e r i v e A
Y
has
complex
is abelian.
a functor
finite
limits
whose
object
category,
component
~
operator
.
Now
~ o. A
of
A
if
A c A
and define
A----~B m
D
for n > 0 by s e t t i n g - H
n
let
in di-
n X
and
i
(-i)
L E." n
L E(A) n
A
is a s i m p l i c i a l
boundary
i
is n o t satis-
when
in an a d d i t i v e
and w h o s e n ~ i-0
i < j
can be a c h i e v e d
it is clear h o w
P.
is
a P-projective
sis j - sJ+is i
degeneracies)
kY is
i > j + 1
is a b e l i a n
class
(with or w i t h o u t
n
--
that
~
9
pseudo-
exist
n
such
has
(k E X)
0
choose
-
The definition resolution
is independent
chosen
3.
jective
3.1
174
A
class
P.
of the
(up to isomorphism)
and functorial
COMPARISON
Let
-
in
WITH
A
by 2.4.
OTHER T H E O R I E S
be a category with
finite
limits
and a pro-
We have
Lemma 2 ~
Let X
c P
A
r
A
If
.
the augmented
Y
is P-exact,
set
(without degeneracies)
simplicial
_A(X,Y) has a contraction.
>A
then for each
>A(X,A)
That is, if we set Y-I = A, then there
are
functions h for n > -i
n
:
A(X,Yn) --
such that if
) A ( X , Y n + I)
f- X
>Y
--
~i hn n+l
and
(f)
= hn-i
8n+l n+l hn
Now if
E: A - - - - ~
choose
as models
subcategory
of
whose
3.1
A
the resulting
and 4.7
of
[1],
(~if)
0 < i < n ---
(f) = f
is abelian,
Denoting
, then n
is an arbitrary
functor where
for the Andre theory
objects
homology
[i]
are the p r o j e c t i v e s theory by Hn(
the full in P.
,E), we have by
-
3.2
175
-
Proposition
There
are n a t u r a l L
Let
G--
P = P~ , where existence
shown
E ~ )H n
(~,r
P~
isomorphisms
(,E)
be a cotriple
in
A
such that
is the class of ~ - p r o j e c t i v e s
of the c o n t r a c t i o n
any P - p r o j e c t i v e plicial
n
(in A and E)
resolution
~-resolution
[2].
given in 3.1 implies in the sense of
in the sense of
there that cotriple h o m o l o g y
[2]
w
The
easily
that
is a sim-
, w
and it is
may be c o m p u t e d with such
resolutions 9
(Simplicial ~ - r e s o l u t i o n s
generacies
[2], but these play no role in the argument.)
in
are assumed
to have de-
Hence we obtain
3.3
Proposition
If
@
is a cotriple
in
A
with
P = P
, then there
- -
are n a t u r a l
isomorphisms L n E ~--~->H n
(,E)
Since most classical examples
of cotriple
of e a s i l y compute
constructed
these
simplicial
3.3
" theories
provides
resolutions
appear as
a large class
from w h i c h
to
theories.
and pullbacks,
simplicial
cohomology
cohomology,
Assume n o w that object
n > 0 --
9
object
in
A
it has A
is abelian. all finite
Since
limits 9
(with or w i t h o u t
A If
has an 0X
degeneracies)
is a then
-
the normal complex
NX
176-
of X is the chain complex given by
(NX)~
= X0
/-~ (NX)n = i> 0 ker
and
=
8n
no
I
i {8 " .LX
(NX)
If P is a projective 4.1
.~Xn_l}
n 9 0
n
class in
A, we have
Proposition If the augmented simplicial object
exact in the sense of
w
X 8~
is P-
t h e n the augmented chain complex
O
NX
~) A
for each
is P-exact in the sense of Eilenberg-Moore P s P
...
[4], i~
the sequence of abelian groups
)A(P,_
(NX)n)
AIP, X )
)A(P,_ (NX)n_ I)
)
...
)AIP, A ) - - ~ 0
O
is exact.
Let us denote by S (A) the category of genuine s implicial objects over degeneracies isfied. write over In
A.
That is, an
X z S (A)
has
and all the usual simplicial identities
Morphisms C(A)
Ao
commute with
are sat-
faces and degeneracies.
for the category of positive
Then,
faces and
chain complexes
the normal complex is a functor
[3] it is shown that N has an inverse,
We
N:S(A)----~C(A).
i.eo there is a
-
functor
K: C(A)
) S(A)
there are n a t u r a l
177-
C c C(A)
and for
and
X c S(A)
equivalences ~C: C~----~NKC
#X: K N X ~-----)X
It follows
from the c o n s t r u c t i o n
we assume
(as we now do)
of coproducts n > 0 i ff C --
Now
to w r i t e
we can still, iterated
~X" KNX
that commutes with generacy
operator
n
[3] that if the formation
P for each
e
X
if
has only pseudo-
where
generacies.
If
satisfy
s
i
s
j
of Dold-Puppe, generacies. degeneracy to
In essence, X
degeneracies,
f. X---+Y
Y X
-- s
i
i <
shows
faces and de-
to have only p s e u d o - d e meaning
they
j, then this ~ is the above it commutes with
c o m m u t a t i o n with
to prove Lemma that
~ is n a t u r a l with
degeneracies,
and then, of course,
is e n o u g h
a
last p s e u d o - d e -
c o m m u t i n g with
has genuine s
define
and the This
is also assumed
j+l
a fixed ord-
)X
in eachdimensiono
In any case,
~X
by c h o o s i n g
all face o p e r a t o r s
to morphisms
generacies,
ies of
(KC)
then
P for each n > 0.
operators,
er in w h i c h
applied
given in
n
degeneracy
respect
K
that P is closed under
and retracts, ~
of
(#X)
w h a t we have p r o v e d
n
3.17 of
faces
all de-
and the last
[3], w h i c h when
is an i s o m o r p h i s m
for n > 0.
is that the p s e u d o - d e g e n e r a c -
can be r e p l a c e d by d e g e n e r a c i e s
satisfying
all the
178-
-
simplicial Barr
identities.
(unpublished)
mation
by means of a direct,
E: A
(relativized)
>B
is the following.
resolution
T h a t is,
be an a r b i t r a r y
m e t h o d of D o l d - P u p p e
functors
jective
4.1.
fact has been p r o v e d by inductive
approxi-
process.
Let
rived
A similar
~
C
~
Then the
functor.
for d e f i n i n g
(0-level)
For A r A choose
de-
a P-pro-
in the sense of E i l e n b e r g - M o o r e .
is P - p r o j e c t i v e
and P-exact
as defined
in
Then set
L'E(A) n
= H
n
By the m e t h o d of w ial r e s o l u t i o n The derived
X ~~
functors
(kEKC)
choose
and assume of w
L E(A) n
a P-projective
simplic-
it has p s e u d o - d e g e n e r a c i e s .
are given by
- H
n
(kEX)
but we have (+x)
9
n
for each n 9 0. that of A.
NX ~a~.A Since
Hence,
since
#X induces
complexes
in
n
P is closed
is an E i l e n b e r q - M o o r e
it follows
P-projective
an i s o m o r p h i s m
k (EKNX)
of chain
x
n
) k (EX)
B, we obtain
isomorphisms
by 4.1
resolution
-
(4.2)
Here
L'E(A) n a little
phisms
care
are n a t u r a l
Finally, and
B
are
must in
~
)L E(A) n
be t a k e n
n 9 0 - -
to s h o w
that
these
isomor-
A.
consider
abelian
179-
and
E
the c a s e
E: A-----)B w h e r e
is a d d i t i v e .
If A
E A
A
and
O
X ~ ;A
is a P - p r o j e c t i v e
resolution kEX
as c h a i n ly,
complexes
chain
in
equivalence
B. and
in the
sense
of
w
then
= EkX
Letting~
and ~
isomorphism
denote,
of c h a i n
respective-
complexes,
we
have (4.4)
kX ~
k(KNX) ~
N(KNX)
~
NX
.
O
Since
NX
)A
is
a P-projective
resolution
in the s e n s e
of
O
Eilenberg-Moore,
it
Thus
functorscf
the
derived
Naturality
follows
is t r i v i a l
from w
in this
(4.3)
coincide case.
that with
kX those
)A of
is also. [4].
180-
-
REFERENCES
[1)
M. Andre,"M~thode
Simpliciale en Alg~bre Homologique
et Alg~bre Commutative",Spa/nger
ie~t~re Noted in
Mathematied, 32, (1967). [2]
Mo Barr, J. Beck,"Homoloay (to appear in Spa~ngz~
[3]
A. Dold, D. Puppe,
and Standard Constructions," Lecture Noted.)
"Homologie nicht-additiver
Ann. Inst. Fourier, ii; 201-312, [4]
S. Eilenberg, J. Moore, logical Algebra",
[51
M. Evrard,
Functoren".
(1961).
"Foundations of Relative HomoAMS Memoir, 55, (1965).
"Homologie dans les Categorles non Ab~liennes",
C.R. Acad. So. Parid, 260~ 749-751, 1044-1051, (1965).
-
181-
ACYCLIC MODELS AND KAN EXTENSIONS by Friedrich Ulmer
Introduction The aim of this note ils to point out the relationship
be-
tween the technique of acyclic models and the standard procedure in homologlcal
algebra to compute derived functors by
means of proJectives, l)
This leads to a useful generalization
of acyclic models reflecting of a functor
G
the fact that the derived functors
can be computed more generally by G-acycllc
resolutions. Let
C
and
proJectives,
A
be categories,
and let
small category,
J : M--~C
[M,A]
and the restriction
Rj
adJoint
~[C,A]
: [M,A]
that for every extension of
abelian with sums and enough be the inclusion of a full
the objects of which are referred to as models.
Then the functor category
Ej
A
t : M-~A t .
has also enough proJectlves
[~,A]-~[M,~]
, T~-~T'J
called the Kan extension. the functor
Roughly speaking,
Ej(t)
algebra to compute the left derived
l)
Ej
: [M,~]--~[~,~]
: C-~A
the technique
models turns out to be the standard procedure
sion
, has a left
functors
Note is an
of acyclic
in homological of the Kan exten-
by means of projective
resolu-
The method of acycllc models was introduced by EilenbergMacLane [6]. Barr-Beck [2] gave a different version by means of cotrlples.
-
182-
tlons. 2) Eilenberg-MacLane T. , T. : ~--~A
[6] showed that two complexes of functors with isomorphic augmentations
homotopically equivalent, "representable" for and
~.M-~T
IM
sion of
T'J
T'J
are
Tn ' Tn
are
provided the functors and the complexes
T.M -~T_IM
are exact for every model
-~0
show that a functor restriction
n~ o
T_l--~@_l
T : C--~A
is "representable"
Is projective in
is again
T
(i.e.
above homotopy equivalence between
[M,A]
T@
T_l.J
and
We
iff the
and the Kan exten-
Ej(T.J) = T ).
In the f o l l o w l n g way 3)., The complexes projective resolutions of
M aM .
--~0
and T..J
Thus the
T @ can be obtained and
T_l.J .
T..J
are
Hence there is
a homotopy equivalence
h. : T . . J ~ T . . J
whlch is compatible
wlth the augmentation
T_l.J ~ T 1.J .
Applying the Kan exten-
sion
Ej : [M,~]'--~[~,A]
yields a homotopy equivalence
2)
I observed this after I had received a first draft of a paper by Barr-Beck in 1967. Their improved version of acycllc models in [3] w and the fact that cotriple derived functors are the left derlved functors of the Kan extension make fairly obvious that acyclic models and Kan extensions are closely related. In a recent paper of Dold, MacLane, Oberst [5] a relationship between acyclic models and projective classes was pointed out. As in Andr6 [1] and Barr-Beck [3] the Kan extension does not enter into the picture of [5] and all considerations are carried out in [C,~] , the range of the Kan extension. It appears that the use of the Kan extension establishes a much closer relationship between acycllc models and homological algebra than the one in [5]. Moreover, it gives rlse to a useful generalization of acyclic models which cannot be obtained by the methods of [5].
3)
This was also observed by D. Swan (unpublished).
-
Ej(h.)
: T.~
T.
183
-
because by the above
Ej(T..J) = T.
and
T,, hold. This procedure also shows that the n-th homology of value of the n-th left derived functor of i.e.
LnEj(T_I.J ) ~ Hn(T.)
Hn(T ) : C
)A
Hn(=,T_l'J)
holds.
Ej
Moreover,
at
T.
is the
T_l.J ,
one can show that
is isomorphic with the n-th homology functor
: C--~
of Andr~
Grothendieck AB4) category.
[1] P.3, provided
A
is a
(Andr4 denotes the category
It is well known that the left derived functors of
by
N .)
Ej
can be computed more generally by
This suggests defining a functor sentable" if
Ej(T.J) = T
and
Ej-acyclic resolutions.
T : C-~A
as "weakly repre-
LnEj(T'J ) = 0
for
This weaker notion of "representability",together acycliclty,
n>o with
no longer guarantees a homotopy equivalence between
the complexes
T.
and
T.
as above, but only that they have
isomorphic homology and that every existing chain map f. : T . - ~ T .
compatible with the augmentation induces a homol-
ogy isomorphism. T.'J ~ ~.'J
Moreover,
can be extended to a chain map
of the Kan extension topy equivalence functors
every chain map on the models
Ej : [M,A]--~[C,A]
.
T.--> T.
The lack of a homo-
can be compensated by conditions
F : A-->~'
, guaranteeing
is still valid and that
Ff.
that
by means
on additive
Hn(F-T .) ~ Hn(F'T .)
: F.T.---~FT. induces a homology
isomorphism. Morphism sets, natural transformation and functor categorles are denoted by brackets
[-,-]
, comma categories by
- 184-
parentheses U-categorles,
(-,-)
.
We assume that all our categories are
where
U
is a sufficiently
large universe,
use the same terminology as Verdier in the appendix of naire geometrie algebrique
1964".
and we "SEmi-
We mostly refrain from men-
tioning this universe except when we also consider categories belonging to a larger universe. abelian groups are denoted by
The categories of sets and S
and
Ab.Gr.
The phrase "Let
be a category with direct limits" always means that direct limits over U-small index categories.
D
is not necessarily small.
prove that this specific
has
However, we some-
times also consider direct limits of functors where
A
F : D ->A
,
Of course we then have to
limit exists.
Our approach is based on the notions of generalized representable functors
(cf. Ulmer
(of. Kan [8], Ulmer text.
[ll]) and Kan extensions,
[13]) which prove very useful in this con-
We first recall these notions and some of their prop-
erties. (I)
Let
M
and
pair of objects
A Ae A
be categories, and
alized representable functor
MeM M-,A
A
with sums.
To each
there is associated a gener(cf.
[Ii]).
It is the com-
posite
A@[M,-]
where
[M,-]
: M->S
: M-~S--~A
is the hom-functor and
A@
: S -~A
is
- 185 -
the
left adJoint
assigns
(2)
of
to a set
Yoneda
Then there
J~
[A,-] the
lemma, cf.
: A-~S A-fold Let
[Ii].
.
Recall
sum of
A .
that
A@
: S-~A
4) be a functor.
t : M-~A
is a b i s e c t i o n
[A@[M,-],tJ --~-- [A,tM] natural
in
A ,
M
is an isomorphism
and
of abelian
The functors
Proof.
a pair of adJoint
{M,A]--> [M,S],
r
the usual Yoneda
t .
A~
(for
and
[A,-]
: A-~S
induce
[M,S]--~[M_,AI, S~'>A|
~>[A,-].r . lemma
the b i J e c t i o n
groups.
: S--~A
functors
is additive,
If
and
Thus we obtain by adJolntness r-t
and
s-{M,-]
and
).
[A(~[M,-],t] =~ [[M,-I , [ A , - ] ' t ] ~_ [A,tM] Q.E.D.
(3)
Lemma.
natural each
t, t'
transformation
M~M
~(M)'T(M) = formation.)
4)
Let
: M-~A which
be functors
is obJectwlse
and
split,
is a morphlsm
~(M)
id
(Note that
need not be a natural
~
t-~t'
i.e.,
there .
: t'M-~tM
~:
a
for
such that trans-
Then every diagram
For the dual notion of a corepresentable functor M-~A we refer to Ulmer [ll]. Note that a corepresentable f-unct--or is also covarlant. The r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n generalized r e p r e s e n t a b l e and corepresentable functors is entirely different from the relationship between covariant and contravariant hom-functorS.
-
186-
-7
t
f f f f
A|
>t'
can be completed as indicated.
In particular,
Jan, this shows that the generalized projective
relative
in
which are obJectwlse
[M,A]
Proof.
Since
~(M)
[A,tM]-9 [A,t'M] from the Yoneda (4)
Remark.
to the class
A
representable
is abel-
functors are
6~ of short exact sequences split exact. is split,
: tM-~ t'M
is epimorphic. lemma
if
the induced map
Thus the assertion follows
(2).
A(~ [M,-]
It is obvious that (3) remains valid if
is replaced by a direct sum
~(Ai~[Mi,-] ) . A
(5)
Another variation
abellan and
AEA
projective,
need not be obJectwlse preserves wise
~
objects
Ai
M--~A
functors Let and by (6)
and
A
are proJectlves are projective
Theor@m
in
A~[M,-]
in
[M,A] A .
is
W~ : t -~t'
the hom-functor
This shows that
[A,-]
and llke-
, provided
the
Using constant
one can show that the converse is also true.
be a morphlsm in r~
A
then the eplmorphism
split, because
eplmorphlsms.
( A i @ [Mi,-] )
If
of (B) is the following:
M .
Denote by
d~
its domain
its range.
[11].2~15.
with direct sums ( M
Let
M
and
need not be small).
be categories, Then for every func-
-
tot
t : M-gA
187-
there is a direct limit representation t = llm t d ~ @ [ r s , - ]
The objects of the corresponding M 9
phlsms of
The morphlsm set
ment if either empty (cf. Proof: erty of
:x' = Idd~
or
For every
[~, ,~! ]
consists
o<' = Idr .
mor-
of one ele-
Otherwise
it is
[12] 2.19).
We give an outline, @
index category are the
making use of the adJointness
, the dual of [12] 2.21 and the usual Yoneda X eM
and
Ya A
llm ----> td~,| llm
,
tX
=lim
lemma.
there are natural isomorphisms ~--
Im
~r~,X], [td~,Y~ ~
This shows that
prop-
d~[r~,X],
[-,X],[t-,Y] i ~
td~ @[r~,X]
[tX,Y]
.
J
Q.E.D. (7)
R e m a r k ~ ) Moreover, Y
: M_~
one can show that the Yoneda functor [M_,A]
, M x A
shares with the usual Yoneda embedding
5)
the property that it is
The properties (2), (5) and (7) show that generalized representable functors are a reasonable substitute for homfunctors in an arbitrary functor category [M,A] . In the following we omit "generalized" and call a functor A | [M,-] : M - ~ A representable. In order not to confuse Eilenberg-MacLa~e's notion of a "representable" functor with ours, we use quotation marks for the former. We will show later that the two notions are closely related.
-
dense
(cf. Ulmer
otherwords,
[12]) or adequate in the sense of Isbell.
every functor
presentables
t e [M,A]
(Y,t)
(8)
(K an_extension
Definition
functor
is the direct
In
limit of re-
over the canonical index category which is the
comma category
t : M-CA
188-
.
be functors. Ej(t)
: ~-~A
Let
[8]).
J
and
: M-gC
The right Kan J-extension such that for any functor
of
t
is a
s : ~ *
there is a blJection
[Ej(t),s] ~ [t,s.J] , natural in
s .
Dually,
~JCt) : C_-~A
the left Kan J-extension
t
of
is a functor
such that there are natural blJections
[s,~J(t)] ~ [s-J,t] It follows immediately up to equivalence.
that
Ej(t)
and
We are mainly concerned with
short we call it the Kan extension. to state the dual theorems faithful, Ej(t) (9)
EJ(t)
for
EJ(t)
ere determined Ej(t)
and in
We leave it to the reader .
If
J
is full and
it follows from (i0) below that
is an extension of Lemma.
Let
of a representable
t .
E (t).J ~ t , i.e. J This explains the terminology.
J : M .,->C be a functor. functor
A@[M,-]
Ae[JM,-]
The Kan extension
: M_-~ A_ is
: C_-~A
-
Likewise
189~4. (Ai~ [M1,-])
for an infinite sum
the Kan extension
is
[JMi,-] ) : C--~ A
(Ai|
Similarly, is
[aM,-]
Proof.
the Nan extension
: c--,s_
of a hom-functor
[M,-]
: M-~S
.
For every functor
s : C-~A
the Yoneda
lemma (2)
gives rise to biJectlons [ A ~ [ J M , - ] , S ] -~ [A,sJM] ~ [ A ~ [ M , - ] , S ' J ] which are natural in
S
The second half can be established
.
similarly. Q.E.D. Assume that
E (t)
exists for every functor
t : M-~A
J
Then the Kan extension the restriction direct limits.
.
~
[~,A]~
Ej
: [M,A]--~[~,A]
[M,A], s ~ s . J
This is also true if
.
is left adJoint to Thus
Ej
preserves
Ej is not defined every-
where. (i0) Assume
Theorem. A
lim td~ | , )
Let
J : M-,C
has arbitrary sums.
Then
t : M-,A Ej(t)
exists and
~a(t) is valid.
and
= lira t d ~ |
-]
be functors.
: ~-~A
exists iff
190
-
(Ii)
Corollary
limits,
(Kan [81~.
If
then for every functor
-
M
is small and
t : M C}A
A
has direct
the Kan extension
exists. Proof of ( i 0 ~
By (6) there is a representation
t = lit t d ~ |
.
Assume that
lim t d ~ [ J r ~ , - ]
From (9) it follows for every functor Wlim t d ~ [ J r ~ , - ] , L-~
=~/ lim (m
s : C--~A
exists. that
~ d ~ @ [ J r ~ , - ] , ~ "%" I--
<
Hence ly, if
Ej(t)
exists and
Ej(t)
exists,
(12)
Let
subcategory
it follows
that
Ej(t)
Converse. in
is the limit
.6)
J : M--~
be the full inclusion of a full small
(referred to as models) and let
category with sums and enough proJectives.
A
functor
P@[M,-]
is projective
in
Choose for every functor
A
.
: M-+A
be an abelian
As shown in (5), a
representable
6)
.
then by reading the above isomorphism
the opposite direction, lim t d ~ @ [ J r ~ , - ]
Ej(t)--- lim t d ~ [ J r ~ , - ]
is projective
iff
t : M-+~
P and
The theorem shows that the existence of Kan extensions is equivalent with the existence of certain direct limits in A whose index systems are not sets but proper classes. From-this it is fairly obvious that not every functor admits a Kan extension. For a counterexample see [13] p.6. Sometimes special properties of M or t guarantee the existence of E~(t) . For instanc--e, if t is a small direct limit of representable functors, then one can show, as in (i0), that Ej(t) exists, provided the range of t has direct limits.
-
every
Me M
tlve.7)
an epimorphism
191-
PM--~ tM , where
By means of the Yoneda lemma
PM
is proJec-
~PM~[M,-],t]
~ [PM,tM]
the family of epimorphlsms determines a natural transformation ~(t)
: M~M(PM@[M,-]) - > t
which can be easily shown to be
eplmorphlc (use the Yoneda lemma (2)). In
[M,A]
Thus
t
is projective
iff it is a direct summand of a sum of projective
representables.
If
t
is the restriction of a functor
T : C--~A , then this family and the Yoneda isomorphlsms BM@[JM,-], mation (13)
~(t)
=
determine also a natural transfor-
: H,.we( P M e [ J M , - ] ) - - ) T
Theorem.
Let
T : ~ >A
.
be a functor.
The following
are equivalent: I)
T
is "representable"
in the sense of Ellenberg-MacLane.
(We use quotation marks to distinguish thelrnotlon of representability from ours~ ll) T.J is
is projective in T , l.e.
Moreover,
[M,A]
and the Kan extension of
Ej(T.J) = T .
the restriction
Rj : [~,A]--P[M,A]
morphism between the "representable" functors projective functors in Kan extension
[M,A] .
Ej : [M,A]~-e[~,A]
tion of a "representable"
7)
T.J
sets up an iso[~,~]
and the
The inverse is given by the .
(This shows that the no-
functor (Eilenberg-MacLane)
and a
If A is the category of abellan groups, one can choose P~ to be the free abellan group on tM It is instructive for the following to have this example in mind. It links our approach wlth the one of Eilenberg-MacLane [6].
-
representable
192
-
functor (Ulmer [II]) are closely related.
ally the functor
T
is also projective
in
Actu-
[~,A] , but thls is
irrelevant in the following.) Proof.
Eilenberg-MacLane
sentable"
call a funct0r
T : ~-~
if the above natural transformation
~(t)
: ~ (PM@[JM,-])--~T M is a direct summand of
admits a section
T
,$ (PM ~[JM'-])
E (PM
"repre-
[M,-]) --- PM Ej-Rj
sum
on itself.
~(PM@[JM,-]) M direct summand T
of
~M ( P M @ [ J M
By (12) the restriction
ly, if
T-J
Kan extension
is projective and ~(t)
Since
J
is a full Inclumaps the
Obviously the same holds for a J
~])
T.J
'
i.e.
Ej(T-J) = T
is projective.
Ej(T.J) : T
: ~(PM@[M,-])--~T-J
?~
(in other words,
: [C,A] --> [M,A] --> [C,A]
valid.
epimorphism
.
(of. (9)) and
sion, the composite
~
: ~(PM|
is
Converse-
holds, then the
splits and" so does its .
It follows easily
M
from this and (12) that the restriction functor Kan extension
Ej
sentable" functors
Rj
and the
set up an isomorphism between the "repreC-~ A
and the projective functors
M~A
.
Q.E.D. From this we obtain immediately the following: (14) Theorem.
Let
T, : ~ - ~ A
be a positive complex 8) of
functors together with an augmentation
T.-~T
i .
The follow-
ing are equivalent: 8)
This means that Ing we abbreviate
T , = o for negative n . In the follow"positive complex" to "complex".
-
l)
The functors
Tn
are "representable"
augmented complex
ll)
T.'J
T.-J--~T 1 . J - ~ 0
is a projective resolution of
Ej(Tn'J) = T n holds for (15)
Corollar F.
satisfying T.
193-
i)
If
n~o
T*-~T-I
such that
T1-J
holds, then
Every chain map
T.
(i.e.
T. ~ T . .
Ej
at
By (14)il) the complexes
T..J ~ T..J .
and Is
is com-
T_l.J % T 1-J . 5.) Is the value of t , where
Hn(T.) ~ LnEj(t)
projective resolutions of equivalence
(and
T.
T.--~ ~.
provided its restriction on M
the n-th left derived functor of
Proof of (15).
and
.
T_I.J ~ T_I-J
the n-th homology of
T_l.J ~ t ~ T 1.J
and the
is exact.
patlble wlth the augmentation isomorphism Moreover,
n~ o
is another augmented complex
are homotopically equivalent.
a homotopy equivalence,
for
). T..J
and
T..J
are
t , and hence there is a homotopy Applying the Kan extension yields
Clearly the restriction of every chain map
f. : T.~-~T.
on
provided
f.J
T 1.J~T
1.J .
yields again
M
is a homotopy equivalence
f.J : T.J ~ T.J
is compatible with the augmentation isomorphism Applying the Kan extension
f..
Hence
f.
By standard homologlcal algebra
Ej
on
f.J
Is also a homotopy equivalence. LnEj(t) ~ H n E j ( T . - J ) = HnT *
holds. (16)
Remark.
The method of acycllc models can be duallzed by
replacing the representable
functors
A~[M,-]
by corepresent-
-
able functors
[-,A] - [-,M]
by Injectlve functors intro.).
left
"corepresentable" ~ : T
[.T=Id
injections
and projective functors
[-,I].[-,M]
Kan extension
has enough InJectlves.
l.e.
-
( 16~
Thereby the right Kan extension
placed by the
morphlsm
194
A functor
InJectlve, cf. [ll] Ej
has to be re-
(cf. (8)).
T : ~--~
Assume
is sald to be
(In the sense of Eilenberg-MacLane) ~-[-,IM]-[-,M]~_ _
.
EJ
P@[M,-]
(As In (12)
[TM~IM}M,
~'
Iff the
has a left inverse
~- ,
Is associated wlth a family of
9 , where
IM~ ~
Is InJectlve.)
Wlth
this, one can easily duallze (13)-(15) and also the considerations below. (17)
Remark.
Of course the notion of acycllclty Is self-dual. Roughly speaking, the above shows that the
method of acycllc models Is the standard procedure In homologlcal algebra to compute the left derived functors of the Kan extension by means of proJectlves. left derived functors of
Ej
It is well known that the
can be computed not only wlth pro-
proJectlves but more generally by Ej-acycllc resolutlons. 9) Thls leads to a useful generalization of acycllc models.
For
the considerations below, one can drop the assumption that has sums and enough proJectlves and assume instead that the Kan extension and its left derlved functors exist (for instance, if A
is a Grothendleck AB4) category (cf. [7]) or If
M
consists
of the proJectlves of a cotrlple, cf. [3]).
9)
Recall that for n > o .
t~[M,A]
Is called Ej-acycllc If
LnEj(t) = 0
-
(18)
Definition.
presentable"
A functor
iff
A
-
T : C --~A
Ej(T-J) = T
Clearly a "representable" If
195
and
is called
"weakly re-
LnEj(T-J ) = 0
for n > o
.lO)
functor is "weakly representable".
is AB4), then every direct summand of a sum
(A i @ [ J M i , - ] ) Ai ~ A .
is "weakly representable",
where
Further examples are A-representable
M jaM
and
functors in the
sense of M. Andre [1] p.ll. (19)
Theorem.
presentable" and
T.-e~_l
Let
where
Then t
: C--~A
such that
T 1.J ~ T 1.J
T..J--~T_I.J ~ 0
is a functor isomorphic
tended to a chain
T.-->T.
Ej : [M,A] -->[C,~]
.
1
is valid and the augT..J ~ T 1 - J - ~ O holds for
T 1.J
T..J--~T..J
or
are
n ~o ,
T 1.J .
can be uniquely ex-
In other words, the restriction of chain
f. : T . - ~ T .
vided its restriction on
lO)
to
T.-~T
by the Kan extension
[T.,T.]->[T..J,T.-J]
chain map
and
Hn( T. ) ~= L n E J (t ) ~= Hn(T . )
Every chain map on the models
maps
be complexes of "weakly re-
functors together with augmentations
mented complexes exact.
T.,T.
is a blJection.
Moreover,
induces a homology isomorphism, M
every pro-
is compatible with the augmenta-
There is a useful modification of the notion "weakly representable". Let ~ be a proper class of short exact sequences in [M,A] in the sense of MacLane [9] p.367, for instance, the class of obJectwise split exact sequences. Then the condltion LnE~(T.J) = 0 can be replaced by ~ L ^ E ~ ( T J) = 0 , w n e r e ~-L~ denotes the left derived functors with respect to ~ . If the complexes T. and T. in (19) below have the property that T.J-*T~J-90 and T~J--,T.IJ-~0 a r e ~ - e x a c t , then the statements (19)-(22) also hold if L~E~ is replaced by ~-L,Ej.
-
tlon
T -- l-J
Proof.
5_1
~
oJ
-
9
The first half is standard homological algebra
see Grothendieck
[7], RShrl
[T.,T.]-->[T..J,T..J] tlon isomorphism (cf. (8)). tion
196
[10])9
The restriction map
is a blJectlon because it is the adJunc-
[T.,T.] ~ [Ej(T..J),T.]~-
Hence for every chain map
Ej(f.J) = f.
striction of
f.
holds, where on
M .
Ej-acyclic
f.J : T . - J - g T . - J also exact and (20) are
Remark 9
[T..J ,T.-J]
f. :
T.-~T.
the equa-
f.J : T . . J - e ~ . . J
The mapping cone
Kan extension of the mapping cSne of sists of
(e.g.
f.J
is the re-
Cf~ of
f.
is the
II)~ The latter con-
objects and is exact because by assumption
is a homology isomorphism.
f. : T.--> T.
Hence
C~
is
induces a homology isomorphism.
It is clear from the above that
homotopically equivalent iff
T -J
and
T.
T -J
and
T.
are.
In
general there need not be a homotopy equivalence between and
T..
T.
In practice this lack can be compensated by the
following: Let
F : ~--~'
be an additive functor,
assume that the objects and
C ~E
.
isomorphism,
ii)
Then where
Ff.
TnC
and
Tn C
: FT. > F T .
f. : T.--~T.
A'
abelian, and
are F-acyclic
for
n ~o
still induces a homology
is as in (19).
This can be
For the definition of the mapping c~ne and its elementary properties, we refer to Dold [4]. Recall that a chain map g~ between complexes induces a homology isomorphism iff the mapping c6ne of g~ is an exact complex.
-
197
-
proved in the same way as above by means of the mapping cone technlquel2),If either Jects 13) or
A
~
is AB4) and has enough F-acycllc ob-
has sums and enough proJectlves,
construct a resolution
P.(t)
of
t
then one can
consisting in each dimen-
sion of a sum of representable functors which can be embedded into a diagram T.J ~ T-I 9J
P.(t)
~__
0
One can choose F-acycllc
Pn(t)
=
> T..J
t
~ --
T -i .J
0
0
~(QM@[M,-])
where
Q, is either
(first case) or projective (second case).
the values of
EjPn(t ) : ~--,A
Clearly the complex
are F-acycllc for
EjP.(t)--~Ej(t)
and acyclic on the models.
Moreover nDo
.
is "weakly representable"
Thus we obtain from the preceding
argument homology isomorphisms
Hn(FT.) = ~ H n (FEjP. (t)) =
H n (FT.) The theorem below, which we state without proof, gives further information about this problem. (21)
Theorem 9
Let
T : C -~A
be a "weakly representable"
12)
In the examples, the objects proJectlves.
TnC
and
Tn C
are usually
13)
i.e. every object in 6 is a quotient of an object such that LnF(Q) = 0 for n ~ o .
Q
-
functor and let
F : A --~A'
right adJoint.
198-
be an additive functor with a
Assume either that
gories with enough F-acyclic
A
and
A'
are AS4) cate-
objects or that they have sums and
enough proJectives. Then TC
F.T : C ~ A ' are F-acyclic
L.Ej(F-T-J)(C) (22)
for
objects
CeC
Let
of functors TnC , Tn C
CeC
.
and
T.
~T_I
from
C
and
MeM
.
TIM
other assertions
[email protected]_I (23)
L F(TC)
and to
, cf. [14] (19).)
T*-'~T-I
A
as in (19) such that the
~ T iM
are F-acyclic
, where
for
n~o
T_I "J =~t =~ @ -I .J
denot~ the Kan extension.
in (19) also hold for
and
Clearly the
FT.--~FT_I
and
.
Remark.
The isomorphism
Hn(T.) ~ H n ( T . )
also be obtained from Andre's computational homology functors
H.(,-)
AB4) [cf. [I] P.7). H.(,-)
be augmented
Then it follows from (19) that
H n ( F T.) ' ~= L n Ej(F't) ~= H n(F@.) E~ : [M,A']--9"[~,A']
iff the objects
(This follows from the equations
~ L.F{Ej(T.J)(C))=-
Corollary.
complexes
and
is "weakly representable"
Ho(,-)
Thus an augmented
device for his , provided
A
is
One can show that the functors
: [M,A]--~ [~,A]
in particular
: [M,A]--~[~,A]
in (19) can
coincide with = Ej(-)
(cf.
complex of functors
L.Ej(-)
[14], ( 4 ) T.-~T_I
: [M,A]--->[~,A]y this volume). satisfies
Andre's condition in [i] prop. 1.5 Iff it is acycllc on the models and
Tn
is "weakly representable"
prop. 1.5 in [I] implies that
for
n~ o .
Hn(T.) ~ Hn(-,T_I'J)
Hence
~ H n ( T .) .
-
This shows that Andre's eralization
199
-
computational
of acyclic models 9
the notion
replaced by "weakly representable". this method to improve
category
[~,A]
"representable"
Barr-Beck
their original
in [4],but all considerations
method is actually a gen-
[3] w
used
version of acyclic models
were carried out in the functor
without using the Kan extension.
sentation in [3] w
being
Their pre-
made me realize the relationship
between
acyclic models and Kan extensions.
Before we discuss their ap-
proach, we sketch how the technique
of acyclic models works
when
M
(24)
Let
of
~
is not small. M
be a full but not necessarily
and let
proJectlves.
A
be an abellan category with sums and enough
Denote by
groups 9 the underlying large universe of objects
V
M , C and
the category of abellan
sets of which belong to a sufficiently
A .
Let
A
U
functors
from
A
to
which take U-small direct limits in inverse limits.
rect limits. Jectlves. PeA
I : A
Note that
~
The proJectlves is projective.
>A
is exact and preserves U-dl-
has V-direct
Define a functor
T : C-->A
: ~)(PM~[JM,-])--91"T IM
limits and enough pro-
are V-sums of hom-functors Using the V-completion
can proceed as before 9 and (12)-(22)
~(t)
(cf. intro.) and the sets
be the category
of contravarlant
The Yoneda embedding
where
A_~b.Gr.
which contains
COntu(A~149 Ab.Gr.
small subcategory
[-,P] 9
one
carry over to this case.
to be "representable" has a section (of.
if
(12)).
A
,
-
functor
T : C-->A
M J~ C T_~ A ~
extension.
is "representable" Iff the composite i
(I'T'J) = I'T
200-
is projective in [M,~]
holds, where
Ej . [M,~]
and
~ [C,~]
9
is the Kan
Two complexes of "representable" functors
T.,~. : C--*A
with augmentations
T.~> T_I
and
are
T.~T_I
homotopically equivalent, provided the augmented complexes
T..J-->T_I.J ~ 0 ~_l'J
and
is valid.
@ . . J ~ T_I-J ~ 0
Every chain map
is
T.--~@.
T_I'J ~ T_I.J .
is isomorphic with the value of where
T 1-J ~ t ~ T 1.J .
Jectlves.) T : ~-~
(Note that
Hn(T.) at
I.t,
As before, the notion of a "representable" functor can be replaced by the notion of a "weakly repre-
and
LnEj(T.J)=
or
for
n ~o .
and
Hn(T .) ~ LnEj(t)
0
Then
T~
Ej(I.T-J) = I-T and or
T.
and
with the augmentation isomorphism
f. : T.--) T.
also a homology isomorphism, provided C~ C
and
0
induces a homolM
is compatible
T_I.J ~ T_I.J .
is an additive functor, then
F-acycllc for
LnEj(I.T.J)=
I'Hn(T.) X Hn(I'T.) ~ LnEj(l't)
Likewise every chain map
A'
Ej(T'J) = T
still have isomorphic homology
ogy isomorphism, provided its restriction on
(25)
Moreover
[M_,~] has enough pro-
The latter can mean either
F : A~
homotopy
LnE J : [M_,~I-~ [C,~]
sentable" functor.
hold.
a
J~
is compatible with
equivalence, provided its restriction on the augmentation isomorphism
T
are exact and
TnC
If
Ff. : F T . - , F T . and
Tn C
is
are
n~ o , etc.
Barr-Beck [2] gave a version of acycllc models in which
-
the model category
M
201-
For the sake of complete-
is not small.
ness, we briefly recall their approach. in category note by
~
(cf. [3]) and
J : M ~ ~
T. : C - , A
Tn
triple.
and T.
GC , where
M
TnG
where
C e~
iff
.
A complex of funcis called
T.-~T_I
T..G -~T_I-G
has a contraction.
~
Tn
~ : G - ~ idc
admits a section is the co-unit of the co-
Barr-Beck proved in [2] that two complexes of repreT. , T. : ~ - ~
sentable functors tions
De-
is called representable iff the canonical nat-
ural transformation U- : Tn--~ T n G 9
be a cotriple
be an abelian category.
with an augmentation
acyclic on the models The functor
6
the inclusion of the full subcategory con-
sisting of the objects tors
~
Let
T-I
-~
T-I
T*-~ T-1 and
in [3] w
T.
with isomorphic augmenta-
are homotopically equivalent if
are acyclic on the models. 14) have isomorphic homology.
that for the latter (i.e.
T.--> T_I
In particular
Later they pointed out Hn(T.) :~Hn(T.) ) their
notions of representability and acyclicity can be considerably weakened.
Denote by
associated with
G
H.(-,T)G
: ~--~
the cotriple homology
and a coefficient functor
T : C--*A
Their modified definition of representability is: and
Ho(-,Tn) G :
Tn; of acyclicity:
Hj(-,Tn) G = O
for
J ~o
T.M ~ T _ I M
~0
14)
It should be noted that this homotopy equivalence cannot be obtained by the method outlined in (24) if one takes J : M--*~ to be the full inclusion of the objects of the form GC , where C ~ ~ . To obtain the homotopy equivalence one has to define J : M - ~ C in a more elaborate way which we omit in view of the more general situation we discuss below.
-
is an exact complex for ly weaker because hold
15)
202
M~M .
-
These definitions
Ho(-,T.G)~ = T.G
for every functor
and
T : ~-~A
and
connection between this (generalized)
are obvious-
Hj(-,T-G)G~ J 7o
.
To make the
version of acycllc models
and classical homological
algebra we first recall that
Ho( ,-)~ : [~,A]
is the composite
~ [~,~]
Rj : [~,A]--~[M,A]
with the Kan extension
(of. [14] this volume). the composite
of
Rj
Moreover
with
L.Ej
0
of the restriction Ej : [M,~] --~[~,A]
H.( '-)G : [~'~] --~[~'~] : [M,A]-~[C,A]
.
This shows
that the modified notions of acyclicity and representability Barr-Beck
[3] w
is
of
coincide with "acyclic" and "weakly repre-
sentable" as defined in (18). models is essentially
Hence their method of acyclic
the standard procedure in homological
algebra to compute the left derived functor of the Kan extension
Ej : [M,A]--~[~,~]
by means of
Ej-acyclic
resolutions.
We leave it to the reader to state theorems analogous
to
(19)-(22).
15)
Clearly the same is valid for every direct summand of T-G.
-
203
-
BIBLIOGRAPHY
[1]
Andre, M., Me~thode ~impliciale
et alg~bre commutative,
en alg~bre homologique
(Lecture notes in Mathematics,
#32), Springer, 19679 [2]
Barr, M. and J. Beck, "Acyclic models and triples", in;
Conference on Categorical Algebra, pp.336-343, Springer, [3]
(1966).
. "Homology and standard constructions",
(to
appear in Lecture notes in Mathematics.) [4]
Dold, A., "Zur Homotopietheorie der Kettenkomplexe",
Math. Annalen, [5]
140; 278-298,
(1960)9
, S. MacLane, U. Oberst, "Projective classes and acyclic models", in; A. Dold, Heidelberg and Eckmann (eds.), Report8 of the Midwest
Seminar,
Category
(Lecture notes in Mathematics, #47);
78-91, Springer, 1967. [6]
[7]
Eilenberg, S
and S
Am. J. Math9
75; 189-199,
(1953).
Grothendieck, A., "Sur quelques points d'alg~bre homologique"
[8]
MacLane, "Acyclic models"
Tohoku, Math
J., 9; 119-221,
(1957)
Kan, D., "Adjoint Functors", Trans. Amer. Math9 Soc., 87; 295-329,
(1958).
-
[9]
204
-
MacLane, S., Homology, Springer, 1963.
[i0] R~hrl, H., "Satelliten halbexakter Funktoren", Math.
Zeitschrift, 79; 193-223, (1962). [ii] Ulmer, F., "Representable functors with values in arbitrary categories" [12]
J. of Algebra, 8; 96-129, (1968)
. "Properties of dense and relative adjoint functors", J. of Algebra, 8; 77-95,
(1968)9
. "Properties of Kan extensions", Mim. Notes,
[13] E.T.H.,
(1966).
[14]
"Kan extensions, Cotriple and Andr6 (co)homology" in;
Lecture
notes
in mathematics,
this
volume.
-
205
-
I
D E R I V E D C A T E G O R Y AND P O I N C A R E D U A L I T Y
by
M.
The n o t a t i o n s functors
Zisman*
for d e r i v e d c a t e g o r i e s
are those of H A R T S H O R N E
Z, d e s i g n
[3].
Capital
locally c o m p a c t H a u s s d o r f f spaces;
and d e r i v e d letters X,Y,
A is a r i n g
w i t h unity given once for all; we w r i t e A x, A Y, ~or the categories
of sheaves of left A - m o d u l e s
over X,Y.
not s u p p o s e the ring A to be c o m m u t a t i v e , add the h y p o t h e s i s commutative
ring.)
(If we do
we g e n e r a l l y m u s t
that A is a A - f l a t A - a l g e b r a w h e r e A is a In the f o l l o w i n g a sheaf always means
a
s h e a f of A - m o d u l e s .
i.
THE F U N C T O R f!
i.i t
Let f: X sheaf over X. way:
> Y be a c o n t i n u o u s map,
We d e f i n e a s h e a f f!F o v e r Y in the f o l l o w i n g
G i v e n any open set U in Y, then flF(U)
all s e c t i o n s
and let F be a
s 6 F(F-Iu)
the r e s t r i c t i o n
flK: K
* I n s t i t u t Henri Poincar~,
is the set of
w h o s e s u p p o r t K c f-l(u)
is such that
> U is a p r o p e r map.
Ii Rue P i e r r e Curie,
Paris.
-
It is e a s y
to c h e c k
that
i. 2
>
flF(U)
a sheaf.
Examples
1.2.1. fiF =
Fc(X,F)
F with
If the
where
compact
subset
putting
space
Fc stands
Y is a p o i n t , for the
then we have
s e t of all
sections
of
support.
1.2.2. open
-
the presheaf U
is in f a c t
206
If
X i n t o Y,
(F Y)
f: X
"
- Y
is the
inclusion
then
flF is the e x t e n s i o n
of an
FY
of F to Y,
= 0 for y ~ X. I) Y
1.2.3. then
Of c o u r s e
f! is n o t h i n g
but
if f: X
the u s u a l
> Y is a p r o p e r
direct
image
functor
map, f,.
1.3
Consider entiable
manifold
the u n i q u e numbers. the
map
constant
the
of d i m e n s i o n
the c a s e w h e r e
sheaf
known
R over
) ~
following
>
X
n, Y is a p o i n t ,
f r o m X to a p o i n t ,
It is w e l l
0 has
for a w h i l e
that
a n d A = R the
the d e R H A M ' s
is a d i f f e r f: X
> Y
field
of r e a l
resolution
of
X ~o
;
fll
;
...
>
~n
> 0
property:
I) G i v e n a s h e a f F o v e r w r i t e F x f o r the s t a l k
a space X and a point of F o v e r x.
x 6 X,
then we
-
Given
any o p e n
207
-
set U in X we g e t Rqf! (~Pu) = Hq(U'~P)c = 0
for any q > 0 and any p > 0.
More
generally,
if f: X
> Y is a c o n t i n u o u s
and F a s h e a f o v e r X, w e say t h a t F is f - s o f t
if t h e
map
follow-
ing r e l a t i o n holds: R qflF u = 0 for any q > 0 a n d any U o p e n In o t h e r w o r d s , s e t U c X.
1.4
F is f - s o f t
if F u is f ! - a c y c l i c
(Confer G O D E M E N T
The c o n d i t i o n
(i) qo
for any o p e n
[2] f o r the n o t a t i o n
F ). U
A(A)
We say t h a t the c o n d i t i o n f: X
in X.
A(A)
holds
for a m a p
> Y iff f is of f i n i t e
> 0 such that
(ii) T h e r e
cohom0!0@ical
dimension
(i.e.
there exist
R q f ! F = 0 for any s h e a f F a n d any q ~ qo).
exist
a finite
) A
) no
resolution
of the c o n s t a n t
sheaf
A over X 0 where
the s h e a v e s
The maps
for w h i c h
~P are f - s o f t
following A(A)
three
9
...
> ~r
> 0
and A-(right)-flat.
lemmas
assert
that there exist
holds.
1 . 4 . 1 Lemma. dimension
) ~i
If f
!
is of f i n i t e
a n d if f is n o t h e r i a n ,
then
A(A)
cohomological holds
f o r f.
-
1.4.2 Lemma.
2 0 8
-
Let A
> B be a ring homomorphism
(which send the unity of A into the unity of B). holds
If ~(A)
for f, then ~ (B) holds for f. 1.4.3 Lemma.
and compositions.
~ (A) is closed under change of basis
Moreover,
if 5 (A) holds
for g.f,
it holds
for f~ Using these lemmas we easily for any map between any change
(topological)
of basis,
1.5 Theorem
see that ~(A)
manifolds
and then, using
for a lot of maps.
(Poincar~ Duality)
Let X and Y be locally compact Haussdorff and let f: X condition to natural
) Y be a continuous
~(A) holds for f.
(*) R Hom
(For a proof,
see
Hom D ,
Suppose
f!
:
D + (AY)
spaces
that the /
a unique
(up
> D § (Ax) pro-
isomorphism
(Of!F',G')
where F" is any object
map.
Then there exists
isomorphism ) functor
vided with a bifunctor!al
but
holds
~ - R Hom
in D(AX)
[4] expos~
(F',fIG ")
and G" any object
4.)
Since H~
Hom"
in D+(AY). is nothing
we get, taking the 0-cohomology: I
HOmD(AY ) (Rf!F'oG') so that the f u n c t o r
f"
I
is
in
~ HomD(AX ) (F',f'G') some sense
right
adjoint
to
Rf
I "
Q
1.5.1. following way.
The description
of f! can be done in the
-
Since
the category
whose
objects
sheaf
in the complex being
homotopy
D+(AY)
to the category
below complexes injective
of maps b e t w e e n
that G" is such a complex. 1.4
-
is e q u i v a l e n t
are b o u n d e d
classes
209
Given
of sheaves,
(and whose maps
complexes),
each are
we may suppose
a resolution
fl" as in
(ii), we put (fiG')
The complex
(U) = Hom" (f!~ u,G
)
of presheaves > fIG'(U)
U is in fact a complex
of sheaves,
the complex we are looking
for.
1.6
In order to make u n d e r s t a n d a b l e theorem
1.5 is called
now compute
both
a Poincar~
duality
sides of our formula
X is a topological
manifold
the reason why theorem,
we shall
(*) in the case where
of dimension
n, Y is a point,
and where we take G" = A. 2)
Let ~ sheaves.
design
If x is a point
the cohomology
of a complex
in X, a c c o r d i n g
to GODEMENT
of [2],
4.1, we have: ~q(f!A)x
= lim ---~ H q Hom'(f !n" U 'I'A)
2) Recall that a complex of sheaves over a point is simply a complex of A-modules. Moreover, we write F for the complex which has 0 in any degree @ 0 and has F in degree 0.
210
-
where
I'A is an injective
through X.
the filtered
-
resolution
of A, and w h e r e U runs
set of all open n e i g h b o r h o o d s
Since X is a manifold,
we are allowed
of x in
to suppose U = R n,
and then we get
~q(f!A)
A0 if q @ -n if q = -n
x =
so that the c o m p l e x of sheaves
f IA is q u a s i - i s o m o r p h i c
to the
c o m p l e x w h i c h has 0 in any degree ~ -n and has the usual orientation
sheaf 0 of X in degree -n.
c o m p l e x F" is simply a sheaf F.
Suppose
The formula
now that the
(*) gives
an
isomorphism H q Hom" (RF i.e.
a
spectral
c
(X,F),
I'A) ~ Extq+n(F,0)
sequence
E p'q = ExtP(Hcq(X,F) , A) ~ ExtP+q+n(F,0)
In particular,
if A is a field, we have the usual
isomorphism Hom(H~(X,F),
2.
PERFECT
COMPLEXES
(Confer
If we w a n t to w a l k formula
for sheaves,
tions on the sheaves
A) ~ Extn-q(F,0)
9
OF SHEAVES
[4] expos~
9)
in the d i r e c t i o n
we must introduce
some
used in the theory;
of a L E F S C H E T Z
finiteness
condi-
-
211-
more precisely we first define a perfect complex of A-modules as a complex which is bounded, each degree and afterwards subcategory
of
Db(A x)
free and O f finite type in b denote by Df.f.Z.(AX) the full
whose objects
sheaves which are quasi-isomorphic whose sheafs
are those complexes
of
to bounded com~!exes
are flat in each degree;
(f.f./. stands for
"finite flat length") 9 2.1 Theorem Let F" be a complex in locally compact Haussdorff A(A) holds for the map two conditions
Df b.f./.(A x)
where X is a
space such that the condition
nX: X
> point.
Then the following
are equivalent:
For any Doint X in X, (i)
The local inverse system
U
- RFc(U,F
) is essen-
tially perfect. (ii)
The local direct system
U
; RF(U,F')
is essentially
perfect. (U runs through the set of all open neighborhoods Recall that the conditions
(i) and
(ii) mean that,
given x 6 U, there exist two open neighborhoods x, contained
V and V' of
in U, such that the natural maps RFc (V,F") RF(U,F')
factor
of x in X.)
~ RFc (U,F') -
-
RF(V',F')
(in the derived category D(A) of the category of
-
A-modules)
through
a perfect
212
-
complex.
2.2 D e f i n i t i o n A complex of sheaves the p r e c e d i n g
satisfying
t h e o r e m will be called
the conditions
a perfect
complex
of (of
sheaves). Perfect of sheaves) ([i] and
complexes
satisfying
[4]).
look like sheaves
the B O R E L - W I L D E R
(or complexes
equivalent
conditions
In fact we have the
2.3 T h e o r e m
Let X be a spac e as in 2.1 and F" be a p e r f e c t complex (i)
of sheaves
Given
over X.
an[ compact
subset
K of X and an[ open subset U
of X such that U D K, then the canonical RF(U,F') factors
in D(A)
through
~ RF(K,F')
a perfect
(ii) Given two open subspaces
factors
in D(A)
c
(U,F')
through
complex.
U and V of X such that U c V
and U compact , then the canonical RF
morphism
morphism
> RF
c
(V,F')
a p!erfect complex.
213
-
3.
-
A FEW PROPERTIES OF f!
(Confer [4] exposes 9, i0, ii) 31
The dual com lex Let X be a space as in 2.1, we define the dual
complex Dx(F') of a complex of sheaves F" by the formula D x(F') = R ~ m " where~m
(F',~IA)
is the inner Hom in the category A x (see for
example GODEMENT
[2], 2.2).
a natural morphism
F"
>
3.1.1 . . .Theorem . . comple x F" is perfect 9
from F" into its bidual.
Suppose the
Then the complex DxF" is also perfect
(In particular, ~iA:
DxDxF"
(Bidualit[ Theorem).
and the natural morphism
perfect, so is
As in the usual cases, we get
F"
> DxDxF"
is an isomorphism.
if the constant sheaf A over X is
confer 1.6 for the case where X is a
manifold 9 3.2 Consider a map for f.
f: X
) Y
such that A (A) holds
In both cases
(i)
G" 6 0b D f.f./.(AY), b F
(ii)
G" 6 Ob D+(AY), F" 6 Ob Df6.f./. (AYA), flF" 6 D b(AYA )
6 Ob D+(AYA )
-
we are able to construct
where
~ stands
product
that
-
a natural
morphism
for the left derived
and f* is the usual
(and last)
214
theorem
gives
functor
inverse
image
a condition
of the tensor
functor.
The next
on f in order to involve
r is an isomorphism. 3.2.1 Definition.
A map f: X
product
if for each point
borhood
U in x, an open n e i g h b o r h o o d
logical
space
making
diagram
U
a
x 6 X there exist an open neigh-
Z p r o v i d e d with
the following
> Y is locally
~
V of f(x),
an h o m e o m o r ~ h i s m
and a topou
~ v x z
commutative
> V
•
Z
V
3.2.2
Theorem.
Under
a)
f: X
b)
the condition
c)
for any y 6 Y, the constant
the following
assumptions
- Y is loca!l [ a p r o d u c t A(A)
holds
for f sheaf A over f-l(y)
is
p e r f e c t , W e have (1) If F
is an object
in D .f.s
(AY)
then f!F"
is an object
in D b f.f.s
x)
(2) In both cases
is perfect)
(resp.
i s perfec t)
(i) and - (ii) of 3.2 the m o r ~ h i s m r
is an isomorphism.
(resp.
fIF'~f*G"
9 f l (F'~G')
-
3.2.3
How to define
struction in case constructions
-
~ (in case
(i) is quite different;
(ii); the conhowever both
agree when F" and G" satisfy conditions
and
(ii) together).
a)
Because
flF'~?
is left adjoint to
since flF" is bounded, F'G" b)
215
(i)
R~m'(f!F',?)
it is enough to define a morphism 9 R ~m"
(flF',f! r
But f* is left adjoint to Rf, and then we just need a
morphism 9 Rf, R ~ 0 m
G.
c)
"
(flF',f'" (F " |L
Now the Poincar~ Duality theorem
instead of Hom')
(using the functor ~ m "
gives an isomorphism Rf
R ~ o m " (flF',fl (F'~G'))
!
and so we seek a morphism G"
d)
> R ~ 0 m " (Rflf!F"
,F' G " ) ,
or, using once more the adjunction between ~ and R ~ 0 m ' ,
a morphism
Rf,fl ' G" e)
>
at this stage we very happily remember the adjunction
between Rf! and fl:
in fact this gives a natural morphism !
~: Rflf"
9 Id
-
216
-
so that we finally define ~' by the formula ~' = ~(F')
~ Id(G')
9
REFERENCES [i]
BOREL, A.
"Poincar~ Duality in Generalized
Manifolds", Michigan Math. J., ~; 227-239, [2]
GODEMENT, Theorie des [aisceauz,
Hermann
scientifiques et industrielles, [3]
HARTSHORNE, Residues and Duality, Mathematics,
[43
VERDIER-ZISMAN,
(1957).
(Actualites
#1252),
(1958).
(Lecture Notes in
#20), Springer Verlag,
"Seminaire sur la f o ~ l e
(1966). de Lefschetz,',
(multigraphi~) Publication IRMA Dept de
Mathematique Faculte des Sciences a Strasbourg.
Offsetdruck:Julius lklt'z. Weinheim/Ikrgstr.